The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

humanities.mcmaster.ca
from humanities.mcmaster.ca More from this publisher
20.12.2013 Views

landing site. In chapter 3, I will use the formalization offered in this chapter to show how G-movement, a relatively simple syntactic tool, can account for complex word order patterns. 2.1 The target of G-movement In this section, I will address the question of the landing site of G-movement. I will show that in Czech there is no unique syntactic position that is always interpreted as given. The argument will be based on properties of movement to T. The logic behind this move is that the element that moves to Spec,TP or to T is often interpreted as given. In the same time such an element can be new as well. If, for example, Spec,TP were a unique syntactic position for being interpreted as given, the possibility of new elements in Spec,TP would be unexpected. 1 I will argue that movement to Spec,TP is a result of an Attract Closest condition on T and as such it has nothing to do with the information structure nature of the projection. I suggest that the ambiguous property of movement to Spec,TP can be extended to other functional projections as well. 2 Notice that the argument goes only in one direction. It says that it cannot be true that whatever moves to Spec,TP must be given. Thus, the argument does not exclude the possibility that whatever is to be interpreted as given moves to Spec,TP. We have seen, however, in section 1.4 that this is not true either. In section 2.2, I will provide examples that make the point that G-movement can target other positions as well. We now proceed to the first half of the argument, i.e., to the claim that Spec,TP does not have a uniform interpretation. We have already seen in the discussion of basic word orders (in section 1.2), that in the basic word order the leftmost element can be either given or new. Consider the example in (1). Nějaká paní ‘some lady’ does not need to be presupposed and it can still occupy the subject position (Spec,TP). (1) a. What happened? b. Nějaká paní poslala osamělým dětem dárky. some lady.Nom sent lonely children.Dat presents.Acc ‘Some lady sent presents to lonely children.’ I argue that movement to T (Spec,TP or head-adjunction to T) in Czech is driven by an EPP-like principle, not by, for example, some given feature (see also Saito (1989); Tateishi (1994); Sauerland (1999) for scrambling in Japanese). If this is correct, we predict that movement to Spec,TP is dependent on the internal structure of vP, in the sense that it is the highest element within vP that moves to Spec,TP by virtue of being closest. Thus, even in 1 The argument is in line with Lavine and Freidin (2002); Bailyn (2003), among others, who argue that Spec,TP is not a designated given position. 2 The argument crucially assumes that given DPs target an A-position. One might argue that the given interpretation arises only if the relevant DP undergoes A-bar movement. I will argue in the appendix that G-movement is indeed A-movement. Thus, there is no reason to assume that there is a positional difference between a DP being interpreted as given and a DP being interpreted as new. 42

asic word order cases we expect word order variations depending on the internal structure of vP. We have already seen such a case in the discussion of unergative and unaccusative verbs in section 1.1. Consider again the examples in (2) and (3). As these examples show, there is a word order difference between unergative and unaccusative verbs. While an unergative verb follows the subject, an unaccusative verb linearly precedes the subject. (2) Basic word order of unergative verbs: a. [Marie tancovala] New Marie danced b. #[Tancovala Marie] New danced Marie ’Marie danced.’ (3) Basic word order of unaccusative verbs: a. [Přijel vlak] New arrived train b. #[Vlak přijel] New train arrived ‘A train arrived.’ If the subject of an unaccusative verb is structurally lower (VP) than the subject of an unergative verb (vP), the word order difference follows under the following assumptions. First, an inflected verb must undergo movement from V to v. 3 Second, in Czech a DP can establish syntactic relations by Agree; it therefore does not need to raise from its base generated position. Third, v does not need to have a specifier. The resulting structures are given in (4) and (5). In the case of unergatives, T attracts the subject because it is the closest element. On the other hand, in the case of unaccusatives, T attracts the v head (or the v-V complex) because it is the structurally closest element. 4 3 In Czech, this condition holds both for finite and inflected infinitival forms such as participles. For more details on syntax of Czech verbal morphology see, for example, Junghanns (1999); Veselovská (2004); Veselovská and Karlík (2004); Kučerová (2005). 4 In functionalist Czech literature, verbs like ‘arrive’ are traditionally classified as ‘verbs of appearing on the scene’ (Sgall et al., 1980, 1986, among others). Putting aside that it is unclear how to determine this category, other unaccusative verbs behave in the same way even when they are not semantically verbs of appearing on the scene (David Pesetsky, p.c.). See the examples in (i) and (ii). (i) a. [Líbí se mi knihy] New like REFL to-me books.Nom b. #[Knihy se mi líbí] New books.Nom REFL to-me like ‘Books appeal to me.’ (ii) a. [Existují různé názory na dějiny] New exist various opinions.Nom at history b. #[Různé názory na dějiny existují] New various opinions.Nm at history exist 43

landing site. In chapter 3, I will use the formalization <strong>of</strong>fered in this chapter to show<br />

how G-movement, a relatively simple syntactic tool, can account for complex word order<br />

patterns.<br />

2.1 <strong>The</strong> target <strong>of</strong> G-movement<br />

In this section, I will address the question <strong>of</strong> the landing site <strong>of</strong> G-movement. I will show<br />

that in Czech there is no unique syntactic position that is always interpreted as given. <strong>The</strong><br />

argument will be based on properties <strong>of</strong> movement to T. <strong>The</strong> logic behind this move is that<br />

the element that moves to Spec,TP or to T is <strong>of</strong>ten interpreted as given. In the same time<br />

such an element can be new as well. If, for example, Spec,TP were a unique syntactic<br />

position for being interpreted as given, the possibility <strong>of</strong> new elements in Spec,TP would<br />

be unexpected. 1 I will argue that movement to Spec,TP is a result <strong>of</strong> an Attract Closest<br />

condition on T and as such it has nothing to do with the information structure nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

projection. I suggest that the ambiguous property <strong>of</strong> movement to Spec,TP can be extended<br />

to other functional projections as well. 2<br />

Notice that the argument goes only in one direction. It says that it cannot be true that<br />

whatever moves to Spec,TP must be given. Thus, the argument does not exclude the possibility<br />

that whatever is to be interpreted as given moves to Spec,TP. We have seen, however,<br />

in section 1.4 that this is not true either. In section 2.2, I will provide examples that make<br />

the point that G-movement can target other positions as well.<br />

We now proceed to the first half <strong>of</strong> the argument, i.e., to the claim that Spec,TP does not<br />

have a uniform interpretation. We have already seen in the discussion <strong>of</strong> basic word orders<br />

(in section 1.2), that in the basic word order the leftmost element can be either given or new.<br />

Consider the example in (1). Nějaká paní ‘some lady’ does not need to be presupposed and<br />

it can still occupy the subject position (Spec,TP).<br />

(1) a. What happened?<br />

b. Nějaká paní poslala osamělým dětem dárky.<br />

some lady.Nom sent lonely children.Dat presents.Acc<br />

‘Some lady sent presents to lonely children.’<br />

I argue that movement to T (Spec,TP or head-adjunction to T) in Czech is driven by an<br />

EPP-like principle, not by, for example, some given feature (see also Saito (1989); Tateishi<br />

(1994); Sauerland (1999) for scrambling in Japanese). If this is correct, we predict that<br />

movement to Spec,TP is dependent on the internal structure <strong>of</strong> vP, in the sense that it is the<br />

highest element within vP that moves to Spec,TP by virtue <strong>of</strong> being closest. Thus, even in<br />

1 <strong>The</strong> argument is in line with Lavine and Freidin (2002); Bailyn (2003), among others, who argue that<br />

Spec,TP is not a designated given position.<br />

2 <strong>The</strong> argument crucially assumes that given DPs target an A-position. One might argue that the given<br />

interpretation arises only if the relevant DP undergoes A-bar movement. I will argue in the appendix that<br />

G-movement is indeed A-movement. Thus, there is no reason to assume that there is a positional difference<br />

between a DP being interpreted as given and a DP being interpreted as new.<br />

42

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!