25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

108 MUGG<br />

avoid such speculations when another option exists. Shoemaker offers pure dispositionality as<br />

an alternative. Without taking into consideration the idea that qualitative and dispositional<br />

properties are the same (which is admittedly a surprising identity (Heil 2003: 218)), a pure<br />

powers view of properties does look like the most viable theory.<br />

3. Pure Dispositionality<br />

Many metaphysicians have noted problems with pure dispositionality, usually assuming that<br />

this position stands or falls with a purely relational account of substance (for example, see<br />

Heil 2003: 102). Martin is among the few who do not assume that pure dispositionality<br />

stands or falls with a relational account of objects. Instead, Martin argues that a purely<br />

dispositional account of properties leads to two regresses. The first comes from properties<br />

reducing to dispositions, the second from the manifestation of dispositions reducing to<br />

dispositions. I will briefly outline his reasons for thinking that two regresses follow.<br />

First, let us examine what a pure powers account of properties says about alleged ‘qualitative<br />

properties.’ On a pure powers account of properties, a property that appears qualitative (e.g.<br />

length) reduces to a capacity (e.g. <strong>bei</strong>ng capable of <strong>bei</strong>ng measured at six inches), but this<br />

capacity reduces to a disposition “for the formation of other capacities” (Martin 2008: 63).<br />

Now, these capacities, which are the reduction of a disposition, also reduce to the formation<br />

of other capacities. The same holds with a dispositional property, which is a capacity. This<br />

capacity reduces to a disposition “for the formation of other capacities” (Martin 2008: 63).<br />

These capacities, which are the reduction of this particular disposition, also reduce to more<br />

capacities. Problematically, any time we are confronted with a property, it reduces to a<br />

capacity, and any time we are confronted with a capacity, it reduces to another capacity.<br />

Because every capacity reduces to a reducible capacity, we have an infinite regress. So we<br />

need qualitative properties in our analysis of property identities.<br />

Now let us examine the manifestation of dispositions. According to the pure powers view,<br />

when a disposition manifests, there is no manifestation of a qualitative property. The<br />

manifestation is merely another causal power (or a collection of causal powers). And when<br />

this new casual power is manifested, it will also merely be manifesting another causal power.<br />

Martin writes, “this image appears absurd even if one is a realist about capacities—<br />

dispositions. It is a promissory note that may be actual enough, but if it is for only another<br />

promissory note that is [for another promissory note, and so on], it is entirely too<br />

promissory” (Martin 2008: 63). The purely dispositional account does not allow that a real<br />

thing happens in a manifestation (I mean something beyond its gaining the power to cause<br />

something else); a manifestation is merely a promissory note. By this, Martin means that we<br />

receive a promise that, although the manifestation was not what we expected, some real<br />

event—the new dispositions—will lead to an eventual manifestation that we expect. In other<br />

words, the causal potentiality that the object acquired may lead to causing a real something to<br />

happen. However, each new disposition is only a disposition for gaining or losing dispositions<br />

(see Martin 2008: 61-63). Therefore, a world of dispositions is a world of mere potentialities.<br />

All that happens is the introduction or loss of potentialities.<br />

Perhaps the above reasoning is unconvincing to one who is already a pure power theorist. My<br />

hope is that it gives some reason to deny the elimination of qualitative properties. But now it<br />

seems that we face a dilemma: on the one hand, positing qualitative properties as<br />

ontologically distinct from dispositional properties leads to epistemic worries; on the other<br />

hand, eliminating qualitative properties seems absurd. The identity theory is a way between<br />

these two unpalatable options. In asserting that properties are simultaneously dispositional<br />

and qualitative the identity theory avoids the epistemic worries arising from positing<br />

qualitative properties as distinct from dispositional properties.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!