The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

commonsenseatheism.com
from commonsenseatheism.com More from this publisher
12.07.2013 Views

Notes 159 burden of proof falls on the state.’’ That is to say, in a criminal court, the state (or the Crown) bears a burden labeled ‘proof ’ or ‘having to prove things’, and the defense does not. And this is not because a proposition of the form ‘‘The accused is guilty as charged’’ is always inherently less plausible than its denial (that, after all, is often not the case). It is because of a rule that rests on a moral, not an epistemological, foundation: the court presumes the accused to be innocent till proved guilty—and, in a trial by jury, instructs the jurors to presume the same. In our imaginary debate about the existence of God (in the part of it that figures in these lectures, the part in which Atheist attempts to turn the agnostics into fellow atheists by laying the argument from evil before them), the burden labeled ‘proof ’ is carried by Atheist—and, as is the case with the counsel for the prosecution in a criminal trial, this is not because the proposition that is the conclusion of her argument is inherently less plausible than its denial. (Some will say it is, and some will say it isn’t; whether it is, is irrelevant to where the burden of proof falls.) Unlike the rules that govern the procedures of a criminal court, however, the rules that govern our debate are not founded on moral considerations. The burden of proof, the burden of having to prove things (or at any rate of having to provide arguments for them), falls on Atheist, and does not fall on Theist (at this point in the debate), because it is she and not he whose job it is to change someone’s beliefs. 3. But does ‘agnostic’ not mean ‘someone who does not know whether God exists’? If we so understand ‘agnostic’, we must understand ‘someone who does not know whether God exists’ to mean ‘someone who does not profess to know whether God exists’. (In the most literal sense of the words ‘‘knows whether’’, someone who knows whether God exists is someone who, if God exists, knows that God exists, and who, if God does not exist, knows that God does not exist. In the most literal sense of the words, therefore, if God exists, no atheist knows whether God exists, and if God does not exist, no theist knows whether God exists.) A person who does not profess to know whether God exists is a person who is willing to say (with perfect sincerity), ‘‘I do not know whether God exists.’’ And anyone who is willing to say, with perfect sincerity, ‘‘I do not know whether God exists’’ will, unless that person is involved in some sort of pragmatic contradiction, neither believe that God exists nor believe that God does not exist. And anyone who neither believes that God exists nor believes that God does not exist, should be willing to say—prudential considerations aside—‘‘I do not know whether God exists.’’ I could present arguments for these assertions, but I will not, for it will make no difference to my larger argument whether they are true. Instead of defending them, I will simply define an ‘agnostic’ as someone who does not believe that—lacks the belief that—God exists and does not believe that—lacks the belief that—God does not exist. What I said about pragmatic contradictions and related

160 Notes matters was said only to defend my application of the term ‘agnostic’ to people simply on the ground that they lack certain beliefs—an application that some might fault on etymological grounds. If the sense of ‘agnostic’ I have introduced by fiat is in any way objectionable, it is at any rate clear what I mean by the term, and that is all that really matters. (But I do think that it captures what most people today mean by the term, even if what they mean is not so noble as what its inventor, Thomas Henry Huxley, meant by it.) And, in any case, it is ‘‘agnostics’’ in just this sense who must make up my audience if I am to apply to arguments against the existence of God the criterion of success in philosophical argument that I have set out. 4. These arguments can be found in my book An Essay on Free Will. 5. If so, my proposed criterion of philosophical success and failure has the same consequence as the two criteria I have rejected: most if not all arguments for substantive philosophical conclusions are failures. And it wasthisconsequencethatwasmyreasonforrejectingthosecriteria.Should I not, therefore, for just this reason, reject the proposed criterion and look for some more liberal criterion? Alas, there is no more liberal criterion. The criterion I have proposed is the most liberal possible criterion. (It is more liberal than the other two. It sets the philosopher seeking to offer a successful argument for a philosophical thesis an easier task than the other two do, even if that task is impossible. If it is objected that one impossible task cannot be easier than another, I reply that it is in a very obvious sense ‘‘easier’’ to convince 90 percent of the electorate to vote for one than it is to convince every voter to vote for one, even if, as things stand, it is impossible to convince 90 percent of the electorate to vote for one.) My position, then, is that, sadly, every known argument for a substantive philosophical position is a failure—by the most liberal (by the most possibility-of-success-friendly) possible criterion of success and failure. LECTURE4THEGLOBALARGUMENTFROMEVIL 1. In the poem as it is printed in the novel there are (for reasons of the plot, as they say: the fictional author of the poem was an educated man who was attempting to disguise his authorship) several illiteracies (e.g. ‘whose’ for ‘who’s’ in l. 1). I have ‘‘corrected’’ them—with apologies to Martin Amis, in whose opinion they are an important part of the intended effect of the poem on the reader (i.e. the effect Kingsley Amis intended the poem to have on the readers of The Anti-Death League). For Martin Amis’s argument for this conclusion (and the poem without my officious corrections), see his memoir Experience, 188. 2. From ch. 4 (‘‘Rebellion’’) of Book V (the quotation is from the Constance Garnett translation). Ivan is speaking. It is very nearly obligatory for writers on the problem of evil to quote something from this chapter.

160 Notes<br />

matters was said only to defend my application <strong>of</strong> the term ‘agnostic’ to<br />

people simply on the ground that they lack certain beliefs—an application<br />

that some might fault on etymological grounds. If the sense <strong>of</strong> ‘agnostic’<br />

I have introduced by fiat is in any way objectionable, it is at any rate clear<br />

what I mean by the term, and that is all that really matters. (But I do think<br />

that it captures what most people today mean by the term, even if what<br />

they mean is not so noble as what its inventor, Thomas Henry Huxley,<br />

meant by it.) And, in any case, it is ‘‘agnostics’’ in just this sense who must<br />

make up my audience if I am to apply to arguments against the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

God the criterion <strong>of</strong> success in philosophical argument that I have set out.<br />

4. <strong>The</strong>se arguments can be found in my book An Essay on Free Will.<br />

5. If so, my proposed criterion <strong>of</strong> philosophical success and failure has the<br />

same consequence as the two criteria I have rejected: most if not all<br />

arguments for substantive philosophical conclusions are failures. And it<br />

wasthisconsequencethatwasmyreasonforrejectingthosecriteria.Should<br />

I not, therefore, for just this reason, reject the proposed criterion and look<br />

for some more liberal criterion? Alas, there is no more liberal criterion.<br />

<strong>The</strong> criterion I have proposed is the most liberal possible criterion. (It is<br />

more liberal than the other two. It sets the philosopher seeking to <strong>of</strong>fer a<br />

successful argument for a philosophical thesis an easier task than the other<br />

two do, even if that task is impossible. If it is objected that one impossible<br />

task cannot be easier than another, I reply that it is in a very obvious<br />

sense ‘‘easier’’ to convince 90 percent <strong>of</strong> the electorate to vote for one than<br />

it is to convince every voter to vote for one, even if, as things stand, it<br />

is impossible to convince 90 percent <strong>of</strong> the electorate to vote for one.)<br />

My position, then, is that, sadly, every known argument for a substantive<br />

philosophical position is a failure—by the most liberal (by the most<br />

possibility-<strong>of</strong>-success-friendly) possible criterion <strong>of</strong> success and failure.<br />

LECTURE4THEGLOBALARGUMENTFROMEVIL<br />

1. In the poem as it is printed in the novel there are (for reasons <strong>of</strong> the plot,<br />

as they say: the fictional author <strong>of</strong> the poem was an educated man who was<br />

attempting to disguise his authorship) several illiteracies (e.g. ‘whose’ for<br />

‘who’s’ in l. 1). I have ‘‘corrected’’ them—with apologies to Martin Amis,<br />

in whose opinion they are an important part <strong>of</strong> the intended effect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

poem on the reader (i.e. the effect Kingsley Amis intended the poem to have<br />

on the readers <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong> Anti-Death League). For Martin Amis’s argument for<br />

this conclusion (and the poem without my <strong>of</strong>ficious corrections), see his<br />

memoir Experience, 188.<br />

2. From ch. 4 (‘‘Rebellion’’) <strong>of</strong> Book V (the quotation is from the Constance<br />

Garnett translation). Ivan is speaking. It is very nearly obligatory for writers<br />

on the problem <strong>of</strong> evil to quote something from this chapter.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!