06.09.2013 Views

CONFLICT MANAGEMENT The Psychology of conflict and conflict ...

CONFLICT MANAGEMENT The Psychology of conflict and conflict ...

CONFLICT MANAGEMENT The Psychology of conflict and conflict ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2. <strong>CONFLICT</strong> AT WORK THROUGHOUT THE HISTORY OF ORGANIZATIONS 61<br />

task. <strong>The</strong> “one best way” meant that every production process could be<br />

reduced to tasks involving basic physical motions <strong>and</strong> requirements <strong>and</strong><br />

that human labor could be assigned these narrowly defined tasks as<br />

parts are fitted into a machine. Labor would then conform to the existing<br />

scientifically determined tasks already in place, rather than determining<br />

its structure. In this way, the organization would operate as a harmonious,<br />

well-oiled machine.<br />

Scientific management represented an engineering solution to a human<br />

problem. If human organizations <strong>of</strong> production could be conceptualized as<br />

machines, then machine design principles could be applied to organizing<br />

the division <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> primary challenge was the humans who populate<br />

the machine, possessing properties that engineers find least attractive—temperament,<br />

resistance, friction, <strong>and</strong> nonuniformity. Taylor’s (1911)<br />

science <strong>of</strong> management was aimed at minimizing the <strong>conflict</strong> <strong>and</strong> tension<br />

generated by this variable <strong>and</strong> unpredictable factor <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

<strong>The</strong> horizontal differentiation <strong>of</strong> tasks built into the labor as machine<br />

parts paradigm also entailed a vertical dimension. Taylor (1911) noted that,<br />

in contrast to earlier systems <strong>of</strong> management where “practically the whole<br />

problem is up to the workman,” under scientific management “fully onehalf<br />

<strong>of</strong> the problem is up to the management” (p. 38). While the 50–50 split<br />

can be viewed as an “equal division” quantitatively, there is a clear qualitative<br />

division. Vertically, there are the mental labor exercised by management<br />

<strong>and</strong> the manual labor exercised by workers. <strong>The</strong> managers conceive.<br />

<strong>The</strong> workers execute. Of course, this perpetual organizational principle <strong>of</strong><br />

hierarchy would generate further <strong>conflict</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong> application <strong>and</strong> implementation <strong>of</strong> scientific management principles<br />

produced a predictable response from human labor. Much <strong>of</strong> this<br />

is documented in a remarkable study <strong>of</strong> scientific management that was<br />

published in 1915 by Robert Hoxie (1966), who was appointed special<br />

investigator for the United States Commission on Industrial Relations. He<br />

included in his study the <strong>of</strong>ficial “trade union” position <strong>and</strong> its specific<br />

objections to scientific management. On the question <strong>of</strong> the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

scientific management, labor argued,<br />

“Scientific management” thus defined is a device employed for the purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> increasing production <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its; <strong>and</strong> tends to eliminate consideration<br />

for the character, rights <strong>and</strong> welfare <strong>of</strong> employees. It looks upon the worker<br />

as a mere instrument <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> reduces him to a semiautomatic<br />

attachment to the machine or tool. It does not take all the elements into consideration<br />

but deals with human beings as it does with inanimate machines.<br />

. . . “Scientific management” is undemocratic, it is a reversion to industrial<br />

autonomy which forces the workers to depend upon the employers’ conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> fairness <strong>and</strong> limits the democratic safeguards <strong>of</strong> the workers . . . It<br />

allows the worker ordinarily no voice in hiring or discharge, the setting<br />

<strong>of</strong> the task, the determination <strong>of</strong> the wage rate or the general conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

employment. (pp. 15, 18)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!