21.07.2013 Views

Apartheid

Apartheid

Apartheid

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

22<br />

particular by armed frontier settlers. 11<br />

A further difference between South Africa and Israel is that South Africa was<br />

conquered by the barrel of the gun, whereas a large portion of what today is Israel was given<br />

in 1948 to the Jews by the United Nations and the British, who had ruled it as a colony up to<br />

that point, though more than half of what is today Israeli-controlled territory was later<br />

conquered with military force. The UN-granted independence of a Jewish state, one of the few<br />

elements of international law to which Israel adheres, however, is also in my view a<br />

superficial difference from the total illegitimacy of white supremacist rule in South Africa,<br />

mainly because Palestinians and Arabs had no voice at all in the UN at the time of the birth of<br />

the modern state of Israel, nor were they ever asked. The establishment of Israel therefore<br />

amounts to a de facto invasion by foreigners. One group of foreigners handed over the land to<br />

another, without even asking the indigenous people what they thought about this. Egypt under<br />

Greek rule presents a scenario much more similar to modern Israel than to South Africa in this<br />

regard. The country was taken over by the Macedonians and Greeks from earlier, colonialist<br />

occupiers, namely the Persians.<br />

In summary, these three apartheid societies share being so-called ‘civilized societies’.<br />

They all had strong centralized states. They all built cities. They all knew and used the<br />

inventions of phonographic writing, metallurgy, the wheel, the sail, money, and more. These<br />

are all inventions which only go back 5,000-6,000 years. I am not aware of any earlier<br />

apartheid societies, or of any that do not share these basic characteristics. This sets apartheid<br />

societies apart from the vast majority of human societies. But then they are also different from<br />

the vast majority of civilized societies. They are countries, to some extent even ‘civilizations’<br />

in their own right (though the root meaning of ‘civil’ may be overstretched by such strong<br />

states as apartheid states), where the land was conquered by force or mainly by force by an<br />

invading group of people who shared much with each other but little with the indigenous,<br />

conquered, and oppressed group of people, who remained the majority. My definition of<br />

apartheid is at the same time an analysis of these kinds of human rights violations. The second<br />

part of this book is the evidence that provides an empirical underpinning for the use of the<br />

concept of apartheid for Graeco-Roman Egypt, for South Africa under white rule, and for<br />

modern Israel.<br />

In the course of this first part I hope to point to the desirability of a powerful general<br />

theory of war and oppression, especially of one that takes the – in my opinion so far<br />

underestimated – role of ethnicism into account. 12 That underestimation is not necessarily one<br />

11 Cf. Fredrickson: Racism: A Short History, 2002: 4: ‘racism does not require the full and explicit support of the<br />

state and the law.’ This is a very simple but, in my opinion, crucial insight, necessary especially for the<br />

understanding of apartheid, but also for genocide and for domestic kinds of ethnicism.<br />

12 An opposite and pessimistic outlook can be found in US philosopher Richard Rorty’s post-modernist essay,<br />

‘The End of Leninism, Havel and Social Hope’, 1998: 239: ‘We shall have to get over the hope for a successor to<br />

Marxist theory, a general theory of oppression which will provide a fulcrum that lets us topple racial, economic,<br />

and gender injustice simultaneously.’ It is unclear what Rorty means exactly by ‘simultaneously’, but I see it as<br />

being a rather inclusive term in his context, which would justify my calling his idea ‘pessimistic’. Marxism, of<br />

course, never was as general a theory of oppression as many came to believe. (See, for instance, footnote 14,<br />

below.) By overemphasizing economic injustice in particular, it effectively – and to some extent probably<br />

unconsciously – marginalized other kinds of injustice. Feminist theory seems to do the same in favor of gender<br />

issues. (See Chapman: The Feminist Perspective, 1995: 113.) An improved theory of ethnicism should be careful<br />

not to perpetuate that trend. Not only if it understands itself as a successor to Marxist theory: it must be more<br />

differentiating and less reductionist than that. To cite just one example of reductionism, exaggerating the<br />

importance of racism, or rather, overlooking the importance of economic injustice: in an otherwise excellent<br />

treatment of the insidious and in many ways very special kinds of racism perpetrated against middle-class Blacks<br />

in the USA, author Ellis Cose mentions different kinds of discrimination in that country beside racism, including<br />

sexism, ageism, and discrimination of people due to their sexual orientation. In this context, however, he entirely<br />

forgets about economic discrimination and exploitation (of employees) and state discrimination against noncitizens<br />

in particular, but also against citizens, as well as the many mixed forms of oppression that exist between

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!