12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Philosophical Failure 39<br />

suggestion I borrow from Alvin Plantinga’s book God and Other Minds.<br />

(I don’t mean to imply that Plantinga endorsed this suggestion.) <strong>The</strong><br />

argument is a success if it starts with premises almost no sane, rational<br />

person would doubt, and proceeds by logical steps whose validity almost<br />

no sane, rational person would dispute, to the conclusion that God<br />

exists. Otherwise, it is a failure. (I say ‘‘almost no sane, rational person’’<br />

because <strong>of</strong> cases like the following. St Thomas’s First Way begins with<br />

the premise that some things change. And Zeno denies that anything<br />

changes. I should not want to say that Thomas’s argument was defective,<br />

not a success, simply because it assumed without argument that change<br />

was a real feature <strong>of</strong> the world. And I should also not want to say that<br />

Zeno was insane or irrational.)<br />

Only one thing can be said against this standard <strong>of</strong> philosophical<br />

success: if it were accepted, almost no argument for any substantive<br />

philosophical thesis would count as a success. (I say ‘‘substantive philosophical<br />

thesis’’ because I concede that there are, so to call them, minor<br />

philosophical theses—such as the thesis that, whatever knowledge may<br />

be, it is not simply justified true belief—for which there are arguments<br />

that should convert any rational person. I call this thesis minor<br />

not because I think that the problem <strong>of</strong> the analysis <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

is unimportant, but precisely because the thesis does not constitute<br />

an analysis <strong>of</strong> knowledge; its message is only that a certain proposed<br />

analysis is a failure. Or suppose, as many have supposed, that Gödel’s<br />

incompleteness results show, establish that the formalists were wrong<br />

about the nature <strong>of</strong> mathematics. <strong>The</strong> thesis that formalism is false may<br />

in one way be an important philosophical thesis, but only because a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> people had thought that formalism was true. It is not a substantive<br />

philosophical thesis in the way formalism itself is. I am inclined to think<br />

that most philosophical theses for which there is an argument that is<br />

a success by the standard we are considering are <strong>of</strong> this general sort,<br />

theses to the effect that a certain analysis does not work, or that some<br />

plausible generalization has exceptions, or that some argument turns on<br />

a logical fallacy.) If there were an argument, an argument for a substantive<br />

philosophical thesis, that was a success by this standard, there<br />

would be a substantive philosophical thesis such that every philosopher<br />

who rejected it was either uninformed—unaware <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

certain argument—or irrational or mad. Are there any? Well, I used to<br />

think that Church’s <strong>The</strong>sis (a rather recondite thesis in the philosophy<br />

<strong>of</strong> mathematics—it has to do with how to provide a certain important<br />

intuitive concept with a mathematically precise definition) could be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!