24.11.2013 Views

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

i8z<br />

I Social Theory and Social Action<br />

Naturalization of Convention I 183<br />

ation of natural-law theories which assumed that historically developed rules<br />

were "supposed to have been evolved from the unassisted contemplation of the<br />

conception of Nature" (Maine 1972:59). Rather, for Maine, the momentous invention<br />

that made state-level society (that is, based on territory rather than kinship)<br />

possible is "legal fiction," the artificial and conventional stipulation that a<br />

state of affairs exists when in fact it does not. Early states, for example, were<br />

based on the useful fiction that immigrant groups were genealogically related to<br />

the local population (Maine 1875:69). Legal fictions are more complex versions<br />

of fictions which create "definite social forms" such as the family, the tribe, and<br />

the village community out of "broken hordes, mere miscellanies of men" (Maine<br />

1886:285). Once this convention was acknowledged and consecrated through<br />

common sacrifices, the "permanence and solidity" of the social order was assured.<br />

Thus, "the composition of the state, uniformly assumed to be natural, was<br />

nevertheless known to be in great measure artificial" (Maine 1972:77). This<br />

growth of legal fictions was the model for a constitutive openness which Maine<br />

sees as the distinguishing feature of modern society. Whereas in primitive societies<br />

a person's social position is naturally fixed by the irreversable assignment of<br />

status at birth, civilization developed the mechanism of contractual law through<br />

which a person could alter this natural state of affairs and "create it by himself<br />

by convention" (Maine 1972:183).<br />

Whether in Hobbes's anchoring of the hypothetical original contract in natural<br />

law or in Maine's positive valuation of customary or legal conventions as<br />

diacritic of civilization, civil society is at one remove from bondage in nature,<br />

which is viewed either as the perpetual state of war or as the fixity of status. In<br />

other evolutionary theories, however, these terms are inverted, so that earlier<br />

states of society are explained by standards derived from the natural or practical<br />

logic of contemporary life. Maine's observation that advances in modes of legal<br />

reasoning are grounded in fictitious customs struck many nineteenth-century<br />

thinkers as a call for positivistic reform. The apparent irrationality of many customs,<br />

that is, the evident lack of means-ends appropriateness, should not be glorified<br />

but overcome, so that social conventions perpetuated through force of<br />

habit, while perhaps serving as "way-marks full of meaning" (Tylor 1871:16)<br />

for the expanding enterprise of developmental reconstruction, must in the end<br />

fall to the necessary logic of modern science. In place of Maine's recognition of<br />

the positive contribution of fictions, evolutionists such as E. B. Tylor and Lewis<br />

Henry Morgan endeavored to weed out unnecessary and irrational "survivals,"<br />

that is, customs which have outlived their contextual appropriateness and practical<br />

motivation.<br />

Morgan, for example, discovered an unexpected consistency in consanguineal<br />

kin terms of various American Indian societies. At first Morgan thought that<br />

these instances of the "classificatory system of relationship," that is, systems<br />

which lump under one linguistic label relations which our own system of terminology<br />

distinguishes (e.g., brother and male cousin), were, in the words of his<br />

friend and colleague the Rev. J. S. Mcllvaine, "invented and wholly artificial"<br />

(Morgan in Kuper 1985:12). In contrast, the "descriptive systems" found in<br />

what Morgan and his contemporaries called "civilized" society "evidently follow<br />

the flow of blood" in supposedly providing a natural or objective match-up between<br />

biological and linguistic facts. Thanks to suggestive comments from Mcllvaine,<br />

Morgan soon postulated a natural explanation for what he had earlier considered<br />

entirely artificial: the practice of brothers' having wives in common meant that<br />

no man could in principle distinguish his own from his brothers' children, so<br />

that the resulting classificatory pattern reflects a set of natural—though peculiar—facts.<br />

When J. F. McLennan, another important evolutionary theorist, attacked<br />

Morgan's explanation of classificatory kinship systems on the grounds<br />

that the evidence presented, namely, the extensive lists of kinship terms Morgan<br />

collected from all over the world, were ephemeral conventions of address, Morgan<br />

replied that the classificatory system is not at all "conventional," since it is<br />

based on "actual facts of social condition" and since it appears "identical in minute<br />

details over immense sections of the earth" (Morgan 1974:531).<br />

Morgan assumed that the cultural practices of his own society are the result<br />

of logical, practical reflection on objective conditions of life (Sahlins 19763:60).<br />

This state of self-evident objectivity then becomes the standard to render explicable<br />

diverse cultural practices at other stages on the evolutionary ladder. Moreover,<br />

Morgan is a paradigmatic case of the paradoxical attitude toward convention<br />

noted above. On the one hand, as we have just seen, he reduced artificial or<br />

customary classifications to their natural practicality. On the other hand, he<br />

thought that societies were entities constructed by the willful association of individuals,<br />

whether in the League of the Iroquois he made famous or in the less<br />

well-known Grand Order of the Iroquois, a fraternal order of gentlemen from<br />

western New York he helped found. For Morgan (1962:7) the confederacy was<br />

a clear historical example of convention by agreement: "Iroquois chiefs assembled<br />

in general congress, to agree upon the terms and principles of the compact,<br />

by which their future destinies were to be linked together." In 1845, m<br />

fact,<br />

Morgan and his brothers from the order were eyewitnesses to a ceremony reaffirming<br />

the charter of the Iroquois confederacy during which an Onondaga<br />

leader solemnly repeated, as one of the brothers reports, "the regulations adopted<br />

by the originators of the Confederacy, to render it stable and lasting" (Isaac Hurd<br />

in Bieder 1980:354).<br />

A popular modern variant on Hobbes's reduction to mechanistic principles<br />

and Morgan's reduction to practical rationality is the sociobiological explanation<br />

of social behavior. Not content with dismissing the uniquely cultural content of<br />

institutions such as warfare, religion, and kinship, sociobiology's aim is to show

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!