18.09.2013 Views

Rule of Law

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> & Cooperative Society<br />

Chandra Nath ∗<br />

April 15, 2013<br />

∗ nath@computer.org He is an Independent researcher engaged in research in information security, privacy, law & justice.<br />

1


Contents<br />

1 Introduction 3<br />

2 <strong>Rule</strong> Egoism 3<br />

3 Locke and Natural Rights 4<br />

4 The rule <strong>of</strong> law 4<br />

5 <strong>Law</strong> should govern 4<br />

6 No one is above the law 4<br />

7 <strong>Rule</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Recognition & Ability to change 5<br />

8 <strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> v <strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> Men 5<br />

9 Principles <strong>of</strong> supremacy <strong>of</strong> law 5<br />

10 Will as law 5<br />

11 Zero exploitation 6<br />

12 Coperative & Rochdale Principles 6<br />

A Open and Voluntary Membership . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6<br />

B Democratic member control . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6<br />

C Member economic participation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

D Autonomy and independence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

E Education, training, and information . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

F Cooperation among cooperatives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

G Concern for community . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

H Democratic operations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

I People first . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

J Giving clients what they want . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8<br />

K Member-driven business enterprises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8<br />

L Member/Customer focus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8<br />

13 Conclusion 9<br />

2


RULE OF LAW & COOPERATIVE SOCIETY<br />

The proprietor, the robber, the hero, the sovereign for all these titles are synonymous imposes his will<br />

as law, and suffers neither contradiction nor control; that is, he pretends to be the legislative and the<br />

executive power at once . . . [and so] property engenders despotism . . .<br />

1 Introduction<br />

AWHO was established as a Society<br />

under the <strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong><br />

expressly for the welfare <strong>of</strong><br />

its members and NOT established as<br />

a foray by Army Headquarters into<br />

Real Estate business in a thriving real<br />

estate market at this particular stage<br />

in the country’s economy.<br />

2 <strong>Rule</strong> Egoism<br />

2.1 <strong>Rule</strong> egoism is the doctrine<br />

under which an individual evaluates<br />

the optimal set <strong>of</strong> rules according<br />

to whether conformity to those<br />

rules bring the most benefit to himself<br />

The state <strong>of</strong> nature is a state <strong>of</strong><br />

war where everyone must fend for his<br />

or herself and all are against all. No<br />

one has any sort <strong>of</strong> moral obligation<br />

to anything else except to maximize<br />

ones own satisfaction: The action violates<br />

the following Hobbe’s laws <strong>of</strong><br />

nature:<br />

• The ninth <strong>Law</strong> is that every<br />

man acknowledge another for<br />

his equal by nature. The breach<br />

<strong>of</strong> this precept is pride.<br />

• The tenth law is that at the<br />

entrance into the conditions<br />

<strong>of</strong> peace, no man require to<br />

reserve to himself any right,<br />

which he is not content should<br />

be reserved to every one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rest. The breach <strong>of</strong> this precept<br />

is arrogance, and observers <strong>of</strong><br />

the precept are called modest.<br />

• The eleventh law is that if a<br />

man be trusted to judge between<br />

man and man, that he<br />

deal equally between them.<br />

• The twelfth law is that such<br />

things as cannot be divided, be<br />

enjoyed in common, if it can be;<br />

and if the quantity <strong>of</strong> the thing<br />

permit, without stint; otherwise<br />

proportionably to the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> them that have right.<br />

• The thirteenth law is the entire<br />

right, or else...the first possession<br />

(in the case <strong>of</strong> alternating<br />

use), <strong>of</strong> a thing that can neither<br />

be divided nor enjoyed in common<br />

should be determined by<br />

lottery.<br />

• The fourteenth law is that those<br />

things which cannot be enjoyed<br />

in common, nor divided, ought<br />

to be adjudged to the first possessor;<br />

and in some cases to the<br />

first born, as acquired by lot.<br />

• The fifteenth law is that all men<br />

that mediate peace be allowed<br />

safe conduct.<br />

• The sixteenth law is that they<br />

that are at controversie, submit<br />

their Right to the judgement <strong>of</strong><br />

an Arbitrator.<br />

3<br />

• The seventeenth law is that no<br />

man is a fit Arbitrator in his<br />

own cause.<br />

• The eighteenth law is that no<br />

man should serve as a judge in a<br />

case if greater pr<strong>of</strong>it, or honour,<br />

or pleasure apparently ariseth<br />

[for him] out <strong>of</strong> the victory <strong>of</strong><br />

one party, than <strong>of</strong> the other.<br />

2.2 Hobbes posits a primitive, unconnected<br />

state <strong>of</strong> nature in which<br />

men, having a “natural proclivity...to<br />

hurt each other” also have “a Right<br />

to every thing, even to one anothers<br />

body”; and “nothing can be Unjust”<br />

in this “warre <strong>of</strong> every man against<br />

every man” in which human life is<br />

“solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and<br />

short.” Rejecting Cicero’s view that<br />

men join in society primarily through<br />

“a certain social spirit which nature<br />

has implanted in man,” Hobbes declares<br />

that men join in society simply<br />

for the purpose <strong>of</strong> “getting themselves<br />

out from that miserable condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> Warre, which is necessarily<br />

consequent...to the naturall Passions<br />

<strong>of</strong> men, when there is no visible Power<br />

to keep them in awe.” As part <strong>of</strong> his<br />

campaign against the classical idea <strong>of</strong><br />

natural human sociability, Hobbes inverts<br />

that fundamental natural legal<br />

maxim, the Golden <strong>Rule</strong>. Hobbes’s<br />

version is “Do not that to another,<br />

which thou wouldst not have done to<br />

thy selfe.”


3 Locke and Natural<br />

Rights<br />

3.3 Locke turned Hobbes’ prescription<br />

around, saying that if the ruler<br />

went against natural law and failed to<br />

protect “life, liberty, and property,”<br />

people could justifiably overthrow the<br />

existing state and create a new one.<br />

While Locke spoke in the language<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural law, the content <strong>of</strong> this<br />

law was by and large protective <strong>of</strong><br />

natural rights, and it was this language<br />

that later liberal thinkers preferred.<br />

Thomas Jefferson, arguably<br />

echoing Locke, appealed to unalienable<br />

rights in the Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence,<br />

“We hold these truths to<br />

be self-evident, that all men are created<br />

equal, that they are endowed by<br />

their Creator with certain unalienable<br />

Rights, that among these are Life,<br />

Liberty and the pursuit <strong>of</strong> Happiness.<br />

According to Aquinas, to lack any<br />

<strong>of</strong> these virtues is to lack the ability<br />

to make a moral choice. For example,<br />

consider a man who possesses the<br />

virtues <strong>of</strong> justice, prudence, and fortitude,<br />

yet lacks temperance. Due to<br />

his lack <strong>of</strong> self-control and desire for<br />

pleasure, despite his good intentions,<br />

he will find himself swaying from the<br />

moral path.<br />

4 The rule <strong>of</strong> law<br />

4.4 The rule <strong>of</strong> law is the<br />

“supremacy <strong>of</strong> regular power as<br />

opposed to arbitrary power.” The<br />

phrase can be traced back to the<br />

17th century, and it was popularized<br />

in the 19th century by British jurist<br />

A. V. Dicey. The concept was familiar<br />

to ancient philosophers such<br />

as Aristotle, who wrote “<strong>Law</strong> should<br />

govern”. <strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> law implies that<br />

every citizen is subject to the law. It<br />

stands in contrast to the idea that the<br />

ruler is above the law, for example by<br />

divine right.<br />

5 <strong>Law</strong> should govern<br />

5.5 Plato nevertheless hoped that<br />

the best men would be good at respecting<br />

established laws, explaining<br />

that “Where the law is subject to<br />

some other authority and has none<br />

<strong>of</strong> its own, the collapse <strong>of</strong> the state,<br />

in my view, is not far <strong>of</strong>f; but if<br />

law is the master <strong>of</strong> the government<br />

and the government is its slave,<br />

then the situation is full <strong>of</strong> promise<br />

and men enjoy all the blessings that<br />

the gods shower on a state.” More<br />

than Plato attempted to do, Aristotle<br />

flatly opposed letting the highest<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials wield power beyond guarding<br />

and serving the laws. In other words,<br />

Aristotle advocated the rule <strong>of</strong> law: It<br />

is more proper that law should govern<br />

than any one <strong>of</strong> the citizens: upon the<br />

same principle, if it is advantageous<br />

to place the supreme power in some<br />

particular persons, they should be appointed<br />

to be only guardians, and the<br />

servants <strong>of</strong> the laws.<br />

5.6 According to the Roman statesman<br />

Cicero, “We are all servants<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laws in order that we may<br />

be free.” During the Roman Republic,<br />

controversial magistrates might<br />

be put on trial when their terms <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong>fice expired.<br />

5.7 An early example <strong>of</strong> the phrase<br />

“rule <strong>of</strong> law” is found in a petition<br />

to James I <strong>of</strong> England in 1610, from<br />

the House <strong>of</strong> Commons: Amongst<br />

many other points <strong>of</strong> happiness and<br />

freedom which your majesty’s sub-<br />

4<br />

jects <strong>of</strong> this kingdom have enjoyed<br />

under your royal progenitors, kings<br />

and queens <strong>of</strong> this realm, there is<br />

none which they have accounted more<br />

dear and precious than this, to be<br />

guided and governed by the certain<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> the law which giveth both to<br />

the head and members that which<br />

<strong>of</strong> right belongeth to them, and not<br />

by any uncertain or arbitrary form<br />

<strong>of</strong> government.... In 1607, English<br />

Chief Justice Sir Edward Coke said<br />

in the Case <strong>of</strong> Prohibitions (according<br />

to his own report) “that the law was<br />

the golden met-wand and measure to<br />

try the causes <strong>of</strong> the subjects; and<br />

which protected His Majesty in safety<br />

and peace: with which the King was<br />

greatly <strong>of</strong>fended, and said, that then<br />

he should be under the law, which<br />

was treason to affirm, as he said; to<br />

which I said, that Bracton saith, quod<br />

Rex non debed esse sub homine, sed<br />

sub Deo et lege(That the King ought<br />

not to be under any man but under<br />

God and the law.).”<br />

6 No one is above the<br />

law<br />

6.8 In 1776, the notion that no one<br />

is above the law was popular during<br />

the founding <strong>of</strong> the United States.<br />

For example, Thomas Paine wrote in<br />

his pamphletCommon Sense that “in<br />

America, the law is king. For as in absolute<br />

governments the King is law, so<br />

in free countries the law ought to be<br />

king; and there ought to be no other.”<br />

In 1780, John Adams enshrined this<br />

principle in the Massachusetts Constitution<br />

by seeking to establish “a<br />

government <strong>of</strong> laws and not <strong>of</strong> men.”


6.9 This formal approach allows laws<br />

that protect democracy and individual<br />

rights, but recognizes the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> “rule <strong>of</strong> law” even in societies<br />

and countries that do not necessarily<br />

have such laws protecting democracy<br />

or individual rights.<br />

7 <strong>Rule</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Recognition<br />

& Ability to<br />

change<br />

7.10 HLA Hart’s assertion that a law<br />

is valid if and only if it satisfies the<br />

criteria <strong>of</strong> an accepted rule <strong>of</strong> recognition<br />

to be the most compelling. I<br />

believe that legal validity is necessarily<br />

a social fact.We are now considering<br />

the validity <strong>of</strong> entire systems <strong>of</strong><br />

law, rather than the validity <strong>of</strong> particular<br />

laws based on their content.<br />

To Hart’s definition <strong>of</strong> legal validity,<br />

I would like to add the clause “and<br />

the entire legal system is considered<br />

to be valid”. According to Hart’s theory,<br />

the system <strong>of</strong> law is governed by a<br />

set <strong>of</strong> secondary rules, and these rules<br />

would have to be valid. But I think<br />

there may be additional requirements<br />

for a legal system to be valid. I propose<br />

that the definition <strong>of</strong> validity <strong>of</strong> a<br />

system includes a notion <strong>of</strong> fairness.<br />

I will not rigidly define this fairness<br />

here, but by it I refer to a system in<br />

which the people who are governed by<br />

the laws have a role in making and<br />

amending the laws. A law is valid<br />

when it is defined as valid by a rule <strong>of</strong><br />

recognition which is accepted by <strong>of</strong>ficials.<br />

In addition to Hart’s criteria,<br />

I believe that for a law to be valid<br />

the system <strong>of</strong> law <strong>of</strong> which it is a part<br />

must itself be valid. For a system <strong>of</strong><br />

law to be valid, the rule <strong>of</strong> recognition<br />

must be accepted, and the members<br />

<strong>of</strong> the society must have the ability<br />

to change the laws which will govern<br />

them. On both this counts, AWHO<br />

rules are invalid!<br />

8 <strong>Rule</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> v <strong>Rule</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> Men<br />

8.11 The functional interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

the term “rule <strong>of</strong> law”, consistent<br />

with the traditional English meaning,<br />

contrasts the “rule <strong>of</strong> law” with the<br />

“rule <strong>of</strong> man.” According to the functional<br />

view, a society in which government<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficers have a great deal <strong>of</strong><br />

discretion has a low degree <strong>of</strong> “rule<br />

<strong>of</strong> law”, whereas a society in which<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficers have little discretion<br />

has a high degree <strong>of</strong> “rule <strong>of</strong> law”.<br />

The rule <strong>of</strong> law is thus somewhat at<br />

odds with flexibility, even when flexibility<br />

may be preferable.<br />

8.12 The rule <strong>of</strong> law has been considered<br />

as one <strong>of</strong> the key dimensions that<br />

determine the quality and good governance<br />

<strong>of</strong> a country.<br />

8.13 All government <strong>of</strong>ficers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

United States, including the President,<br />

the Justices <strong>of</strong> the Supreme<br />

Court, and all members <strong>of</strong> Congress,<br />

pledge first and foremost to uphold<br />

the Constitution. These oaths affirm<br />

that the rule <strong>of</strong> law is superior to the<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> any human leader.<br />

9 Principles <strong>of</strong><br />

supremacy <strong>of</strong> law<br />

9.14 In 1959, an international gathering<br />

<strong>of</strong> over 185 judges, lawyers,<br />

and law pr<strong>of</strong>essors from 53 countries,<br />

meeting in New Delhi and speaking<br />

5<br />

as the International Commission <strong>of</strong><br />

Jurists, made a declaration as to the<br />

fundamental principle <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law. This was the Declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

Delhi. They declared that the rule<br />

<strong>of</strong> law implies certain rights and freedoms,<br />

that it implies an independent<br />

judiciary, and that it implies social,<br />

economic and cultural conditions conducive<br />

to human dignity.<br />

9.15 The Secretary-General <strong>of</strong> the<br />

United Nations defines the rule <strong>of</strong><br />

law as: a principle <strong>of</strong> governance in<br />

which all persons, institutions and entities,<br />

public and private, including<br />

the State itself, are accountable to<br />

laws that are publicly promulgated,<br />

equally enforced and independently<br />

adjudicated, and which are consistent<br />

with international human rights<br />

norms and standards. It requires, as<br />

well, measures to ensure adherence to<br />

the principles <strong>of</strong> supremacy <strong>of</strong> law,<br />

equality before the law, accountability<br />

to the law, fairness in the application<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law, separation <strong>of</strong> powers,<br />

participation in decision-making,<br />

legal certainty, avoidance <strong>of</strong> arbitrariness<br />

and procedural and legal transparency.<br />

10 Will as law<br />

10.16The proprietor, the robber, the<br />

hero, the sovereign for all these titles<br />

are synonymous imposes his will<br />

as law, and suffers neither contradiction<br />

nor control; that is, he pretends<br />

to be the legislative and the executive<br />

power at once . . . [and so] property<br />

engenders despotism . . . That is so<br />

clearly the essence <strong>of</strong> property that,<br />

to be convinced <strong>of</strong> it, one need but remember<br />

what it is, and observe what<br />

happens around him. Property is the


ight to use and abuse . . . if goods<br />

are property, why should not the proprietors<br />

be kings, and despotic kings<br />

kings in proportion to their facultes<br />

bonitaires? And if each proprietor<br />

is sovereign lord within the sphere <strong>of</strong><br />

his property, absolute king throughout<br />

his own domain, how could a government<br />

<strong>of</strong> proprietors be any thing<br />

but chaos and confusion?<br />

11 Zero exploitation<br />

11.17Toward “zero exploitation”<br />

against the consumer: Lon Walras,<br />

economist and mathematician, found<br />

that in a hypothetical situation <strong>of</strong><br />

perfect competition (or <strong>of</strong> quasiperfect<br />

competition) prices would<br />

approach costs, and pr<strong>of</strong>its would<br />

approach zero. To ensure fairness<br />

within a cost price network, the main<br />

advantages <strong>of</strong> membership should be<br />

under the conditions <strong>of</strong>: 1. cautious<br />

deposits; 2. allowing to their customers<br />

the complete transparency <strong>of</strong><br />

the business; 3. previous acceptance<br />

to boycott whatever violator until<br />

reparation. “Cost the limit <strong>of</strong> price”<br />

aims to establish an equitable exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor. Incomes should not<br />

include pr<strong>of</strong>its: one’s pr<strong>of</strong>it is always<br />

another’s exploitation <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

amount (“plusprice”) by pricing. In<br />

such a “reciprocal transparent cost<br />

price network” whatever currency<br />

would change the real meaning itself<br />

<strong>of</strong> money, it would become a sharp<br />

tool just to measure only everybody’s<br />

working time, and no more measuring<br />

somebody’s extortion by prices.<br />

The generalization <strong>of</strong> the “cost the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> price” principle (obtainable<br />

by the “reciprocal transparent cost<br />

price” golden rule) and its concur-<br />

rence, makes the intrinsic “surplus”<br />

from the productivity, without having<br />

any form <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, gets the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> purchasing power per currency<br />

unit, so that among the possible<br />

consequences are: a lesser need <strong>of</strong><br />

money to live, deflation, distributed<br />

investment power among consumers.<br />

Money should mean and measure<br />

only workingtime, neither violence<br />

on wants, nor merchandization in<br />

any humiliating sense.<br />

11.18It stands for individual rights<br />

tempered by considerations <strong>of</strong> justice,<br />

equity and fair dealing as between<br />

man and man, and its one great aim<br />

is to prevent the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

weaker by the stronger party.<br />

12 Coperative &<br />

Rochdale Principles<br />

12.19A cooperative (“coop”), cooperative<br />

(“co-op”), or coperative<br />

(“cop”) is an autonomous association<br />

<strong>of</strong> persons who voluntarily cooperate<br />

for their mutual, social, economic,<br />

and cultural benefit.[1] Cooperatives<br />

include non-pr<strong>of</strong>it community organizations<br />

and businesses that are owned<br />

and managed by the people who<br />

use its services (a consumer cooperative)<br />

or by the people who work<br />

there (a worker cooperative) or by<br />

the people who live there (a housing<br />

cooperative), hybrids such as<br />

worker cooperatives that are also consumer<br />

cooperatives or credit unions,<br />

multi-stakeholder cooperatives such<br />

as those that bring together civil society<br />

and local actors to deliver community<br />

needs, and second and third<br />

tier cooperatives whose members are<br />

6<br />

other cooperatives.“Cop” should follow<br />

Rochdale Principles.<br />

A Open and Voluntary<br />

Membership<br />

12.20The first <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale Principles<br />

states that co-operative societies<br />

must have an open and voluntary<br />

membership. A “Co-operatives<br />

are voluntary organisations, open to<br />

all persons able to use their services<br />

and willing to accept the responsibilities<br />

<strong>of</strong> membership, without gender,<br />

social, racial, political or religious discrimination.”<br />

However, this does not<br />

prohibit the co-operative from setting<br />

ground rules for membership, such as<br />

residing in a specific geographic area<br />

or payment <strong>of</strong> a membership fee to<br />

join, so long as all persons meeting<br />

such criteria are able to participate if<br />

they so choose.<br />

B Democratic member<br />

control<br />

12.21The second <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale Principles<br />

states that co-operative societies<br />

must have democratic member<br />

control. According to the ICA’s<br />

Statement on the Co-operative Identity,<br />

Co-operatives are democratic organizations<br />

controlled by their members,<br />

who actively participate in setting<br />

their policies and making decisions.<br />

Men and women serving as<br />

elected representatives are accountable<br />

to the membership. In primary<br />

co-operatives members have equal<br />

voting rights (one member, one vote)<br />

and co-operatives at other levels are<br />

also organised in a democratic manner.


C Member economic participation<br />

12.22Member economic participation<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> the defining features <strong>of</strong><br />

co-operative societies, and constitutes<br />

the third Rochdale Principle<br />

in the ICA’s Statement on the Cooperative<br />

Identity. According to the<br />

ICA, co-operatives are enterprises in<br />

which Members contribute equitably<br />

to, and democratically control, the<br />

capital <strong>of</strong> their co-operative. At least<br />

part <strong>of</strong> that capital is usually the<br />

common property <strong>of</strong> the co-operative<br />

12.23The second part <strong>of</strong> the principle<br />

deals with how members are compensated<br />

for funds invested in a Cooperative,<br />

and how surpluses should<br />

be used. Unlike for pr<strong>of</strong>it corporations,<br />

co-operatives are a form <strong>of</strong><br />

social enterprise. Given this, there<br />

are at least three purposes for which<br />

surplus funds can be used, or distributed,<br />

by a Co-operative. Members<br />

usually receive limited compensation,<br />

if any, on capital subscribed<br />

as a condition <strong>of</strong> membership. Developing<br />

their co-operative, possibly by<br />

setting up reserves, part <strong>of</strong> which at<br />

least would be indivisible; in other<br />

words, the surplus can be reinvested<br />

in the co-operative. Benefiting members<br />

in proportion to their transactions<br />

with the co-operative; for example,<br />

a Consumers’ Co-operative may<br />

decide to pay dividends based on purchases<br />

(or a ’divvi’). Supporting<br />

other activities approved by the membership.<br />

D Autonomy and independence<br />

12.24The fourth <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale Principles<br />

states that co-operative soci-<br />

eties must be autonomous and independent.<br />

According to the ICA’s<br />

Statement on the Co-operative Identity,<br />

Co-operatives are autonomous,<br />

self-help organizations controlled by<br />

their members. If they enter into<br />

agreements with other organizations,<br />

including governments, or raise capital<br />

from external sources, they do so<br />

on terms that ensure democratic control<br />

by their members and maintain<br />

their co-operative autonomy.<br />

E Education, training,<br />

and information<br />

12.25The fifth <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale Principles<br />

states that co-operative societies<br />

must provide education and training<br />

to their members and the public.<br />

According to the ICA’s Statement<br />

on the Co-operative Identity,<br />

Co-operatives provide education and<br />

training for their members, elected<br />

representatives, managers and employees<br />

so they can contribute effectively<br />

to the development <strong>of</strong> their cooperatives.<br />

F Cooperation among cooperatives<br />

12.26The sixth <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale Principles<br />

states that co-operatives cooperate<br />

with each other. According<br />

to the ICA’s Statement<br />

on the Co-operative Identity, Cooperatives<br />

serve their members most<br />

effectively and strengthen the cooperative<br />

movement by working together<br />

through local, national, regional<br />

and international structures.<br />

7<br />

G Concern for community<br />

12.27The seventh <strong>of</strong> the Rochdale<br />

Principles states that co-operative societies<br />

must have concern for their<br />

communities. According to the ICA’s<br />

Statement on the Co-operative Identity,<br />

Co-operatives work for the sustainable<br />

development <strong>of</strong> their communities<br />

through policies approved<br />

by their members.<br />

H Democratic operations<br />

12.28The founding principle <strong>of</strong> any cooperative<br />

can be found in its governance<br />

model: a cooperative belongs<br />

to its members. It is they who decide<br />

on the directions it will take, and who<br />

make strategic choices for their cooperative,<br />

in tandem with the salaried<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficers.<br />

12.29This principle echoes one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

basic rules <strong>of</strong> continuous improvement,<br />

which requires that people on<br />

the ground (operators, technicians,<br />

and so on) must be involved in the<br />

process and be given as great a voice<br />

as their managers when it comes to<br />

correcting problems and choosing solutions.<br />

I People first<br />

12.30In a cooperative business, people<br />

are the central concern. Cooperatives<br />

look after the well being <strong>of</strong> not just<br />

the members, but the larger community<br />

as well.<br />

12.31The key to operational excellence<br />

is that everyone does their part<br />

to the best <strong>of</strong> their ability, and that<br />

mistakes are not caused by a flawed<br />

person, but by flawed, incomplete or<br />

poorly defined processes. Every ap-


proach is based on this concept <strong>of</strong> respect<br />

for the individual.<br />

J Giving clients what they<br />

want<br />

12.32Cooperatives are very clientoriented.<br />

Often, member and client<br />

are one and the same. The cooperative<br />

will strive to provide members<br />

with the product or service they need.<br />

The same is true in the world <strong>of</strong> operational<br />

excellence, where decisions<br />

always revolve around the client. To<br />

give clients what they want, you need<br />

to listen to them.<br />

12.33This focus on client-members<br />

and on meeting their needs is further<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> how cooperatives and operational<br />

excellence target the same values<br />

and principles.<br />

K Member-driven business<br />

enterprises<br />

12.34Cooperatives member-driven<br />

business enterprises that put people<br />

front and centre <strong>of</strong>fered a viable and<br />

vibrant alternative economic model,<br />

12.35enterprises organized around cooperative<br />

principles selfhelp, democracy,<br />

equality, equity and solidarity<br />

reduced poverty, created jobs and<br />

promoted social integration, and did<br />

so with a firm belief in the ethical<br />

values <strong>of</strong> openness, honesty, social<br />

responsibility and caring for others.<br />

Cooperatives <strong>of</strong>fered a memberowned<br />

model <strong>of</strong> economic organization that<br />

reconciled the logic <strong>of</strong> a market economy<br />

with imperatives <strong>of</strong> social inclusion<br />

and ownership, particularly relevant<br />

in the aftermath <strong>of</strong> the global<br />

economic and financial crisis.<br />

12.36In the same vein, Deputy SecretaryGeneral<br />

AshaRose Migiro said<br />

that there were increasing demands<br />

for change in the ways we live and<br />

work for choices and values that were<br />

sustainable, responsible and inclusive.<br />

In confronting those challenges,<br />

strength could be drawn from the cooperative<br />

spirit, which balanced economic<br />

viability with social responsibility.<br />

12.37We must do more than simply<br />

talk about our interdependence. It<br />

was not antiwealth to say that wealth<br />

must do more than serve the wealthy;<br />

it was not anticompetition to say<br />

that, without cooperation, competition<br />

might not lift us up, but pull<br />

us down. The nearly 1 billion people<br />

driving the worldwide cooperative<br />

movement had proved that the<br />

human principle <strong>of</strong> cooperation could<br />

make for a better economy.<br />

12.38More people in decisionmaking<br />

positions [] should know about the<br />

size, scale and scope <strong>of</strong> the cooperative<br />

business model, and should<br />

acknowledge it in public policy and<br />

regulation. Cooperatives were valuesled<br />

businesses, and should be<br />

given equal promotion alongside the<br />

stockholder model. Further, cooperatives<br />

were peopleled, and led in<br />

particular by young people, similar<br />

to those presently seeking a voice<br />

in North Africa, on Wall Street and<br />

across the world.<br />

12.39Cooperatives and mutuals represent<br />

a distinct and successful business<br />

model as well as an alternative<br />

to the prevailing business model. Cooperatives<br />

and mutuals have shown<br />

that they have the financial strength<br />

and resilience to weather today’s economic<br />

crises. They have also demonstrated<br />

that they can remain competitive<br />

while staying true to their<br />

mission <strong>of</strong> meeting their members’<br />

8<br />

needs and adhering to their governance<br />

practices. How have they managed<br />

to stand out from the dominant<br />

business model? What are the<br />

growth levers at the disposal <strong>of</strong> cooperatives<br />

and mutuals given the need<br />

for sustainability?<br />

12.40To promote their unique features,<br />

cooperatives most <strong>of</strong>ten refer to<br />

the statutes that define their business<br />

ownership system, surplus distribution<br />

mechanisms and mode <strong>of</strong> governance<br />

that make them more resistant<br />

to cyclical economic downturns than<br />

shareholder-based companies. But,<br />

aside from this, they present themselves<br />

as traditional enterprises that<br />

are fully integrated into product and<br />

labour markets like other businesses.<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> this, they seriously underestimate<br />

their market regulation influence.<br />

Yet a growing number <strong>of</strong><br />

macroeconomic studies show that the<br />

rules and organizational structure <strong>of</strong><br />

cooperatives affect their behaviour,<br />

which could be described as sociomarket<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the specific features<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cooperative social compromise.<br />

L Member/Customer focus<br />

12.41Cooperative banks have a strong<br />

customer focus, take into account<br />

the interests <strong>of</strong> many different stakeholders,<br />

have a moderate risk pr<strong>of</strong>ile<br />

and are well-capitalized. They<br />

must cherish their governance structure<br />

with member ownership and influence,<br />

which can be employed as<br />

key differentiator. At the same time,<br />

they must be entrepreneurial, costeffective,<br />

efficient and businesslike organizations,<br />

providing adequate and<br />

innovative products and services at


fair prices and via state-<strong>of</strong>-the-art distribution<br />

concepts. Moreover, member<br />

influence and involvement must<br />

be firmly institutionalized. Finally,<br />

the attitude and behavior <strong>of</strong> all employees<br />

should be in line with the<br />

original Cooperative principles, thus<br />

putting the customer interests first.<br />

13 Conclusion<br />

13.42This paper elucidates how the<br />

social orientation in business model<br />

helps the financial cooperatives to<br />

achieve business success through the<br />

perpetual loyalty and patronage <strong>of</strong><br />

service, thereby making membership<br />

meaningful. And in every aspect <strong>of</strong> it,<br />

AWHO has violated each <strong>of</strong> the principles<br />

<strong>of</strong> co-operatives created for the<br />

welfare <strong>of</strong> its members!<br />

9

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!