25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

WHEN IS IT RATIONAL TO BELIEVE A MATHEMATICAL STATEMENT 195<br />

Yet the mathematical community seems to have accepted the non-existence of the plane of<br />

order 10 as an established fact, just like the proposition that four colors suffice to color any<br />

map.<br />

4. Conclusion<br />

So where does this leave us? Both arguments we encountered seem to share the same flaw—<br />

the argument for the Riemann Hypothesis in section 2 was merely probabilistic (even though<br />

the probability for RH <strong>bei</strong>ng true was one), and the computer-aided proof for the nonexistence<br />

of finite projective planes of order ten in section 3 is only accurate if no random<br />

hardware errors have given us a false solution, which in itself is highly unlikely. Why, then, do<br />

we accept the second, but reject the first argument?<br />

One of the more common arguments here goes roughly as follows. Mathematicians operate<br />

under the premiss that acceptable proofs are those that can in principle be transformed into a<br />

formal chain of deductive, gapless arguments in some formal calculus. The conclusion of such<br />

a chain of reasoning is the established theorem, which then holds immutably true, given that<br />

the starting points of the deductive chain are true. Perhaps the most fervent supporters of this<br />

view were the group of mathematicians who collectively worked under the nom de guerre<br />

Nicholas Bourbaki:<br />

In practice, the mathematician who wishes to satisfy himself of the perfect correctness<br />

or ‘rigour’ of a proof or a theory hardly ever has recourse to one or another of the<br />

complete formalizations available nowadays, nor even usually to the incomplete and<br />

partial formalizations provided by algebraic and other calculi. In general he is content<br />

to bring the exposition to a point where his experience and mathematical flair tell him<br />

that translation into formal language would be no more than an exercise of patience<br />

(though doubtless a very tedious one). (Bourbaki 1968: 8)<br />

Under this view, rejected argumentations like the one by Denjoy would fail to satisfy<br />

mathematicians because the impression is that they cannot be explicated into a formal chain<br />

of reasoning. On the other hand, since the calculations done by the computers to establish the<br />

non-existence of a finite projective plane of order ten are by their very nature Turingcomputable<br />

and thus recursive, they can certainly be formalized, and hence the calculations<br />

constitute a proof.<br />

I think there are several problems with this view. First, there is the general issue that “proof<br />

in a formal calculus” is, strictly speaking, a notion devoid of content. Formal calculi come in<br />

various shades and forms, and even under the reasonable understanding that we want<br />

formalizations that are in some form tractable, we are left with a huge variety of possibly<br />

admissible rules, ranging from the mathematical puritanism of Russian-style recursive<br />

intuitionism, through the cautiously liberal formalism in the vein of Gentzen to the hedonistic<br />

irresponsibility of higher set theory. And this does not even begin to face the problems<br />

stemming from the fact that we can derive any result we want by introducing suitable<br />

premisses and axioms.<br />

Much more pressing, however, is the fact that Denjoy’s reasoning can be brought into formal<br />

form—at least as much as we assume that any purely mathematical argument within analytic<br />

number theory can. We end up (presumably) with a gapless sequence of logical deductions<br />

that lead, invariably, to the “absurd” conclusion that the Riemann Hypothesis might be false,<br />

but with probability zero. On the other hand, the central theorem of section 3 can be brought<br />

into formal form if and only if no computational errors occurred. In case some random<br />

hardware errors influenced the calculations, the whole argument can no longer, even in<br />

principle, be formalized. Note that this holds even if the hardware errors are negligible in the<br />

sense that they do not lead to a false result. Even if the conclusion is factually correct and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!