The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

commonsenseatheism.com
from commonsenseatheism.com More from this publisher
12.07.2013 Views

Philosophical Failure 49 be able to convert the agnostics to realism, despite the best efforts of the nominalist to prevent their conversion. It would seem, however, that the first possibility vanishes if the realist knows of R, and that the second possibility vanishes if the nominalist knows of N. Consider the first case. (We need not also consider the second: what we say about the first will apply equally to the second.) Norma the nominalist presents the agnostics with the argument N, and this would, in the end, be sufficient to convert them to nominalism—if Ronald the realist did not know of R. But suppose that Ronald does know of R. Then, it would seem, he does have a way to prevent the agnostics from assenting to the premises of N: he need only present R. If R is an argument that would, in the absence of N, have succeeded in converting the agnostics to realism, it seems that it ought, in the presence of N, to have the power to convince the agnostics that at least one of the premises of N might well be false. (Remember: Ronald’s task with respect to N is not to convince the agnostics that at least one of the premises of N is false, but only that at least one of its premises may well be false. And he need not identify some particular premise or premises of N as doubtful; he need only establish that the proposition that all the premises of N are true is open to reasonable doubt.) Would there not be, in this case, in Hume’s fine phrase, ‘‘a mutual destruction of arguments’’, a destruction that would leave the agnostics agnostics? I will mention but not discuss one final problem for the criterion of success I have proposed. How can this criterion be applied to philosophical arguments whose conclusions are doubted by no one or almost no one—arguments for the reality of motion, the reliability of induction or sense-perception, or the existence of an external world or other minds? I mention this problem out of vanity, lest you conclude I had not thought of it. I will not discuss it because to do so would take us out of our way, and the argument we shall be considering, the argument from evil, is not of this sort. We have, then, our criterion of success and failure in philosophical argument. My purpose is to defend the conclusion that the argument from evil is to be judged a failure by the—I think—very liberal terms of this criterion. Let us therefore imagine a debate. Two ideal characters, whom I shall call Atheist and Theist, are debating before an audience of ideal agnostics—and now we understand by this term agnostics of the common-or-garden variety, people who neither believe that God exists nor believe that God does not exist. 3 But our ideal agnostics are not

50 Philosophical Failure mere agnostics. They are, so to speak, neutral agnostics. When I was using a debate about nominalism and realism as my example of an ideal debate, I said the following about the audience : ‘‘they... stand to the question whether there are universals as you, no doubt, stand to the question whether the number of Douglas firs in Canada is odd or even.’’ This sort of neutrality is no consequence of agnosticism simpliciter. I am an agnostic in respect of the question whether there are intelligent non-human beings inhabiting a planet within, say, 10,000 light-years of the Earth. That is, I do not believe that such beings exist, and I do not believe that no such beings exist. But here is a belief I do have: that the existence of such beings is vastly improbable. (If I were a bookie, and if there were some way to settle the bet, I’d be willing to give anyone who wanted to bet that there were such beings just about any odds I needed to give him to get him to place his bet with me and not some rival bookie.) There is no inconsistency in saying both that one does not believe (does not have the belief) that p and that one regards p as very, very probable, although the unfortunate currency of the idea of ‘‘degrees of belief’’ has caused some confusion on this point. After all, the proposition that Jill is in Budapest today and the proposition that it’s highly probable that Jill is in Budapest today are distinct propositions, neither of which entails the other, and it is possible to accept the latter without accepting the former. I would suppose that most real agnostics, most actual people who do profess and call themselves agnostics, are not neutral agnostics. Most agnostics I have discussed these matters with think that it’s pretty improbable that there’s a God. Their relation to the proposition that God exists is very much like my relation to the proposition that there are intelligent non-human beings inhabiting some planet within 10,000 light-years of the Earth. And this consideration suggests a possible objection to my definition of philosophical success. Call those agnostics who think that it’s very improbable that there is aGodweighted agnostics. An argument for the non-existence of God, the argument from evil for example, might be a failure by my criterion because it lacked the power to transform ideal (and hence neutral) agnostics into atheists. But it might, consistently with that, have the power to transform neutral agnostics into weighted agnostics. If it does, isn’titratherhardonittocallitafailure?Inresponse,Iwillsayonlythat if you want to revise the definition to take account of this, I don’t object. In practice, it will make no real difference. I’m going to try to convince you that the argument from evil has not got the power to transform ideal (and hence neutral) agnostics into atheists. But I should be willing

Philosophical Failure 49<br />

be able to convert the agnostics to realism, despite the best efforts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

nominalist to prevent their conversion. It would seem, however, that<br />

the first possibility vanishes if the realist knows <strong>of</strong> R, and that the second<br />

possibility vanishes if the nominalist knows <strong>of</strong> N. Consider the first<br />

case. (We need not also consider the second: what we say about the first<br />

will apply equally to the second.) Norma the nominalist presents the<br />

agnostics with the argument N, and this would, in the end, be sufficient<br />

to convert them to nominalism—if Ronald the realist did not know <strong>of</strong><br />

R. But suppose that Ronald does know <strong>of</strong> R. <strong>The</strong>n, it would seem, he<br />

does have a way to prevent the agnostics from assenting to the premises<br />

<strong>of</strong> N: he need only present R. If R is an argument that would, in the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> N, have succeeded in converting the agnostics to realism, it<br />

seems that it ought, in the presence <strong>of</strong> N, to have the power to convince<br />

the agnostics that at least one <strong>of</strong> the premises <strong>of</strong> N might well be false.<br />

(Remember: Ronald’s task with respect to N is not to convince the<br />

agnostics that at least one <strong>of</strong> the premises <strong>of</strong> N is false, but only that<br />

at least one <strong>of</strong> its premises may well be false. And he need not identify<br />

some particular premise or premises <strong>of</strong> N as doubtful; he need only<br />

establish that the proposition that all the premises <strong>of</strong> N are true is open<br />

to reasonable doubt.) Would there not be, in this case, in Hume’s fine<br />

phrase, ‘‘a mutual destruction <strong>of</strong> arguments’’, a destruction that would<br />

leave the agnostics agnostics?<br />

I will mention but not discuss one final problem for the criterion<br />

<strong>of</strong> success I have proposed. How can this criterion be applied to<br />

philosophical arguments whose conclusions are doubted by no one or<br />

almost no one—arguments for the reality <strong>of</strong> motion, the reliability <strong>of</strong><br />

induction or sense-perception, or the existence <strong>of</strong> an external world or<br />

other minds? I mention this problem out <strong>of</strong> vanity, lest you conclude<br />

I had not thought <strong>of</strong> it. I will not discuss it because to do so would<br />

take us out <strong>of</strong> our way, and the argument we shall be considering, the<br />

argument from evil, is not <strong>of</strong> this sort.<br />

We have, then, our criterion <strong>of</strong> success and failure in philosophical<br />

argument. My purpose is to defend the conclusion that the argument<br />

from evil is to be judged a failure by the—I think—very liberal terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> this criterion.<br />

Let us therefore imagine a debate. Two ideal characters, whom I<br />

shall call Atheist and <strong>The</strong>ist, are debating before an audience <strong>of</strong> ideal<br />

agnostics—and now we understand by this term agnostics <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common-or-garden variety, people who neither believe that God exists<br />

nor believe that God does not exist. 3 But our ideal agnostics are not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!