25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Statistical and Non-Statistical Normality<br />

Corina Strößner<br />

Logics of normality which have been suggested so far interpret normality non-statistically. In<br />

this sense, something is normally the case if it is true in the most typical or plausible<br />

circumstances. On the other hand, one might think of normality as majority. In this sense<br />

something is normally the case if it is true in most circumstances. The paper argues that a<br />

descriptive explication of normality must imply statistical majority. Finally it introduces a<br />

formal logic of statistical normality and compares it to other approaches.<br />

1. Principles of Normality Statements<br />

“Normal” and “normally” are frequently used in natural language. We speak about normal<br />

days, normal members of species, normal properties of someone or something etc. In this<br />

discussion we define normality statements as nearly universal generalizations which allow for<br />

exceptions. Not any statement with the word “normal”, “normality” or “normally” is a<br />

normality statement in the sense of this investigation nor is any of these expressions a<br />

necessary part of a normality statement. The word “normally” as a sentential modifier is a<br />

sure indication for a normality statement, e.g. in “Birds can normally fly” or “John normally<br />

sleeps long”. However, statements like “Birds can fly”, “A normal bird can fly” or “John is a<br />

long sleeper” mean often the same as a sentence with “normally” and should be regarded as<br />

normality statements too.<br />

Normality statements are especially important to defeasible reasoning since they justify<br />

predictions which can be revised when more information becomes available. This property of<br />

normality statements can be explained by two different principles of normality statements:<br />

statistical justification and epistemic ordering.<br />

1.1 Statistical Justification<br />

Why should one believe a normality statement like “Birds can normally fly”? Under which<br />

circumstances should we reject such a sentence? One suggestion is that the acceptance of<br />

normality statements should be justified by statistical reasons. Though the statistical reading<br />

is not popular in non-monotonic logic, even Reiter, one father of default reasoning,<br />

interpreted his defaults initially as statistical information: “Such facts usually assume the<br />

form ‘Most P’s are Q’s’” (Reiter 1980: 82). 1<br />

The plausibility of statistical justification for normality statements in natural language is<br />

demonstrated by the obscurity of the following sentences:<br />

(1) Normally, the train is on time; but mostly it is delayed.<br />

(2) Bears are normally shy; but most bears are not shy.<br />

Whoever utters these sentences makes a normality assumption against his statistical<br />

knowledge. This seems to be incoherent. He violates the following principle:<br />

1<br />

Later Reiter strongly rejected this view. See (Reiter 1987).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!