12.07.2013 Views

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

The Problem of Evil - Common Sense Atheism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

96 <strong>The</strong> Local Argument from <strong>Evil</strong><br />

that involved much less suffering, and an omniscient God would have<br />

known that and acted accordingly.)<br />

Now a moment ago, I mentioned the enormous amount <strong>of</strong> evil in<br />

the world, and it is certainly true that there is an enormous amount <strong>of</strong><br />

evil in the world. <strong>The</strong> phrase ‘‘the amount <strong>of</strong> evil’’ suggests—perhaps<br />

it even implies—that evil is quantifiable, like distance or weight. That<br />

may be false or unintelligible, but if it is true, even in a rough-andready<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> way, it shows that horrors raise a problem for the theist<br />

that is distinct from the problem raised by the enormous amount <strong>of</strong><br />

evil. If evil can be, even roughly, quantified, as talk about amounts<br />

seems to imply, it might be that there was more evil in a world in<br />

which there were thousands <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> relatively minor episodes<br />

<strong>of</strong> suffering (broken ribs, for example) than in a world in which<br />

there were a few horrors. But an omnipotent and omniscient creator<br />

could be called to moral account for creating a world in which there<br />

was even one horror. And the reason is obvious: that horror could<br />

have been ‘‘left out’’ <strong>of</strong> creation without the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> any great<br />

good or the permitting <strong>of</strong> some even greater horror. And leaving it<br />

out is just what a morally perfect being would do; such good things<br />

as might depend causally on the horror could—given the being’s<br />

omnipotence and omniscience—be secured by (if the word is not<br />

morally <strong>of</strong>fensive in this context) more ‘‘economical’’ means. Thus, the<br />

sheer amount <strong>of</strong> evil (which might be distributed in a fairly uniform<br />

way) is not the only fact about evil that <strong>The</strong>ist needs to take into<br />

account. He must also take into account what we might call (again with<br />

some risk <strong>of</strong> using morally <strong>of</strong>fensive language) high local concentrations<br />

<strong>of</strong> evil—that is, horrors. And it is hard to see how the free-will<br />

defense, however elaborated, could provide any resources for dealing<br />

with horrors.<br />

Rowe’s well-known example <strong>of</strong> a horror, the fawn that died an<br />

agonizing death in a forest fire that was not caused, in any way, however<br />

remote, by human beings—and whose death leaves no trace that could<br />

ever be discovered by human beings—is a particularly difficult case for<br />

<strong>The</strong>ist. (If the episode left no trace, how do we know it occurred? Well,<br />

we’re not really talking about a particular event, but about a type <strong>of</strong><br />

event. Our knowledge <strong>of</strong> nature and our acceptance <strong>of</strong> the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> the uniformity <strong>of</strong> nature make it impossible for us to believe that<br />

no events <strong>of</strong> this type have ever occurred.) True, however sentimental<br />

we may be about animals, this is not much <strong>of</strong> a horror compared

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!