12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

42 Philosophical Failure<br />

which premises <strong>of</strong> the argument from evil might seem doubtful to the<br />

members <strong>of</strong> an ideal audience—an audience composed <strong>of</strong> people whose<br />

nature is suggested by that ‘‘ideal observer’’ to which certain ethical<br />

theories appeal. But in trying, in my own mind, to flesh out this idea,<br />

I have found it necessary to consider not only an ideal audience but an<br />

ideal presentation <strong>of</strong> an argument to that audience. <strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> an<br />

ideal presentation <strong>of</strong> an argument, I think, is best explained by supposing<br />

that argument to be presented within the context <strong>of</strong> an ideal debate.<br />

Let us take a moment to think about what a debate is, for there is<br />

more than one way to understand this idea. When philosophers think<br />

<strong>of</strong> a debate—at least this is what my experience <strong>of</strong> philosophers seems<br />

to show—they usually think <strong>of</strong> two people, generally two philosophers,<br />

arguing with each other. On this model, so to call it, <strong>of</strong> debate, a debate<br />

comprises two people who hold opposed positions on some issue each<br />

trying to convert the other to his own position—and each trying himself<br />

to avoid being converted to the other’s position. Thus, a debate about<br />

the reality <strong>of</strong> universals would be <strong>of</strong> this nature: Norma the nominalist<br />

and Ronald the realist carry on an exchange <strong>of</strong> arguments; Norma’s<br />

purpose in this exchange is to turn Ronald into a nominalist (and, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, to prevent Ronald from turning her into a realist), and Ronald’s<br />

purpose is to turn Norma into a realist (and, <strong>of</strong> course, to prevent<br />

Norma from turning him into a nominalist). This model <strong>of</strong> debate<br />

suggests a definition <strong>of</strong> what it is for a philosophical argument to be a<br />

success. A successful argument for nominalism would be an argument<br />

that a nominalist could use to turn a realist into a nominalist—and<br />

a successful argument for realism would be similarly understood. But<br />

how are we to understand the generality implied by the phrases ‘‘a<br />

nominalist’’ and ‘‘a realist’’? Perhaps we could make this generality<br />

more explicit, and therefore clearer, by saying something like this: A<br />

successful argument for nominalism would be an argument that any<br />

ideal nominalist could use to turn any ideal realist into a nominalist. By<br />

ideal nominalists, I understand nominalists who satisfy the following<br />

two conditions, or something that could be obtained from them by a<br />

minimal amount <strong>of</strong> tinkering and adjustment <strong>of</strong> detail:<br />

ideal nominalists are <strong>of</strong> the highest possible intelligence and <strong>of</strong> the highest<br />

degree <strong>of</strong> philosophical and logical acumen, and they are intellectually<br />

honest in this sense: when they are considering an argument for some<br />

thesis, they do their best to understand the argument and to evaluate it<br />

dispassionately.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!