The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová The Syntax of Givenness Ivona Kucerová

humanities.mcmaster.ca
from humanities.mcmaster.ca More from this publisher
20.12.2013 Views

To sum up, we have seen that the G-operator that we need anyhow in order to mark presupposition does a lot of useful work for us. Now we have a system that can capture all the Czech data we have encountered so far. The only tools we need are G-movement, the G-operator and the assumption that the semantic component is able to compute global comparison of derivations. 4.5 The interpretation of Givenness In this chapter I have introduced a recursive G-operator whose purpose is to mark a part of a structure as presupposed. I have not, however, defined yet what it means to be given in a technical sense. The leading intuition is that given is something that is salient in the discourse and which gives rise to a presupposition that must be satisfied for the utterance to be felicitous in the relevant context. In principle we could adopt various definitions of givenness. I will adopt here Sauerland (2005)’s definition of givenness. The relevant lexical entries for type e and type et follow. (99) Lexical entry for Given of type e: Given g e ∃x & ∃i.g(i) = x = λx x (100) Lexical entry for Given of type et: where f has a salient antecedent in C Given = λf et ∃x ∈ De .f(x) = 1 f If Given applies to an element of type < α,t >, Given presupposes the existential closure of the complement of Given. If Given applies to an element of type e, the lexical entry requires the element to be evaluated with respect to an assignment previously established in the discourse. As we will see in section 4.6 these lexical entries are too weak but I will stay with them for lack of a better alternative. To see how these lexical entries combine with our current system, consider the following example, after Sauerland (2005). (101) English version: a. Q: Who ate a cookie? b. A: LINA [ate a cookie]-Given (102) Czech version: a. Q: Kdo snědl koláček? who ate cookie? ‘Who ate a/the cookie?’ b. A: Koláček snědla || Lina. cookie ate Lina ‘Lina ate a/the cookie.’ 120

In this case, the given part is ‘ate a/the cookie’. Let’s go step by step through the derivation and its interpretation. A simplified LF of the Czech sentence in (102-b) is given in (103). Basic lexical entries are given in (104). (103) E cookie D ate C G B 8 A 7 vP Lina VP (104) a. ate = λx.λy. y ate x b. Lina = lina c. cookie = cookie where lina and cookie are individuals t7 ate t8 cookie Let’s compute the semantics of the LF in (103) step by step, starting with the denotation of VP and vP. (105) VP = λy. f 7 (x 8 )(y) (106) vP g = 1 iff [λy. f 7 (x 8 )(y)] (Lina) = 1 iff [λy. f 7 (x 8 )(y)] (lina) = 1 iff f 7 (x 8 )(lina) After taking into account lambda abstraction induced by G-movement of the object and the verb we get the following denotation. (107) B = λf 7 .λx 8 . f 7 (x 8 )(lina) Now the G-operator can take the constituent B as its argument because B is not of type t. The resulting denotation is given in (108). Notice that the G-operator applies in two steps. First, it induces that there is going to be a given function of type e,et. In the following step, the operator induces a given individual. (108) C = G(B) = G(λf 7 .λx 8 . f 7 (x 8 )(lina)) = λh e,et : Given(h). G ([λf 7 .λx 8 . f 7 (x 8 )(lina)](h)) = λh e,et : Given(h).G ([λx 8 . h(x 8 )(lina)]) = 121

To sum up, we have seen that the G-operator that we need anyhow in order to mark<br />

presupposition does a lot <strong>of</strong> useful work for us. Now we have a system that can capture<br />

all the Czech data we have encountered so far. <strong>The</strong> only tools we need are G-movement,<br />

the G-operator and the assumption that the semantic component is able to compute global<br />

comparison <strong>of</strong> derivations.<br />

4.5 <strong>The</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Givenness</strong><br />

In this chapter I have introduced a recursive G-operator whose purpose is to mark a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> a structure as presupposed. I have not, however, defined yet what it means to be given<br />

in a technical sense. <strong>The</strong> leading intuition is that given is something that is salient in the<br />

discourse and which gives rise to a presupposition that must be satisfied for the utterance<br />

to be felicitous in the relevant context.<br />

In principle we could adopt various definitions <strong>of</strong> givenness. I will adopt here Sauerland<br />

(2005)’s definition <strong>of</strong> givenness. <strong>The</strong> relevant lexical entries for type e and type et follow.<br />

(99) Lexical entry for Given <strong>of</strong> type e:<br />

Given g e ∃x & ∃i.g(i) = x<br />

= λx<br />

x<br />

(100) Lexical entry for Given <strong>of</strong> type et:<br />

where f has a salient antecedent in C<br />

Given = λf et ∃x ∈ De .f(x) = 1<br />

f<br />

If Given applies to an element <strong>of</strong> type < α,t >, Given presupposes the existential closure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the complement <strong>of</strong> Given. If Given applies to an element <strong>of</strong> type e, the lexical entry<br />

requires the element to be evaluated with respect to an assignment previously established<br />

in the discourse. As we will see in section 4.6 these lexical entries are too weak but I will<br />

stay with them for lack <strong>of</strong> a better alternative. To see how these lexical entries combine<br />

with our current system, consider the following example, after Sauerland (2005).<br />

(101) English version:<br />

a. Q: Who ate a cookie?<br />

b. A: LINA [ate a cookie]-Given<br />

(102) Czech version:<br />

a. Q: Kdo snědl koláček?<br />

who ate cookie?<br />

‘Who ate a/the cookie?’<br />

b. A: Koláček snědla || Lina.<br />

cookie ate Lina<br />

‘Lina ate a/the cookie.’<br />

120

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!