12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Philosophical Failure 51<br />

to defend the following conclusion, although I shall not explicitly do<br />

so: if the considerations I shall present indeed show that the argument<br />

from evil is incapable <strong>of</strong> turning neutral agnostics into atheists, these<br />

considerations will also show that the argument from evil is incapable<br />

<strong>of</strong> turning neutral agnostics into weighted agnostics.<br />

To return to the main line <strong>of</strong> argument, Atheist and <strong>The</strong>ist are<br />

carrying on a debate before an audience <strong>of</strong> ideal agnostics. <strong>The</strong> debate is<br />

divided into two innings or halves. In one, Atheist attempts to turn the<br />

agnostics into atheists like herself. In the other, <strong>The</strong>ist attempts to turn<br />

the agnostics into theists like himself. (I am going to make Atheist a<br />

woman and <strong>The</strong>ist a man. I make my debaters <strong>of</strong> opposite sexes to make<br />

things easier for myself: it will automatically be clear which <strong>of</strong> them<br />

any third-person-singular pronoun refers to. As to the match <strong>of</strong> sex and<br />

doctrine I have chosen—well, I suppose I could get into trouble either<br />

way.) In these lectures, we shall be concerned only with one half <strong>of</strong> the<br />

debate, Atheist’s attempt to turn the agnostics into atheists. And, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, I shall be concerned only with her attempt to do so by laying one<br />

particular argument, the argument from evil, before the agnostics. Here<br />

is a very general, abstract description <strong>of</strong> the course the debate will take.<br />

Atheist opens the debate by laying out the argument from evil. (We<br />

shall assume that the argument she presents is formally valid.) <strong>The</strong>ist<br />

then attempts to cast doubt on at least one premise <strong>of</strong> the argument.<br />

(Of course, one way to ‘‘cast doubt on’’ a proposition is to show it to be<br />

false,but<strong>The</strong>istisnotrequired to do that.) And the doubts are to exist<br />

in the minds <strong>of</strong> the agnostics; it is not required <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ist that he in any<br />

way weaken Atheist’s allegiance to the premises he is attempting to cast<br />

doubt on. Atheist then presents a rejoinder to this reply; perhaps she<br />

finds some flaw in <strong>The</strong>ist’s counterargument (a flaw that the agnostics<br />

will be willing to accept as such; it will be a waste <strong>of</strong> time for her to point<br />

to something she sees as a flaw if they don’t see it as a flaw); perhaps she<br />

reformulates her argument in such a way that the reformulated argument<br />

escapes <strong>The</strong>ist’s criticism; that’s really up to her: she can say anything<br />

she likes. When she has done this, <strong>The</strong>ist replies to the rejoinder to his<br />

criticism <strong>of</strong> the argument. And so it goes—for as long as at least one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the participants still has something to say. In the end, we shall have<br />

to ask ourselves what the agnostics will make <strong>of</strong> all this. How will they<br />

respond? Will they become atheists, or will they remain agnostics? If<br />

the former, Atheist’s argument is a success. If the latter, it is a failure.<br />

(What if some <strong>of</strong> them are converted and some are not? Well, I’ll make<br />

an idealizing assumption: since the debaters and the audience are ideal

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!