25.10.2012 Views

Secularization as Kenosis

Secularization as Kenosis

Secularization as Kenosis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

210 | postmodern condition and secularity<br />

effort is to continue the Christian tradition in its kenotic and secularizing intent and<br />

to develop religion in a secular and aesthetic mode. Falling back into a positivistic or<br />

transcendental religion would mean a betrayal of this central message of Christianity.<br />

Vattimo’s discourse on secularization is thus not only a polemic on traditional metaphysical<br />

theology, but also on supposed alternatives to metaphysical theology. All too<br />

e<strong>as</strong>ily such alternatives slide back into modes of thinking that have considerable similarity<br />

with ontotheology. A truly historicist theology cannot think of God <strong>as</strong> an ineffable<br />

‘God beyond God.’<br />

But does Vattimo’s model remain loyal to its concerns with historical contingency?<br />

The discussion of Derrida and Levin<strong>as</strong> brings Vattimo to a remarkable observation, that<br />

h<strong>as</strong> to do with the ‘Judaic’ character of some contemporary philosophy of religion. Vattimo<br />

speaks of a ‘predominance of Judaic religiosity in the return of religion.’ 173 His<br />

complaints about the Judaic predominance is articulated <strong>as</strong> follows: “It is a fact that<br />

the total otherness of God with respect to the world appears to be affirmed at the expense<br />

of any recognition of novelty in the Christian event.” With regard to Levin<strong>as</strong> and<br />

Derrida this h<strong>as</strong> to do with the alleged a-historic character of Jewish thought. 174 The<br />

Jewish character of Levin<strong>as</strong>’ philosophy h<strong>as</strong> been an object of critique on several other<br />

occ<strong>as</strong>ions, for example in his contribution to the seminar with Gadamer and Derrida<br />

on Religion. 175 What I find striking in this critique of the Judaic character of Levin<strong>as</strong>’s<br />

philosophy is that Vattimo interprets this <strong>as</strong> a lack of awareness of the historical destiny<br />

of Being. It is “historicity reduced to its finitude.” The experience of contingency<br />

for Vattimo h<strong>as</strong> its limits in the recognition of a process in history, which cannot be<br />

interrupted by a free, willing God or experiences of contingency. But this is to say that<br />

secularization means that there is an undeniable concurrence between experience and<br />

God and to neglect this concurrence would mean to be on the wrong side of history. 176<br />

I agree with Vattimo, when he opposes a theology of radical alterity. A theological<br />

insistence on the radical alterity of God is fated to leave the secular bereft of any inherent<br />

meaning. Vattimo puts forward a quite different account of secularization than<br />

certain forms of death-of-God theology. 177 If emph<strong>as</strong>izing God’s transcendence leads to<br />

a loss of meaning of the secular, I think Vattimo is right to resist such an approach. This<br />

is, however, but one horn of the dilemma. The other is the insistence on a process of<br />

173 Vattimo, Belief, 84.<br />

174 He writes: “There is no real difference between historical times; since every historical moment is<br />

immediately related to eternity, the historicity of existence is entirely reduced to its finitude, that is, to the fact<br />

we are always already thrown into a situation whose particular traits are given little consideration, compared<br />

to the purely ‘vertical’ relation to the eternal”. Vattimo, Belief, 84.<br />

175 Gianni Vattimo, ‘The trace of the trace’, in: Jacques Derrida and Gianni Vattimo, editors, Religion<br />

(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), 79–94.<br />

176 Sciglitano draws on Vattimo’s dealing with the sacred-profane dichotomy in a discussion on Altizer:<br />

“As for Vattimo and for Hegel, love appears to have for Altizer the quality of an identity between the divine<br />

and the secular that h<strong>as</strong> overcome alienation which includes the Old Testament picture of God’s relation to<br />

the world and many <strong>as</strong>pects of the New Testament. In this sense, difference, whether between the divine<br />

and the world or within the divine, construed <strong>as</strong> Trinity, gets eliminated or dissolved, and with it goes the<br />

ground for a world that is genuinely other than the divine and rooted in God’s gracious Being.” Anthony C.<br />

Sciglitano, ‘Contesting the world and the Divine. Balth<strong>as</strong>ar’s trinitarian ‘response’ to Gianni Vattimo’s secular<br />

Christianity’, Modern Theology 23(4) (2007), 536.<br />

177 As Sciglitano explains, for Vattimo they fail to articulate ‘. . . an explicit theory of secularization and<br />

of the death of God <strong>as</strong> the positive affirmation of divinity b<strong>as</strong>ed on the idea of incarnation contemporary<br />

thought emph<strong>as</strong>izes the disappearance of the sacred from the world precisely by affirming transcendence <strong>as</strong><br />

the total ‘alterity’ of the biblical God.’ Sciglitano, 535.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!