The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

humanities.mcmaster.ca
from humanities.mcmaster.ca More from this publisher
20.12.2013 Views

given counterpart, and (ii) why is one instance of G-movement sometimes sufficient but more than one instance of G-movement is required other times. I will leave the questions open for now and I will come back to them in chapter 4. In this section, I have provided two arguments that G-movement is a last resort syntactic operation. The arguments were based on two facts about the distribution of pronouns in Czech. First, I have shown that pronouns do not undergo G-movement. I have suggested that this shows that G-movement applies only to elements that are to be interpreted as given but that at the same time do not enter the derivation lexically marked as given. The second part of this section addressed the question of what happens if an element cannot undergo G- movement because of independent syntactic restrictions on movement, such as islands. We have observed that in such configurations an element must already come from the lexicon marked as given because there is no other way it could be marked as given in syntax. Last, we have seen that if an element is trapped within an island but high enough in the structure, the fact that it cannot undergo movement does not matter because the relevant interpretation can be obtained without movement. Thus G-movement is not required. 1.6 Summary In this chapter, I have offered several generalizations about the distribution of given and new information in a Czech clause. I have shown that in an optimal configuration, the given part linearly precedes the new part and the partition is marked by a verb which can be on either side of the partition. I have proposed to account for the linear order facts in terms of G-movement: an economy restricted movement that requires a given element to move only if such an element is asymmetrically c-commanded by a new element and is not lexically marked as given. I have presented several arguments in favor of understanding G- movement as a last resort operation, including arguments from the distribution of pronouns and the semantic ambiguity of certain strings. We have also seen that elements that are lexically given do not undergo G-movement and that the linear partition between given and new is not always perfect. In chapters 2 and 3 I will develop the current toy system in detail. After that, in chapter 4, I will refine my answer to the question of how G-movement is motivated and how it is treated by the interfaces. In particular, I will argue that G-movement is a free syntactic movement, the purpose of which is to create a configuration which can be semantically interpreted in a way that is required by the contextually established common ground. 40

Chapter 2 G-movement In chapter 1, I introduced several basic generalizations about Czech word order and its dependence on the information structure of an utterance. I proposed to account for the Czech word order facts by movement which takes place only if a given element is asymmetrically c-commanded by a new element. I called this movement G-movement. I provided evidence that G-movement is restricted by head movement. In particular, a given element may G-move only if the head in the projection of which the given element was base generated moves as well. Another important point I made was that G-movement cannot be the grammatical tool that marks or licenses elements as given. The evidence comes from the fact that only some given elements undergo G-movement. If a given element is in a configuration where there is no asymmetrically c-commanding new element, the given element not only does not move, it cannot move. A consequence of this observation is that G-movement does not seem to be feature-driven. The purpose of this chapter is to formalize the notion of G-movement and to fill in parts of the syntactic system that are still missing. In particular, I will look closely at the following three questions: (i) what is the syntactic target of G-movement? (ii) at what point of the derivation may G-movement take place? and (iii) what kind of syntactic operation is G-movement? In section 2.1, I will provide a partial answer to the question of what a plausible landing site of G-movement might be. I will argue that Czech has no unique syntactic position that is always interpreted as given. Thus, we cannot associate G-movement with any particular syntactic projection. I will refine the analysis of possible landing sites of G-movement in section 2.2. I will concentrate on the question of when during the derivation G-movement takes place. I will argue that G-movement may take place after any merge (both internal and external), thus strengthening the point that G-movement may target various syntactic positions. In section 2.3, I will explain the apparent lack of a unique landing site of G- movement and the fact that G-movement may take place after any merge as a consequence of G-movement being parasitic on head movement. I will show how the head movement restriction relates to the timing of G-movement and to the apparent lack of a landing site for G-movement. In particular, I will argue that the parasitic nature of this type of merge is closely connected to the strict locality conditions and to the lack of a unique syntactic 41

Chapter 2<br />

G-movement<br />

In chapter 1, I introduced several basic generalizations about Czech word order and its dependence<br />

on the information structure <strong>of</strong> an utterance. I proposed to account for the Czech<br />

word order facts by movement which takes place only if a given element is asymmetrically<br />

c-commanded by a new element. I called this movement G-movement. I provided<br />

evidence that G-movement is restricted by head movement. In particular, a given element<br />

may G-move only if the head in the projection <strong>of</strong> which the given element was base generated<br />

moves as well. Another important point I made was that G-movement cannot be<br />

the grammatical tool that marks or licenses elements as given. <strong>The</strong> evidence comes from<br />

the fact that only some given elements undergo G-movement. If a given element is in a<br />

configuration where there is no asymmetrically c-commanding new element, the given element<br />

not only does not move, it cannot move. A consequence <strong>of</strong> this observation is that<br />

G-movement does not seem to be feature-driven.<br />

<strong>The</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> this chapter is to formalize the notion <strong>of</strong> G-movement and to fill in parts<br />

<strong>of</strong> the syntactic system that are still missing. In particular, I will look closely at the following<br />

three questions: (i) what is the syntactic target <strong>of</strong> G-movement? (ii) at what point <strong>of</strong><br />

the derivation may G-movement take place? and (iii) what kind <strong>of</strong> syntactic operation is<br />

G-movement?<br />

In section 2.1, I will provide a partial answer to the question <strong>of</strong> what a plausible landing<br />

site <strong>of</strong> G-movement might be. I will argue that Czech has no unique syntactic position that<br />

is always interpreted as given. Thus, we cannot associate G-movement with any particular<br />

syntactic projection. I will refine the analysis <strong>of</strong> possible landing sites <strong>of</strong> G-movement in<br />

section 2.2. I will concentrate on the question <strong>of</strong> when during the derivation G-movement<br />

takes place. I will argue that G-movement may take place after any merge (both internal<br />

and external), thus strengthening the point that G-movement may target various syntactic<br />

positions. In section 2.3, I will explain the apparent lack <strong>of</strong> a unique landing site <strong>of</strong> G-<br />

movement and the fact that G-movement may take place after any merge as a consequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> G-movement being parasitic on head movement. I will show how the head movement<br />

restriction relates to the timing <strong>of</strong> G-movement and to the apparent lack <strong>of</strong> a landing site<br />

for G-movement. In particular, I will argue that the parasitic nature <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> merge<br />

is closely connected to the strict locality conditions and to the lack <strong>of</strong> a unique syntactic<br />

41

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!