12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

38 Philosophical Failure<br />

Note the word ‘must’ here. <strong>The</strong> author writes as if he or she—never<br />

mind who it is—has established the conclusion that if one regards the<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> material individuals as universals, one must either accept<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> ‘‘elements elusive or opaque to the understanding’’ or<br />

else accept a bundle theory <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> material individuals. If you<br />

say that you could produce a much clearer example <strong>of</strong> a philosopher<br />

who believes he has proved something <strong>of</strong> philosophical interest, I will<br />

remind you that I really did find these words on two pages chosen at<br />

random (and if you recognize the passage and think I meant to pillory<br />

a particular author, I will remind you <strong>of</strong> the same thing). I mean these<br />

words to be an example <strong>of</strong> something absolutely typical in philosophical<br />

writing. We all write this way. We have no other way <strong>of</strong> writing—not,<br />

at least, when we are defending a conclusion. <strong>The</strong>se lectures themselves<br />

will provide a fund, a plethora in fact, <strong>of</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> the very conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophical argument that I am now attempting to undermine.<br />

That conception <strong>of</strong> philosophical argument is an ‘‘all but irresistible<br />

idea’’ because it is inherent in the way we philosophers have learned<br />

to write philosophy—not that I have an alternative way <strong>of</strong> writing<br />

philosophy to recommend to you. We are, after all, philosophers. We<br />

do not, we flatter ourselves, simply assert: we argue. To argue is to put<br />

forward reasons for believing things. And what is the point <strong>of</strong> putting<br />

forward reasons for believing things if those reasons are not decisive?<br />

That this rhetorical question represents the way we think, or a way we<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten think, is implied by the way we treat the reasons we present. <strong>The</strong><br />

reasons we present our readers with when we write do generally seem<br />

decisive to us when we are putting them forward—this is shown by the<br />

fact that we do not generally immediately qualify our presentations <strong>of</strong><br />

reasons for accepting philosophical theses with some variant on ‘‘But <strong>of</strong><br />

course these considerations are merely suggestive, not decisive’’.<br />

But if argument in philosophy does not have the enviable indisputability<br />

<strong>of</strong> mathematical pro<strong>of</strong>, what good is it? Is there even such a<br />

thing as success and failure in philosophical argument? If philosophical<br />

arguments are not pro<strong>of</strong>s, what can we mean by calling them successes<br />

or failures? What can I mean when I say that the argument I am going<br />

to examine in these lectures, the argument from evil, is a failure?<br />

Let us consider an example. Suppose someone <strong>of</strong>fers an argument<br />

for some philosophical thesis—for the existence <strong>of</strong> God, it may be,<br />

or for the non-existence <strong>of</strong> universals, or for the impossibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

private language. Let us say an argument for the existence <strong>of</strong> God. What<br />

would it be for this argument to be a success or a failure? Here is a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!