12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

144 <strong>The</strong> Hiddenness <strong>of</strong> God<br />

If this was the best God could do in twelfth-century England, it would<br />

seem that he just wasn’t trying! (And, obviously, he hasn’t done any<br />

better since.)<br />

My second observation is that some might find this argument more<br />

persuasive if ‘rational belief’ were substituted for ‘belief’ in it. If this<br />

substitution is made, the first two premises <strong>of</strong> the argument read:<br />

If God exists, he wants all finite rational beings to believe rationally in<br />

his existence.<br />

If every finite rational being observed signs and wonders <strong>of</strong> the right<br />

sort, every finite rational being would believe in God rationally.<br />

I am not sure which version <strong>of</strong> the argument is the more persuasive, but<br />

I mean my remarks to apply equally to either.<br />

Now how should the theist respond to this argument? I propose that<br />

the theist’s response be strictly parallel to <strong>The</strong>ist’s response to the global<br />

argument from evil. That is, that the theist should attempt to tell a story<br />

that has the following logical consequences:<br />

<strong>The</strong> world was created and is sustained by a necessary, omnipresent,<br />

omniscient, omnipotent, morally perfect being—that is, by God. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

are rational beings in this world, and God wants these beings, or some<br />

<strong>of</strong> them at some times, to believe in his existence. <strong>The</strong> world is devoid<br />

<strong>of</strong> signs and wonders—<strong>of</strong> ‘‘special effects’’. Or if the world contains any<br />

such events, they are so rare that very few people have actually observed<br />

one or even encountered anyone who claims to have observed one. (In<br />

the latter case, among those people whom God wants to believe in his<br />

existence are many <strong>of</strong> the people who are distant in space and time from<br />

any <strong>of</strong> the very rare signs and wonders.)<br />

And I propose that the doxastic argument should be judged a failure just<br />

in the case that the theist is able to tell a story with these consequences<br />

such that an audience <strong>of</strong> ideal agnostics (who have been presented<br />

with the doxastic argument and have been trying to decide whether<br />

it is convincing) will respond to it by saying, ‘‘Given that God exists,<br />

the rest <strong>of</strong> that story may well be true. I don’t see any reason to rule<br />

it out.’’ And, <strong>of</strong> course, we require that this reaction be achieved in<br />

the presence <strong>of</strong> an ideal atheist who does everything possible to block<br />

this reaction, everything possible to defend the truth <strong>of</strong> the premises<br />

<strong>of</strong> the argument against the doubts raised by the theist’s story. We<br />

may as well call such a story what we called stories that played an<br />

analogous role in relation to the argument from evil: we may as well

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!