20.12.2013 Views

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

(31) Derivation <strong>of</strong> [Subject]-G verb-G Object<br />

vP<br />

Subject G<br />

vP<br />

v-G<br />

VP<br />

t V<br />

Object<br />

<strong>The</strong> logic that arises is the following: if a structure is monotonous in the sense that there is<br />

no point where a new element would asymmetrically c-command a given element, syntax<br />

does not have any tool to mark what part exactly is given and what part exactly is new. In<br />

contrast, if there is any deviance from the basic word order, the partition between given<br />

and new is syntactically realized. Thus, the interpretation <strong>of</strong> the utterance is restricted by<br />

syntactic tools. I will argue in chapter 4 that if there is no G-movement, the partition is<br />

established by the semantic component.<br />

I argue that any basic word order sentence – if presented out <strong>of</strong> the blue – is ambiguous<br />

with respect to its information structure. Since there is no syntactic marking <strong>of</strong> the partition<br />

between given and new within basic word order determining the partition is left entirely to<br />

the semantic interface. I argue that this follows from the fact that in a neutral word order<br />

sentence there is no G-movement taking place. Thus the syntactic output <strong>of</strong> such a sentence<br />

is identical no matter how many semantic interpretations <strong>of</strong> the sentence are available.<br />

This conclusion is supported by the fact that there is no difference in prosody between<br />

(27-a) and (30-a). If we assume that phonology reads prosody directly <strong>of</strong>f the syntactic<br />

structure (see, for example, Bresnan 1972; Truckenbrodt 1995; Wagner 2005; Büring 2006,<br />

among many others) this is an unsurprising result. <strong>The</strong>refore, it is only the semantic component<br />

that may interpret such a clause in different ways depending on the actual context.<br />

For syntax and the syntax-phonology interface there is only one structure to be considered.<br />

Crucially, this behavior is a consequence <strong>of</strong> G-movement being a last resort operation. If G-<br />

movement had to take place whenever there was something potentially given, the semantic<br />

(but also word order and prosodic) ambiguity <strong>of</strong> the basic word order would be unexpected.<br />

In this section, we have seen that there is a close connection between the last resort<br />

character <strong>of</strong> G-movement and the multiple interpretations available for basic word orders.<br />

In the next section we will look at ambiguities that arise within derived orders. I will argue<br />

that this type <strong>of</strong> ambiguity follows from G-movement being dependent on head movement.<br />

1.3 Verb partitions and their semantic ambiguity<br />

In Czech the partition between given and new is <strong>of</strong>ten manifested by a finite verb. <strong>The</strong><br />

fact that Czech verbs usually appear between the given and the new part has already been<br />

observed by Vilém Mathesius (Mathesius, [1929] 1983, 1939). In the following Czech<br />

22

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!