04.09.2013 Views

HandoutPDF - Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle - CNRS

HandoutPDF - Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle - CNRS

HandoutPDF - Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Mini-workshop on Nominalizations<br />

Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona<br />

December 14 2009<br />

Outline<br />

On Tensed Nominalizations<br />

Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

<strong>Laboratoire</strong> <strong>de</strong> <strong>Linguistique</strong> <strong>Formelle</strong><br />

<strong>CNRS</strong>-Université Paris 7<br />

lecarme@llf.cnrs.fr<br />

http://www.llf.cnrs.fr/Gens/Lecarme/<br />

Within a constructional approach of word formation, categorization and argument structure<br />

(Marantz 1996, Borer 2003), the question arises as to how much syntactic structure<br />

(if any) nominalizations share with verbal environment. Here, I focus on the role of nominal<br />

tense and event structure in the licensing of arguments in Somali nominalizations. I<br />

provi<strong>de</strong> evi<strong>de</strong>nce for the fact that the argument structure of nominalizations comes from<br />

a structure internal to the nominal itself. A full explanation of the Somali data hopefully<br />

will not be a particular statement about Somali, but rather a <strong>de</strong>eper un<strong>de</strong>rstanding of the<br />

‘right domains’ in the structure of nominal expressions.<br />

1 Parallels between verbal / nominal domains<br />

There are many suggested and suggestive parallels between the verbal / nominal domains.<br />

Such parallels have been discussed in philosophy, cognitive semantics (Jackendoff 1983),<br />

formal semantics (Carlson 1982, Krifka 1992), syntax (Abney 1987, Pesesky and Torrego<br />

2001, Hiraiwa 2005).<br />

Semantic si<strong>de</strong>: VPs name ‘properties of eventualities’ (events and states), not single events.<br />

Events have the same logical type as individual entities, i.e. . Quantifying over<br />

the event variable (‘sentence <strong>de</strong>termination’) yields ‘<strong>de</strong>finite’ or ‘in<strong>de</strong>finite’ <strong>de</strong>scriptions of<br />

events (Higginbotham 1983, Kratzer 1988).<br />

Syntactic si<strong>de</strong>: there is a <strong>de</strong>ictic reference mechanism ‘above’ the <strong>de</strong>scription of events and<br />

objects. C, like D, turns a proposition to something that can act as a argument.<br />

Verbal domain: vP has a full argument (event) structure. Voice introduces the external<br />

argument (Kratzer 1996) and interacts with (transitive) v to <strong>de</strong>termine whether accusative<br />

case is available for a vP internal constituent.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 2<br />

Nominal domain: nP is an intransitive structure. Yet nominal predicates preserve the<br />

active / stative distinction (be a hero vs. be a person, cf. Chomsky 1970).<br />

Nominals and clauses share ‘structural meanings’ carried by functional categories or features<br />

which do not <strong>de</strong>termine a phase, such as [plural] and Tense.<br />

1.1 Verbal [plural]<br />

Number can refer to entities or events <strong>de</strong>noted by nominal or verbal elements; it <strong>de</strong>rives<br />

from the ability to perceive something as a token. In natural language, we find both<br />

nominal and verbal number (e.g. Ojeda 1998, Matthewson 2000).<br />

In most Afroasiatic languages, verbal plurality is realized by morphological processes similar<br />

to those found in nominals, e.g. reduplication (Newman 1990, Fassi Fehri 2003).<br />

• No singular available, cf. pluralia tantum: <strong>de</strong>g-<strong>de</strong>g ‘to hurry’, bad-baadi ‘to look after’,<br />

guur-guur ‘to crawl’, gil-gil ‘to shake’, etc.<br />

• Shift of meaning between singular and plural: dóon ‘to want’, doon-dóon ‘to search<br />

(for)’; már ‘to pass’, mar-már ‘to travel (about)’.<br />

• Plural nominalizations: event nouns suffixed with -id, -in-, -is, -sho exhibit ‘verbal<br />

pluralization’:<br />

(1) a. qor-íd (f) ‘witing’ → qor-qor-íd (f) ‘writings’<br />

b. dil-íd (f) ‘killing’ → dil-dil-íd (f) ‘killings’<br />

c. cel-ín (f) ‘repetition’→ cel-cel-ín (f) ‘repetitions’<br />

d. qaba-shó (f) ‘arrest’ → qab-qabasho (f)‘arrests’<br />

• Pluractionality:<br />

(2) a. Shálay baa boolíis-ku sóo qabtáy 26 ká míd ah<br />

Yesterday C/F police-<strong>de</strong>fM[nom] dir. catch.past.3s 26 from one be<br />

burcád-dii<br />

gang-<strong>de</strong>fF<br />

Yesterday, the police caught 26 gangsters’ (nondistributive)<br />

b. Shálay baa boolíis-ku sóo qab-qabtáy 26 ká míd<br />

Yesterday C/F police-<strong>de</strong>fM[nom] dir. catch-catch.past.3s 26 from one<br />

ah burcád-dii<br />

be gang-<strong>de</strong>fF<br />

Yesterday, the police caught 26 gangsters’ (distributive)


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 3<br />

(2a) there is exactly one catching event → (2a) expresses a pure collective reading, where<br />

the policemen jointly caught 26 gangsters.<br />

(2b) there is more than one (non-i<strong>de</strong>ntical, spatiotemporally separated) catching events →<br />

(2b) expresses a kind of distribution reading, which implies that we can find subsets of<br />

policemen and subsets of gangsters.<br />

→ [plural] does not always originate within a DP: the source of distributive interpretation<br />

is the verbal [plural] feature (not the DP’s plural inflection).<br />

Semantic pluralization: [plural] ascends from the v head and functions as an operator that<br />

pluralizes the vP predicate (cf.. Link’s (1983) cross-categorial *plural operator).<br />

1.2 Nominal Tense (and aspect)<br />

‘Nominal tense’ is a well-attested morphological phenomenon (See Lecarme 1996, 1999,<br />

2004, 2008 and the references cited there. Other manifestations in the absence of specific<br />

nominal tense morphology: non-<strong>de</strong>monstrative uses of that in English; presence of two<br />

semantically different types of <strong>de</strong>finite articles in German, see Roehrs 2006, Schwartz 2009).<br />

I assume that DP has the structure (3), where D is formally parallel to C, n*P is parallel<br />

to Voice and introduces the external ‘possessor’ argument, n is a light noun, and nP, n*P<br />

and DP <strong>de</strong>fine 3 syntactic domains for tense interpretation.<br />

(3) DP<br />

D<br />

T n*P<br />

(Poss)<br />

APPL-n nP<br />

n Root<br />

Assuming that syntax and semantics run in parallel from bottom to top, 3 (sets of) times<br />

are potentially involved in the temporal interpretation of noun phrases:<br />

(4) the predication time (i.e. the times at which a property like ‘presi<strong>de</strong>nt’ is asserted<br />

to hold of an individual),<br />

Madaxweyní-hii hore (waa imáanayaa)<br />

presi<strong>de</strong>nt-<strong>de</strong>tM.past before F is-coming


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 4<br />

The former presi<strong>de</strong>nt (is coming)<br />

(5) the time of the genitive/possessive relation,<br />

(Waxaan ku bárayaa) afá-daydii<br />

hore<br />

Expl.F.1S 2S introduce wife-<strong>de</strong>tF.1S.<strong>de</strong>tF.past before<br />

(I am introducing you) my ex-wife<br />

(6) the time of (existence of) the individual (or event).<br />

a. Madaxweyní-hii wúu dhintay<br />

presi<strong>de</strong>nt-<strong>de</strong>fM.past F3MS die.past<br />

The presi<strong>de</strong>nt died<br />

b. Aníg-ii waan iská tagay<br />

Me-<strong>de</strong>fM.past F.1S<br />

As for me, I left<br />

refl.from go<br />

c. Yáa mas’úul ká ah burburín-tii Soomaaliya?<br />

who responsible from is <strong>de</strong>struction-<strong>de</strong>fF.past Somalia<br />

Who is responsible for the <strong>de</strong>struction of Somalia?<br />

Like English before, horé ‘before’ express temporal prece<strong>de</strong>nce IFF it is bound by a PAST<br />

tense (spatial otherwise).<br />

• In (4) horé applies to the predicate → the predicate is true of invividuals that once<br />

had the property ‘presi<strong>de</strong>nt’,<br />

• In (5) horé applies to the possession relation: the nominal can be used to refer to<br />

someone who was formerly ‘my wife’ and is ‘my wife’ no longer (= perfective or ‘outer<br />

aspect’) =‘the one who was my wife’ (and still is).<br />

→ cf. Chomsky (1970): there is an argument for taking the form John’s wife to<br />

un<strong>de</strong>rlie John has a wife, rather than conversely. ‘Functional category verbs’ inserted<br />

into v no<strong>de</strong>s (have, be, do, perhaps light verbs) are precisely what is lacking in<br />

nominals.<br />

• The strong pronouns have the same distribution of ordinary DPs. As pronouns<br />

contain no ‘<strong>de</strong>scriptive’ material, (6b) illustrates a clear case of temporal location of<br />

an individual.<br />

(6c) is a ‘tensed nominalization’: the nominal itself refers to a past event of <strong>de</strong>struction.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 5<br />

1.3 Event structure<br />

(Davidsonian) events are particular things, and they are <strong>de</strong>notations of - among other<br />

categories - verbs. Ordinary sentences implicitly mark reference to an event. ‘Simple<br />

event’ nouns (Grimshaw 1990) such as trip or war <strong>de</strong>note sets of events as well.<br />

(7) a. Dagáal-kii Ogaa<strong>de</strong>enya<br />

war-<strong>de</strong>fM.past Oga<strong>de</strong>n<br />

The Oga<strong>de</strong>n War (book title)<br />

b. wéerar-kii 11-kii Setembar<br />

attack-<strong>de</strong>fM.past 11-<strong>de</strong>fM.past September<br />

the 11 September attack<br />

In (7a) (a book title), nominal [past] locates the event temporally, in<strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>ntly of any<br />

‘discourse’ context or situation. In (7b), the effect of a nominal [past] is to constrain the<br />

<strong>de</strong>notation of ‘September 11’ to a set of past times.<br />

→ Nominals then are much similar to clauses with regard to temporal interpretation (tense<br />

and event structure). Tense makes it possible to chain together the various elements of the<br />

interpretation of noun phrases.<br />

→ Question: what do sentences/CPs have that nominalizations/DPs do not?<br />

2 Argument structure in Nominalizations<br />

In a constructional approach such as Distributed Morphology (Marantz 1996, 1997), the<br />

syntax (thus LF) provi<strong>de</strong>s the only way the mind has to represent compositional meanings<br />

(i.e., constructed by the computational system).<br />

Every word is the result of a syntactic <strong>de</strong>rivation interpreted with the use of the Encyclopedia,<br />

where non-compositional meanings of linguistic expressions are stored. Phases<br />

<strong>de</strong>termine the cyclic domains of semantic and phonological interpretation (Chomsky 2008,<br />

Marvin 2002).<br />

→ (cf. Chomsky 1970) N, V are not syntactic categories - need not have any essential<br />

distributional property (X’ theory). N and V must be distinguished by some internal<br />

property, i.e. some feature(s): something becomes nominal when it merges with D.<br />

→ Destruction and growth (as opposed to -ing gerunds) are never verbs at any stage of the<br />

<strong>de</strong>rivation (cf. Chomsky 1970). Roots like DESTROY and GROW are category neutral.<br />

When the root is placed in a nominal environment, the result is a ‘nominalization’.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 6<br />

2.1 ‘Agentive’ nominalizations<br />

Chomsky (1970): transitive grow involves [+cause], a lexical feature.<br />

Marantz (1996, 1997): Differences between sentential / nominal environment is syntactic,<br />

not lexical. Sentential/verbal environments allow syntactically projected agents, nominal<br />

environments do not.<br />

John’s (<strong>de</strong>struction of the city) is not a projected agent. The root DESTROY implies an<br />

agent much the way it implies a time of <strong>de</strong>struction (yesterday’s <strong>de</strong>struction of the city).<br />

→ Problem: If nominalizations embed no verbal context, what is the relation between their<br />

implied (or ‘inherent’) agent and the syntactically projected agent in a verbal environment?<br />

Why <strong>de</strong>struction, but not growth, seems to retain its agent?<br />

2.2 The ‘Possessor’ argument<br />

Nominals do not assign case to their selected objects, yet functional structure is responsible<br />

for interpreting ‘external arguments’ within nominals. Gentitive constructions crosslinguistically<br />

involve a ‘strong’ <strong>de</strong>finite artice (cf. *a book of John vs. a book of John’s).<br />

In somali, the ‘possessor’ argument (a multi-role argument) is structurally <strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>nt of a<br />

(tensed) <strong>de</strong>finite article (D+T). The prenominal ‘possessor’ must be an argument, not a<br />

modifier (8b):<br />

(8) a. búug-ga Maryan / Máryan búug-geeda<br />

book-<strong>de</strong>tM Maryan / Maryan book-<strong>de</strong>tM.Poss3F<br />

Maryan’s book<br />

b. búug-ga xisáab-ta / *xisáab-ta búug-geeda<br />

book-<strong>de</strong>tM mathematics-<strong>de</strong>tF / mathematics-<strong>de</strong>tF book-<strong>de</strong>M.Poss3F<br />

the book of mathematics<br />

In<strong>de</strong>finite constructions do not license ‘possessor’ arguments. The ‘possessive’ relation<br />

must be explicitly expressed in a ‘reduced’ relative clause:<br />

(9) a. *búug Maryan → búug [Máryan léedahay]<br />

book Maryan → book Maryan is-possessing<br />

a book that Maryan is possessing<br />

b. *ínan Maryan → ínan [Máryan dhalatay]<br />

son Maryan → son Maryan bore<br />

a son that Maryan bore


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 7<br />

In Lecarme (2004), I establish a parallel between possessive constructions and double object<br />

constructions (cf. Larson 1988, Pesetsky 1995, Pylkkänen 2007). An ‘extra’ layer of<br />

semantic predication is created by adding an external argument to the nP predicate (see<br />

(3)): APPL takes nP as its complement in a complex predicate construction → transitive<br />

nominalizations do have a projected external argument, but this argument is not projected<br />

by Voice.<br />

→ If ‘possessors’ in nominalizations can be interpreted as agents even in the absence of a<br />

Voice head, where does the agentive interpretation come from?<br />

2.3 Somali nominalizations<br />

As in many languages within and outsi<strong>de</strong> Afroasiatic (e.g. Bohnemeyer 2002), roots or<br />

stems create verbs as well as nouns 1 .<br />

Somali nominalizations are never ambiguous. Roots and themes (causative, middle, passive,<br />

frequentative...) all have corresponding nominal forms.<br />

(10) a. joog- (intr.) ‘stay, wait, remain’<br />

jóog (m), jóog-id (f) ‘stay, act of standing’<br />

b. joogsa- (intr.)‘come to a halt, end’<br />

joogsa-shó ‘stopping onself’<br />

c. jooji- (tr.) ‘bring to a halt, stop’<br />

joojín (f) ‘halt, pause’<br />

d. joogjoog-(intr.) ‘stay a while, hang around’<br />

joogjóogid (f) ‘(act/fact of) hanging around’<br />

2.4 Causative formation<br />

Proposed analysis: agentive nominalizations involve CAUSE, but CAUSE has no verbal<br />

status.<br />

• CAUSE is a semantic relation between 2 events (Parsons 1990). CAUSE, like Tense,<br />

is not a category-<strong>de</strong>termining morpheme, nor a phase head.<br />

1 Note on the ‘nouniness’ of the Somali lexicon: As verbs have no infinitive form, Somali dictionaries<br />

(e.g. Yaasiin C. Keenadiid’s Qaamuska Af-Soomaliga (1976)) traditionally have no entries for verbs, but<br />

use nominal forms instead. A large subset of the verbal stems can be argued to be <strong>de</strong>nominal (Hale &<br />

Keyser 1993, 1997’s ‘unergative verbs’, e.g. cayáar ‘play’, hées ‘sing’, féker ‘think’, hádal ‘talk’). Many<br />

roots, such as dagáal ‘attack’ jóog ‘stay’, jír ‘existence/exist, are ‘ambicategorial’: there is no evi<strong>de</strong>nce to<br />

<strong>de</strong>ci<strong>de</strong> whether nominal or verbal forms are basic.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 8<br />

• CAUSE heads introduce event or eventualities syntactically: a root merged with<br />

CAUSE has the semantics of an event modifier.<br />

• CAUSE <strong>de</strong>scribes a semantic operation; whether it may attach to a particular stem<br />

or root is a matter of semantic compatibility, not syntactic selection. CAUSE selects<br />

for roots, VPs or phases (xPs) (cf. Pylkkänen 2007).<br />

In Somali, causative verb stems involve merger of CAUSE to the root, not to the unaccusative<br />

verb (vP): the causative -i suffix can affect the vowel or consonant of the root<br />

before the point of the <strong>de</strong>rivation when the xP is sent to PF → it must be attached within<br />

the xP phase, i.e. before the point of the <strong>de</strong>rivation when the theme becomes a noun or a<br />

verb (see 12).<br />

(11) a. √ XANUUN ‘pain’ + i → xanuuji- (palatalization: see Bendjaballah 1998)<br />

xanúun (m) ‘pain’<br />

xanuun- (intr.) ‘be in pain’ (both stative)<br />

xanuujín (f) ‘act of inflicting a pain’<br />

xanúuji (tr.) ‘hurt’<br />

b. √ JAB ‘break’ + i → jebi-(vowel assimilation)<br />

jáb (m) ‘fragment’<br />

jab- (intr.) ‘break’<br />

jabíd (f) ‘break’(names an event of change of state)<br />

jébi (tr.) ‘break’<br />

jébis (m), jebín (f) ‘act of breaking’<br />

c. √ JOOG ‘stay’ + i → jooji- (palatalisation)<br />

jóog (m) ‘stay’<br />

jooji- (tr.) ‘bring to a stop’<br />

joojín (f) / jóojis (m) ‘act of stopping s.o/th’<br />

(12) Root-selecting CAUSE: n/vP<br />

n/vROOT CAUSE<br />

Denominal verbs (agentive activity verbs <strong>de</strong>rived from nouns) involve merger of CAUSE to<br />

a phase head (nP). The -i suffix in (13) is attached above the domain of the phonological<br />

rule → palatalization does not occur.<br />

(13) a. tifíq (f) ‘drop’ → tifqi- ‘cause to drip’ (tr.)


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 9<br />

b. fáraq (m) ‘fringe’ → farqi- ‘put a fringe on’<br />

(14) nP-selecting CAUSE:<br />

2.5 CAUSE and agentivity<br />

nP CAUSE<br />

n ROOT<br />

→ What is nee<strong>de</strong>d in a transitive nominalization is a CAUSE head, not a Voice head.<br />

• Causative uses have a wi<strong>de</strong> range of meanings. ‘Special meanings’ are realized with<br />

causative morphology, even though they do not have any agentive (or obviously<br />

causative) meaning (e.g. kac- ‘rise’; kici- ‘rouse’; kicínta códka ‘the accentuation of<br />

the vowel’).<br />

• CAUSE is semantically in<strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>nt from Voice (in Finnish, Japanese, Somali...<br />

causative heads are in<strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>nt of the Voice head as well).<br />

• CAUSE is a relation between two events; a theta-role (e.g. ‘agent’) is a relation between<br />

an individual and an event (cf. Pylkkänen 2007). The semantics of DESTROY<br />

requires an external causer, but an ‘external causer’ is not a projected argument.<br />

→ Agent interpretation is <strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>nt on CAUSE, but not vice versa: agent arguments then<br />

must be merged higher than CAUSE.<br />

→ if we combine this with the assumption that the external argument is introduced by<br />

APPL (see above), we get a syntactic tree where the predicate CAUSE first merges with<br />

the root <strong>de</strong>scribing the caused event; APPL then the relates a ‘possessor’ to the event<br />

introduced by CAUSE.<br />

(15)<br />

Poss-Agent<br />

APPL<br />

n<br />

CAUSE Root


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 10<br />

The structural source of the external argument is APPL, agentive interpretation (external<br />

causer) is <strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>nt on CAUSE. The causative meaning applies first, so that the external<br />

argument can then be related to the causing (rather than the caused) event.<br />

→ If agent arguments in nominalizations were introduced by Voice, they would have to<br />

occur in the ‘possessor’ argument position. In Somali (at least), this is not the case:<br />

(16) a. Diyaarín-ta cáshar-ka (ee Máryan) waa wanaagsán tahay<br />

preparation-<strong>de</strong>fF lecture-<strong>de</strong>fM (and Maryan) F/C good<br />

The preparation of the lecture (by Mary) is good<br />

f-is<br />

b. cáshar-ka diyaarín-tiisa<br />

(ee Máryan)<br />

lecture-<strong>de</strong>fM preparation-<strong>de</strong>fF.Poss3MS (and Maryan)<br />

the lecture’s preparation (by Mary)<br />

c. *Máryan diyaarín-teeda (ee) cáshar-ka<br />

Maryan preparation-<strong>de</strong>fF.poss3F (and) lecture-<strong>de</strong>fM<br />

Maryan’s preparation of the lecture<br />

d. Máryan cashar-diyaarín-teeda (waa wanaagsán tahay)<br />

Maryan lecture-preparation-<strong>de</strong>fF.Poss3F (F/C good<br />

Maryan’s (way of) preparing lectures (is good)<br />

f-is<br />

Incorporating the theme argument (cáshar) forces the agent in the ‘possessor’ position, but<br />

the structure is not ‘eventive’ in an episodic sense (no existential reading of the incorporated<br />

noun) → cashar-diyaarínta is an ‘action type’ - a kind of preparation, with possibly<br />

spatiotemporally discontinuous manifestations (e.g., <strong>de</strong>noting the set of Maryan’s lecture<br />

notes) - or may have a result interpretation.<br />

2.6 ‘Deverbal’ agentive nouns<br />

English -er nominals are not necessarily agentive (Rappaport Hovav & Levin 1992 a. o.)<br />

The ‘<strong>de</strong>verbal’ agentive nominal analysis (i.e., root and verbalizing head combine and are<br />

subsequently nominalized by n) has problems as well, since the requirement that an object<br />

be present is not met.<br />

→ Somali agentive -é formation does not involve an affix creating a verb, but involves a<br />

possibly null, uncategorized CAUSE affix. CAUSE introduces event semantics within the<br />

nP, but the event involved is only a ‘potential’ (not existentially bound) event.<br />

(17) a. ‘Lexical’ causatives - overt CAUSE suffix (-i):<br />

arrín (f) ‘problem, affair’<br />

arrimi- ‘make a <strong>de</strong>cision’ (tr.)


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 11<br />

arrimi-(y)é (m) ‘director’<br />

fáal (m) ‘omen’<br />

falli- ‘take omens, tell s.o. fortune’<br />

falli-(y)é (m) ‘fortune teller’<br />

xóog (m) ‘strength’<br />

xooji- ‘strengthen’ (tr.)<br />

xooji-(y)é (m) ‘reinforcer, amplifier’<br />

búrbur (m) ‘fragment’<br />

burburi- ‘<strong>de</strong>stroy’ (tr.)<br />

burburi-(y)é (m) ‘<strong>de</strong>stroyer, bulldozer’<br />

duul- ‘fly’ (intr.)<br />

duuli- ‘cause to fly, pilot’ (tr.)<br />

duuli-(y)é (m) ‘pilot (of airplane)’<br />

xiríir (m) ‘relationship’<br />

xiriiri- ‘link together’ (tr.)<br />

xiriiri-(y)é (m) ‘conjunction (grammar)’<br />

b. ‘Lexical’ causatives - ‘inherent’ CAUSE suffix: (action verbs/nouns)<br />

fál (m) ‘action’<br />

fal- ‘do, act’<br />

falé (m) ‘one who acts, doer; subject (grammar)’<br />

fur- ‘open’ (tr.)<br />

furé (m) ‘opener, key’<br />

díl (m) ‘mur<strong>de</strong>r’<br />

dil- ‘kill’ (tr.)<br />

dil-é (m) ‘killer’<br />

bar- ‘teach’<br />

bar-é (m) ‘teacher’


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 12<br />

(18)<br />

RootP n<br />

é<br />

Root CAUSE<br />

D<br />

At the point of the <strong>de</strong>rivation where n is merged, no ‘verbalizing head’ is involved in the<br />

structure. The ‘agentive’ nominal is interpreted as an ‘external causer’, but no agent is<br />

projected.<br />

→ There are <strong>de</strong>nominal verb formation (the class of <strong>de</strong>nominal verbs laugh, cough, cry<br />

(Halle & Keyser 1993) = ‘verbalizations’, but are there (true) ‘nominalizations’?<br />

Conclusions<br />

Nominals (and nominalizations) involve an articulated event structure, but the relevant<br />

structure fundamentally does not have a ‘verbalizing’ function (cf. Alexiadou 1999, contra<br />

Borer 2003).<br />

→ Event/argument structure does not always require the projection of a verbal constituent.<br />

Nominals (and nominalizations) introduce events semantics and their own event modifiers.<br />

→ Tense and event structure can be associated with nominals. There is no evi<strong>de</strong>nce for<br />

the fact that the argument structure of nominalizations comes from a structure external<br />

to the nominal itself (cf. Chomsky 1970).<br />

3 References<br />

Abney, Steven Paul. 1987, The English Noun Phrase in its Sentential Aspect. Doctoral<br />

Dissertation, MIT.<br />

Alexiadou, Artemis. 1999. On the syntax of nominalization and possession: Remarks on<br />

patterns of ergativity. Habititation, University of Postdam.<br />

Bendjaballah, Sabrina. 1998. La palatalisation en somali. <strong>Linguistique</strong> africaine, 21, 5-52.<br />

Bohnemeyer, J. 2002. The Grammar of Time Reference in Yukatek Maya. Lincom Europa,.<br />

Munich.<br />

Borer, Hagit. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. Endo-skeletal Explanations: Syntactic Projections<br />

and the Lexicon, in M. Polinsky and J. Moore (eds.) The Nature of Explanation in Linguistic<br />

Theory. Chicago : CSLI and. University of Chicago Press.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 13<br />

Carlson, Gregory. 1982. Generic terms and generic sentences. Journal of Philosophical<br />

logic 11, 14: 145-181.<br />

Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on nominalizations. In Studies on Semantics in Generative<br />

Grammar, The Hague: Mouton 1972, 11-61.<br />

Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Kem Hale: A life in Language, ed.<br />

Michael Kenstovicz, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Chomsky, Noam. 2008. On Phases. In Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays<br />

in honor of Jean-Roger Verganud, ed. Carlos Otero, Robert Freidin, and Maria-Luisa<br />

Zubizarreta, 133-166. Cambridge: MIT Press.<br />

Fassi Fehri, Ab<strong>de</strong>lka<strong>de</strong>r. 2003. Verbal plurality, transitivity, and causativity. In Lecarme,<br />

Jacqueline (ed.), Research in Afroasiatic Grammar II, 151-185.<br />

Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press<br />

Hale, Kenneth and Samuel J. Keyser. 1993. Argument structure and the lexical expression<br />

of syntactic relations. In Hale, Kenneth and Samuel J. Keyser (eds.), The View from<br />

Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Hornor of Sylvain Bromberger. 111-176, Cambidge,<br />

MA: MIT Press.<br />

Harley, Heidi and Rolf Noyer. 1998. Mixed nominalizations, object shift, and short verb<br />

movement in English. Proceedings of NELS 28, University of Massachusetts-Amherst:<br />

GLSA. ames T.<br />

Higginbotham, James. 1983. The Logic of Perceptual Reports: An Extensional Alternative<br />

to Situation Semantics. Journal of Philosophy 80: 100-127.<br />

Hiraiwa, Ken. 2005. Dimensions of symmetry in syntax: agreement and clausal architecture.<br />

Doctoral dissertstion, MIT.<br />

Jackendoff, Ray. 1983. Semantics and cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.<br />

Kratzer, Angelika. 1988. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In M. Krifka (ed.)<br />

Generiticy in Natural Language. Tubingen.<br />

Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Johan Rooryck<br />

and Laurie Ann Zaring, eds., Phrase Structure and the Lexicon, 109-137. Kluwer, Dordrecht.<br />

Kratzer, Angelika. 2007. On the Plurality of Verbs. In J. Dölling, T. Hey<strong>de</strong>-Zybatow<br />

and M. Schäfer (eds.), Event Structures in Linguistic Form and Interpretation, Mouton <strong>de</strong><br />

Gruyter, Berlin.<br />

Krifka, Manfred. 1992. Thematic relations as links between nominal reference and temporal<br />

constitution. In: Ivan Sag and Anna Szabolsci (eds.) Lexical Matters. CSLI/ University<br />

of Chicago Press.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 14<br />

Larson, Richard. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19, 335-391.<br />

Lecarme, Jacqueline. 1996. Tense in the nominal system: The Somali DP, in J. Lecarme,<br />

J. Lowenstamm & U. Shlonsky (eds), Research in Afroasiatic Grammar, Selected papers<br />

from the Second Conference on Afroasiatic Languages, Sophia Antipolis 1994, pp. 159-178.<br />

The Hague: Holland Aca<strong>de</strong>mic Graphics.<br />

Lecarme, Jacqueline. 1999. Nominal tense and tense theory. In Francic Corblin, Carmen<br />

Dobrovie-Sorin and Jean-Marie Marandin (eds), Empirical Issues in Formal Syntax and<br />

Semantics 2, Selected papers from CSSP 1997, The Hague: Thesus.<br />

Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2003. Nominal tense and evi<strong>de</strong>ntiality. In Jacqueline Guéron and<br />

Liliane Tasmovski (eds), Tense and Point of View. Presses <strong>de</strong> l’Université <strong>de</strong> Nanterre.<br />

Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2004. Tense in nominals. In Jacqueline Guéron and Jacqueline<br />

Lecarme (eds), The Syntax of Time, pages 441-475. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2008. Tense and Modality in Nominals. In Jacqueline Guéron and<br />

Jacqueline Lecarme (eds), Time and Modality, Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic<br />

Theory, Springer.<br />

Link, Go<strong>de</strong>hard. 1983. The logical analysis of plural and mass terms: a lattice theoretic<br />

approach. In R. Bauerle, Ch. Schwarze and A. von Stechow (eds.), Meaning, Use and<br />

Interpretation of Language. Berlin: <strong>de</strong> Gruyter.<br />

Marantz, Alec. 1984. On the nature of grammatical relations. Cambridge, Mass: MIT<br />

Press.<br />

Marantz, Alec. 1996. ‘Cat’ as a Phrasal Idiom. Ms, MIT.<br />

Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: don’t try the morphological analysis in the<br />

privacy of your own lexicon, In Alexis Dimitriadis et al. (eds), Proceedings of the 21th<br />

Pemn Colloquium: Penn Working Papers in Linguistics 2:4, 201-225.<br />

Marantz, Alec. 2008. Phases and words. In Sook-Hee Choe (ed) Phases in the theory of<br />

Grammar, 191-222. Seoul: Dong In.<br />

Marvin, Tatiana. 2002. Topics in the stress and syntax of words. Doctoral dissertation,<br />

MIT.<br />

Matthewson, Lisa. 2000. On Distributivity and Pluractionality. In B. Jackson and T.<br />

Matthews (eds) Proceedings of SALT 10. Ithaca/N.Y., CLC Publications.<br />

Newman, Paul. 1990. Nominal and verbal plurality in Chadic. Foris, Dordrecht.<br />

Ojeda, Almerindo. 1998. The semantics of collectives and distributives in Papago. Natural<br />

Language Semantics 6: 245-270.


Jacqueline Lecarme<br />

On tensed nominalizations 15<br />

Parsons, Terence. 1990. Events in the Semantics of English: A Study of Subatimic Semantics.<br />

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Pesetsky, David. 1995. Zero Syntax: Experiencers and casca<strong>de</strong>s. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT<br />

Press.<br />

Pesetsky, David and Esther Torrego. 2001. T-to-C: Causes and Consequences, in M.<br />

Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in Language. Cambridge: MIT Press.<br />

Pylkkänen, Liina. 2007. Introducing arguments. Cambridge: MIT Press. [2002 Doctoral<br />

dissertation, MIT]<br />

Prior, Arthur. 1968. Change in events and change in things. Papers on Time and Tense,<br />

Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Rappaport Hovav, Malka and Beth Levin. 1992. -er nominals: Implications for a theory<br />

of argument structure. In Tim Stowell and Eric Wehrli (eds), SYntax and Semantics 26:<br />

Syntax and the Lexicon, Aca<strong>de</strong>mic Press, New York, 127-153.<br />

Roehrs, Dorian. 2009. Demonstratives and <strong>de</strong>finite articles as nominal auxiliaries. John<br />

Benjamins.<br />

Schwartz, Florian. 2009. Two types of <strong>de</strong>finites in natural language. Doctoral Dissertation,<br />

UMass Amherst.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!