12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

146 <strong>The</strong> Hiddenness <strong>of</strong> God<br />

(2) Patricia believes that God does not exist.<br />

(3) Patricia believes, for reason B, that God exists.<br />

It is, for example, consistent with God’s wanting Patricia to believe in<br />

him that he regard (1) as a good state <strong>of</strong> affairs, (2) as a bad state <strong>of</strong><br />

affairs, and (3) as a bad state <strong>of</strong> affairs that is much worse than (2).<br />

(And this would be consistent with reason B’s being an epistemically<br />

unobjectionable reason for belief in God: reason B might be, from the<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> someone interested only in justification or warrant, a<br />

perfectly good reason for believing in the existence <strong>of</strong> God.) And this is<br />

no idle speculation about a logical possibility. Most theists hold that God<br />

expects a good deal more from us than mere belief in his existence. As<br />

James says in his epistle, ‘‘You believe in the one God—that is creditable<br />

enough, but the demons have the same belief, and they tremble with<br />

fear’’ (2: 19). 10 God expects a complex <strong>of</strong> things, <strong>of</strong> which belief in his<br />

existence is a small (although essential) part. It is certainly conceivable<br />

that someone’s believing in him for a certain reason (because, say, that<br />

person has witnessed signs and wonders) might make it difficult or even<br />

impossible for that person to acquire other features God wanted him or<br />

her to have.<br />

Can we make this seem plausible? Let us wander a bit, and look at<br />

some examples and analogies. Let us consider a second New Testament<br />

text. Remember the story <strong>of</strong> the rich man in Hell in chapter 16 <strong>of</strong><br />

Luke’s Gospel. <strong>The</strong> rich man, who had in life treated the poor with<br />

contemptuous neglect, is in Hell (for that very reason), and petitions<br />

Abraham (who is somehow able to converse with him across a ‘‘great<br />

gulf ’’) that a messenger should be sent to his still living brothers, who<br />

also have starving beggars at their sumptuous gates, to warn them to<br />

mend their ways before it is too late. Abraham replies, ‘‘If they do not<br />

hear Moses and the Prophets, neither will they be persuaded though one<br />

rose from the dead.’’ A very striking parable, but can its message really<br />

be true? That is, can it be true that witnessing a miracle, even a very<br />

personal and pointed miracle, would have no effect on the character <strong>of</strong><br />

values <strong>of</strong> someone who witnessed it, no effect on the type <strong>of</strong> person<br />

he or she is? In order that our imaginations may not be distracted by<br />

the quaint literary devices <strong>of</strong> an old book, let us imagine a parable<br />

for our own time. This parable has two central characters. <strong>The</strong> first<br />

is the Russian strategist whose contribution to his country’s cause in<br />

Afghanistan was the clever idea <strong>of</strong> placing powerful bombs disguised as<br />

bright shiny toys in the vicinity <strong>of</strong> unreliable villages. This man dies (in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!