Stony Brook University - SUNY Digital Repository

Stony Brook University - SUNY Digital Repository Stony Brook University - SUNY Digital Repository

dspace.sunyconnect.suny.edu
from dspace.sunyconnect.suny.edu More from this publisher
25.12.2013 Views

as well as among members of a given audience. Rhetors and audiences bring different backgrounds, aspirations, and assessments of the current state of affairs to any rhetorical situation. If there were no differences of this kind at all, rhetoric would not be necessary. (167) Although this is Crowley’s general definition of rhetoric, it is an ideal that is definitely based upon the classical model, and, because of that emphasis upon “difference,” it is an ideal that is defined by Uncertainty, whether Crowley names it as such or not. Regardless, this theory of classical rhetoric having origins in Uncertainty is also shared by William Covino, as articulated in his book The Art of Wondering. For Covino, the realities of classical rhetoric – the realities of the epistemology that informs classical rhetoric – has fallen victim to century after century (after century) of interpretation, each undertaken to suit the particular rhetorical needs of the time and each drawing classical rhetoric’s techniques and methods further and further away from its original defining perspective of “reality” and “truth.” As Covino explains: [T]here are differences that distinguish the pedagogical use of classical rhetoric from age to age; however, a common emphasis prevails, upon rhetoric as technique. In the Gorgias and the Phaedrus, Plato opens the contest between philosophical and technical rhetoric, and the technical rhetoric remains dominant through the centuries, so that the history of rhetoric is a continually stronger refutation of the suppleness of discourse, a progressive denial of the ambiguity of language and literature, a more and more powerful repression of contextual variables by textual authority. (8) 116

It was this “technical rhetoric” that branched off from classical rhetoric, it would seem, that earned Knoblauch and Brannon’s criticisms. However, it is Covino’s intention with his book to unveil that “philosophical rhetoric” that has become forgotten or ignored over time. To that end, he offers reinterpretations of the defining works of those rhetoricians who represent the “classical” tradition, with the hopes that such a rereading will remove them from that limited and limiting definition of “technical rhetoric.” Covino begins with Plato and it is that discussion that I would focus upon here. For Covino, all of the disparate readings that have been offered of Plato’s Phaedrus are a testimonial to that Greek philosopher’s willful attempts to confuse his work’s readers by filling it with inexplicable ambiguities. He explains: Commentary on the Phaedrus writes a history of confusion. Since Antiquity, those engaged and seduced by the dialogue ask the urgent question, “What is it about?'” […] The critical urgency to locate a unifying subject or purpose in the Phaedrus sets aside the irresolute complexity that informs philosophical rhetoric and writing for Plato. Reducing the conceptual and personal drama of this dialogue to academic summary follows the tendency to read philosophical rhetoric as a digest of information, as a taxonomy of instructions, and thus effectively discounts the striking ambiguity of form and meaning that makes philosophy (and rhetoric) possible and necessary. (10, emphasis mine) Covino compares those attempts to “locate a unifying subject or purpose in the Phaedrus” and thus capture its meaning with certainty to the misunderstandings of Phaedrus, Socrates’ 117

It was this “technical rhetoric” that branched off from<br />

classical rhetoric, it would seem, that earned Knoblauch and<br />

Brannon’s criticisms. However, it is Covino’s intention with<br />

his book to unveil that “philosophical rhetoric” that has become<br />

forgotten or ignored over time. To that end, he offers<br />

reinterpretations of the defining works of those rhetoricians<br />

who represent the “classical” tradition, with the hopes that<br />

such a rereading will remove them from that limited and limiting<br />

definition of “technical rhetoric.”<br />

Covino begins with Plato and it is that discussion that I<br />

would focus upon here. For Covino, all of the disparate<br />

readings that have been offered of Plato’s Phaedrus are a<br />

testimonial to that Greek philosopher’s willful attempts to<br />

confuse his work’s readers by filling it with inexplicable<br />

ambiguities. He explains:<br />

Commentary on the Phaedrus writes a history of<br />

confusion. Since Antiquity, those engaged and<br />

seduced by the dialogue ask the urgent question,<br />

“What is it about?'” […] The critical urgency to<br />

locate a unifying subject or purpose in the Phaedrus<br />

sets aside the irresolute complexity that informs<br />

philosophical rhetoric and writing for Plato.<br />

Reducing the conceptual and personal drama of this<br />

dialogue to academic summary follows the tendency to<br />

read philosophical rhetoric as a digest of<br />

information, as a taxonomy of instructions, and thus<br />

effectively discounts the striking ambiguity of form<br />

and meaning that makes philosophy (and rhetoric)<br />

possible and necessary. (10, emphasis mine)<br />

Covino compares those attempts to “locate a unifying subject or<br />

purpose in the Phaedrus” and thus capture its meaning with<br />

certainty to the misunderstandings of Phaedrus, Socrates’<br />

117

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!