Apartheid

Apartheid Apartheid

media.manila.at
from media.manila.at More from this publisher
21.07.2013 Views

20 emphasizes hierarchies of gender, age and ‘arbitrary sets’. Ethnicity, race, class, tribe, and nation belong to the ‘arbitrary sets’ and are, according to this theory, developed only in human populations that have achieved a sustained production of economic surplus. 8 The multidisciplinary scholar and profound critic of eurocentric historiography, Martin Bernal, goes a step further and emphasizes urgency in this matter. He calls ‘European racism…by far the greatest social problem in the world today’. 9 I agree with Bernal, provided that ‘racism’ not only refer to violence, oppression, and discrimination according to (real or imagined) biological differences but also according to (real or imagined) cultural, i.e. acquired and/or specifically human differences, for instance, to language or religion. In order to avoid misunderstandings in this regard, and also in order to avoid using a biological term (‘race’) in contexts where it is most certainly not always applicable, e.g. in the ‘intra-semitic’ Jewish-Arab conflict, 10 I have chosen to employ ‘ethnicism’ as my label for the greatest social problem today. I will use ‘ethnicism’ rather than ‘ethnocentrism’ (and I also prefer ‘racism’ over ‘ethnocentrism’), because ‘ethnicism’ and ‘racism’, as Bernal and others have pointed out, presuppose power, whereas ‘ethnocentrism’ does not. Under ‘European’, in the quote from Bernal, one should of course not only refer to people in the northwest extremity of the Eurasian continent (and not to all of them, either) but also understand the now traditional – overwhelmingly white and male – political, economic and military elites of North and South America, Southern Africa, Oceania and elsewhere. My concept of ethnicism thus 8 Sidanius & Pratto: Social Dominance: An Intergroup Theory of Social Hierarchy and Oppression, 1999. Yet another approach to the main kinds of oppression in humans emphasizes anthropocentrism and speciesism. Analogous to ethnocentrism and racism in some regards, the former two are also both arrogant and devaluing stances, not against other humans, but against non-human animals. Anthropocentrism is characterized by ignorance of other animals’ needs and desires. Speciesism is stronger. It includes hate and contempt towards other forms of life. For contributions to the debate on these issues, see Regan: The Case for Animal Rights, 1985: 13-26; Warren: Difficulties with the Strong Animal Rights Position, 1987: 163-173; Callicott & Overholt: Traditional American Indian Attitudes Toward Nature, 1993: 57-78; Guha: Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness Preservation, 1989: 71-83; Löwstedt: Kultur oder Evolution? Eine Anthropologische Philosophie, 1995: 21-23, 52-56. 9 Bernal & Moore (ed.): Black Athena Writes Back: Martin Bernal Responds to His Critics, 2001: 75, 218. On Bernal’s predecessors on this issue, see footnote 106, below. Bernal, who deals mainly with racism of Whites against Africans, is keenly aware of the arbitrariness inherent to the application of the concept of race to human beings (ibid: 92; see also footnote 82 below), which in the end makes his concept of racism roughly equal to my concept of ethnicism. See, further, Kossek: Preface, Counter-Racisms, 1997. 10 A research paper on the genetic near-identity of Palestinians and Middle Eastern Jews that was published in the esteemed academic research journal, Human Immunology, was ‘withdrawn’ after publication in 2001, an unheard-of contradiction in terms in research publishing. Subscribers to the journal were actually instructed by the editor to rip out the pages containing the article, ‘The Origin of Palestinians and their Genetic Relatedness with Other Mediterranean Populations’, whose lead author is the previously well-respected Antonio Arnaiz- Villena, professor at Complutensa University in Madrid. The journal’s editor, Nicole Susio-Foca of Columbia University in New York, said she was forced to ‘repudiate’ the article after an avalanche of complaints about its ‘extreme political writing’. The article was taken away from Human Immunology’s website, and subsequent letters from the editorial department to libraries, universities and other subscribers around the world asked them to ignore or ‘preferably to physically remove the relevant pages’. Moreover, Arnaiz-Villena was fired from the board of the journal. In fact, the bulk of the article confirmed and corroborated earlier research findings that there is nothing special about genes of Jews. In doing so, however, the article also explicitly challenged the powerful claims that Jews are a unique, chosen people and that Judaism is a religion which can only be inherited, but not adopted. See McKie: Journal Axes Gene Research on Jews and Palestinians, 2001. On the various origins of European Jews, see footnotes 638-645, below. Throughout this book, I deliberately avoid usage of the ideologically loaded and imprecisely used terms, ‘anti-semitic’, ‘Anti-Semite’ and ‘anti-semitism’. This decision does not mean that I will not mention racism or ethnicism against Jews, nor that I condone or wish to belittle or deny these in any way. I will employ more precise and less confusing expressions, such as ‘anti-Jewish’ or ‘racist and anti-Jewish’ or ‘Judeophobia’, instead of ‘anti-Semitic’, ‘anti-semitism’, etc. On the selective, onesided, pars pro toto, biased, ideological, and pro-Israeli use of the latter terms in general parlance, which would, among other things, make anti-Arab racism a contradiction in terms, see Herman.: Anti-Semitism, 2002. See also N.N.: “Wer Kritik an Israel verbietet, zwingt mich, in einem Apartheidstaat zu leben”: Michel Warschawski spricht in Wien, 2003; Plitnick: Reclaiming Anti-Semitism, 2003 and Chapter II.9.3, below.

includes racism, but it also goes beyond it. It is more inclusive. After all, it would simply sound strange if one spoke of an Arab race and a Jewish race, or a Serb race and a Croatian race, instead of the respective ethnicities. A generalized and consistent theory of human rights and human rights violations, I believe, is now needed more than ever. Among other things, it should be able to solve the following apparent paradox: On the one hand, both class- and gender-based oppression, both classism and sexism, would fit in under the broad definition of ethnicism, proposed above. They both invoke real and imagined, cultural and biological differences between unevenly powerful, competing groups of people. On the other hand, to take just one example of ethnicism, an apartheid society is a class society par excellence, with very strong patriarchal and repressive aspects. Ethnicism and ‘domestic’ oppression are thus parts of each other, which is of course impossible from the powerful perspective of analytical logic. My investigation will not resolve this paradox. I merely wish to draw attention to it and to some of the other problems inherent in attempts to develop a general theory of human rights or oppression. The theory of ‘arbitrary sets’, cited above, does not seem able to solve the paradox either. In my view, it makes an unwarranted categorical distinction between biological and cultural dominance by distinguishing gender and age on the one hand from arbitrary sets, on the other, and thus to some extent it overlooks the numerous and indeed essentially arbitrary elements of gender and ageism. The distinction may therefore lead to confusions of sex with gender, and of age with ageism. Perhaps human rights as a whole must be thought over and thought differently. Maybe the current understandings of ‘ethnicity’, ‘race’, ‘economic class’ and ‘gender’ do not employ precise enough concepts for a general and improved theory of war and oppression. It is also possible that ‘war and oppression’ or ‘human rights violations’ are not the concepts that are ideally used for a general theory of racism, sexism, classism, etc. Unfortunately, I will not be able to pursue these basic theoretical issues further in this investigation. An important, additional kind of problem for any general theory of war and oppression is that oppression continues to exist today. Its perpetrators have learned to skillfully wipe their tracks and distract investigators as well as opponents. One example of this activity, which we will look at in some detail, is the Israeli society’s effort to make its legal system as different as possible from the South African apartheid laws, apparently only for cosmetic reasons of public relations, because the reality on the ground is obviously very similar, but Israel does not wish to be accused of apartheid, due to the illegality and the notoriety of South African apartheid as well as to its eventual and dramatic failure. A further motivation might well be that investigations into Israeli apartheid could successfully be derailed by getting caught up and entangled in relatively superficial differences such as those of legal texts and even legal structures. As we shall see in Chapters II.2.3 and II.4.3 respectively, the Israeli elites have successfully banned interfaith – i.e. interethnic – marriage, and minimized Palestinian land ownership in relative and absolute terms even more successfully than the South African apartheid elites were ever capable of minimizing black land ownership. And the Israelis did this without invoking the legal machinery of the state at all, unlike the South African elites. The problem whether these Israeli kinds of discrimination should be called ‘apartheid’ issues or not, however, is one that I hope to solve with a definitive, affirmative answer in the course of this investigation. Although a strong state, which discriminates against the indigenous majority, is a necessary precondition for apartheid, it is not always a sufficient one. Neither apartheid nor ethnicism in a wide sense needs the state or the law to support it with regard to every aspect of the human rights violations. Another example of this basic characteristic is that coercion and physical violence in apartheid societies are often practiced, not only by state employees, but also by vigilante and paramilitary individuals and groups, in 21

includes racism, but it also goes beyond it. It is more inclusive. After all, it would simply<br />

sound strange if one spoke of an Arab race and a Jewish race, or a Serb race and a Croatian<br />

race, instead of the respective ethnicities.<br />

A generalized and consistent theory of human rights and human rights violations, I<br />

believe, is now needed more than ever. Among other things, it should be able to solve the<br />

following apparent paradox: On the one hand, both class- and gender-based oppression, both<br />

classism and sexism, would fit in under the broad definition of ethnicism, proposed above.<br />

They both invoke real and imagined, cultural and biological differences between unevenly<br />

powerful, competing groups of people. On the other hand, to take just one example of<br />

ethnicism, an apartheid society is a class society par excellence, with very strong patriarchal<br />

and repressive aspects. Ethnicism and ‘domestic’ oppression are thus parts of each other,<br />

which is of course impossible from the powerful perspective of analytical logic.<br />

My investigation will not resolve this paradox. I merely wish to draw attention to it<br />

and to some of the other problems inherent in attempts to develop a general theory of human<br />

rights or oppression. The theory of ‘arbitrary sets’, cited above, does not seem able to solve<br />

the paradox either. In my view, it makes an unwarranted categorical distinction between<br />

biological and cultural dominance by distinguishing gender and age on the one hand from<br />

arbitrary sets, on the other, and thus to some extent it overlooks the numerous and indeed<br />

essentially arbitrary elements of gender and ageism. The distinction may therefore lead to<br />

confusions of sex with gender, and of age with ageism.<br />

Perhaps human rights as a whole must be thought over and thought differently. Maybe<br />

the current understandings of ‘ethnicity’, ‘race’, ‘economic class’ and ‘gender’ do not employ<br />

precise enough concepts for a general and improved theory of war and oppression. It is also<br />

possible that ‘war and oppression’ or ‘human rights violations’ are not the concepts that are<br />

ideally used for a general theory of racism, sexism, classism, etc. Unfortunately, I will not be<br />

able to pursue these basic theoretical issues further in this investigation.<br />

An important, additional kind of problem for any general theory of war and oppression<br />

is that oppression continues to exist today. Its perpetrators have learned to skillfully wipe their<br />

tracks and distract investigators as well as opponents. One example of this activity, which we<br />

will look at in some detail, is the Israeli society’s effort to make its legal system as different as<br />

possible from the South African apartheid laws, apparently only for cosmetic reasons of<br />

public relations, because the reality on the ground is obviously very similar, but Israel does<br />

not wish to be accused of apartheid, due to the illegality and the notoriety of South African<br />

apartheid as well as to its eventual and dramatic failure. A further motivation might well be<br />

that investigations into Israeli apartheid could successfully be derailed by getting caught up<br />

and entangled in relatively superficial differences such as those of legal texts and even legal<br />

structures. As we shall see in Chapters II.2.3 and II.4.3 respectively, the Israeli elites have<br />

successfully banned interfaith – i.e. interethnic – marriage, and minimized Palestinian land<br />

ownership in relative and absolute terms even more successfully than the South African<br />

apartheid elites were ever capable of minimizing black land ownership. And the Israelis did<br />

this without invoking the legal machinery of the state at all, unlike the South African elites.<br />

The problem whether these Israeli kinds of discrimination should be called ‘apartheid’<br />

issues or not, however, is one that I hope to solve with a definitive, affirmative answer in the<br />

course of this investigation. Although a strong state, which discriminates against the<br />

indigenous majority, is a necessary precondition for apartheid, it is not always a sufficient<br />

one. Neither apartheid nor ethnicism in a wide sense needs the state or the law to support it<br />

with regard to every aspect of the human rights violations. Another example of this basic<br />

characteristic is that coercion and physical violence in apartheid societies are often practiced,<br />

not only by state employees, but also by vigilante and paramilitary individuals and groups, in<br />

21

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!