24.11.2013 Views

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

184 I Social Theory and Social Action<br />

the genetic basis for the general human ability to make conventions. The opposition<br />

between nature and convention, between genetic determination and cultural<br />

determination, is thus transcended. As Robin Fox (1980:185-86) puts it:<br />

If we can analyze society itself as a natural product of natural selection, then<br />

the categories arising from it are themselves products of the same process, deriving,<br />

certainly, not from "individual experience" but from the collective genetic<br />

experience of the group—its gene pool. They are thus at once both<br />

"social" and "innate." . . . Culture and society are natural phenomena, and<br />

concepts and categories, rules and emotions, have all developed together as interconnected<br />

responses to recognizable selection pressures. Conceptual thought<br />

and language, inhibitions by obedience to rules, emotional responses to objects<br />

of social and environmental classification, all developed together.<br />

Since the tendency to follow social customs is itself genetically specified, conventions<br />

are rendered epiphenomenal, as merely linguistic labels for patterns of behavior<br />

regulated by noncultural factors.<br />

In The Red Lamp of Incest (1980) Fox sets out to explain, among other<br />

things, one of the ur-conventions of anthropological discourse, namely, prescriptive<br />

marriage rules stipulating that individuals must find mates outside their own<br />

kin group yet from a specifically defined other group. At least since Morgan's<br />

time, nothing—language excepted—has more challenged our ability to construct<br />

universalistic explanations than the variety and complexity of documented patterns<br />

of marriage alliance, with corresponding systems of lineage organization<br />

and kin-term typologies. Fox argues that our early hominid ancestors faced an<br />

increasingly difficult time reconciling two needs, the need to maximize genetic<br />

replication through inbreeding and the need to maximize genetic strength<br />

through outbreeding. The solution to this dilemma was forced upon more developed<br />

homo sapiens when they began hunting for meat. With the males out hunting<br />

and the females out gathering, the sexes began to rely on each other not just<br />

for procreation but as exchange partners, so that rather than fight over women,<br />

men exchange near-kin among themselves, thereby establishing the category of<br />

"marriageable kin." In other words, a man does not marry his sister but rather<br />

is guaranteed the sexual services of a second or third cousin. Whereas hominid<br />

males had a "tendency to accumulate females" for breeding purposes, primitive<br />

hunting and gathering peoples maximized sexual capital through the "investment"<br />

in marriage. The parallel to the transition from mercantilist accumulation<br />

of wealth to capitalist investment is remarkable. Fox even phrases this development<br />

in terms of the switch from women as "use-values" to women as "exchange-values"!<br />

Instead of keeping females for themselves, dominant males in<br />

some groups began to exchange sisters; the perpetuation of this arrangement,<br />

called cross-cousin marriage, ensured the constant circulation of the most valued<br />

commodity, women.<br />

Naturalization of Convention I 185<br />

But what happened to the notion of a marriage rule, if everything is determined<br />

in the end by the selective pressure? Fox's (1979:133-34) answer is, as<br />

he admits, "tedious":<br />

Our uniqueness lies not in having, recognizing, and behaving differentially to<br />

different kin (this happens throughout nature), it lies in giving this process<br />

names and rules of naming; in the classification not the kinship. . . . Kinship<br />

grouping and kin-derived behavior do not make us unique: the naming of kin<br />

does. In each case a universal, hence biological, feature is associated with a<br />

"cultural practice." But by the same logic, the cultural practice—ruling and<br />

naming, i.e., classification—if universal, must also be biological. Hence one set<br />

of biological features—the propensity to classify and regulate—comes into<br />

conjunction with two others: the propensity to outbreed and to behave differentially<br />

toward kin. All this is possible through the mediation of language. The<br />

latter, however, being universal, is also biological, and hence the unifying feature<br />

of the other two biological features is itself biological. Ergo, there is no<br />

nature-culture distinction, everything is natural-biological. Hence the argument<br />

that we cannot use analyses developed for nature to interpret culture fails<br />

since by its own logic the supposedly unique cultural features turn out to be<br />

natural.<br />

Fox's just-so attack on conventionality is double-edged: the ability to make conventions,<br />

that is, to impose linguistic classification upon patterns of action, is<br />

merely the inconsequential labeling of already established practices. And because<br />

rules for kinship and marriage are found universally in human society they must<br />

be products of the same biological forces which determine the behavior they<br />

name. That is, conventions are either pointless or natural. 3<br />

Naturalization and Conventionalization in Social Reality<br />

Lastly we should realize that dancing in a partner's arms is a product of<br />

modern European civilization. Which shows you that things we find natural<br />

are historical. Moreover, they horrify everyone in the world but ourselves.<br />

—Marcel Mauss (1979:116)<br />

Thus, the concept of conventionality has in principle a relative, rather than<br />

absolute meaning: it is impossible to say that a given form is more<br />

conventional and another less conventional without taking into account how<br />

these forms function in the LANGUAGE under consideration, whether it is a<br />

natural language or a language of art.<br />

—Boris Uspensky (1976:8z, n. 34)<br />

We have seen that several strands of positivistic discourse, namely, Hobbes's<br />

deductive mechanics, Morgan's practical rationality, and Fox's sociobiological<br />

reductionism, posit the theoretical naturalness of social convention. Moreover, in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!