12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Notes 157<br />

4. For more on this topic, see my essays ‘‘Ontological Arguments’’ and<br />

‘‘Modal Epistemology’’; see also the Introduction to God, Knowledge, and<br />

Mystery, pp. 11–21.<br />

5. Compare Thomas Aquinas, Summa <strong>The</strong>ologiae 1, q.25, art. 3: ‘‘But if one<br />

were to say that God was omnipotent because he was able to do all things<br />

that were possible for a being with the power that was his, there would be<br />

a vicious circle in explaining the nature <strong>of</strong> that power. To say that would<br />

be to say only that God can do what he can do.’’<br />

6. I’m helping Descartes out a bit here. <strong>The</strong> question Descartes actually raises<br />

(letter to Arnauld, 29 July 1648) is whether God ‘‘can make a mountain<br />

without a valley’’. But, <strong>of</strong> course, if God wishes to make a mountain<br />

without a valley, he need only place the mountain he has made in the midst<br />

<strong>of</strong> a plain. I take it that the words I used in the text do not misrepresent<br />

what Descartes had in mind. I am not going to enter into the intricate<br />

scholarly dispute about what Descartes meant by saying that God ‘‘creates<br />

the eternal truths’’. My interest lies in the ‘‘strong’’ theory <strong>of</strong> omnipotence<br />

and its implications, not in the question whether Descartes really did<br />

subscribe to that theory.<br />

7. Here I follow common philosophical usage and speak <strong>of</strong> ‘‘believing’’<br />

propositions. I feel compelled to apologize for this, if only to myself. I<br />

am uncomfortable with this usage; I much prefer to speak <strong>of</strong> accepting<br />

or assenting to propositions—or hypotheses, theses, premises, ... (This<br />

preference is entirely a matter <strong>of</strong> English usage. No philosophical point<br />

is involved.) My scruples—which I have suppressed in the text because<br />

talk <strong>of</strong> believing propositions has certain stylistic advantages—could be<br />

accommodated by the following wording: A being is omniscient if, for every<br />

proposition, that being accepts either that proposition or its denial, and it<br />

is metaphysically impossible for that being to accept a false proposition.<br />

8. Some philosophers have said that if I believe that, e.g., Imyselfam hungry,<br />

the content <strong>of</strong> my belief is a first-person proposition that only I can believe<br />

(or accept: see the preceding note). If this is true, then the second definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> omniscience (and perhaps the first as well; but this is less clear) faces<br />

an obvious difficulty. I will not discuss this (as I see it) purely technical<br />

difficulty—beyond the simple assertion that, in my view, the difficulty is<br />

only apparent and can be seen to be only apparent when it is viewed from<br />

the perspective <strong>of</strong> a correct understanding <strong>of</strong> first-person belief sentences.<br />

9. See my essay ‘‘Ontological Arguments’’.<br />

10. But suppose that someone maintains that the greatest possible being<br />

is not—or would not be if it existed—a person. (A Neoplatonist, or<br />

Plato himself, might maintain this, as would, perhaps, Spinoza and the<br />

British Absolute Idealists.) Those who accept the Anselmian account <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> God as the greatest possible being, I think, presuppose<br />

that the greatest possible being must be a person—that <strong>of</strong> course the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!