24.11.2013 Views

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SIGNS IN SOCIETY - STIBA Malang

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

192. I Social Theory and Social Action<br />

I / trary to analysts and necessary to actors. In fact, for an important part of West-<br />

/ em social theory the positivist apprehension of convention involves the effort to<br />

reduce arbitrariness to rational (Hobbes), practical (Morgan), or adaptive (Fox)<br />

logic. As we have seen, naturalization of convention can be found even in theorists<br />

who stress the importance of unconstrained agreement as the foundation of<br />

social order. On the other hand, the ethnographic cases presented illustrate various<br />

modes of articulation of the natural and conventional poles within societies.<br />

Conventions of masculine domination operate hegemonically among the Baruya<br />

so that women are trained to accept their subordination as an immutable result<br />

of biological differentiation, while men concentrate on perpetuating the elaborate<br />

rituals of indoctrination that ensure their legitimizing power. In Belau, conventions<br />

are subject to hierarchical typification as a function of social rank; though<br />

accepted as given, stable, and binding, "paths" of convention are essentially cultural,<br />

without any naturalization to some extra-cultural standard. The French<br />

example shows that conventions stipulating couttly behavior are viewed as second<br />

nature by those who live and die by their social indexical implications. And<br />

finally in the Russian case, the aristocratic class presents itself to the larger society<br />

as if it were a foreign culture by adopting "poeticized" and idiosyncratic<br />

forms of behavior and thereby encourages a contrasting ideology of naturalness<br />

for rural, peasant life.<br />

The tension between the naturalization of convention and the poeticization<br />

of convention exhibited within societies makes it impossible to adopt a theoretical<br />

stance which tries to reduce or transcend the opposition of nature and convention.<br />

In other words, there can be no strictly positivist theory of society which<br />

VV does not profoundly distort its object of inyesïïgatïolï."FuTthermore, arguments<br />

' similar "to"that proposed by Roland Barthes (1967:89—98, 1972:115,<br />

1983:285-86, i988b:i9o), according to which the naturalization of convention<br />

is a process restricted to societies dominated by commodity fetishism, overlook<br />

the obvious fact that naturalization occurs in all types of social formations and,<br />

1<br />

conversely, that conventions can appear as arbitrary, fabricatecLTor "semiotic"<br />

even in modern industrial societies (cf. Baudrillard 1981:158—59). There will<br />

always be, to return to Plato's Cratylus, those who insist that the basis of social<br />

convention is collective agreement and those who posit a natural or rational fitness<br />

in existing rules and customs. But so long as this tension continues to be<br />

observed by social theory we stand in little danger of the fate envisioned by<br />

Markus for a philosophy which fails to see the nature/convention opposition as<br />

a problem.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Peirce Divested for Nonintimates<br />

1. Exemplary summaries of Peirce's semiotic theory can be found in Fisch 1986; Oehler<br />

1981; Randsell 1977; Savan 1987-88; and Tejera 1988.<br />

2. The classical traditions are surveyed in Eco 1984:2.6-33; Kretzmann 1974; Telegdi<br />

1982; and Todorov 1982:15-35. On Peirce's use of the Stoic tradition see Cosenza 1988.<br />

3. I cite Peirce's writings using the abbreviations established in Fisch I986:xi: CP: Collected<br />

Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (1931-1958); MS: Peirce manuscripts in the collection<br />

of Harvard University, catalogued in Robin (1967); N: Charles Sanders Peirce: Contributions<br />

to The Nation (1975-1979); NEM: The New Elements of Mathematics (1976); SS: Semiotic<br />

and Signifies: The Correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby ( 1977);<br />

W: Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition (1982.-).<br />

4. It is erroneous to say, as several commentators do, that the icon is a First, the index<br />

a Second, and the symbol a Third. As signs, all three of these are triadic.<br />

5. It is important not to think of icons, indices, and symbols as exclusive classes of signs.<br />

As Fisch (1986:333) helpfully explains: "We may therefore call a sign, for short, by the name<br />

of that element or aspect which is most prominent in it, or to which we wish to direct attention,<br />

without thereby implying that it has no element or aspect of the other two kinds."<br />

6. For further discussion of Peirce's views on language see Brock 1981; Dewey 1946;<br />

Eco 1981; Jakobson 1980a; and Ransdell 1980.<br />

2. Peirce's Concept of Semiotic Mediation<br />

I. Several stylistic conventions need to be briefly noted. I use quotation marks to indicate<br />

the first occurrence of a technical term from Peirce's often bizarre semiotic vocabulary. (Peirce's<br />

own convention is to use capitalization). For bibliographic abbreviations see Note 3 in Chapter<br />

I. Other studies of the development of Peirce's semiotic ideas include Deledalle 1986; Fisch<br />

1986; Kloesel 1983; and Reiss 1984.<br />

1. Peirce refined his definition of the sign constantly from 1867 to 1911. A few key<br />

references include: CP 1.541, 1903; CP 2.228, 1897; CP 2.230, 1910; CP 2.274, 1902; CP<br />

5.484, C.1907; CP 8.177-85, 1902; NEM 3.233, 1909; NEM 4.239, C.1904; NEM 4.297;<br />

SS 31-33, 1904; SS 80—81, 1908; SS 196, 1906.<br />

3. For "mediate determination" and "mediate representation" see, e.g., CP 1.553, ^ 6 7 ;<br />

CP 6.347, 1909; NEM 3.233, 1909; NEM 3.867, 1909; NEM 3.886, 1908; NEM 4.242!<br />

1904; SS 80—81, 1908; MS 2783.10; MS 283.128.<br />

4. Ayer (1968:161) argues that Peirce is confusing because he "conflates" the view of<br />

semiosis as an infinite series of sign production and the view of semiosis as an "infinite metalinguistic<br />

hierarchy." It seems to me that Peirce never doubted that these are equivalent conceptualizations.<br />

193

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!