25.07.2013 Views

Trust Formation in New Organizational Relationships - MISRC ...

Trust Formation in New Organizational Relationships - MISRC ...

Trust Formation in New Organizational Relationships - MISRC ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

TRUST FORMATION IN NEW ORGANIZATIONAL RELATIONSHIPS<br />

D. HARRISON MCKNIGHT<br />

LARRY L. CUMMINGS<br />

NORMAN L. CHERVANY<br />

University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota--Curtis L. Carlson School of Management<br />

395 Hubert H. Humphrey Center<br />

271-19th Avenue South<br />

M<strong>in</strong>neapolis, MN 55455<br />

Direct all correspondence to D. Harrison McKnight<br />

hmcknight@csom.umn.edu<br />

Acknowledgements: The authors wish to express appreciation to Shawn Curley, Fred<br />

Davis, Gerald Smith and Aks Zaheer for their helpful reviews and comments on earlier<br />

versions of this paper.<br />

ABSTRACT:<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> is a key enabler of cooperative human actions. Three ma<strong>in</strong> deficiencies about<br />

our current knowledge of trust are addressed by this paper. First, due to widely<br />

divergent conceptual def<strong>in</strong>itions of trust, the literature on trust is <strong>in</strong> a state of construct<br />

confusion. Second, too little is understood about how trust forms and on what trust is<br />

based. Third, little has been discussed about the role of emotion <strong>in</strong> trust formation.<br />

To address the first deficiency, this paper develops a typology of trust. The rest of the<br />

paper addresses the second and third deficiencies by propos<strong>in</strong>g a model of how trust is<br />

<strong>in</strong>itially formed,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the role of emotion. Dispositional, <strong>in</strong>terpersonal, and impersonal (system)<br />

trust are <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong> the model. The paper also clarifies the cognitive and emotional<br />

bases on which <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust is formed <strong>in</strong> early relationships. The implications<br />

of the model are drawn for future research.


NOTE: This paper was presented by the first author <strong>in</strong> October, 1995 at the Information & Decision<br />

Sciences workshop, University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota.<br />

2


TRUST FORMATION IN NEW ORGANIZATIONAL RELATIONSHIPS<br />

INTRODUCTION<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> is widely acknowledged as an important concept to study because it enables<br />

many cooperative human endeavors (e.g. Dunn, 1988; Gambetta, 1988). It is a key to<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal relationships <strong>in</strong> various sett<strong>in</strong>gs (e.g. Arrow, 1974; Fox, 1974; Lewis &<br />

Weigert, 1985a). Yet trust received relatively little research attention until the 1970s<br />

(Luhmann, 1991). The literature on trust <strong>in</strong> various discipl<strong>in</strong>es has displayed<br />

<strong>in</strong>adequacies that fall <strong>in</strong>to three categories that relate to: trust def<strong>in</strong>ition, trust creation<br />

dynamics, and emotion. First, due to widely differ<strong>in</strong>g conceptual def<strong>in</strong>itions of trust,<br />

the literature on trust presents a confus<strong>in</strong>g picture of what trust is. Second, too little is<br />

understood about how trust forms and on what trust is based. Third, little has been<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>ed about the role of emotion <strong>in</strong> trust formation. Each of the three deficiencies<br />

is discussed. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a model is developed that addresses these problems.<br />

PROBLEM 1--CONCEPTUAL DEFINITION<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>itions of trust have become a "confus<strong>in</strong>g potpourri," (Shapiro, 1987a: 625), a<br />

"conceptual confusion" (Lewis & Weigert, 1985a: 975). They have proliferated <strong>in</strong><br />

divergent ways, and yet, <strong>in</strong> any given paper, are usually quite narrow (Kee & Knox,<br />

1970). This problem, termed homonymy, means that one label encompasses more<br />

than one concept. (Smith, 1990). The concept of trust fits this def<strong>in</strong>ition of<br />

homonymy. <strong>Trust</strong> has been def<strong>in</strong>ed as: a behavior (e.g., Zand, 1972); an attitude<br />

(Kegan & Rubenste<strong>in</strong>, 1973); a confidence (Cohen, 1966); an expectancy (Rotter,<br />

1980; Scanzoni, 1979); a belief or set of beliefs (Barber, 1983; Bromiley &<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995; Rotter, 1967); a dispositional variable (Rosenberg, 1957; Rotter,<br />

1967, 1980); a situational variable (Johnson-George & Swap, 1982); a structural<br />

variable (Fox, 1974; Lewis & Weigert, 1985a,b): a social agency relationship variable<br />

(Shapiro, 1987a); and, an <strong>in</strong>terpersonal variable (Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985).<br />

Some have discussed and described trust and its effects without specifically def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g it<br />

(Granovetter, 1985). Only a few researchers have attempted to display more than one<br />

3


of the dimensions of trust and how those relate to one another (Bromiley &<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995; Dob<strong>in</strong>g, 1993; Lewis & Weigert, 1985a,b; Luhmann, 1991; Zucker,<br />

1986). This raises the question: If one researcher def<strong>in</strong>es trust <strong>in</strong> a widely different<br />

way from another researcher, how can the theoretical formulations and the empirical<br />

results of researchers build on each other?<br />

One specific aspect of this problem is that study<strong>in</strong>g a s<strong>in</strong>gle narrow type of trust does<br />

not adequately capture the breadth of mean<strong>in</strong>g assigned to the word trust <strong>in</strong> everyday<br />

usage. To be effective, scientists should start with, or be grounded <strong>in</strong>, common terms<br />

(such as "trust"). Then they should strive "to extract from [common-sense<br />

psychology] the essence of everyday terms that lend themselves to [scientific<br />

psychology] uses." (Kelley, 1992:11) F<strong>in</strong>ally, the scientific terms should then be<br />

compared back to common terms to see whether they reflect the breadth of mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the common terms connote <strong>in</strong> everyday usage. The <strong>in</strong>terplay between common terms<br />

and scientific terms improves the practical applicability of the scientific and makes<br />

researchable the common. When scientific usages of the same common term diverge<br />

widely, researchers should re-evaluate the way the term has been used. Such<br />

dissatisfaction is manifest <strong>in</strong> the trust literature (Barber, 1983). For example, rather<br />

than us<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g trust conceptualizations, Mishra (1993) felt compelled to distill<br />

four specific dimensions of trust from the literature. Similarly, those study<strong>in</strong>g trust<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the Prisoner's Dilemma arena have recognized that "some of the everyday<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs of trust and trust<strong>in</strong>g behavior are, no doubt, not captured by [the Prisoner's<br />

Dilemma] framework." (Orbell, Dawes, and Schwartz-Shea, 1994:112). But what can<br />

be done about this problem? Van de Ven (1989: 487) warned that when theories on a<br />

topic widely diverge, the advocates "for each theory engage <strong>in</strong> activities to make their<br />

theory better by <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g its <strong>in</strong>ternal consistency, often at the expense of limit<strong>in</strong>g its<br />

scope...such impeccable micro logic is creat<strong>in</strong>g macro nonsense!" There is evidence<br />

that this is happen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the trust literature. 1 To counter such tendencies, Van de Ven<br />

1 For example, the various attempts <strong>in</strong> the psychology literature to divide and<br />

operationalize dispositional and situational trust are catalogued <strong>in</strong><br />

4


ecommended that scholars should "deal with the tensions, debates, and forced choices<br />

between overly narrow compet<strong>in</strong>g theories" by utiliz<strong>in</strong>g these "<strong>in</strong>consistencies and<br />

contradictions between theories...to develop better and more encompass<strong>in</strong>g theories."<br />

(1989: 488)<br />

We believe that this advice applies to the trust literature. The divergence of narrow<br />

trust def<strong>in</strong>itions provides motivation for improv<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical basis of the study of<br />

trust. If there are really several types of trust, what are they, and how do they fit<br />

together? The primary challenge, then, is to synthesize and def<strong>in</strong>e carefully the<br />

various types of trust and to demonstrate how they both differ from, and relate to, each<br />

other.<br />

PROBLEM 2--TRUST CREATION DYNAMICS<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> has usually been studied as a static, rather than a dynamic, variable (exceptions:<br />

Lewis & Weigert, 1985a,b; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985; Zucker, 1986). This may<br />

have occurred because of the preponderant use of experimental or cross-sectional<br />

research methods (e.g. Bonoma, 1976; Solomon, 1960). But the method should not<br />

drive the research stream. Rather, the methods should fit the phenomenon, and the<br />

trust phenomenon appears to be very dynamic. Here are some examples. The<br />

literature is full of statements to the effect that trust is "fragile" or easily destroyed<br />

(Baier, 1986; Dasgupta, 1988; Luhmann, 1991; McGregor, 1967). Some say trust<br />

takes a great deal of time to form (R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven, 1994). Others have found that<br />

it may form very quickly (McKnight, 1994). These arguments <strong>in</strong>dicate that trust<br />

should be viewed and studied as a dynamic construct. Add<strong>in</strong>g the time dimension<br />

should improve theory on trust (Poole & Van de Ven, 1989).<br />

Wrightsman (1991). At the same time, sociologists have been further ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

their own specific conceptualizations of trust (e.g., Barber, 1983; Luhmann,<br />

1991; Shapiro, 1987a). Further evidence that the psychological and<br />

sociological views are diverg<strong>in</strong>g is found <strong>in</strong> one major sociological work on<br />

trust, which assails the psychological conceptualization of trust (Lewis &<br />

Weigert, 1985b).<br />

5


Further, discussions about trust should not only answer the question of "what" results<br />

from trust, but should answer the question of "how" trust forms. Static approaches<br />

provide answers to the "what" questions, but do not adequately address "how" or<br />

"why" someth<strong>in</strong>g develops. The "what" questions have been researched for some time<br />

<strong>in</strong> the trust literature. It seems time to address the "how" questions. In addition to<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g our theoretical understand<strong>in</strong>g, this is important for a practical reason.<br />

Address<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

question of how trust develops will <strong>in</strong>crease the ability for researchers to derive<br />

practical prescriptions. Hence, this paper addresses the question: How does trust<br />

develop at the onset of a relationship, and on what is it based?<br />

PROBLEM 3--ROLE OF EMOTION<br />

The role of emotion <strong>in</strong> trust formation has not been fully addressed (Lewis & Weigert,<br />

1985a). Scholars have long recognized the important role of emotional security for<br />

trust (Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985). For example, Luhmann (1991) has po<strong>in</strong>ted<br />

out that the role of emotion is critical <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g how, and under what<br />

circumstances trust turns to distrust (Luhmann, 1991). Still, a large gap rema<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Although scholars like Lewis &<br />

Weigert (1985b) have asserted that emotion is important to trust, they have not<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>ed emotion's role <strong>in</strong> trust formation <strong>in</strong> the earliest stages of a relationship.<br />

Instead, they have assumed that <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust "is ma<strong>in</strong>ly cognitive and<br />

assumptive" (Lewis & Weigert, 1985b: 466). The question addressed here is: What is<br />

the role of emotion <strong>in</strong> the formation of trust <strong>in</strong> new relationships?<br />

SECTION 1: A TYPOLOGY OF TRUST-RELATED CONCEPTS<br />

A typology of types of trust concepts is def<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>in</strong> order to provide an overview of<br />

how to dist<strong>in</strong>guish one type from another. In Section 2, each type of trust will be<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> terms of a model propos<strong>in</strong>g how several of these types form a foundation<br />

for other types. Collectively, Sections 1 and 2 address Problem 1 above by<br />

6


synthesiz<strong>in</strong>g the divergent def<strong>in</strong>itions of trust <strong>in</strong>to a comprehensive set of<br />

cognitive/emotional constructs that fit together and yet can be dist<strong>in</strong>guished from one<br />

another. The typology is not fully comprehensive; it does not cover every type of trust<br />

<strong>in</strong> the literature. The types of trust this paper addresses have been selected to cover<br />

what the authors consider the more important forms of trust, such that a broad, but<br />

parsimonious group of constructs emerges.<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> as a behavior is excluded because of the difficulty of dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g it from other<br />

concepts such as cooperation and <strong>in</strong>formation shar<strong>in</strong>g openness, which have<br />

sometimes been called trust (e.g., Mishra, 1993). In game theory research, for<br />

example, the act of not defect<strong>in</strong>g may be called a "trust<strong>in</strong>g behavior;" but it may also<br />

be called "cooperation'"or "cooperative behavior." Call<strong>in</strong>g it "trust<strong>in</strong>g behavior"<br />

makes clear the assumption that the act of not defect<strong>in</strong>g is based on some set of trust-<br />

related cognitions/emotions; but this does not clearly dist<strong>in</strong>guish the act from<br />

cooperation. The question that can be asked is, "wouldn't it be more accurate to call<br />

this behavior a consequent of trust, rather than trust itself?" Because the act of reliance<br />

or dependence on<br />

another seems to be the essence of trust<strong>in</strong>g, some have equated trust with dependence<br />

or reliance (e.g., Giff<strong>in</strong>, 1967). The weakness of this def<strong>in</strong>ition is that reliance is only<br />

one of a number of behaviors that demonstrate cognitive/emotional trust. It would be<br />

very difficult to agree on a list of all the types of behaviors that are manifestations of<br />

trust. Even if scholars could agree on the list, the task of dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g these trust<strong>in</strong>g<br />

behaviors from their common usage terms (e.g., cooperation, helpfulness, openness)<br />

would<br />

be daunt<strong>in</strong>g. Therefore, we do not here deal with behavioral trust. We dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

such behaviors from (cognitive/emotional) trust by treat<strong>in</strong>g them as behavioral<br />

manifestations of what we call trust. Five trust-related constructs are def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> this<br />

section: <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust, trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs, system trust, dispositional trust and<br />

decision to trust. These concepts will be def<strong>in</strong>ed and dist<strong>in</strong>guished from each other<br />

largely based on the dimensions shown <strong>in</strong> Table 1.<br />

7


--------------------------------<br />

Insert Table 1 about here<br />

--------------------------------<br />

8


INTERPERSONAL TRUST<br />

We def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust as one party's will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on the other party<br />

with a feel<strong>in</strong>g of relative security even though negative consequences are possible.<br />

Interpersonal trust is a person-specific concept; one person is ready to depend on a<br />

specific other person. It is a situation-specific concept; it applies <strong>in</strong> a specific<br />

situation. Interpersonal trust is an <strong>in</strong>tentional state; the person is will<strong>in</strong>g (or ready or<br />

plann<strong>in</strong>g) to depend on<br />

the other <strong>in</strong> the situation. For simplicity, the follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion will refer to only one<br />

side of the <strong>in</strong>terpersonal dyad. Further, we will use the unmodified term "trust" to<br />

mean <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust.Our def<strong>in</strong>ition of trust embodies three essential elements<br />

found <strong>in</strong> the trust literature: (a) potential negative consequences, (b) dependence, and<br />

(c)<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security:<br />

(a) The prospect of negative consequences (Bonoma, 1976; Gambetta, 1988; Good,<br />

1988; Luhmann, 1988; Mishra, 1993; Zand, 1972) is what makes trust important but<br />

problematic. Some researchers refer to the possibility of negative consequences as<br />

risk (Coleman, 1990; Giff<strong>in</strong>, 1967; Johnson-George & Swap, 1982; Luhmann, 1991;<br />

Riker, 1971; Scanzoni, 1979; Shapiro, 1987a; Sw<strong>in</strong>th, 1967), while others describe it<br />

as uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty (Deutsch, 1973; Gambetta, 1988; Schlenker, Helm & Tedeschi, 1973) .<br />

In each case, scholars believe that when negative results are possible, successful<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction requires trust.<br />

(b) <strong>Trust</strong> <strong>in</strong>volves dependence on another party. A number of researchers refer to trust<br />

as a dependence (Atwater, 1988; Dob<strong>in</strong>g, 1993; Lewis & Weigert, 1985b; Scanzoni,<br />

1979) or reliance (Giff<strong>in</strong>, 1967; Good, 1988; McGregor, 1967; R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven,<br />

1994) upon others. If one is not required to depend on the other, one does not need to<br />

trust the other. The word "depend" is also important because it l<strong>in</strong>ks trust to the power<br />

literature. Astley & Zajac (1991: 399) po<strong>in</strong>t out that Emerson def<strong>in</strong>ed dependence as<br />

the "obverse of power." That is, one who becomes dependent on another party places<br />

the other party <strong>in</strong> a<br />

9


position of power over her/him. S<strong>in</strong>ce trust means a will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend, one who<br />

trusts is will<strong>in</strong>g to place the other person <strong>in</strong> a situational position of power over<br />

him/her. The trust literature has already noted the <strong>in</strong>terplay between trust and power<br />

(Solomon, 1960; Bonoma, 1976). However, trust and power have not previously<br />

been l<strong>in</strong>ked def<strong>in</strong>itionally.<br />

(c) To trust, the person fac<strong>in</strong>g negative consequences must be will<strong>in</strong>g to depend on<br />

the other person with feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security (Lewis & Weigert, 1985b; Rempel, Holmes<br />

& Zanna, 1985), comfort (Eayrs, 1993), confidence (Deutsch, 1973; Dunn, 1988;<br />

Rempel,<br />

Holmes & Zanna, 1985; Luhmann, 1991; McGregor, 1976; R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven, 1994;<br />

Scanzoni, 1979), or lack of fear (Bradach & Eccles, 1989). These feel<strong>in</strong>gs dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

trust from a less secure will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend, which would be characterized by<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>gs of<br />

anxiety or fear. This aspect of trust is an emotional component, whereas the<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional aspect of trust is a cognitive component. The emotional aspect and the<br />

cognitive <strong>in</strong>tention are <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed; a person feels secure with respect to her/his<br />

will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend.<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> is dist<strong>in</strong>guished from will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on another based upon control of the<br />

other. Riker (1971:66) said, "If one has power over other people,...then one can by<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition control events, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g them to a desired conclusion. In this sense the man<br />

of power need not trust others to do what he wants because he can coerce them<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead." 2 This dist<strong>in</strong>ction rests on the idea that the person who trusts another must<br />

"trust trust" (Gambetta, 1988: 213, 228) or "rely on trust" (R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven,<br />

1994:93) and not solely depend on control mechanisms. For example, a supervisor<br />

who monitors an<br />

2 This does not mean that control mechanisms are irrelevant. Indeed, such<br />

mechanisms may facilitate trust (Dasgupta, 1988). However, one party cannot<br />

fully control the other. This dist<strong>in</strong>ction has also been drawn <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itions of<br />

cooperation (Williams, 1988).<br />

10


employee by video camera depends on the camera for assurance of the employee's<br />

good behavior. Hence, the supervisor is not will<strong>in</strong>g to depend on the employee to<br />

behave properly. Therefore, based on our def<strong>in</strong>ition, the supervisor does not really<br />

trust the employee.<br />

TRUSTING BELIEFS<br />

<strong>Trust</strong>, as is typical of <strong>in</strong>tentions (Fishbe<strong>in</strong> & Ajzen, 1975), is based upon the person's<br />

cognitive beliefs about the other person (Bromiley & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995; Gabarro,<br />

1978) and the person's emotional security about those beliefs. Together, these<br />

cognitive beliefs and the related emotional security form a construct we call trust<strong>in</strong>g<br />

beliefs. Beliefs about the other person means that one person believes that the other<br />

person is trustworthy <strong>in</strong> the situation. Therefore, this construct is shown as person-<br />

and situation-specific <strong>in</strong> Table 1. Beliefs about the other person's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess,<br />

based on the trust literature, 3 <strong>in</strong>clude beliefs that the other person possesses such<br />

attributes as benevolence, 4 honesty, 5 competence, 6 and predictability. 7 In other<br />

research, these beliefs are often referred to as<br />

3 A review of the trust literature reveals that the most common belief<br />

components <strong>in</strong> trust def<strong>in</strong>itions can be <strong>in</strong>formally clustered as follows. The<br />

word "cite" refers to the number of articles or books on trust, of a possible 79<br />

reviewed, that <strong>in</strong>clude this type of trust <strong>in</strong> their description of what trust is.<br />

(a) Benevolence (car<strong>in</strong>g, goodwill, not opportunistic/self-<strong>in</strong>terested,<br />

favorable motives/<strong>in</strong>tentions, fiduciary responsibility) --35 cites<br />

(b) Honesty (honesty, <strong>in</strong>tegrity, credibility, reliability, dependability)--27 cites<br />

(c) Competence (competent, skilled expert, efficacious)--15 cites<br />

(d) Predictability --12 cites<br />

4 Benevolence is perhaps best captured by Gambetta's def<strong>in</strong>ition: "...trust<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

person means believ<strong>in</strong>g that when offered the chance, he or she is not likely<br />

to behave <strong>in</strong> a way that is damag<strong>in</strong>g to us..." (1988:219). Others mention<strong>in</strong>g<br />

forms of benevolence <strong>in</strong>clude: Bradach & Eccles, 1989; Bromiley &<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995; Deutsch, 1958; Dunn, 1988; Larzelere & Huston, 1980;<br />

Pellegr<strong>in</strong>o, 1991; R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven, 1994.<br />

5 For example: Barber, 1983; Blakeney, 1986; Bromiley & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995;<br />

Cooprider & Victor, 1993; Johnson-George & Swap, 1982; Larzelere & Huston,<br />

1980; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985; R<strong>in</strong>g & Van de Ven, 1994; Worchel,<br />

1979.<br />

6 For example: Barber, 1983; Blakeney, 1986; Dob<strong>in</strong>g, 1993; Giff<strong>in</strong>, 1967;<br />

11


trust itself. We propose that such beliefs form the core cognitive concept that is<br />

manifest <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions to trust, which <strong>in</strong> turn are manifest <strong>in</strong> trust<strong>in</strong>g behaviors.<br />

<strong>Trust</strong><strong>in</strong>g beliefs also encompass belief-related emotional security. This refers to the<br />

level of security one possesses <strong>in</strong> one's beliefs about the other person. The term<br />

"emotion" is used primarily <strong>in</strong> the sense of feel<strong>in</strong>gs, based on cognitive evaluation and<br />

assignment of positive or negative values (Berscheid, 1983: 123) to the object of those<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

SYSTEM TRUST<br />

System trust is the belief that proper impersonal structures are <strong>in</strong> place to enable one<br />

to anticipate a successful future endeavor. Impersonal structures <strong>in</strong>clude such<br />

safeguards as regulations, guarantees, or contracts. System trust may also refer to<br />

belief <strong>in</strong> the proper structure of one's own role and others' roles <strong>in</strong> the situation. But, it<br />

is not specific to a person. System trust does, however, relate to a specific situation<br />

and its context.<br />

System trust is based on the effectiveness of social structures <strong>in</strong> reduc<strong>in</strong>g uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty<br />

and provid<strong>in</strong>g foundations for secure feel<strong>in</strong>gs about the future (Luhmann, 1991; Lewis<br />

& Weigert, 1985a; Shapiro, 1987b). For example, Zucker (1986) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that much<br />

of the personal-based trust of the 1700s and early 1800s <strong>in</strong> the United States was<br />

displaced <strong>in</strong> the late 1800s because the populace became much more heterogeneous<br />

through immigration. Hence, it became necessary for system trust--trust <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions<br />

(e.g., banks, courts, regulations, professional associations) --to fill <strong>in</strong> for the absence of<br />

personal<br />

trust.<br />

DISPOSITIONAL TRUST<br />

Mishra, 1993; Pellegr<strong>in</strong>o, 1991; Sitk<strong>in</strong> & Roth, 1993.<br />

7 For example: Deutsch, 1958; Giff<strong>in</strong>, 1967; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985.<br />

12


To this po<strong>in</strong>t, we have treated trust as a situational variable. But it can also be viewed<br />

as a cross-situational, cross-personal variable (e.g. Deutsch, 1973; Harnett &<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1980; Wrightsman, 1991). Def<strong>in</strong>itionally, a person has dispositional trust<br />

if s/he has a consistent tendency to trust across a broad spectrum of situations and<br />

persons. There are two types of reason<strong>in</strong>g that underly dispositional trust. The first is<br />

that one assumes that others are generally trustworthy people--hence, one should<br />

usually trust others. The second is that one assumes that irrespective of whether<br />

people are good or not, one will obta<strong>in</strong> better outcomes by trust<strong>in</strong>g them--hence, one<br />

should trust them.<br />

DECISION TO TRUST<br />

Decision to trust differs from dispositional trust <strong>in</strong> that it is an <strong>in</strong>tentional construct and<br />

relates to specific situations. It means that one has formed an <strong>in</strong>tention to trust every<br />

time a particular situation arises, irrespective of beliefs about the attributes of the other<br />

party <strong>in</strong> the situation. Like the second type of dispositional trust, it means that a<br />

person has decided to trust because the benefits of trust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this situation outweigh<br />

the risks associated with trust<strong>in</strong>g. The difference between decision to trust and<br />

dispositional trust is that decision to trust is limited to a situation, whereas<br />

dispositional trust goes across many situations. Decision to trust is different from<br />

system trust <strong>in</strong> that it is an <strong>in</strong>tention, not a set of beliefs.<br />

DISTRUST CONSTRUCTS<br />

Although this paper focuses on the positive side of trust, we do occasionally discuss<br />

the negative side. Distrust will be discussed <strong>in</strong> relation to one of the mechanisms that<br />

creates it and <strong>in</strong> terms of trust's fragility. Each of the above trust constructs has its<br />

distrust opposite. These are probably separate constructs rather than just ly<strong>in</strong>g at the<br />

far end of the same scale as trust (Bromiley & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995). They are def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

here briefly such that, for simplicity, their def<strong>in</strong>itions mirror those of the trust<br />

constructs. Interpersonal distrust means that one is not will<strong>in</strong>g to depend on the other<br />

party with a feel<strong>in</strong>g of relative security <strong>in</strong> a situation <strong>in</strong> which negative consequences<br />

13


are possible. Distrust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs means that one believes that the other person is not<br />

trustworthy <strong>in</strong> the situation--not benevolent, honest, competent and/or predictable.<br />

System distrust means one believes that impersonal structures that will enable one to<br />

be successful are not <strong>in</strong> place.<br />

Dispositional distrust means one has a tendency to distrust across a broad spectrum of<br />

situations and persons. Decision not to trust means that one has made a decision to<br />

distrust <strong>in</strong> a particular situation, irrespective of beliefs about the attributes of the other.<br />

SECTION 1 CONCLUSION<br />

Lewis & Weigert (1985a) called trust a highly complex and multi-dimensional<br />

phenomenon. Harrison White (1992: 174) said, "<strong>Trust</strong> is itself a term for a cluster<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of perceptions." The above set of def<strong>in</strong>itions help address Problem 1 by represent<strong>in</strong>g<br />

trust as a set of constructs <strong>in</strong>stead of limit<strong>in</strong>g it to one narrow type. This trust<br />

typology is appropriate <strong>in</strong> terms of coverage; it extends to both personal and<br />

impersonal, and to situational and across-situational contexts. It represents both trait<br />

and state (<strong>in</strong>tentions, beliefs) aspects of trust. It <strong>in</strong>cludes several core beliefs, which<br />

comprise the central motivator of trust<strong>in</strong>g behaviors. But, because these beliefs may<br />

be somewhat distal from trust<strong>in</strong>g behaviors, we have also <strong>in</strong>cluded an <strong>in</strong>tentional state,<br />

which should relate closely to trust<strong>in</strong>g behaviors. Hence, we have def<strong>in</strong>ed a<br />

manageable set of constructs that capture a wide and appropriate range of the overall<br />

concept we know as trust.<br />

SCOPE OF THE REST OF THE PAPER<br />

The rema<strong>in</strong>der of the paper applies the trust constructs to the earliest portion of a<br />

relationship. 8 The discussion addresses the question posed by Orbell, Dawes, &<br />

Schwartz-Shea (1994:113): "Absent [an <strong>in</strong>teraction] history, on what do we base our<br />

trust?" In particular, we will:<br />

(a) analyze the formation of trust by identify<strong>in</strong>g the types of trust and cognitive<br />

mechanisms by which it is created, and<br />

8 The term "relationship" will be def<strong>in</strong>ed at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of Section 2.<br />

14


(b) expla<strong>in</strong> the role of emotion <strong>in</strong> trust formation.<br />

Early relationship trust is extremely important. It helps create an <strong>in</strong>itial direction for<br />

the relationship. Most scholars agree that trust usually progresses unidirectionally,<br />

either <strong>in</strong> upward spirals or <strong>in</strong> downward spirals (e.g., Golembiewski & McConkie,<br />

1975; Sitk<strong>in</strong> & Roth, 1993; Zand, 1972). On the positive side, people tend to confirm<br />

their early positive beliefs and hopes, strengthen<strong>in</strong>g trust over time. Such confirmation<br />

occurs through<br />

attribution processes (Kramer, 1994; Holmes, 1991). People evaluate the other's<br />

actions and attribute them to the positive attributes of the other person. Similarly, on<br />

the negative side, peoples' attributions tend to confirm their early beliefs that the other<br />

person is not trustworthy. Because trust often moves <strong>in</strong> such self-confirm<strong>in</strong>g cycles,<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g of the formation of early trust is critical.<br />

Before proceed<strong>in</strong>g, we must bound the level of analysis. The discussion explores trust<br />

as an <strong>in</strong>terpersonal variable. We recognize that <strong>in</strong>tergroup or <strong>in</strong>terorganizational trust<br />

may use different, or, at least additional, formational processes than will <strong>in</strong>terpersonal<br />

trust. The discussion, however, does not address those differences. Rather, it focuses<br />

on the <strong>in</strong>terpersonal level of analysis, because this level is more conducive to a close<br />

look at the cognitive and emotional mechanisms that form trust. We believe that a<br />

thorough grasp of these mechanisms is essential to understand relationships more fully<br />

(Rob<strong>in</strong>s, 1990:80) and at more macro levels. Also, the discussion is limited to the<br />

above-def<strong>in</strong>ed trust constructs themselves. It recognizes, but does not address, the<br />

potential of other variables (e.g., communication, equity, power--see Loomis, 1959;<br />

Organ, 1990; Solomon, 1960) to impact trust significantly. The reason for this scope<br />

limitation will become apparent: trust by itself is complex enough <strong>in</strong> the several<br />

manifestations treated <strong>in</strong> this paper. The paper proceeds as follows: The dynamics of<br />

<strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust formation are expla<strong>in</strong>ed (Section 2), address<strong>in</strong>g Problem 2<br />

above. This section also addresses the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g portion of Problem 1 by expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

how the types of trust relate to each other. In addition, Section 2 addresses Problem<br />

15


3 by expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the role of emotion <strong>in</strong> trust formation. The implications for both<br />

research and practice are discussed <strong>in</strong> Section 3.<br />

SECTION 2: TRUST FORMATION<br />

DEFINITION OF THE INITIAL RELATIONSHIP<br />

Two parties are said to have a relationship when they are behaviorally <strong>in</strong>terdependent.<br />

This means that each is dependent on the other (Brehm, 1992; Berscheid, 1985), and<br />

each recognizes that dependence (Berscheid & Graziano, 1979). Interdependence<br />

means that one party is not able to fulfill its function or achieve its objectives without<br />

action by the other party (Mishra, 1993; Thompson, 1967). In this situation, each<br />

party desires assurance that the other's actions will enable their <strong>in</strong>terdependent<br />

objectives to be met. Such assurance can come either through control mechanisms or<br />

through trust (Barber, 1983). <strong>Relationships</strong> differ <strong>in</strong> strength along a cont<strong>in</strong>uum that<br />

has close family ties at the strong end and impersonal market relationships at the weak<br />

end. In market relationships, two parties may do no more than exchange money for<br />

already-priced goods. At the other end of the spectrum, family relationships may be<br />

extremely strong -- characterized by high levels of <strong>in</strong>fluence and <strong>in</strong>teraction<br />

frequency between parties (Berscheid, Snyder & Omoto, 1989). S<strong>in</strong>ce they are more<br />

or less socially embedded (Granovetter, 1985; Shapiro, 1987a), most organizational<br />

relationships lie somewhere between these two extremes (Bradach & Eccles, 1989).<br />

The rema<strong>in</strong>der of this paper addresses trust <strong>in</strong> the context of what is called the "<strong>in</strong>itial"<br />

relationship, which is dist<strong>in</strong>guished by time and <strong>in</strong>terdependence dimensions. In terms<br />

of the time dimension, the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship beg<strong>in</strong>s when the parties first become<br />

aware of each other. In terms of the <strong>in</strong>terdependence dimension, the parties both<br />

become aware that they are dependent on the other to accomplish some objective.<br />

The "<strong>in</strong>itial relationship" ends after the first few <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> their <strong>in</strong>terdependent<br />

roles. Therefore, the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship period is very brief. The end of the <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

relationship is marked by a change <strong>in</strong> the manner <strong>in</strong> which one's views about the other<br />

are formed. As will be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Section 2, <strong>in</strong>itial relationship views of the other<br />

16


are based on cognitive mechanisms. The period after the <strong>in</strong>itial one is called the<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g relationship. As the<br />

parties <strong>in</strong>teract dur<strong>in</strong>g the cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g relationship, their judgments about each other<br />

become more a function of the <strong>in</strong>teractions themselves. Recall<strong>in</strong>g that our construct of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust means a will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend, our overall argument proceeds as<br />

follows:<br />

(a) In spite of the newness of the relationship, <strong>in</strong>itial period <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust may be<br />

relatively high because of some comb<strong>in</strong>ation of five supports: dispositional trust, a<br />

situational decision to trust, categorization mechanisms, illusionary mechanisms, and<br />

system trust.<br />

(b) System trust and a decision to trust directly affect <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust itself, while<br />

the effects of categorization and illusion on trust are mediated by trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

Dispositional trust works on trust both directly and through the mediation of trust<strong>in</strong>g<br />

beliefs. These arguments are justified as each of the five supports is <strong>in</strong>dividually<br />

discussed below. Pictorially (shown as Figure 1), these supports of trust might be<br />

thought of as the bases that underly trust.<br />

17


--------------------------------<br />

Insert Figure 1 about here<br />

--------------------------------<br />

18


Interpersonal trust is like a platform that rests on one or more of the five bases. <strong>Trust</strong><br />

is more firm when several bases undergird it. Section 2 discusses how:<br />

(2.1) dispositional trust underlies both trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs and trust itself; a decision to<br />

trust also underlies trust;<br />

(2.2) categorization and illusion underly trust through their effects on trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs;<br />

(2.3) system trust underlies trust;<br />

(2.4) the trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs construct underlies trust.<br />

Section 2.5 discusses why <strong>in</strong>itial trust is properly characterized as fragile.<br />

Section 2.6 expla<strong>in</strong>s the extent to which one may assign necessary and sufficient<br />

conditions to the formation of trust.<br />

2.1 DISPOSITIONAL TRUST AND A SITUATIONAL DECISION TO TRUST<br />

Table 1 shows that dispositional trust and decision to trust are both cross-personal<br />

phenomena. As apparent from their Section 1 def<strong>in</strong>itions, these concepts are closely<br />

related. Therefore, they will be discussed together <strong>in</strong> Section 2.1.<br />

2.1.1 DISPOSITIONAL TRUST<br />

As def<strong>in</strong>ed earlier, a person has dispositional trust if s/he has a consistent tendency to<br />

trust across a broad spectrum of situations and persons. The question that needs to be<br />

raised is: "Is dispositional trust important, and if so, under what conditions?" Based<br />

on a literature search (e.g., Schlenker, Helm & Tedeschi, 1973), Dob<strong>in</strong>g (1993) felt<br />

dispositional trust would not be as salient as situation-based trust. Johnson-George &<br />

Swap (1982) argue that one's will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on another "<strong>in</strong> any given situation<br />

will be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a variety of more specific factors [besides dispositional trust]"<br />

(p. 1306).<br />

They cite evidence that dispositional trust predicts trust<strong>in</strong>g behavior only when parties<br />

are new to each other <strong>in</strong> "highly ambiguous, novel, or unstructured situations, where<br />

one's generalized expectancy is all one can rely on." (p. 1307) More recently, Holmes<br />

(1991: 63) says that although researchers assume dispositional trust is a contributor to<br />

19


the development of relationship-specific trust, this l<strong>in</strong>k has not been proven. In light<br />

of our<br />

framework, this l<strong>in</strong>k may have been difficult to prove because dispositional trust is<br />

only one of several structures upon which trust may be based. If all of the bases of<br />

trust are taken <strong>in</strong>to account, the dispositional trust to <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust l<strong>in</strong>kage may be<br />

tested <strong>in</strong> a controlled manner.<br />

We propose that relationship newness itself is important <strong>in</strong> predict<strong>in</strong>g the effects of<br />

dispositional trust. In new relationships, it is likely that dispositional trust will have<br />

some impact on some people's trust <strong>in</strong> others. Already-developed patterns of th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(schemas) about relationships should transfer, to some degree, to an <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

relationship. This is particularly true if the person cannot draw on other bases (e.g.,<br />

trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs or system trust) because the situation, the type of relationship, and the<br />

type of other person<br />

are new. In other words, if no more specific <strong>in</strong>formation is available, one would rely<br />

on one's basic beliefs about human nature, as reflected <strong>in</strong> dispositional trust<br />

(Wrightsman, 1991). This is similar to the argument presented by Mull<strong>in</strong>s &<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs (1994: 6) that "weak situations" display ambiguity <strong>in</strong> terms of the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of the situation. In weak situations, the person's disposition will be more salient than<br />

the situation. Therefore, we<br />

propose:<br />

Proposition 1: To the extent that situational factors (e.g., system trust) are not<br />

salient, dispositional trust will have a significant effect on trust and on<br />

trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs dur<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>itial relationship .<br />

We dist<strong>in</strong>guish between two types of dispositional trust, each with different effects on<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust: Type A and Type B. Type A dispositional trust means that one<br />

believes that others are generally good people, typically trustworthy, and therefore<br />

should be treated as such. Type B dispositional trust means that one believes that<br />

20


irrespective of whether people are good or not, one will obta<strong>in</strong> better <strong>in</strong>terpersonal<br />

outcomes by treat<strong>in</strong>g people as though they are good and trustworthy people. Both<br />

Type A and Type B dispositional trust would apply across most situations.<br />

Dispositional trust Type A affects one's beliefs about the other's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess<br />

(Kramer, 1994). Hence, this general belief may easily be translated <strong>in</strong>to a belief that<br />

the specific other <strong>in</strong> the relationship is trustworthy. Type B <strong>in</strong>fluences one to trust the<br />

other without respect to beliefs <strong>in</strong> the other person. It means one believes that th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

turn out best when one trusts others, even though others may not be trustworthy.<br />

Thus, this type of dispositional trust does not lead to beliefs about the other person, but<br />

still supports one's will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on that person.<br />

Proposition 2a: In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, Type A dispositional trust will be<br />

positively related to trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs, and its effect on <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust will<br />

be mediated by those beliefs.<br />

Proposition 2b: In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, Type B dispositional trust will be<br />

positively related to trust, but not to trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

2.1.2 A DECISION-TO-TRUST<br />

Kee & Knox (1970) proposed that people may manifest trust even when they believe<br />

the other party will likely be untrustworthy. Kee & Knox said this may occur "when<br />

there is much to ga<strong>in</strong> from trust<strong>in</strong>g..., but little attendant risk." (1970: 360) We are<br />

suggest<strong>in</strong>g that such trust may be based on a situation-based decision to trust. This is<br />

very similar to Riker's (1971) conceptualization of trust as a situation-based decision to<br />

depend on another. In Section 1, we differentiated such a decision to trust from<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal<br />

trust itself, and from our other trust-related constructs. We posit that such a decision<br />

may be a basis for trust.<br />

21


A decision-to-trust <strong>in</strong>tention is formed when situational characteristics cause one to<br />

choose to trust <strong>in</strong> this situation irrespective of beliefs about the attributes of the other<br />

party. This is similar to Type B dispositional trust, except that it only applies to<br />

particular sett<strong>in</strong>gs. For example, a person may decide that the benefits of trust<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

other person <strong>in</strong> this situation outweigh the downside risk of trust<strong>in</strong>g. The situational<br />

nature of the decision dist<strong>in</strong>guishes decision-to-trust from dispositional trust. In a<br />

given situation, other, and without form<strong>in</strong>g beliefs about the other's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess.<br />

The situation (with which one is familiar) is more salient than the people <strong>in</strong>volved. 9 A<br />

personal <strong>in</strong>tention is thus formed to trust the other "tentatively and conditionally"<br />

(Gambetta, 1988: 228) until the other proves unworthy of the trust. A person may<br />

fear the other's ability to defect and cause harm, but at the same time realize that the<br />

outcome of the relationship<br />

may be endangered if an <strong>in</strong>itial stage decision to trust is not made. For example, a<br />

person dependent on a specific project team may decide that s/he will trust the team<br />

leader with which s/he <strong>in</strong>teracts because s/he hopes that this decision to trust will<br />

improve the chances for project success. However, if the <strong>in</strong>tention is applied to all, or<br />

nearly all, situations, (Gambetta, 1988: 228) then it becomes Type B dispositional<br />

trust.<br />

Proposition 3: In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, a decision-to-trust <strong>in</strong>tention will be<br />

positively related to trust, but not to trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

2.2 TWO MECHANISMS ENABLING TRUST: CATEGORIZATION AND<br />

ILLUSION<br />

Categorization and illusion are two mechanisms that play an important role <strong>in</strong> the<br />

formation of trust. By mechanism we mean cognitive processes that can affect a<br />

person's beliefs. These mechanisms help form trust by their impact on trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

2.2.1 CATEGORIZATION MECHANISMS<br />

9 This strategy may extend to cover a category of situations, as well.<br />

22


People try to simplify a complex, uncerta<strong>in</strong> world by organiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>to<br />

categories so they can use an "equivalent response to all <strong>in</strong>stances of a category"<br />

(Shetzer, 1993). In a new relationship, a person may <strong>in</strong>itiate three types of trust-<br />

related categorization mechanisms: (a) unit group<strong>in</strong>g, (b) reputation categorization,<br />

and (c) stereotyp<strong>in</strong>g. Each of these mechanisms supports trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

Unit group<strong>in</strong>g--Unit group<strong>in</strong>g means that one person, because of the new relationship,<br />

now perceives the other person <strong>in</strong> a new group<strong>in</strong>g that places the pair <strong>in</strong>to a natural<br />

cohesive partnership. That is, the other person is categorized as part of a group<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

<strong>in</strong>cludes oneself. It is believed that those grouped together share common goals and/or<br />

beliefs, values, and assumptions. For example, one of the authors was study<strong>in</strong>g a large<br />

corporate division <strong>in</strong> which (due <strong>in</strong> part to functional specialization) there were<br />

significant communication and cooperation barriers between manager groups. One of<br />

the division's managers asked the author why it was that, <strong>in</strong> spite of these barriers,<br />

people who were formed <strong>in</strong>to cross-functional task forces seem to drop immediately<br />

all their prior parochial feel<strong>in</strong>gs and act as a cohesive team. One possible answer<br />

could be that people tend to alter some of their beliefs about the other party when they<br />

become part of the same team.<br />

Evidence for this phenomenon is found <strong>in</strong> social psychology. In study<strong>in</strong>g prospective<br />

dat<strong>in</strong>g couples, Darley & Berscheid (1967) found experimentally that the knowledge<br />

that one will be paired with the other often changes (positively) one's beliefs about the<br />

other's characteristics. Borden & Lev<strong>in</strong>ger (1991: 35) describe how a couple's be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

identified as a unit is "more than merely a label. It reflects a transformation from self-<br />

oriented to jo<strong>in</strong>tly-oriented criteria for formulat<strong>in</strong>g goals and evaluat<strong>in</strong>g experiences--a<br />

transformation from an 'I'-- to a 'we'--orientation." We posit that the same can happen<br />

<strong>in</strong> other <strong>in</strong>terdependent relations, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> what Culbert and McDonough (1985:<br />

128) call alignment. "Alignments give an <strong>in</strong>dividual a frame of reference for <strong>in</strong>stantly<br />

recogniz<strong>in</strong>g the opportunities and threats <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> each situation and the importance<br />

or dismissability of various <strong>in</strong>terpersonal relationships." Hence, unit group<strong>in</strong>g can<br />

23


enable one to call up learned cognitive relationship schemas and scripts (Baldw<strong>in</strong>,<br />

1992) to facilitate cooperation <strong>in</strong> jo<strong>in</strong>t endeavors. Lewis & Weigert (1985b: 464) posit<br />

that emotional trust will be high <strong>in</strong> "primary group relations," the group of which the<br />

person considers him/herself and the other person to be closely <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g members.<br />

Hav<strong>in</strong>g both parties <strong>in</strong> the "<strong>in</strong>-group" would lead to belief-related feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security<br />

because one's schema of <strong>in</strong>-group membership would portray the other favorably. The<br />

schema would <strong>in</strong>clude images that future <strong>in</strong>teractions with the other person will not be<br />

"uncerta<strong>in</strong>, complex, and...threaten<strong>in</strong>g." (Lewis & Weigert, 1985b: 462) If the<br />

categorization mechanism places the dyad <strong>in</strong>to a clan-like or family-like relationship,<br />

emotional security will be high. On the other hand, if the categorization mechanism<br />

places the other person <strong>in</strong> an out-group category, emotional trust of that person may be<br />

low.<br />

Unit group<strong>in</strong>g will also produce <strong>in</strong> one party positive affect for the other. In most<br />

organizational contexts, these feel<strong>in</strong>gs will not reflect the "hot" emotion experienced <strong>in</strong><br />

an <strong>in</strong>timate relationship. They will, however, produce feel<strong>in</strong>gs of lik<strong>in</strong>g and respect.<br />

Just as important for trust formation, unit group<strong>in</strong>g is also likely to produce feel<strong>in</strong>gs of<br />

security that one's beliefs about the other's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess are valid. This feel<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

security, comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the cognitive beliefs, forms a basis for <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust.<br />

Reputation categorization--A second k<strong>in</strong>d of categorization is based on one party's<br />

reputation, as known by the other party. Reputation may reflect professional<br />

competence (Barber, 1983; Dob<strong>in</strong>g, 1993). It may also extend to issues of <strong>in</strong>tegrity.<br />

(Dasgupta, 1988). Reputation may reflect either what is known about the person or<br />

what is known about the person's group. The person may be perceived as a competent<br />

person because of her/his own actions, or because s/he is a member of a competent<br />

group. As an example of this latter type of categorization, Dasgupta (1988) says that<br />

the Gurkhas have a reputation for bravery <strong>in</strong> battle. While <strong>in</strong>dividual Gurkhas may<br />

vary <strong>in</strong> levels of bravery, we would still judge a Gurkha about whom we know noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to our op<strong>in</strong>ion of the Gurkha group. We would "impute a high probability<br />

24


to his be<strong>in</strong>g brave, not necessarily because he has done anyth<strong>in</strong>g--he may have gone<br />

untested so far--but because he is a Gurkha, he is one of them." (Dasgupta, 1988: 63)<br />

Hence, through group or <strong>in</strong>dividual reputation, one puts the other <strong>in</strong> a category of<br />

those on whom one may depend.<br />

Stereotyp<strong>in</strong>g--The third type of categorization has to do with more general biases<br />

(stereotypes) about the other person. Stereotyp<strong>in</strong>g may be done at the broadest level,<br />

such as gender (e.g., Orbell, Dawes, and Schwartz-Shea, 1994), or at more specific<br />

levels, such as prejudices aga<strong>in</strong>st specific small groups. These prejudices may cause<br />

immediate distrust between majority and m<strong>in</strong>ority groups (Johnson & Johnson, 1989:<br />

108). Johnson & Johnson po<strong>in</strong>t out that such stigmatization "takes place even before<br />

direct contact beg<strong>in</strong>s" (Johnson & Johnson, 1989: 109). Stereotypes may be formed<br />

on the basis of<br />

the first bit of second-hand knowledge one obta<strong>in</strong>s regard<strong>in</strong>g the other party. Or, they<br />

may be formed at the first meet<strong>in</strong>g between the parties, based on the other's voice (e.g.<br />

male/female, domestic/foreign) (Baldw<strong>in</strong>, 1992, p. 462) or physical appearance (Lewis<br />

& Weigert, 1985b:468; Riker, 1971: 78). In social psychology experiments, for<br />

example, subjects more often placed the physically attractive person <strong>in</strong>to the "good"<br />

person category than they did one who was not physically attractive. Researchers<br />

called this the "what is beautiful is good" stereotype (Dion, Berscheid, & Walster,<br />

1982). As another<br />

example, <strong>in</strong> an even<strong>in</strong>g MBA course <strong>in</strong> which students were randomly assigned to<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdependent work groups, one foreign student reported that conflict and low trust<br />

levels existed <strong>in</strong> his group because one of the other students, on see<strong>in</strong>g his obviously<br />

foreign name on his bus<strong>in</strong>ess card, was <strong>in</strong>fected by previously acquired prejudices<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st "his type" (McKnight, 1994).<br />

The above three categorization processes enable one to place a person one hardly<br />

knows <strong>in</strong>to a group<strong>in</strong>g from which generalizations may be made. These<br />

generalizations, <strong>in</strong> turn, enable one to form beliefs about the other person's honesty,<br />

25


competence, benevolence, and/or predictability. Categorization also supports<br />

emotional security with respect to trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs. Together, these beliefs and<br />

accompany<strong>in</strong>g emotional security provide a foundation for trust.<br />

Proposition 4: In spite of the newness of a relationship, categorization<br />

mechanisms will enable <strong>in</strong>itial relationship <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust to be high.<br />

The effects of categorization mechanisms on <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust will be<br />

mediated by trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

2.2.2 ILLUSIONARY MECHANISMS THAT DEVELOP TRUST<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> is not developed solely on rational mechanisms, but also on illusionary<br />

mechanisms. Sometimes one does not even know enough about a person to enable<br />

categorization to operate. Categorization requires that one use logic. That is, one<br />

places the person <strong>in</strong> a category, attributes good characteristics to a group, and, through<br />

logic, concludes that the person has the same attributes as found generally <strong>in</strong> the<br />

group. On the other hand, illusionary processes operate without such <strong>in</strong>formation and<br />

logic. That is, a high level of<br />

illusionary overconfidence about the other person's attributes may exist <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

relationship trust. By overconfidence, we mean greater confidence than one's<br />

available data about the other person can reasonably justify. In this time frame,<br />

known facts about the other are sketchy at best. Therefore, Lewis & Weigert (1985b:<br />

466) say that early trust is "assumptive." Luhmann (1991: 68) says that "[trust entails]<br />

reliance upon fictions which work...trust is not concerned with know<strong>in</strong>g the essential<br />

truth about a matter but with the success of the reduction of [mental] complexity." The<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d economizes effort<br />

by draw<strong>in</strong>g a consistent picture of the other, even if the draw<strong>in</strong>g must extend "beyond<br />

the available evidence" (Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985: 97). Holmes (1991: 64)<br />

says that a person's early feel<strong>in</strong>gs about the <strong>in</strong>terdependent other create "a sense of<br />

optimism that belies a lack of hard evidence." The future possibilities "feed their<br />

hopes and fantasies about the potential of the relationship." (Holmes & Rempel, 1989:<br />

26


192) This is especially true when one perceives that the other person has the<br />

characteristics needed to enable one to complete plans or goals important to one's<br />

future. Holmes' analysis of how trust <strong>in</strong>itially forms is consistent with the research <strong>in</strong><br />

cognitive psychology, which says that people use <strong>in</strong>ferential shortcuts to allow them to<br />

make up their m<strong>in</strong>ds "quickly, easily, and with excessive confidence <strong>in</strong> the correctness<br />

of their decisions." (Tetlock, 1985: 302)<br />

A pair of people <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>itial relationship are also likely to use illusionary processes<br />

because they do not know from experience whether the other has the attributes needed<br />

to be considered trustworthy.<br />

The cognitive processes that build this illusion-based trust may be similar to those<br />

related to judgment overconfidence <strong>in</strong> the behavioral decision theory literature. In<br />

particular, (a) one forms a tentative op<strong>in</strong>ion; (b) one then seeks confirm<strong>in</strong>g evidence;<br />

and, (c) even a slight effort to f<strong>in</strong>d out more about the other person may over<strong>in</strong>flate<br />

one's confidence that a high level of trust <strong>in</strong> the other is warranted (e.g. Davis &<br />

Kottemann, 1994; Langer, 1975; Paese & Sniezek, 1991). Kramer (1994) found, for<br />

example, that rum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g for a few m<strong>in</strong>utes about the others' motives and <strong>in</strong>tentions<br />

<strong>in</strong>creased a person's confidence <strong>in</strong> the the accuracy of their judgments of the others.<br />

People tend to fill <strong>in</strong> confidently the miss<strong>in</strong>g pieces of the most sketchy <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

presented to them about the other (e.g. Abelson et al., 1968; Jagac<strong>in</strong>ski, 1991).<br />

Hence, illusion can support a person's beliefs <strong>in</strong> the other's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess.<br />

Illusion can also help support emotional security <strong>in</strong> one's beliefs about the other. It<br />

does this by fill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> miss<strong>in</strong>g facts that would make one feel secure <strong>in</strong> one's beliefs<br />

about the other. For example, one would feel secure about the other if one believes<br />

that the other shares one's basic values and goals. Even without evidence, one may<br />

feel relatively confident that the other has such values and goals. Hence, one will feel<br />

more secure <strong>in</strong> one's beliefs about the other.<br />

Proposition 5: In spite of the newness of a relationship, illusionary<br />

27


mechanisms enable <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust to be high. The effects of<br />

illusionary mechanisms on trust will be mediated by trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

Illusion applies to trust <strong>in</strong> another way. In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, the person may not<br />

yet have a total comprehension of the risks <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> trust<strong>in</strong>g the other. Baier<br />

(1986: 236) says that the consciousness of trust progresses from "<strong>in</strong>itially unself-<br />

conscious trust to awareness of risk along with confidence that it is a good risk, on to<br />

some realization of why we are tak<strong>in</strong>g this particular risk,..." Holmes (1991: 57)<br />

described this progression as a "dialectic between people's hopes and fears." The<br />

illusionary processes underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

trust fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps left by simple lack of total consciousness of the risk issues<br />

pert<strong>in</strong>ent to a well-reasoned decision to trust. S<strong>in</strong>ce they are based on hopes for the<br />

future, illusionary mechanisms will probably be most salient when future relationship<br />

prospects provide outcomes that one or more party greatly desires. But, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is<br />

essentially a mechanism that fills gaps, illusion will be salient only to the extent that<br />

facts about the other are absent or <strong>in</strong>adequate. Illusion would fill <strong>in</strong>, for example,<br />

when one does not have enough <strong>in</strong>formation about the other to use categorization<br />

mechanisms.<br />

Proposition 6: In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, illusionary processes will be most<br />

salient when: (a) prospects for outcomes of the relationship have high value<br />

to persons <strong>in</strong> the dyad, and (b) few facts are known about the other person or<br />

the categories <strong>in</strong> which the other would be placed.<br />

2.3 SYSTEM TRUST<br />

Initial relationship trust may also be high because it is founded on system trust. One's<br />

system trust was def<strong>in</strong>ed as the belief that proper impersonal structures are <strong>in</strong> place to<br />

enable one to act <strong>in</strong> anticipation of a successful future endeavor. The personal<br />

characteristics of the other are not at issue with this k<strong>in</strong>d of trust. Hence, system trust<br />

does not support beliefs about the other person (see Figure 1); however, it does<br />

28


support will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on the other. System trust may be based on the<br />

appearance that th<strong>in</strong>gs are normal (Garf<strong>in</strong>kel, 1963: 188) or "customary," (Baier, 1986:<br />

245) or that "everyth<strong>in</strong>g seems <strong>in</strong> proper order," (Lewis & Wiegert, 1985a: 974).<br />

System trust may also rest on what Shapiro (1987b: 204) calls structural safeguards, or<br />

<strong>in</strong>stitutional "side bets," 10 such as regulations, guarantors and litigations. For example,<br />

a company subcontract<strong>in</strong>g the construction of metric-sized eng<strong>in</strong>e parts trusts that the<br />

other party will use the same measures the company uses, s<strong>in</strong>ce they are specified by<br />

well-accepted metric standards makers.<br />

In addition to <strong>in</strong>stitutional structures, system trust may be based on the situation itself.<br />

System trust can <strong>in</strong>clude both the proper sett<strong>in</strong>g and one's comfort with one's own<br />

roles and other persons' roles <strong>in</strong> that sett<strong>in</strong>g. Baier says, "We take it for granted that<br />

people will perform their role-related duties, and trust any <strong>in</strong>dividual worker to look<br />

after whatever her job requires her to." (1986: 245) Baier also argues: "Social<br />

artifices such as property, which allocate rights and duties as a standard job does...<br />

generally also create a climate of trust, a presumption of a sort of trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess."<br />

(1986:245-6) That<br />

is, roles and duties often <strong>in</strong>here from social structures. These socially constructed<br />

roles and duties create a shared understand<strong>in</strong>g among members of the social system<br />

that facilitates trust among them. System trust provides assurances that, given the<br />

current conducive sett<strong>in</strong>g, the other party is likely to act <strong>in</strong> a way that can be depended<br />

on, hence enabl<strong>in</strong>g trust.<br />

System trust can be dist<strong>in</strong>guished from illusionary processes. First, illusionary<br />

processes are mental mechanisms, while system trust is a belief construct. Second,<br />

illusionary processes are based largely on hope and desire, while system trust is based<br />

on the specific <strong>in</strong>stitutions that provide safeguards aga<strong>in</strong>st personal damages.<br />

10 Blau (1964: 98) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that "commitment has been conceptualized as a<br />

side bet that promotes trust by mak<strong>in</strong>g it disproportionately disadvantageous<br />

for a person to violate an agreement."<br />

29


System trust may also operate through promises or contracts. Baier speaks of a<br />

promise, <strong>in</strong> Hume's words, as "a bond or security" and "the sanction of the <strong>in</strong>terested<br />

commerce of mank<strong>in</strong>d." (1986: 246) When one relies on a promise for the basis of<br />

trust <strong>in</strong> the other, two conditions apply. First, the truster feels comfortable that the<br />

promise has the type of significance <strong>in</strong> the particular sett<strong>in</strong>g such that the trusted<br />

person will make every effort to fulfill it, or reap certa<strong>in</strong> sanctions. This can apply<br />

even where <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust is low:<br />

"...the only trust Hobbist man shows is trust <strong>in</strong> promises, provided there is assurance of<br />

punishment for promise breakers..." (Baier, 1986: 252). Second, the truster feels<br />

comfortable that the trusted person, out of either <strong>in</strong>tegrity or fear of sanctions, will act<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to the norms surround<strong>in</strong>g promise <strong>in</strong> the social sett<strong>in</strong>g. The first condition is<br />

a function of system trust, while the second condition reflects beliefs about the other<br />

person's probable actions <strong>in</strong> that social sett<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Proposition 7: In the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, system trust will be positively<br />

related to <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust. Its effects on <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust will not be<br />

mediated by trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs.<br />

2.4 TRUSTING BELIEFS AS A FOUNDATION OF TRUST<br />

<strong>Trust</strong><strong>in</strong>g beliefs <strong>in</strong>cludes both cognitive and emotional components, both of which are<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> this section.<br />

2.4.1 COGNITIVE BELIEFS<br />

Cognitive beliefs <strong>in</strong> the other person's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess will likely provide a foundation<br />

for cognitive will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on the other person <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>itial relationship. If<br />

one believes that the other party is trustworthy, one is likely to be will<strong>in</strong>g to depend on<br />

that person. Dob<strong>in</strong>g (1993) found evidence of this l<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>in</strong> his questionnaire study.<br />

Proposition 8: In an <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, one's cognitive will<strong>in</strong>gness to<br />

30


depend on another person will be positively related to one's cognitive beliefs<br />

<strong>in</strong> the other person's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess.<br />

2.4.2 EMOTIONAL SECURITY<br />

In Section 1, we def<strong>in</strong>ed both <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust and trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs to have an<br />

emotional component of feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security. A number of researchers have said that<br />

trust has an emotional component or is based on feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security (e.g. Lewis &<br />

Weigert, 1985ab; Luhmann, 1991; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985). Others refer to<br />

confidence or confident beliefs <strong>in</strong> the other (e.g., Deutsch, 1973; Dunn, 1988;<br />

Scanzoni, 1979). By separat<strong>in</strong>g trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs from attitudes/<strong>in</strong>tentions to trust<br />

(will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend), our conception of trust is able to view the emotional aspect of<br />

trust at both levels. Emotions are separated <strong>in</strong>to two levels because each level's<br />

emotions has a different referent. At the trust level, the emotional aspect refers to<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security about one's will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend on the other party. At the belief<br />

level, the emotional aspect means one has feel<strong>in</strong>gs of security about one's beliefs<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g the other party's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess. Emotions, like cognitions, tend toward<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal consistency. That is, one is likely to feel secure both <strong>in</strong> one's will<strong>in</strong>gness to<br />

depend and <strong>in</strong> one's trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs about the other party. The person who feels secure<br />

<strong>in</strong> her beliefs about the other's trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess will tend to feel assured <strong>in</strong> her<br />

will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend. Hence, the emotional security related to trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs will<br />

underly the emotional security aspects of will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend.<br />

Proposition 9: Emotional security <strong>in</strong> one's trust<strong>in</strong>g belief will be positively<br />

related to emotional security <strong>in</strong> one's <strong>in</strong>itial will<strong>in</strong>gness to depend.<br />

2.5 THE FRAGILE NATURE OF INITIAL RELATIONSHIP TRUST<br />

The term "fragile," when applied to trust, refers to a trust level that is subject to the<br />

likelihood of large downward changes dur<strong>in</strong>g a given timeframe. Why is trust fragile<br />

<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship? We argue that <strong>in</strong>itial trust is fragile largely because of the<br />

relatively tenuous nature of its underly<strong>in</strong>g support. The support is tenuous because it is<br />

31


ased on assumptions and tentative decisions about the other person and the situation,<br />

which can easily be replaced by experience-based judgments of the other party.<br />

Hence, experience with the other party that contradicts one's early beliefs may cause a<br />

rapid decrease <strong>in</strong><br />

one's level of trust.<br />

We do not argue that early trust will always be fragile. A comb<strong>in</strong>ation of bases may<br />

allow it to be strong. However, we argue that <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust is likely to be<br />

more fragile than experience-based trust.Intuitively, the more diverse trust's supports,<br />

the less fragile trust will be. The <strong>in</strong>verse would also be true. The fewer its underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

supports, the more trust is subject to abrupt changes toward distrust. For example,<br />

trust may rely almost exclusively for support on system trust. In the case of<br />

agreements or contracts, Dasgupta (1988) says that the trust one person has <strong>in</strong> another<br />

to fulfill a contract depends on the power of the agencies that are able to enforce<br />

contracts: "If your trust <strong>in</strong> the enforcement agency falters, you will not trust persons to<br />

fulfil their terms of an agreement and thus will not enter <strong>in</strong>to that agreement...It is this<br />

<strong>in</strong>terconnectedness which makes trust such a fragile commodity." (1988: 50)<br />

Similarly, the sole belief <strong>in</strong> the other's honesty is a<br />

basis for trust that can crumble quickly (Dasgupta, 1988) if experience <strong>in</strong>dicates that<br />

the belief is mistaken. Riker (1971: 78) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that categorization as a basis for<br />

trust is fragile because "only rarely do they effectively discrim<strong>in</strong>ate between the<br />

trustworthy and the untrustworthy." We have previously discussed how dispositional<br />

trust may be a weak trust base <strong>in</strong> the presence of a strong situation. Situational or<br />

personal bases for trust may become strong quickly as experience is ga<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

<strong>Trust</strong> will be fragile <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship because of the assumptional nature of its<br />

foundation. Intuitively, the illusion-based trust seems most assumptional and therefore<br />

fragile. Decisions-to-trust are also tentative; they are normally decisions to "trust<br />

until" one obta<strong>in</strong>s further <strong>in</strong>formation (Dob<strong>in</strong>g, 1993). Decisions to trust may reflect<br />

32


some level of underly<strong>in</strong>g suspicion of the other. Kee & Knox (1970: 359) propose that<br />

<strong>in</strong> some<br />

circumstances, people will cont<strong>in</strong>ue trust<strong>in</strong>g even when they still have "some mild<br />

doubts about O's <strong>in</strong>tegrity or competence." But when "some critical level of<br />

uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is reached, P will beg<strong>in</strong> to withhold full manifest trust <strong>in</strong> order to protect<br />

himself..."<br />

As facts about the other person displace illusions and presuppositions, the person's<br />

trust may quickly erode. Fazio & Zanna (1981) po<strong>in</strong>ted out two reasons why<br />

experience replaces assumptions: (a) people consider behavioral experience<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation to be more reliable than <strong>in</strong>directly obta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>formation; and, (b) people's<br />

direct experience <strong>in</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g an attitude or judgment makes that attitude more readily<br />

accessible <strong>in</strong> memory. Riker<br />

(1971:78) agreed with Fazio & Zanna's first reason, say<strong>in</strong>g that people won't long be<br />

satisfied with trust based on non-experiential data. Rather, they will seek data that<br />

br<strong>in</strong>gs them greater assurance that their <strong>in</strong>itial conceptions are valid.<br />

Added to Fazio & Zanna’s two reasons is a third reason: emotion. People are likely to<br />

have emotional experiences through <strong>in</strong>teraction early <strong>in</strong> a relationship (Berscheid,<br />

1983). Dur<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>itial relationship, people are more likely to be surprised or to have<br />

their expectations <strong>in</strong>terrupted by the other's actions or words. Surpris<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

<strong>in</strong>terrupt<strong>in</strong>g events are likely to have emotional effects (Berscheid, 1983). With<strong>in</strong> the<br />

range of emotional <strong>in</strong>tensity expected <strong>in</strong> most <strong>in</strong>teractions, emotional events are likely<br />

to be remembered better than are non-emotional events (Baddeley, 1990). Hence,<br />

emotion-caus<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>teractions will be more likely to be recalled later as <strong>in</strong>put to one's<br />

trust judgments of the other. Emotional events are also likely to impact trust because<br />

they often arouse the person's autonomic nervous system (Berscheid, 1983), which<br />

heightens the person's attention to the other party when placed <strong>in</strong> a similar situation<br />

with her/him. Heightened attention comb<strong>in</strong>ed with a negative emotional feel<strong>in</strong>g make<br />

it more likely that the person will f<strong>in</strong>d evidence counter to her/his current trust and<br />

33


trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs. Any evidence found will lead to further suspicion. Hence, a self-<br />

fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy spiral will result. Based on emotion theory, we suggest that for<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdependent parties, emotion-laden <strong>in</strong>terruptions may raise such questions as: "Will<br />

the other party obstruct my higher-order plans the next time a similar opportunity<br />

arises?" If the answer is "yes," or even "maybe," then the person's will<strong>in</strong>gness to<br />

depend on the other would decrease.<br />

The fragility of trust is also affected by the strength of the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of beliefs one<br />

party holds about the other. As mentioned earlier, four core beliefs about the other<br />

emerge from the trust literature: benevolence, honesty, competence, and<br />

predictability. If only one of these beliefs is held, the relationship may be very<br />

unstable. But even with more than one belief, particularly <strong>in</strong> their under-<strong>in</strong>formed<br />

<strong>in</strong>itial state, they may be fragile. In fact, if one is miss<strong>in</strong>g only one of the four<br />

foundational beliefs, trust may still be fragile. Why? First, belief <strong>in</strong> the other's<br />

competence, which we def<strong>in</strong>e as efficacy--"capacity for produc<strong>in</strong>g a desired result or<br />

effect" (Ste<strong>in</strong>, 1971: 455)--is critical to trust. Unless the other has the power and<br />

ability to accomplish what is needed, the dependent party has no reason to trust that it<br />

will be done.<br />

But even a competent partner may make promises that are not kept. Second, then, a<br />

person needs to believe that the other is honest--def<strong>in</strong>ed as mak<strong>in</strong>g honest efforts<br />

(Bromiley & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, 1995) to accomplish the th<strong>in</strong>g implicitly promised <strong>in</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdependent relationship. Third, even if one believes that the other is competent<br />

and honest, one needs to feel assured that more than the letter of the agreement will be<br />

kept. This requires that the person believe the other is benevolent, not self-serv<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

opportunistic. F<strong>in</strong>ally, non-fragile trust requires that the level of predictability of the<br />

other's behavior become evident. Predictability means the ability of one to forecast the<br />

other's actions. Without this belief, the person may still fear that an unpredictably<br />

honest, competent and benevolent partner may not perform on the next occasion when<br />

an <strong>in</strong>terdependent action is required.<br />

34


For all of the above reasons, we propose:<br />

Proposition 10: Initial relationship trust is likely to be very fragile.<br />

2.6 CONSIDERING THE NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS<br />

FOR TRUST FORMATION<br />

It is difficult to apply necessary and sufficient conditions to <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust<br />

formation. As we have discussed, <strong>in</strong>itial trust is complex both <strong>in</strong> its composition and<br />

<strong>in</strong> terms of the number of bases on which it rests. Little empirical research has been<br />

done that sheds light on our propositions about the formation of trust. However,<br />

Dob<strong>in</strong>g (1993) found that trust<strong>in</strong>g beliefs are highly correlated with will<strong>in</strong>gness to<br />

depend. Goldsteen, Schorr & Goldsteen (1989) found that dispositional trust had a<br />

significant effect on what they call mistrust. However, they do not report on the<br />

validity of their unique trust operationalizations. Zucker (1986) discusses how<br />

<strong>in</strong>stitutional-based trust<br />

substituted for process-based trust from 1840-1920 <strong>in</strong> the United States, but does not<br />

explore the effects one type of trust has on another. Orbell, Dawes & Schwarz-Shea<br />

(1994) studied the effects of gender categorization on trust<strong>in</strong>g expectations, but found<br />

it had very little predictive power. To our knowledge, no one has studied the effects of<br />

illusion on trust. More critically, no one has simultaneously studied the effects of<br />

several of the trust bases on trust. Due to lack of research on how the bases of trust<br />

impact trust, our discussion of necessary and sufficient conditions for trust rests on<br />

logical arguments rather than on empirical evidence.<br />

From prior discussion, it seems reasonable that with several possible<br />

mechanisms/bases for trust, none of them is likely to be solely necessary for trust. The<br />

various mechanism(s) can act as substitutes for one another. For example, Zucker<br />

showed that system trust can replace more personal types of trust. Similarly, it seems<br />

logical that beliefs about the other person can substitute for dispositional trust.<br />

35


We do not preclude the possibility that a s<strong>in</strong>gle basis may be sufficient for the<br />

development of a high level of trust. In a weak situation, where no other basis is<br />

available, dispositional trust may be sufficient. A decision-to-trust <strong>in</strong>tention may be<br />

strong enough to warrant trust <strong>in</strong> a given situation. Categorization alone may be<br />

sufficient if the category places the two parties <strong>in</strong> a clan-like, emotionally secure<br />

position with each other. System trust would<br />

be sufficient alone if it is strong enough to provide one a secure enough feel<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

overcome the uncerta<strong>in</strong>ties presented by the new <strong>in</strong>terpersonal situation. Illusion<br />

would probably not be sufficient alone, s<strong>in</strong>ce it normally works <strong>in</strong> conjunction with<br />

system or dispositional trust.<br />

It seems reasonable that the presence of two or more of the five bases would normally<br />

provide a stronger reason for high trust than would one alone. For example, Kramer<br />

found a fairly high trust level among MBA's, attribut<strong>in</strong>g the high level to <strong>in</strong>group bias,<br />

which is like our unit group<strong>in</strong>g categorization. However, their level of trust may have<br />

also been higher due to: (a) higher-than-average dispositional trust; (b) illusionary<br />

processes (s<strong>in</strong>ce Kramer had them rum<strong>in</strong>ate about their judgments of the others); (c) a<br />

decision-to-trust <strong>in</strong>tention; or/and (d) some form of system trust. However, we caution<br />

that the number of bases alone is the only factor. Rather, the strength of each base will<br />

also affect the level of trust.<br />

Proposition 11: Typically, <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust will be based upon a<br />

multiplex of bases. The more diverse and strong the bases, the higher the<br />

level of trust.<br />

36


SECTION 3: CONCLUSION<br />

The trust concept is difficult to conceptualize and operationalize <strong>in</strong> ways that are<br />

theoretically sound, empirically testable, and applicable to common usage and<br />

practice. A major <strong>in</strong>tent of this paper is to differentiate the various types of trust <strong>in</strong> a<br />

way that allows each part to be used on its own, but still relate to the other types.<br />

Employ<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terplay between <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust and its bases will shed light on<br />

such unexpected research results as high trust <strong>in</strong> new relationships and situations (e.g.,<br />

Kramer, 1994).<br />

In addition, this research highlights additional possible explanations for results <strong>in</strong><br />

game theory research. This is important because of the historical prevalence of game<br />

theory approaches <strong>in</strong> trust-related research. For example, dispositional trust, system<br />

trust, and categorization mechanisms need to be elim<strong>in</strong>ated as possible reasons for<br />

observed experimental outcomes--or used to expla<strong>in</strong> the outcomes. The result will be<br />

a more thorough explanation of trust-related phenomena, not merely an ability to<br />

predict trust-related outcomes. Twenty-five years ago, Kee & Knox (1970: 365)<br />

recommended that<br />

Prisoner's Dilemma research should <strong>in</strong>clude "cont<strong>in</strong>uous" measures of the <strong>in</strong>dividuals'<br />

subjective state (e.g., beliefs) <strong>in</strong> addition to the behavioral choices they make. Our<br />

model's rich set of constructs provides a theoretical basis for do<strong>in</strong>g so.<br />

To build a proper foundation for cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g research <strong>in</strong> trust, operationalizations<br />

should correspond as closely as possible to the conceptualizations provided above.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g reflects some of the key research steps that need to be taken <strong>in</strong> this area:<br />

(a) Reliable and valid <strong>in</strong>struments reflect<strong>in</strong>g the constructs <strong>in</strong> this paper<br />

should be developed (Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs & Bromiley, 1995, <strong>in</strong> press).<br />

(b) The <strong>in</strong>struments should be tested aga<strong>in</strong>st what people mean when they<br />

use the term "trust" <strong>in</strong> everyday life.<br />

37


(c) The <strong>in</strong>itial relationship trust propositions should be tested both <strong>in</strong> laboratory and<br />

organizational sett<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

(d) S<strong>in</strong>ce trust has been def<strong>in</strong>ed to be juxtaposed aga<strong>in</strong>st other social control<br />

mechanisms, additional work should be done to exam<strong>in</strong>e the <strong>in</strong>terplay between the<br />

types of trust discussed here and social control mechanisms.<br />

Several researchers have suggested that the trust concept needs considerable<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegrative effort (Barber, 1983; Kramer, 1994; Lewis & Weigert, 1985a; Sitk<strong>in</strong> &<br />

Roth, 1993), both def<strong>in</strong>itionally and <strong>in</strong> ways that l<strong>in</strong>k the micro (psychological) level<br />

with the macro (organizational or social) level. This paper contributes as follows:<br />

(a) It synthesizes several views of trust <strong>in</strong>to a coherent set of constructs, represent<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

typology of trust <strong>in</strong> its respective components: beliefs, attitudes/<strong>in</strong>tentions, emotions,<br />

dispositions and impersonal beliefs.<br />

(b) It postulates ways <strong>in</strong> which the bases of trust support trust.<br />

(c) It portrays the cognitive and emotional mechanisms that allow <strong>in</strong>itial relationship<br />

trust to form.<br />

(d) By focus<strong>in</strong>g on the mechanism level, it provides a way to expla<strong>in</strong> and understand<br />

the dynamics of trust formation.<br />

Several implications for practice can also be drawn from this model:<br />

(a) We need to be realistic about the nature of early levels of trust. Early trust may be<br />

more fragile and ephemeral than people <strong>in</strong> various relationships assume (and for<br />

different reasons).<br />

(b) By understand<strong>in</strong>g the nature of early trust's fragility, we can try to strengthen the<br />

bases that support trust. The more bases of trust that one can set up or positively<br />

<strong>in</strong>fluence, the better.<br />

(c) One should work to be trustworthy and have a trustworthy reputation <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

ensure trust lasts past the <strong>in</strong>itial phase of the relationship.<br />

38


(d) Because trust tends to be reciprocally <strong>in</strong>fluenced (Golembiewski & McConkie,<br />

1975), a personal strategy to "trust until" would be appropriate for many new<br />

situations.<br />

However, a caution is <strong>in</strong> order. Because early trust is based more on fiction than fact,<br />

we must be careful how it is extended (Granovetter, 1985). Otherwise, we may<br />

unwitt<strong>in</strong>gly expose ourselves to opportunism. "After all, at the very heart of the<br />

dilemma ... is not simply whether to trust or distrust, but rather how much trust and<br />

distrust are appropriate <strong>in</strong> a given situation" (Kramer, 1994: 226).<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Abelson, R. P., Aronson, E., McGuire, W. J., <strong>New</strong>comb, T. M., Rosenberg, M.<br />

J., & Tannenbaum, P. H. 1968. Theories of cognitive consistency: A<br />

sourcebook. Chicago: Rand-McNally.<br />

Arrow, K. J. 1974. The limits of organization. <strong>New</strong> York: Norton.<br />

Astley, W. G. & Zajac, E. J. 1991. Intraorganizational power and organizational<br />

design: Reconcil<strong>in</strong>g rational and coalitional models of organization.<br />

Organization Science, 2(4): 399-411.<br />

Atwater, L. E. 1988. The relative importance of situational and <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

variables <strong>in</strong> predict<strong>in</strong>g leader behavior: The surpris<strong>in</strong>g impact of subord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

trust. Group and Organization Studies, 13(3): 290-310.<br />

Baddeley, A. 1990. Human memory: Theory and practice. Boston: Allyn and<br />

Bacon.<br />

Baier, A. 1986. <strong>Trust</strong> and antitrust. Ethics, 96:231-260.<br />

Baldw<strong>in</strong>, M. W. 1992. Relational schemas and the process<strong>in</strong>g of social<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation. Psychological Bullet<strong>in</strong>, 112(3): 461-484.<br />

Barber, B. 1983. The logic and limits of trust. <strong>New</strong> Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers<br />

University Press.<br />

Berscheid, E. 1983. Emotion. In Kelley, H. H., Berscheid, E., Christensen, A.,<br />

Harvey, J. H., Huston, T. L., Lev<strong>in</strong>ger, G., McCl<strong>in</strong>tock, E., Peplau, L. A. &<br />

Peterson, D. R. (Eds.), Close <strong>Relationships</strong>: 110-168. <strong>New</strong> York: W. H. Freeman<br />

39


.<br />

Berscheid, E. 1985. Compatibility, <strong>in</strong>terdependence, and emotion. In W. Ickes<br />

(Ed.), Compatible and <strong>in</strong>compatible relationships: 143-161. <strong>New</strong> York:<br />

Spr<strong>in</strong>ger-Verlag.<br />

Berscheid, E. & Graziano, W. 1979. The <strong>in</strong>itiation of social relationships and<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal attraction. In R. L. Burgess & T. L. Huston (Eds.), Social<br />

exchange <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g relationships: 31-60. <strong>New</strong> York: Academic Press.<br />

Berscheid, E., Snyder, M. & Omoto, A. M. 1989. Issues <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g close<br />

relationships: Conceptualiz<strong>in</strong>g and measur<strong>in</strong>g closeness. In C. Hendrick<br />

(Ed.), Review of Personality and Social Psychology: Vol. 10. Close<br />

<strong>Relationships</strong>: 63-91. <strong>New</strong>bury Park, CA: Sage.<br />

Blakeney, R. N. 1986. A transactional view of the role of trust <strong>in</strong><br />

organizational communication. Transactional Analysis Journal, 16: 95-98.<br />

Blau, P. M. 1964. Exchange and power <strong>in</strong> social life. <strong>New</strong> York: John Wiley &<br />

Sons.<br />

Bonoma, T. V. 1976. Conflict, cooperation, and trust <strong>in</strong> three power systems.<br />

Behavioral Science, 21(6): 499-514.<br />

Borden, V. M. H. & Lev<strong>in</strong>ger, G. 1991. Interpersonal transformations <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>timate relationships. In W. H. Jones & D. Perlman, (Eds.), Advances <strong>in</strong><br />

personal relationships: 35-56. Vol. 2. London: Jessica K<strong>in</strong>gsley.<br />

Bradach, J. L. & Eccles, R. G. 1989. Price, authority, and trust: From ideal types<br />

to plural forms. In W. R. Scott & J. Blake (Eds.), Annual Review of Sociology:<br />

97-118.<br />

Brehm, S. S. 1992. Intimate relationships. <strong>New</strong> York: McGraw-Hill.<br />

Bromiley, P. & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, L. L. 1995, <strong>in</strong> press. Organizations with trust. R.<br />

Bies, R. Lemicki & B. Sheppard (Eds.), Research <strong>in</strong> Negotiations. 5th edition,<br />

Greenwich, CN: JAI Press.<br />

Cohen, A. K. 1966. Deviance and control. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.<br />

Coleman, J. S. 1990. Foundations of social theory. Cambridge, MA and<br />

London: Harvard University Press.<br />

Cooprider, J. G. & Victor, K. M. 1993. The contribution of shared knowledge to<br />

IS group performance. In J. I. DeGross, R. P. Bostrom & D. Robey (Eds.),<br />

40


Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the Fourteenth International Conference on Information<br />

Systems: 285-299.<br />

Culbert, S. A. & McDonough, J. J. 1985. Radical management: Power politics<br />

and the pursuit of trust. <strong>New</strong> York: The Free Press.<br />

Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, L. L. & Bromiley, P. 1995, <strong>in</strong> press. The organizational trust<br />

<strong>in</strong>ventory: OTI. In R. Kramer & T. Tyler (Eds.), <strong>Trust</strong> <strong>in</strong> organizations.<br />

Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.<br />

Darley, J. M. & Berscheid, E. 1967. Increased lik<strong>in</strong>g as a result of anticipation of<br />

personal contact. Human Relations, 20(1): 29-40.<br />

Dasgupta, P. 1988. <strong>Trust</strong> as a commodity. In D. Gambetta (Ed.), <strong>Trust</strong>: Mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 47-72. <strong>New</strong> York: Blackwell.<br />

Davis, F. D. & Kotteman, J. E. 1994. User perceptions of decision support<br />

effectiveness: Two production plann<strong>in</strong>g experiments. Decision Sciences, 25(1):<br />

57-77.<br />

Deutsch, M. 1958. <strong>Trust</strong> and suspicion. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 2: 265-<br />

279.<br />

Deutsch, M. 1973. The resolution of conflict: Constructive and destructive<br />

processes. <strong>New</strong> Haven, CN: Yale University Press.<br />

Dion, K. K., Berscheid, E. & Walster, E. 1972. What is beautiful is good.<br />

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 24:285-290.<br />

Dob<strong>in</strong>g, B. 1993. Build<strong>in</strong>g trust <strong>in</strong> user-analyst relationships. Unpublished<br />

doctoral dissertation, Information and Decision Sciences Department,<br />

University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota, M<strong>in</strong>neapolis.<br />

Dunn, M. H. 1988. <strong>Trust</strong> and political agency. In D. Gambetta (Ed.), <strong>Trust</strong>:<br />

Mak<strong>in</strong>g and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 73-93. <strong>New</strong> York: Blackwell.<br />

Eayrs, M. A. 1993. Time, trust and hazard: Hairdressers' symbolic roles.<br />

Symbolic Interaction, 16(1): 19-37.<br />

Fazio, R. H. & Zanna, M. P. 1981. Direct experience and attitude-behavior<br />

consistency. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances <strong>in</strong> Experimental Social<br />

Psychology. 14:162-202. <strong>New</strong> York: Academic Press.<br />

Fishbe<strong>in</strong>, M. & Ajzen, I. 1975. Belief, attitude, <strong>in</strong>tention and behavior: An<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduction to theory and research. Read<strong>in</strong>g, MA: Addison-Wesley.<br />

41


Fox, A. 1974. Beyond contract: Work, power and trust relations. London:<br />

Faber.<br />

Gabarro, J. J. 1978. The development of trust, <strong>in</strong>fluence, and expectations. In<br />

A. G. Athos & J. J. Gabarro (Eds.), Interpersonal behavior: Communication<br />

and understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> relationships. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.<br />

Gambetta, D. 1988. Can we trust trust? In D. Gambetta (Ed.), <strong>Trust</strong>: Mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 213-237. <strong>New</strong> York: Blackwell.<br />

Garf<strong>in</strong>kel, H. 1967. Studies <strong>in</strong> ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliff, NJ:<br />

Prentice-Hall.<br />

Giff<strong>in</strong>, K. 1967. The contribution of studies of source credibility to a theory of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust <strong>in</strong> the communication process. Psychological Bullet<strong>in</strong>,<br />

68(2): 104-120.<br />

Goldsteen, R., Schorr, J. K. & Goldsteen, K. S. 1989. Longitud<strong>in</strong>al study of<br />

appraisal at Three Mile Island: Implications for life event research. Social<br />

Science and Medic<strong>in</strong>e, 28(4):389-398.<br />

Golembiewski, R. T. & McConkie, M. 1975. The centrality of <strong>in</strong>terpersonal<br />

trust <strong>in</strong> group processes. In G. L. Cooper (Ed.), Theories of group processes:<br />

131-185. London: John Wiley & Sons.<br />

Good. D. 1988. Individuals, <strong>in</strong>terpersonal relations, and trust. In D. Gambetta<br />

(Ed.), <strong>Trust</strong>: Mak<strong>in</strong>g and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 31-48. <strong>New</strong> York:<br />

Blackwell.<br />

Granovetter, M. 1985. Economic action and social structure: The problem of<br />

embeddedness. American Journal of Sociology, 91:481-510.<br />

Harnett, D. L. & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, L. L. 1980. Barga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g behavior: An<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternational study. Houston: Dame Publications.<br />

Holmes, J. G. 1991. <strong>Trust</strong> and the appraisal process <strong>in</strong> close relationships. In<br />

W. H. Jones & D. Perlman (Eds.), Advances <strong>in</strong> personal relationships, vol. 2:<br />

57-104. London: Jessica K<strong>in</strong>gsley.<br />

Holmes, J. G. & Rempel, J. K. 1989. <strong>Trust</strong> <strong>in</strong> close relationships. In C.<br />

Hendrick (Ed.), Close relationships: Review of personality and social<br />

psychology, vol. 10: 187-220.<br />

Jagac<strong>in</strong>ski, C. M. 1991. Personnel decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g: The importance of miss<strong>in</strong>g<br />

42


<strong>in</strong>formation. Journal of Applied Psychology, 76:19-30.<br />

Johnson, D. W. & Johnson, R. T. 1989. Cooperation and competition: Theory<br />

and research. Ed<strong>in</strong>a, MN: Interaction Book Company.<br />

Johnson-George, C. & Swap, W. C. 1982. Measurement of specific<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust: Construction and validation of a scale to assess trust <strong>in</strong> a<br />

specific other. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 43(6): 1306-1317.<br />

Kee, H. W. & Knox, R. E. 1970. Conceptual and methodological considerations<br />

<strong>in</strong> the study of trust and suspicion. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 14: 357-366.<br />

Kegan, D. L. & Rubenste<strong>in</strong>, A. H. 1973. <strong>Trust</strong>, effectiveness, and organizational<br />

development: A field study <strong>in</strong> R&D. Journal of Applied Behavioral Science,<br />

9(4): 495-513.<br />

Kelley, H. H. 1992. Common-sense psychology and scientific psychology.<br />

Annual Review of Psychology, 43:1-23.<br />

Kramer, R. M. 1994. The s<strong>in</strong>ister attribution error: Paranoid cognition and<br />

collective distrust <strong>in</strong> organizations. Motivation and Emotion, 18:199-230.<br />

Langer, E. J. 1975. The illusion of control. Journal of Personality and Social<br />

Psychology, 32(2): 311-328.<br />

Larzalere, R. E. & Huston, T. L. 1980. The dyadic trust scale: Toward<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust <strong>in</strong> close relationships. Journal of Marriage<br />

and the Family, 42: 595-604.<br />

Lewis, J. D. & Weigert, A. J. 1985a. <strong>Trust</strong> as a social reality. Social Forces, 63(4):<br />

967-985.<br />

Lewis, J. D. & Weigert, A. J. 1985b. Social atomism, holism, and trust. The<br />

Sociological Quarterly, 26(4) 455-471.<br />

Loomis, J. L. 1959. Communication, the development of trust, and<br />

cooperative behavior. Human Relations, 12: 305-315.<br />

Luhmann, N. 1988. Familiarity, confidence, trust: Problems and alternatives.<br />

In D. Gambetta (Ed.). <strong>Trust</strong>: Mak<strong>in</strong>g and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 94-<br />

107. <strong>New</strong> York: Blackwell.<br />

Luhmann, N. 1991. <strong>Trust</strong> and Power. Ann Arbor, MI: University Microfilms<br />

International.<br />

43


McGregor, D. 1967. The professional manager. <strong>New</strong> York: McGraw-Hill.<br />

McKnight, D. H. 1994. Unpublished data.<br />

Mishra, A. K. 1993. Break<strong>in</strong>g down organizational boundaries dur<strong>in</strong>g crisis:<br />

The role of mutual trust. Unpublished work<strong>in</strong>g paper, Pennsylvania State<br />

University.<br />

Mull<strong>in</strong>s, J. W. & Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs, L. L. 1994. Situational strength: A framework for<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g the role of <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g about proactive strategic<br />

change. Unpublished work<strong>in</strong>g paper, University of Denver and University of<br />

M<strong>in</strong>nesota.<br />

Orbell, J., Dawes, R. & Schwartz-Shea, P. 1994. <strong>Trust</strong>, social categories, and<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals: The case of gender. Motivation and Emotion, 18(2): 109-128.<br />

Organ, D. W. 1990. The motivational basis of organizational citizenship<br />

behavior. In B. M. Staw & L. L. Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs (Eds.), Research <strong>in</strong> <strong>Organizational</strong><br />

Behavior, 12:43-72, Greenwich, CN: JAI Press.<br />

Paese, P. W. & Sniezek, J. A. 1991. Influences on the appropriateness of<br />

confidence <strong>in</strong> judgment: Practice, effort, <strong>in</strong>formation, and decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>Organizational</strong> Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 48:100-130.<br />

Pellegr<strong>in</strong>o, E. D. 1991. <strong>Trust</strong> and distrust <strong>in</strong> professional ethics. In E. D.<br />

Pellegr<strong>in</strong>o, R. M. Veatch & J. P. Langan (Eds.), Ethics, trust and the<br />

professions: Philosophical and cultural aspects. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.:<br />

Georgetown University Press.<br />

Poole, M. S. & Van de Ven, A. H. 1989. Us<strong>in</strong>g paradox to build management<br />

and organization theories. Academy of Management Review, 14(4): 562-578.<br />

Rempel, J. K., Holmes, J. G., & Zanna, M. P. 1985. <strong>Trust</strong> <strong>in</strong> close relationships.<br />

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49(1): 95-112.<br />

Riker, W. H. 1971. The nature of trust. In J. T. Tedeschi (Ed.), Perspectives on<br />

Social Power, 63-81. Chicago: Ald<strong>in</strong>e Publish<strong>in</strong>g Company.<br />

R<strong>in</strong>g, P. S. & Van de Ven, A. H. 1994. Developmental processes of cooperative<br />

<strong>in</strong>terorganizational relationships. Academy of Management Review, 19(1):<br />

90-118.<br />

Rob<strong>in</strong>s, E. 1990. The study of <strong>in</strong>terdependence <strong>in</strong> marriage. In F. D. F<strong>in</strong>cham<br />

& T. N. Bradbury (Eds.), The psychology of marriage: Basic issues and<br />

applications: 59-86. <strong>New</strong> York: The Guilford Press.<br />

44


Rosenberg, 1957. Occupations and values. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.<br />

Rotter, J. B. 1967. A new scale for the measurement of <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust.<br />

Journal of Personality, 35(4): 651-665.<br />

Rotter, J. B. 1980. Interpersonal trust, trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess, and gullibility.<br />

American Psychologist, 35(1): 1-7.<br />

Scanzoni, J. 1979. Social exchange and behavioral <strong>in</strong>terdependence. In R. L.<br />

Burgess & T. L. Huston (Eds.), Social exchange <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g relationships:<br />

61-98. <strong>New</strong> York: Academic Press.<br />

Schlenker, B. R., Helm, B. & Tedeschi, J. T. 1973. The effects of personality and<br />

situational variables on behavioral trust. Journal of Personality and Social<br />

Psychology, 25: 419-427.<br />

Shapiro, S. P. 1987a. The social control of impersonal trust. American Journal<br />

of Sociology, 93(3): 623-658.<br />

Shapiro, S. P. 1987b. Polic<strong>in</strong>g trust. In C. D. Shear<strong>in</strong>g & P. C. Stenn<strong>in</strong>g (Eds.),<br />

Private polic<strong>in</strong>g: 194-220. <strong>New</strong>bury Park, CA: Sage.<br />

Shetzer, L. 1993. A social <strong>in</strong>formation process<strong>in</strong>g model of employee<br />

participation. Organization Science, 4(2): 252-268.<br />

Sitk<strong>in</strong>, S. B. & Roth, N. L. 1993. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the limited effectiveness of<br />

legalistic "remedies" for trust/distrust. Organization Science, 4(3): 367-392.<br />

Smith, G. F. 1990. The method of conceptual analysis: Applications <strong>in</strong> the<br />

management and organization sciences. Unpublished work<strong>in</strong>g paper.<br />

Information and Decision Sciences Department, University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota,<br />

M<strong>in</strong>neapolis.<br />

Solomon, L. 1960. The <strong>in</strong>fluence of some types of power relationships and<br />

game strategies upon the development of <strong>in</strong>terpersonal trust. Journal of<br />

Abnormal and Social Psychology, 61(2): 223-230.<br />

Ste<strong>in</strong>, J. 1971. The Random House dictionary of the English language. <strong>New</strong><br />

York: Random House.<br />

Sw<strong>in</strong>th, R. L. 1967. The establishment of the trust relationship. Journal of<br />

Conflict Resolution, 11:335-344.<br />

Tetlock, P. 1985. Accountability: The neglected social context of judgment and<br />

45


choice. In L. Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs and B. Staw (Eds.), Research <strong>in</strong> <strong>Organizational</strong><br />

Behavior, 7: 297-332. Greeenwich, CN: JAI Press.<br />

Thompson, J. D. 1967. Organizations <strong>in</strong> Action. <strong>New</strong> York: McGraw-Hill.<br />

Triandis, H. C., Feldman, J. M., Weldon, D. E., & Harvey, W. M. 1975.<br />

Ecosystem distrust and the hard-to-employ. Journal of Applied Psychology,<br />

60(1): 44-56.<br />

Van de Ven, A. H. 1989. Noth<strong>in</strong>g is quite so practical as a good theory.<br />

Academy of Management Review, 14: 486-489.<br />

White, H. C. 1992. Identity and control: A structural theory of social action.<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.<br />

Williams, B. 1988. Formal structures and social reality. In D. Gambetta (Ed.),<br />

<strong>Trust</strong>: Mak<strong>in</strong>g and break<strong>in</strong>g cooperative relations: 3-13. <strong>New</strong> York:<br />

Blackwell.<br />

Worchel, P. 1979. <strong>Trust</strong> and distrust. In W. G. Aust<strong>in</strong> & S. Worchel (Eds.), The<br />

social psychology of <strong>in</strong>tergroup relations: 174-187. Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole<br />

Publish<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Wrightsman, L. S. 1991. Interpersonal trust and attitudes toward human<br />

nature. In J. P. Rob<strong>in</strong>son, P. R. Shaver, & L. S. Wrightsman (Eds.), Measures<br />

of personality and social psychological attitudes: Vol. 1: Measures of social<br />

psychological attitudes: 373-412. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.<br />

Zand, D. E. 1972. <strong>Trust</strong> and managerial problem solv<strong>in</strong>g. Adm<strong>in</strong>istrative<br />

Science Quarterly, 17:229-239.<br />

Zucker, L. G. 1986. Production of trust: Institutional sources of economic<br />

structure, 1840-1920. In B. M. Staw & L. L. Cumm<strong>in</strong>gs (Eds.), Research <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Organizational</strong> Behavior, 8:53-111. Greenwich, CN: JAI Press.<br />

46

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!