12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

48 Philosophical Failure<br />

<strong>of</strong> our contemporaries. A present-day advocate <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

finitude <strong>of</strong> space could, for example, point to the fact that many scientists<br />

think that it is a real possibility that space is finite (although unbounded),<br />

a fact that could not have been appealed to in the eighteenth century.<br />

And it is not parochial <strong>of</strong> us to be specially interested in the question <strong>of</strong><br />

which philosophical arguments are successes given what we know today,<br />

or what is for all practical purposes the same thing, what we think we<br />

know today. After all, we know lots <strong>of</strong> things <strong>of</strong> philosophical relevance<br />

that were not known in the Age <strong>of</strong> Reason or the Middle Ages or in<br />

classical antiquity. And we know that lots <strong>of</strong> things that people in those<br />

times and cultures thought they knew are false—things whose falsity is<br />

<strong>of</strong> great philosophical importance.<br />

Here is another important question that confronts my criterion, a<br />

question that confronts it in virtue <strong>of</strong> my limiting membership in the<br />

audience <strong>of</strong> agnostics to our contemporaries. Might there not be an<br />

argument that’s an absolutely perfect and compelling argument in the<br />

eyes <strong>of</strong> God, so to speak, but that would not be a success by my criterion<br />

because <strong>of</strong> some misconception universal in our time and culture?<br />

(And, <strong>of</strong> course, the opposite possibility also exists: an argument might<br />

convince everyone who shares the misconceptions <strong>of</strong> the present day,<br />

but be an abject failure in the eyes <strong>of</strong> God.) <strong>The</strong>se possibilities are real,<br />

but I insist that the criterion is an interesting and useful one despite<br />

their reality. It would be an interesting thing to establish that a certain<br />

argument was a success in my sense, even if there were some deeper,<br />

Platonic sense, in which it might be a failure.<br />

Here is a third question. Might it not be that there was an argument<br />

for p that was a success by my proposed criterion and another argument,<br />

an argument for the denial <strong>of</strong> p, thatwasalso a success? And isn’t this<br />

possibility an embarrassment for the criterion? Shouldn’t a criterion<br />

<strong>of</strong> success in philosophical argument rule out a priori any possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> there being two arguments, both successes, whose conclusions are<br />

logical contradictories? But does this possibility in fact exist? Only, I<br />

think, if we suppose that one <strong>of</strong> the two arguments is unknown to<br />

the debaters. <strong>The</strong>re is no contradiction in supposing that there exist,<br />

Platonically speaking, two arguments, N an argument for nominalism<br />

and R an argument for realism, such that (i) if the nominalist knew <strong>of</strong><br />

N and the realist did not know <strong>of</strong> R, the nominalist, wielding N, would<br />

be able to convert the agnostics to nominalism, despite the best efforts<br />

<strong>of</strong> the realist to prevent their conversion, and (ii) if the realist knew <strong>of</strong><br />

R and the nominalist did not know <strong>of</strong> N, the realist, wielding R, would

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!