12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

44 Philosophical Failure<br />

thesis. Although the ideal philosophers and ideal circumstances <strong>of</strong> the<br />

debate I have imagined do not exist, reasonable approximations <strong>of</strong> them<br />

have existed at various times and places, and the recorded results <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophical debate seem (to me at least) to tell very strongly against<br />

the thesis that any argument has this sort <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

Letmemovetoanotherpicture<strong>of</strong>whatitisforaphilosophical<br />

argument to be a success, a suggestion based on another model <strong>of</strong><br />

debate. Let us not think <strong>of</strong> a debate as an attempt by two persons with<br />

opposed views each to convert the other. Let us think <strong>of</strong> a debate rather<br />

on the forensic model. On this model, two representatives <strong>of</strong> opposed<br />

positions carry on an exchange <strong>of</strong> arguments before an audience, and<br />

their purpose is not to convert each other but rather to convert the<br />

audience—an audience whose members (in theory) bear no initial<br />

allegiance to either position, although they regard the question ‘‘Which<br />

<strong>of</strong> these two positions is correct?’’ as an interesting and important one.<br />

This situation, too, we shall consider in an ideal form. We retain the<br />

idealization <strong>of</strong> the two debaters that we set out in describing the first<br />

model, and the idealization <strong>of</strong> the circumstances <strong>of</strong> debate as well. We<br />

proceed to an idealization <strong>of</strong> the audience.<br />

<strong>The</strong> audience is composed <strong>of</strong> what we may call agnostics. That is, they<br />

are agnostic as regards the subject-matter <strong>of</strong> the debate. If the debate<br />

is about nominalism and realism (let us continue to use that famous<br />

debate as our example), each member <strong>of</strong> the audience will have no<br />

initial opinion about whether there are universals, and no predilection,<br />

emotional or otherwise, for nominalism or for realism. As regards a<br />

tendency to accept one answer or the other, they will stand to the<br />

question whether there are universals as you, no doubt, stand to the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> whether the number <strong>of</strong> Douglas firs in Canada is odd or<br />

even. But that is not the whole story; for you, no doubt, have no desire<br />

to have the question whether that number is odd or even settled. My<br />

imaginary agnostics are not like that in respect <strong>of</strong> the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> universals. <strong>The</strong>y would very much like to come to some<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> reasoned opinion about the existence <strong>of</strong> universals—in fact, to<br />

achieve knowledge on that matter if it were possible. <strong>The</strong>y don’t care<br />

which position, nominalism or realism, they end up accepting, but they<br />

very much want to end up accepting one or the other. And, <strong>of</strong> course, we<br />

attribute to them the same unlimited leisure and superhuman patience<br />

as we previously ascribed to our ideal nominalist and ideal realist—and<br />

the same high intelligence and high degree <strong>of</strong> logical and philosophical<br />

acumen and intellectual honesty.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!