12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

102 <strong>The</strong> Local Argument from <strong>Evil</strong><br />

you must grant his appeal. Now suppose that when it has been granted,<br />

clever Blodgett lodges a second appeal: that his sentence be reduced<br />

to 10 years less two days. This second appeal you will also be obliged<br />

to grant, for there is no difference between 10 years less a day and 10<br />

years less two days as regards the power to deter felonious assault. I am<br />

sure you can see where this is going. Provided only that Blodgett has<br />

the time and the energy to lodge 3,648 successive appeals for a one-day<br />

reduction <strong>of</strong> his sentence, he will escape prison altogether.<br />

This result is, I take it, a reductio ad absurdum <strong>of</strong> the moral principle.<br />

As the practical wisdom has it (but this is no compromise between<br />

practical considerations and strict morality; this is strict morality), ‘‘You<br />

have to draw a line somewhere’’. And this means an arbitrary line. <strong>The</strong><br />

principle fails precisely because it forbids the drawing <strong>of</strong> morally arbitrary<br />

lines. <strong>The</strong>re is nothing wrong, or nothing that can be determined a<br />

priori to be wrong, with a legislature’s setting 10 years in prison as the<br />

minimum punishment for felonious assault—and this despite the fact<br />

that 10 years in prison, considered as a precise span <strong>of</strong> days, is an arbitrary<br />

punishment. If the terrestrial day were about 25 seconds shorter, the law<br />

would no doubt be stated in the same words, and it would be neither<br />

more nor less effective than it in fact is; the interval <strong>of</strong> time denoted by<br />

the phrase ‘10 years’ would, however, be about one day shorter than the<br />

interval <strong>of</strong> time actually denoted by that phrase. It is obvious, when you<br />

think about it, that the lengths <strong>of</strong> the prison sentences written into our<br />

laws depend on accidents <strong>of</strong> astronomy, the (to some degree) accidental<br />

fact that we use a decimal rather than a binary or duodecimal system<br />

<strong>of</strong> numerical representation, and many other arbitrary factors—such<br />

as our preference for numbers that can be specified concisely. And<br />

there is nothing wrong with this. Since, however we ‘‘draw the line’’,<br />

its exact position will be an arbitrary matter, we might as well let its<br />

exact placement depend partly on the set <strong>of</strong> (morally speaking) arbitrary<br />

preferences that nature has dropped into our collective lap.<br />

So: the moral principle is false—or possesses whatever defect is the<br />

analogue in the realm <strong>of</strong> moral principles <strong>of</strong> falsity in the realm <strong>of</strong><br />

factual statements. What are the consequences <strong>of</strong> its falsity, <strong>of</strong> its failure<br />

to be an acceptable moral principle, for the local argument from evil?<br />

Let us return to the expanded free-will defense. This story accounts<br />

for the existence <strong>of</strong> horrors—that is, that there are horrors is a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the story. <strong>The</strong> story explains why there are such things as horrors,<br />

although it says nothing about any particular horror. (It in fact implies

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!