Secularization as Kenosis

Secularization as Kenosis Secularization as Kenosis

adss.library.uu.nl
from adss.library.uu.nl More from this publisher
25.10.2012 Views

212 | postmodern condition and secularity challenges of postmodernism. 180 This turn to communism is comparable to his conversion to Christianity, of which he wrote in the essay Belief. To his mind there is a great deal of similarity between communism and socialism on the one hand and Christianity on the other, as both are radically unnatural projects. 181 In its shared utopian intention, Vattimo sees the possibility of developing a Christian communism. If there is such a thing as a postmodern politics, it must be the awareness of the end of meta-narratives. The awareness of unlimited plurality makes postmodernism preeminently political. 182 For Vattimo this is the central idea of a postmodern politics. 183 Postmodern politics emerges with the disenchantment of utopian ideologies. The great political ideologies of the twentieth century tried to realize an ideal society. Even when these political programs were carried out in the name of the good, or the human, they often lead to horrors on a massive scale. 184 Postmodern politics attempts to shape a new European identity. The quest for this identity acquired a new urgency when the Soviet Union collapsed in 1989. The absence of an ideological counterpart created the need for more substantial identity. Vattimo detects two trends in this quest for a European identity. 185 In the first place there is what he calls the Catholic integralist identity. It defines the essential European identity as a Christian identity that stands in radical opposition to the secular character of modernity. The other position is the secularist position that defines Europe as essentially rooted in Enlightenment rationalism and sees this as discontinuous with the Christian past. Despite their differences, the two positions agree in the idea that there is an opposition between secularity and Christianity. Vattimo argues for a middle position. He neither wants to identify solely with Christian exclusivism, nor with the idea that secular modernity is independent from its religious past. Vattimo holds that modern, secular Europe is essentially a secularization of Christianity. Europe is the non-religious form of Christianity and it embodies values and practices that originate in Christianity. Only in the regions where Christianity was once the dominant religion has secularity flourished. In the discussion on European identity, Vattimo argues that in the constitution of the European Union, no reference needs to be made to Christianity. This is not because he would find Christianity of no value to the European community, but because Europe is itself an embodiment of Christianity. 186 Christianity should not present itself as a fraction, that fights for its case, rather it is the presupposition on which a multicultural and multi-religious Europe rests. Postmodern theory does not simply do away with utopian ideas, rather it first of all criticizes the intertwinedness of utopian politics with a teleological account of history, or the sacralization of the utopian goal as in totalitarian regimes. 187 Instead, in postmod- 180 Gianni Vattimo, Wie werde ich Kommunist (Berlin: Rotbuch Verlag, 2008), 32. 181 Vattimo, Kommunist, 15. 182 “Denn in der Postmoderne wurde die bislang eher latente Pluralität vordringlich und unübersehbar.” Welsch, Postmoderne Moderne, 242. 183 Gianni Vattimo, ‘The End of (Hi)story’, Chicago Review 35:4 (1986), 20–30. 184 Hans Achterhuis, De erfenis van de utopie (Baarn: Ambo, 1998). 185 Vattimo, After Christianity, 73–4. See also Vattimo, Kommunist, 19. For Milbank on the relevance of communism for the ideological course of the West see: Milbank, ‘Gift of Ruling’, 232: “Communism . . . gave the West a binding purpose: oppose the gigantomachy of totalitarian regimes.” 186 “Voor mij moet in de Europese grondwet niet naar het christendom worden verwezen omdat seculariteit tot het christelijk patrimonium behoort.” France Guwy and Gianni Vattimo, ‘Europa en religie (3): Gianni Vattimo. Voor een christendom zonder religie’, De Standaard 01/07 (2004). 187 Michael Burleigh, Sacred Causes: Religion and Politics from the European Dictators to Al Qaeda (New

secularization as kenosis | 213 ern politics the notion of difference plays a dominant role. The older utopian ideologies were flawed in absolutizing a single particular concept; the postmodern utopia is the ‘utopia of the manifold’. 188 But if the aim of postmodern politics is to realize a society in which theoretically endless plurality is desired, how can it be something other than downright anarchy? For Vattimo it is clear that a society that is secular in a postmodern sense is no longer organized according to a dichotomy of Church and state. In a postmodern sense, the modern nation-state is also unmasked as an unjust concentration of power in a central sovereignty. What then is Vattimo’s proposal for a postmodern politics? How does he see the classical distinction of Church and state? And what are the ramifications of the relatedness of secularization and hermeneutics for Vattimo’s political ideas on secularity and religion? It is clearly not his intention to simply do away with the history of utopian politics. His effort is to apply the Heideggerian notion of Verwindung to the Utopian ideal. His political theorizing of secularization and hermeneutics means first of all that Vattimo insists on the essential continuity between Christianity and secular politics. How does Vattimo see the relation between present-day liberal culture and the role of religion in society? Does the rebirth of religion make an end to the privatization of religion and the Church-state divide? Vattimo does not think this was ever really the case. It was precisely the greater – more or less unconscious – continuity between Christian Europe and secular Europe that made secularization possible. As Vattimo sees it ‘this separation succeeded only because it was realized on the solid, if unacknowledged, basis of a common religious heritage.’ 189 The liberal separation of public and private sphere and Church and state was possible on the basis of a tacit agreement on essentially Christian values. 190 When we speak of Christianity, says Vattimo, we also speak of ‘liberal society, of the West, and of modern democracy.” 191 It is exactly this compatibility or even identity of (Christian) religion and liberal democracy that is at stake for Vattimo. He wants to oppose any attempt to separate liberalism and religion along the lines of an anti-modernity or communitarian discourse (‘cultural apartheid’ 192 ) One of the most pressing concerns behind the quarrel over the legitimacy of the secular is its claim to neutrality. Vattimo subscribes to the idea that in the 16th and 17th century, starting with the Reformation, Christianity has become a source of disagreement and violence, instead of a unifying power. He is critical about the way liberal politics has dealt with it since. Religion was declared a private matter and increasingly banned from the public arena. Today, however, not least as a consequence of the growth of non-Christian religions in Europe, such as Islam, it is questionable whether the neutral approach still works. Secularity as neutrality is experienced by Muslims as a threat to authentic religious experience. 193 Moreover, argues Vattimo, neutrality with regard to religious matters is possible due to a tacit agreement that has a Christian inspiration. The success of a profane, public sphere was made possible, not despite, but thanks to a large amount of tacit agreement on Christian morality. 194 Therefore, we will always York: Harper Collins, 2007), 38–122. 188 Welsch, Postmoderne Moderne, 183. 189 Vattimo, After Christianity, 95e. 190 Vattimo, After Christianity, 100. 191 Vattimo, After Christianity, 97. 192 Vattimo, After Christianity, 102. 193 Vattimo, After Christianity, 100. 194 “. . . the separation succeeded, because it arose on the firm basis of a (not as such recognizable)

secularization <strong>as</strong> kenosis | 213<br />

ern politics the notion of difference plays a dominant role. The older utopian ideologies<br />

were flawed in absolutizing a single particular concept; the postmodern utopia is the<br />

‘utopia of the manifold’. 188 But if the aim of postmodern politics is to realize a society<br />

in which theoretically endless plurality is desired, how can it be something other than<br />

downright anarchy? For Vattimo it is clear that a society that is secular in a postmodern<br />

sense is no longer organized according to a dichotomy of Church and state. In a postmodern<br />

sense, the modern nation-state is also unm<strong>as</strong>ked <strong>as</strong> an unjust concentration of<br />

power in a central sovereignty. What then is Vattimo’s proposal for a postmodern politics?<br />

How does he see the cl<strong>as</strong>sical distinction of Church and state? And what are the<br />

ramifications of the relatedness of secularization and hermeneutics for Vattimo’s political<br />

ide<strong>as</strong> on secularity and religion? It is clearly not his intention to simply do away with<br />

the history of utopian politics. His effort is to apply the Heideggerian notion of Verwindung<br />

to the Utopian ideal. His political theorizing of secularization and hermeneutics<br />

means first of all that Vattimo insists on the essential continuity between Christianity<br />

and secular politics. How does Vattimo see the relation between present-day liberal<br />

culture and the role of religion in society? Does the rebirth of religion make an end<br />

to the privatization of religion and the Church-state divide? Vattimo does not think<br />

this w<strong>as</strong> ever really the c<strong>as</strong>e. It w<strong>as</strong> precisely the greater – more or less unconscious –<br />

continuity between Christian Europe and secular Europe that made secularization possible.<br />

As Vattimo sees it ‘this separation succeeded only because it w<strong>as</strong> realized on the<br />

solid, if unacknowledged, b<strong>as</strong>is of a common religious heritage.’ 189 The liberal separation<br />

of public and private sphere and Church and state w<strong>as</strong> possible on the b<strong>as</strong>is of a<br />

tacit agreement on essentially Christian values. 190 When we speak of Christianity, says<br />

Vattimo, we also speak of ‘liberal society, of the West, and of modern democracy.” 191 It<br />

is exactly this compatibility or even identity of (Christian) religion and liberal democracy<br />

that is at stake for Vattimo. He wants to oppose any attempt to separate liberalism<br />

and religion along the lines of an anti-modernity or communitarian discourse (‘cultural<br />

apartheid’ 192 )<br />

One of the most pressing concerns behind the quarrel over the legitimacy of the<br />

secular is its claim to neutrality. Vattimo subscribes to the idea that in the 16th and 17th<br />

century, starting with the Reformation, Christianity h<strong>as</strong> become a source of disagreement<br />

and violence, instead of a unifying power. He is critical about the way liberal<br />

politics h<strong>as</strong> dealt with it since. Religion w<strong>as</strong> declared a private matter and incre<strong>as</strong>ingly<br />

banned from the public arena. Today, however, not le<strong>as</strong>t <strong>as</strong> a consequence of the growth<br />

of non-Christian religions in Europe, such <strong>as</strong> Islam, it is questionable whether the neutral<br />

approach still works. Secularity <strong>as</strong> neutrality is experienced by Muslims <strong>as</strong> a threat<br />

to authentic religious experience. 193 Moreover, argues Vattimo, neutrality with regard<br />

to religious matters is possible due to a tacit agreement that h<strong>as</strong> a Christian inspiration.<br />

The success of a profane, public sphere w<strong>as</strong> made possible, not despite, but thanks to<br />

a large amount of tacit agreement on Christian morality. 194 Therefore, we will always<br />

York: Harper Collins, 2007), 38–122.<br />

188 Welsch, Postmoderne Moderne, 183.<br />

189 Vattimo, After Christianity, 95e.<br />

190 Vattimo, After Christianity, 100.<br />

191 Vattimo, After Christianity, 97.<br />

192 Vattimo, After Christianity, 102.<br />

193 Vattimo, After Christianity, 100.<br />

194 “. . . the separation succeeded, because it arose on the firm b<strong>as</strong>is of a (not <strong>as</strong> such recognizable)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!