05.08.2013 Views

Survey 1979: Equational Logic - Department of Mathematics ...

Survey 1979: Equational Logic - Department of Mathematics ...

Survey 1979: Equational Logic - Department of Mathematics ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

WALTER TAYLOR 13<br />

(2,1) is obviously not intrinsic to the idea <strong>of</strong> a group. Many <strong>of</strong> the properties<br />

considered below are (obviously) equivalence-invariant, but a few, such as being<br />

"one-based" (õ10) are not, as we shall see, comparing 10.3 and 10.10 below.<br />

Moreover, certain results cannot even be stated without mentioning equivalence (14.2<br />

and 14.5 below).<br />

It is possible to define equational classes so as to make all expressable properties<br />

automatically equivalence-invariant, i.e. to give no preference to any <strong>of</strong> the possible<br />

equivalent forms <strong>of</strong> a given variety. This amounts to considering the set (rather than a<br />

sequence (Ft)tCT) <strong>of</strong> all possible operations defined by V-terms. This idea goes back<br />

to P. Hall (see [91, pages 126-132] ), and has been worked out independently in detail<br />

by W. D. Neumann [332] and F. W. Lawvere [254] (see page 362 <strong>of</strong> [420] for more<br />

detailed historical remarks, and pages 390-392 for a pro<strong>of</strong>- independently found by<br />

W. Felscher - <strong>of</strong> the equivalence <strong>of</strong> these two approaches). Some <strong>of</strong> these ideas were<br />

presented independently by Claude Chevalley in a speech at Stanford in November,<br />

1962. Certainly Lawvere's approach came much sooner than Neumann's and has<br />

obtained a much wider following. We will not describe his invention, "algebraic<br />

theories," except to say that they contain precisely the right amount <strong>of</strong> information<br />

to describe varieties without allowing any individual operations to play a special role.<br />

For further references see [420, loc. cit.]; see also [272].<br />

Despite some enthusiastic claims (see e.g. the dustjacket or Chapter 3 <strong>of</strong> [346] or<br />

[443, page 121]) that these category-theoretic ideas would take over the study <strong>of</strong><br />

universal algebra, this hasn't really happened by <strong>1979</strong>. Their significant role, so far,<br />

has been to suggest analogies outside pure algebra (e.g. compact Hausdorff spaces).<br />

But they have had almost no impact yet in the study <strong>of</strong> ordinary varieties (i.e. the<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> subjects discussed in this survey), with one interesting exception: the study <strong>of</strong><br />

Malcev conditions (õ 15 below) was facilitated by viewing it as a study <strong>of</strong> morphisms<br />

between algebraic theories (see [420] and [427] ). Other possible directions are given in<br />

[347], [40], [58], and [244]. Some useful remarks are found in Lawvere [255]. The<br />

reason that direct application <strong>of</strong> "algebraic theories" to equational logic is difficult (or<br />

unnecessary) lies mostly in its model theory; to see this, let us notice (as many others<br />

have before) that the passage

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!