24.11.2013 Views

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

i66 I Social Theory and Social Action Comparison, Pragmatics, and Interpretation I 16'7<br />

At first glance, the application of the notion of "practical reason" to the field<br />

of religion seems to be an uneasy juxtaposition of opposites, since the division<br />

between religious practice and philosophical or theological discourse can correlarticulated<br />

by, say, Hume and Hegel, it will be important to grasp the role of<br />

conclusions about comparative understanding found in their philosophical texts;<br />

at the less obvious level, if we are to compare the implicit philosophies of, say,<br />

medieval Islam and medieval Christianity, part of the task will be to discover the<br />

stances toward other religions embodied in these religious traditions.<br />

This is not to say, of course, that our scholarly comparison will be identical,<br />

in intellectual motive or written discourse, to the comparative motives or discourses<br />

under study. While philosophers and religious traditions may provide<br />

modern scholars with useful tools for comparative analysis—the notions of analogy<br />

(Yearley 1990), metaphor (Poole 1986b; Schweiker 1992:271), and "superimposition"<br />

(Clooney n.d.:ch. 5), for example, have proven particularly helpful—I<br />

do not think that we can simply borrow their models of understanding as<br />

our models of understanding. To the degree that research increasingly reveals the<br />

richness of the interpretive, comparative, metapractical (Kasulis 1992), or metapragmatic<br />

(Silverstein 1993) resources of philosophical texts and religious traditions,<br />

this stricture becomes increasingly difficult to obey. Three options seem to<br />

be open to those who confront this dilemma: to appropriate local interpretive,<br />

comparative, and metapragmatic models as our analytical tools (e.g., using Thomistic<br />

analogy to understand Mencius); to take these local discourses under study<br />

as equal dialogic partners with reference to our analytical discourses (e.g., comparing<br />

their metaphors with our metaphors), ideally leading simultaneously to the<br />

"preservation" of the other's discourse (as Hallisey [1994] argues) and the sharpening<br />

of our conceptual tools; and to find in these local discourses necessary<br />

limitations and biases which in principle exclude them from sharing in the task<br />

of analysis yet which expand the range of things the analyst is forced to comprehend<br />

(Taylor 1985).<br />

Why is it so dangerous to dignify local "theories" of comparison with the<br />

status of explanatory models? First, these kinds of local theories are often rationalizations,<br />

justifications, or secondary elaborations that must themselves be penetrated<br />

in the act of analysis. Second, they often lack time perspective and thus<br />

cannot begin to account for changes in either historical situations or ideological<br />

assumptions. Third, they tend to be decontextualized abstractions that "iron<br />

out" the contextual or indexical dimensions of experience, ignoring precisely<br />

those pragmatic aspects of philosophical reasoning and religious action that are<br />

subject to only limited self-awareness (Silverstein 1981a). Fourth, they often focus<br />

on semantic, propositional, or referential dimensions of discourse and miss<br />

the meaningfulness of rhetorical, organizational, and structural dimensions of<br />

texts and actions. Finally, they are inherently positional within society, whether<br />

the product of elites, radicals, or world renouncers, and need to be linked to<br />

alternative, competing, or contradictory theories from elsewhere in the heteroglossic<br />

social order. Taken together, all these conclusions point to the same general<br />

principle: to the degree that a philosophical or religious discourse approaches<br />

in either formal shape or declared purpose the status of being an abstract, complete,<br />

or true account of comparison, this discourse fails to achieve critical selfawareness<br />

of its own pragmatic features.<br />

So comparative analytics and comparisons within traditions both have pragmatic<br />

dimensions that need to be critically identified. As a first approximation,<br />

several things might be included in an account of the pragmatics of any discourse:<br />

the personal motives or institutional interests behind the production of<br />

texts; the contextually grounded presuppositions and implications of texts; the<br />

strategic design or rhetorical organization of texts that contributes to their function<br />

or efficacy; the social dispersion of texts within a culture, such as the evaluative<br />

opposition between high and low culture, official and carnivalesque (Bakhtin<br />

1968:9-10), or scholarly and popular (Gurevich 1983); explicit text-internal<br />

metapragmatic devices, such as performatives and verba dicendi, and implicit<br />

metapragmatic forms grounded in a discourse's textual properties, both of which<br />

provide a commentary on the function of the discourse in context; 6 the real-time<br />

dynamics of interpretive acts as socially realized practices; and the intertextual<br />

relationship among texts in a culture, including the chain of commentaries on<br />

texts (Doniger 1992:39-41). In sum, the pragmatics of discourse comprehends<br />

almost every kind of meaningfulness other than the decontextualized, distantiated,<br />

semantic meaning that Ricoeur (1984) labels the "said" of the text.<br />

Despite the fact that many philosophical texts attempt to claim that they are<br />

decontextualized discourses asserting universal truths, just as many religious traditions<br />

claim unique access to the "really real," one of the jobs for analysts is to<br />

discover the pragmatics of these discourses or claims. But the analyst's discourse<br />

is not free from pragmatics! One of the great dangers of modern scholarship—<br />

and the discipline of the comparative philosophy of religion is no exception—is<br />

to assume that our own intellectual models, research techniques, and academic<br />

writings are not themselves subject to pragmatic considerations. 7 The ultimate<br />

irony of the position advocated here is that, although our scholarly acts of comparison<br />

can be fundamentally homologous to the comparative doctrines, stances,<br />

and encounters revealed in cross-cultural study, there is no reason in principle to<br />

model our comparative analytics on the specific comparative maneuvers we observe<br />

in religious or philosophical traditions. While the ubiquity of comparative<br />

discourse and cross-tradition interface can lead us to the universal set of pragmatic<br />

conditions and implications of comparison, our comprehension, though itself<br />

an act of comparison, is not compelled by any particular discoverable model.<br />

Comparison and Interpretation as Practical Reason

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!