The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

humanities.mcmaster.ca
from humanities.mcmaster.ca More from this publisher
20.12.2013 Views

In this section I will propose such a recursive operator. I will show how the operator motivates the location of given elements on the left edge of their domain and the fact that the domains correspond to propositions. In section 4.2.1, I will give arguments for the domains being propositional. Next, in section 4.2.2, I will define the operator and I will show how it interacts with the Maximize presupposition maxim. 4.2.1 G-movement domains are propositional domains So far, we have seen several types of domains within which G-movement takes place. Either (i) the domain corresponds to a finite clause, which we can take to be a proposition without any further discussion, or (ii) the domain is whatever is selected by a tense auxiliary, or (iii) the domain is a small clause. 4 If we assume that a tensed auxiliary selects for a proposition, following Ogihara (1996), among others, we can conclude that in all the cases discussed so far, the relevant domain of G-movement is a proposition. The relation is schematized in (24). The examples in (25)–(27) illustrate the relation between a tense auxiliary and the domain of G-movement. (24) a. Future: Aux-v < proposition VP > b. Past: Aux-T < proposition vP + VP > c. Present: < proposition (CP) + TP + vP + VP > (25) Future: (26) Past: a. What will happen with all the money that was found in the building? b. Nějaký úředník [ vP bude [ V P peníze || pravidelně posílat opuštěným some clerk.Nom will money.Acc regularly send lonely dětem.]] children.Dat ‘A clerk will regularly send the money to lonely children.’ a. What happened with all the money that was found in the building? b. Nějaký úředník a já [ TP jsme [ vP peníze || pravidelně posílali some clerk.Nom and I were money.Acc regularly sent opuštěným dětem.]] lonely children.Dat ‘A clerk and regularly sent the money to lonely children.’ (27) Present: 4 I put aside DPs and coordinations where we have not detected G-movement. I will get back to the coordination facts in section 4.4. 94

a. What happens with all the money that was found in the building? b. Peníze || posílá pravidelně nějaký úředník opuštěným dětem. money.Acc sends regularly some clerk.Nom lonely children.Dat ‘A clerk and regularly sends the money to lonely children.’ So far the correlation between auxiliary selection and the domain of G-movement being a proposition is only suggestive. Even though such a correlation is possible, the relation is not straightforward. Furthermore, the assumption that tense selects a proposition has been questioned in recent literature on tense (Kusumoto, 2005). In the rest of this subsection I will build an additional argument for treating domains of G-movement as propositions. The argument is based on behavior of propositional modifiers such as ‘again’. Modifiers such as ‘again’ are known to be able to attach at different levels of a syntactic structure and their different syntactic position corresponds to different scope properties. Bale (To appear) has noticed that while the attachment site of modifiers like ‘again’ may vary, the constituent ‘again’ attaches to is always a proposition. Since only a proposition gives rise to a presupposition we can test whether a constituent is a proposition or not by looking at presuppositions the modifier gives rise to. Thus if the hypothesis about the relation between G-movement and propositions is correct, we predict that different tenses in Czech should have different presuppositions. Let’s consider the difference between perfective versus imperfective future tense formation in Czech. While the imperfect future tense is formed by a v-generated auxiliary and an infinitive, the perfective future tense is formed by a synthetic finite verbal form. See the examples in (28). (28) a. Marie nakoupí (*dvě Marie.Nom shops.Fut.Perf two ‘Marie will shop.’ b. Marie bude nakupovat dvě Marie will.3.sg. shop.Inf.Imp two ‘Marie will shop for two hours.’ hodiny). hours hodiny. hours If we assume that the imperfective auxiliary selects for a proposition and that the subject is base generated as the specifier of vP, we predict that the structure may give rise to a presupposition that excludes the subject. In contrast, since in the perfective future tense the domain of G-movement is bigger than VP, no subject-less proposition is predicted to be possible. The predictions are schematized in (29). As we will see shortly, the predictions are borne out. (29) a. Imperfective Future: [ vP Subject Aux [ V P again event]] → again gives rise to a presupposition in exclusion of the subject b. Perfective Future: [ vP Subject verb [ V P again . . . ]] → again cannot give rise to a presupposition in exclusion of the subject 95

a. What happens with all the money that was found in the building?<br />

b. Peníze || posílá pravidelně nějaký úředník opuštěným dětem.<br />

money.Acc sends regularly some clerk.Nom lonely children.Dat<br />

‘A clerk and regularly sends the money to lonely children.’<br />

So far the correlation between auxiliary selection and the domain <strong>of</strong> G-movement being a<br />

proposition is only suggestive. Even though such a correlation is possible, the relation is<br />

not straightforward. Furthermore, the assumption that tense selects a proposition has been<br />

questioned in recent literature on tense (Kusumoto, 2005).<br />

In the rest <strong>of</strong> this subsection I will build an additional argument for treating domains <strong>of</strong><br />

G-movement as propositions. <strong>The</strong> argument is based on behavior <strong>of</strong> propositional modifiers<br />

such as ‘again’. Modifiers such as ‘again’ are known to be able to attach at different<br />

levels <strong>of</strong> a syntactic structure and their different syntactic position corresponds to different<br />

scope properties. Bale (To appear) has noticed that while the attachment site <strong>of</strong> modifiers<br />

like ‘again’ may vary, the constituent ‘again’ attaches to is always a proposition. Since only<br />

a proposition gives rise to a presupposition we can test whether a constituent is a proposition<br />

or not by looking at presuppositions the modifier gives rise to.<br />

Thus if the hypothesis about the relation between G-movement and propositions is correct,<br />

we predict that different tenses in Czech should have different presuppositions. Let’s<br />

consider the difference between perfective versus imperfective future tense formation in<br />

Czech. While the imperfect future tense is formed by a v-generated auxiliary and an infinitive,<br />

the perfective future tense is formed by a synthetic finite verbal form. See the<br />

examples in (28).<br />

(28) a. Marie nakoupí (*dvě<br />

Marie.Nom shops.Fut.Perf two<br />

‘Marie will shop.’<br />

b. Marie bude nakupovat dvě<br />

Marie will.3.sg. shop.Inf.Imp two<br />

‘Marie will shop for two hours.’<br />

hodiny).<br />

hours<br />

hodiny.<br />

hours<br />

If we assume that the imperfective auxiliary selects for a proposition and that the subject<br />

is base generated as the specifier <strong>of</strong> vP, we predict that the structure may give rise to a<br />

presupposition that excludes the subject. In contrast, since in the perfective future tense the<br />

domain <strong>of</strong> G-movement is bigger than VP, no subject-less proposition is predicted to be<br />

possible. <strong>The</strong> predictions are schematized in (29). As we will see shortly, the predictions<br />

are borne out.<br />

(29) a. Imperfective Future:<br />

[ vP Subject Aux [ V P again event]]<br />

→ again gives rise to a presupposition in exclusion <strong>of</strong> the subject<br />

b. Perfective Future:<br />

[ vP Subject verb [ V P again . . . ]]<br />

→ again cannot give rise to a presupposition in exclusion <strong>of</strong> the subject<br />

95

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!