25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

REGULARITY THEORIES OF CONSTITUTION COMPARED 131<br />

6.2 Symmetry and Reflexivity<br />

In his article, Couch does not explicitly deal with the question whether the constitution<br />

relation as defined is symmetrical, asymmetrical or anti-symmetrical. Furthermore, he does<br />

not specify whether constitution is reflexive. However, in personal correspondence he has<br />

stated that he agrees with Craver in considering constitutive relevance to be symmetric but<br />

not reflexive.<br />

With respect to the issue of symmetry, this may actually be a problem. Unlike Craver, Couch<br />

provides an extensional definition of mechanistic constitution. If symmetry holds for such a<br />

relation, a conditional of the form ABC → F always implies a conditional F → ABC. The latter<br />

conditional, however, is incompatible with a multiple constitution of F, which Couch wished<br />

to allow explicitly (see Section 5 above and Couch 2011, 385). Consequently, the<br />

characterization of mechanistic constitution as a symmetric relation is somewhat at tension<br />

with other assumptions that are present in his article.<br />

With respect to the question of reflexivity, it is clear that Harbecke’s definition of a reflexive<br />

and anti-symmetric relation of constitution offers a criterion for the ontological distinction, or<br />

the reduction, of cognitive and neural processes. With the rejection of reflexivity, Couch,<br />

however, seems to have already introduced an ontological distinction. The point is that now<br />

no cognitive capacity can be identical to the neural mechanisms constituting it. Otherwise<br />

constitution should at least sometimes be reflexive.<br />

This predetermining commitment may be a problem for the analysis of actual constitutional<br />

explanations in neurobiology, as it has been elaborated, for instance, by Craver (2007, 165-<br />

170). At an early stage of research in neuroscience, it typically remains an open question<br />

whether the phenomena under investigation can ultimately be reduced to mechanisms of<br />

lower levels or not. A theory of mechanistic constitution should therefore not exclude identity<br />

a priori.<br />

6.3 Spurious Regularities<br />

A further difference between the two theories lies in the fact that Harbecke’s definition, in<br />

contrast to Couch’s, introduces a condition that excludes certain spurious regularities<br />

between mechanisms and constituted phenomena. These regularities are imagined analogous<br />

to “Factory Manchester Hooters” cases that pose a serious problem for certain regularity<br />

theories of causation (cf. Mackie 1974, 83-87). As it can be easily checked, the causal structure<br />

represented by Figure 1 is a model of the following minimal theory: A¬CF → B. However,<br />

according to the causal structure depicted, A should not be a cause of B. This problem for<br />

regularity theories of causation was only solved by Grasshoff & May (2001).<br />

Figure 1: “Manchester Factory Hooters” (conditions D and E are causally sufficient for A,<br />

and C is the only alternative cause of A; conditions E and F are causally sufficient for, and G<br />

is the only alternative cause of B).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!