25.10.2012 Views

Secularization as Kenosis

Secularization as Kenosis

Secularization as Kenosis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

222 | postmodern condition and secularity<br />

the meaning it attached to history. 231 Löwith apppreciates the non-historicist character<br />

of Christianity (and Stoicism for that matter). Vattimo, on the other hand, stresses the<br />

equivalence of Christianity and historicism and sees it <strong>as</strong> a necessary stage in the history<br />

of Being.<br />

Politically, Vattimo’s idea of a postmodern secularization is a more radical secularization.<br />

Vattimo no longer understands secularity <strong>as</strong> a relative independence of religion<br />

and politics, rather he sees it <strong>as</strong> the dissolution of religion in politics. Vattimo’s weak<br />

thought and his emph<strong>as</strong>is on charity and love might at first sight seem to be the most<br />

modest with regard to historical contingencies. A closer look h<strong>as</strong> demonstrated that not<br />

only does his philosophy of secularization result in a dissolution of world and history,<br />

but it also leaves political philosophy bereft of tools to distinguish between religion and<br />

politics, since Vattimo intends to overcome this distinction. The final outcome of Vattimo’s<br />

religion of love is that he h<strong>as</strong> a hard time granting religion its rightful place <strong>as</strong> a<br />

historically, contingent phenomenon. 232<br />

Compared to Rorty, Vattimo h<strong>as</strong> a significantly different approach to the postmodern<br />

condition. Where<strong>as</strong> both reject the ideal of representational knowledge, for Rorty<br />

this is by and large a theoretical matter, which h<strong>as</strong> no further consequences for liberal<br />

institutions. On the contrary: he tends to reinstall a form of cl<strong>as</strong>sical liberalism that<br />

insists on a rigid separation of public and private and is repressive of religion. The<br />

secular ideal and the Enlightened institutions of state, economy and public sphere (including<br />

media) are the best suited tools for realizing this secular Utopia. For Vattimo on<br />

the other hand, the stakes are quite different. He sees how the changes in late modern<br />

culture call for a new understanding of culture and liberal institutions, <strong>as</strong> in a process<br />

of weakening. For Vattimo it is a good thing that liberal institutions loosen their grip<br />

on our lives. In the postmodern, centreless society, human creativity can fully flourish.<br />

As he sees it, in the emergence of m<strong>as</strong>s media, the dissolution of liberal institutions is<br />

irreversible. This is not to be resisted, rather it is the realization of Being.<br />

The political consequences of the fundamental continuity of Christianity and Western<br />

secular society can be worked out in contr<strong>as</strong>t with Rorty’s thoughts on the subject.<br />

For neither Rorty, nor Vattimo is there a public role for religion. Rorty denies religion<br />

the right to public recognition, because religion is a private affair and the public sphere<br />

does not allow for religious rhetoric. For Vattimo there is a completely different re<strong>as</strong>on<br />

why the Church does not interfere in the public sphere: not because Christianity excludes<br />

secularity; rather the opposite. Far from being a party claiming recognition in the<br />

public sphere, the Christian religion is the silent presupposition that made secular society<br />

possible. Vattimo, in a way attempts to overcome the duality of public and private.<br />

As Raymond Aron explains, in Marxist philosophy, the duality of sacred and profane<br />

is functionally equivalent to the distinction between private and public. 233 Rorty in a<br />

way rejects Marx’ embargo on this distinction, <strong>as</strong> he explicitly makes a c<strong>as</strong>e for religion<br />

and irony <strong>as</strong> private. Vattimo, on the other hand, follows Marx in his rejection of the<br />

231 Löwith, 207–9.<br />

232 Vattimo, Belief, 81.<br />

233 “Het politieke staatsburgerschap is, met betrekking tot de werkzaamheid van de arbeider, vergelijkbaar<br />

met de bestemming van de onsterfelijke ziel volgens het christendom met betrekking tot het ellendige<br />

bestaan op deze aarde. Deze twee splitsingen, deze twee vervreemdingen lopen parallel: de tweespalt van het<br />

profane en het heilige evenals die van het private en het publieke hebben tot oorzaak de niet-vervulling door<br />

de mens van zijn menselijkheid.” Raymond Aron, Essai sur les libertés (Paris: Calmann-Lévy, 1965), 24.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!