12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>The</strong> Global Argument from <strong>Evil</strong> 67<br />

the conclusion <strong>of</strong> the argument follows logically from its premises), at<br />

least one <strong>of</strong> the premises <strong>of</strong> the argument has to be false if my story,<br />

my ‘‘defense’’, is true. If, therefore, my audience reacts to my story<br />

about God and evil as I hope they will, they will immediately draw the<br />

conclusion I want them to draw: that, for all they know, at least one <strong>of</strong><br />

the premises <strong>of</strong> the argument from evil is false. 7<br />

Some people, if they are familiar with the usual conduct <strong>of</strong> debates<br />

about the argument from evil may be puzzled by my bringing the notion<br />

‘‘a very real possibility’’ into my fictional debate at this early point. It<br />

has become something <strong>of</strong> a custom for critics <strong>of</strong> the argument from<br />

evil first to discuss the so-called logical problem <strong>of</strong> evil, the problem <strong>of</strong><br />

finding a defense that satisfies no stronger condition than this, that it<br />

be free from internal logical contradiction; when the critics have dealt<br />

with this problem to their own satisfaction, as they always do, they go<br />

on to discuss the so-called evidential (or probabilistic) problem <strong>of</strong> evil,<br />

the problem <strong>of</strong> finding a defense that (among certain other desirable<br />

features) represents, in my phrase, a real possibility. If defense counsels<br />

followed a parallel strategy in courts <strong>of</strong> law, they would first try to prove<br />

that their clients’ innocence was logically consistent with the evidence<br />

by telling stories (by presenting ‘‘alternative theories <strong>of</strong> the crime’’)<br />

involving things like twins separated at birth, operatic coincidences, and<br />

mental telepathy; only after they had shown by this method that their<br />

clients’ innocence was logically consistent with the evidence, would they<br />

go on to try to raise real doubts in the minds <strong>of</strong> jurors about the guilt<br />

<strong>of</strong> their clients.<br />

As I said in the first lecture, I find this division <strong>of</strong> the problem<br />

artificial and unhelpful—although I think it is easy to see why it arose.<br />

It arose because the earliest attempts to use the argument from evil<br />

to prove the non-existence <strong>of</strong> God—I mean the earliest attempts by<br />

analytical philosophers—were attempts to prove that the statement<br />

‘God and evil both exist’ was logically self-contradictory. And various<br />

philosophers, most notably Nelson Pike and Alvin Plantinga, attempted<br />

to show that these supposed pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> logical self-contradiction were far<br />

from convincing. 8 <strong>The</strong> debate evolved fairly quickly out <strong>of</strong> this early,<br />

‘‘logical’’ stage into a discussion <strong>of</strong> a much more interesting question:<br />

whether the statement ‘God and evil both exist’ could be shown to be<br />

probably false or unreasonable to believe. Discussions <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong><br />

evil even today tend to recapitulate this episode in the evolution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> the argument from evil.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!