24.11.2013 Views

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4 I Foundations ofPeircean Semiotics<br />

Peirce Divested for Nonintimates I 5<br />

cognitions to involve true knowledge, however, object and sign must be connected<br />

in such a way that the former "determines"—specifies or specializes—the<br />

character of the latter which represents it. So there must be some kind of prin-<br />

•J cipled linkage or reason, what Peirce calls the "ground," between the two if the<br />

sign is to become a mediate realization of the object in this process of constantly<br />

developing knowledge-communication.<br />

There are, thus, two opposed yet interlocking vectors involved in semiosis,<br />

- the vector of determination from object to sign and the vector of representation<br />

from sign to object. If these vectors are brought into proper relation, then knowledge<br />

of objects through signs is possible: "I shall endeavor consistently to employ<br />

the word 'object', namely, to mean that which a sign, so far as it fulfills the<br />

function of a sign, enables one who knows that sign, and knows it as a sign, to<br />

know" (MS 599:31-32).<br />

The insertion of the phrase "and knows it as a sign" might seem at first to<br />

be introducing an unnecessary complexity into the situation. If a sign displays<br />

its object as the object has determined it to be represented for some further interpreting<br />

sign, why is it necessary that the knower need not only know the sign<br />

but also know it as a sign? Peirce's point is a subtle yet crucial one for his entire<br />

argument: "A sign does not function as a sign unless it be understood as a sign"<br />

(MS 599:32). In other words, two parts of reality might be in a relationship of<br />

mutual determination and representation, but unless the knower had some inde-<br />

! pendent knowledge of this fact, there would be no sense in which one of the parts<br />

V could function as a sign of the other part for this interpreter. So signs must be<br />

interpreted in order to be signs, but their "significant character which causes<br />

them to be so interpreted" (MS 462:86), namely, the ground, is the basis for this<br />

interpretation, when it occurs.<br />

While I am out golfing the scorecard accidentally falls out of my shirt pocket<br />

and flutters several feet to the left; my partner drops bits of grass from her raised<br />

hand and carefully observes them flutter to the left. Now, the wind will act to<br />

blow both the scorecard and the grass to the left quite apart from my partner's<br />

interpretation of the movement of the grass as a sign of the wind direction so as<br />

to aim her tee shot with the proper compensation. In this elementary semiotic<br />

situation, the relationship between the object (the wind blowing in a certain direction)<br />

and the sign (the grass blowing in a certain direction) is useful only to<br />

the golfer who is already acquainted with the object (that is, that there is this<br />

physical phenomenon of wind) and who further understands the ground involved<br />

' in the wind-grass connection, namely, a combination of physical connectedness<br />

between wind and grass, what Peirce calls "indexicality," and of formal resem-<br />

* blance between wind direction and grass direction, what Peirce calls "iconicity."<br />

The importance of this point is that, for Peirce, the vectors of determination<br />

and representation are each more complex than suggested initially. Determination<br />

does not just flow from object to sign but from the object through the sign<br />

to some further action or mental representation, what Peirce terms the "interprétant,"<br />

which is thus mediately determined by the same object (CP 6.347). The<br />

interprétant is the translation, explanation, meaning, or conceptualization of the<br />

sign-object relation in a subsequent sign representing the same object; a sign<br />

which is highly determined is one which offers little "latitude of interpretation"<br />

(MS 283:136) for the translating sign. In the golfing example, my partner's tee<br />

shot will be determined, that is, causally influenced, by the wind direction, but<br />

to the degree that her shot is directed by an aim corrected because of the knowledge<br />

afforded through the falling grass, the shot is mediatedly determined by the<br />

wind. Peirce's frequent metaphor for this mediate determination is skewing or<br />

slanting, so that the effect of the object operates on the interpreting sign through<br />

the mediating role of the sign.<br />

What about the vector of representation? If the falling grass is known "as a<br />

sign," then the tee shot will also be a representation, but not simply of the physical<br />

fact of wind direction (though the shot will, of course, be acted upon by the<br />

wind). It will display or exhibit—perhaps for the golfers waiting to tee off<br />

next—the complex semiotic relationship of "taking account of the wind." In<br />

other words, what is actually represented is the linkage or ground relating the<br />

wind and the grass: or, the object becomes the "grass taken semiotically." Thus",^<br />

the vector of representation is also more complex than originally stated, since'<br />

each subsequent representation in the semiotic chain represents the prior object-'!<br />

sign relation, taken itself as a higher-level semiotic object.<br />

Symbols and Legisigns<br />

The next step Peirce takes in the argument is truly revolutionary. He postulates<br />

that there is a kind of sign in which the ground between object and sign<br />

would not exist at all unless interpreted by a subsequent sign to be of some kind.<br />

Recall the previous example: the wind continues to determine the direction of<br />

falling grass whether or not we read it as a sign; when interpreted semiotically,<br />

the ground is understood to be the causal patterning of grass direction by wind<br />

direction. To repeat, the grass would not function as a sign unless interpreted<br />

semiotically, but when interpreted the interpretation is based on the independently<br />

existing grounds between object and sign (that is, the indexicality and<br />

iconicity). Now consider the example of the word book, a linguistic sign standing<br />

for a class of objects consisting (roughly) of printed pages bound together and<br />

found in libraries. What is the ground between this particular phonic shape and<br />

this particular class of objects? In what sense does this class of objects determine<br />

any of the identifying properties found in the word as a sign? Peirce's solution<br />

to these question is his concept of the "symbol," a kind of complex semiotic<br />

entity in which there is an irreducibly triadic relation among the sign, the object,<br />

and the interprétant such that the sign and object would not be in any particular

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!