25.06.2013 Views

The Charter, Federalism, and the Constitution, La Charte - Conseil ...

The Charter, Federalism, and the Constitution, La Charte - Conseil ...

The Charter, Federalism, and the Constitution, La Charte - Conseil ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Editorial Board / Comité de rédaction<br />

Editor-in-Chief Rédacteur en chef<br />

Kenneth McRoberts, York University, Canada<br />

Associate Editors Rédacteurs adjoints<br />

Alan Cairns, University of British Columbia, Canada<br />

Mary Jean Green, Dartmouth College, U.S.A.<br />

Lynette Hunter, University of Leeds, United Kingdom<br />

Danielle Juteau, Université de Montréal, Canada<br />

Managing Editor Secrétaire de rédaction<br />

Guy Leclair, ICCS/CIEC, Ottawa, Canada<br />

Advisory Board / Comité consultatif<br />

Aless<strong>and</strong>ro Anastasi, Universita di Messina, Italy<br />

Michael Burgess, University of Keele, United Kingdom<br />

Paul Claval, Université de Paris-Sorbonne (Paris IV), France<br />

Dona Davis, University of South Dakota, U.S.A.<br />

Peter H. Easingwood, University of Dundee, United Kingdom<br />

Ziran He, Guangzhou Institute of Foreign <strong>La</strong>nguages, China<br />

Helena G. Komkova, Institute of <strong>the</strong> USA <strong>and</strong> Canada, USSR<br />

Shirin L. Kudchedkar, SNDT Women’s University, India<br />

Karl Lenz, Freie Universität Berlin, Germany<br />

Gregory Mahler, University of Mississippi, U.S.A.<br />

James P. McCormick, California State University, U.S.A.<br />

William Metcalfe, University of Vermont, U.S.A.<br />

Ch<strong>and</strong>ra Mohan, University of Delhi, India<br />

Elaine F. Nardocchio, McMaster University, Canada<br />

Satoru Osanai, Chuo University, Japan<br />

Manuel Parés I Maicas, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Espagne<br />

Réjean Pelletier, Université <strong>La</strong>val, Canada<br />

Gemma Persico, Universita di Catania, Italy<br />

Richard E. Sherwin, Bar Ilan University, Israel<br />

William J. Smyth, St. Patrick’s College, Irel<strong>and</strong><br />

Sverker Sörlin, Umea University, Sweden<br />

Oleg Soroko-Tsupa, Moscow State University, USSR<br />

Michèle <strong>The</strong>rrien, Institut des langues et civilisations orientales, France<br />

Gaëtan Tremblay, Université du Québec à Montréal, Canada<br />

Hillig J.T. van’t L<strong>and</strong>, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, Pays-Bas<br />

Mel Watkins, University of Toronto, Canada<br />

Gillian Whitlock, Griffith University, Australia<br />

Donez Xiques, Brooklyn College, U.S.A.<br />

ii


International Journal of Canadian Studies<br />

Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8 Spring-Fall/7-8 printemps-automne 1993<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>Federalism</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

<strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong>, le fédéralisme et la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

Table of Contents/Table des matières<br />

Alan C. Cairns<br />

Introduction/Présentation ..........................5<br />

José Woehrling<br />

<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des rapports entre le Québec<br />

et le Canada anglais .............................9<br />

Peter H. Russell<br />

Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada: <strong>The</strong><br />

Politics of Frustration ...........................41<br />

David M. Thomas<br />

Turning a Blind Eye: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

Experience .................................63<br />

Richard <strong>La</strong>Rue et Jocelyn Létourneau<br />

De l’unité et de l’identité au Canada. Essai sur l’éclatement<br />

d’un État ..................................81<br />

Richard Sigurdson<br />

Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada: A Critique of <strong>the</strong><br />

Critics ...................................95<br />

Janet Hiebert<br />

Rights <strong>and</strong> Public Debate: <strong>The</strong> Limitations of a ‘Rights must be Paramount’<br />

Perspective ................................117<br />

Linda Cardinal<br />

Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et<br />

libertés ..................................137<br />

Andrew D. Heard<br />

Quebec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights ...........153


François Rocher et Daniel Salée<br />

Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle : discours et pratique. .....167<br />

Stephen McBride<br />

Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness: Liberal Political<br />

Economy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> .................187<br />

Lilianne E. Krosenbrink-Gelissen<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s Rights:<br />

Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas .........................207<br />

Radha Jhappan<br />

Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights: <strong>the</strong> Evolution of<br />

Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse from 1982 to <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord ..........................225<br />

Jill Vickers<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

......................................261<br />

Max Nemni<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la construction de l’idée de sécession<br />

au Québec. ................................285<br />

Review Essays/Essais critiques<br />

Michael Oliver<br />

<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong> Biculturalism on<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Thought <strong>and</strong> Practice in Canada .............315<br />

David R. Cameron<br />

Not Spicer <strong>and</strong> Not <strong>the</strong> B & B: Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity ............333<br />

Allan Tupper<br />

English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord ........347


Introduction<br />

To an anthropologist from distant<br />

l<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>the</strong> Canadian obsession with<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitution might be seen as a<br />

cargo cult—<strong>the</strong> millenarian belief<br />

that <strong>the</strong> perfect constitution will be<br />

delivered up by some magical<br />

process, after which Canadian lions<br />

<strong>and</strong> lambs will cavort peaceably<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r. Undoubtedly, Canadians<br />

have devoted inordinate time to<br />

constitutional introspection in <strong>the</strong><br />

last three decades. Canadian<br />

scholars have accompanied, <strong>and</strong><br />

sometimes tried to lead, <strong>the</strong> public<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> political elites in <strong>the</strong> search<br />

for a new constitutional<br />

equilibrium.<br />

Both <strong>the</strong> authors <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjects of<br />

<strong>the</strong> articles that follow confirm <strong>the</strong><br />

contrast between yesterday’s <strong>and</strong><br />

today’s constitutional world.<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al analysis is no longer<br />

dominated by lawyers; federalism<br />

does not enjoy an unchallenged<br />

pride of place as <strong>the</strong> subject matter<br />

par excellence of <strong>the</strong> written<br />

constitution; <strong>and</strong> French- English (or<br />

Quebec-Rest of Canada) cleavages do<br />

not exhaust <strong>the</strong> contemporary<br />

national question in Canada.<br />

As this volume reveals, <strong>the</strong> opening<br />

up of <strong>the</strong> constitution means,<br />

among o<strong>the</strong>r things, diversifying <strong>the</strong><br />

disciplinary backgrounds of those<br />

who study it to include political<br />

scientists, philosophers <strong>and</strong><br />

sociologists. This is <strong>the</strong> academic<br />

version of <strong>the</strong> recent democratizing<br />

of Canadian constitutional<br />

discourse. <strong>The</strong> catalyst for this<br />

democratization, which induced<br />

resort to a referendum judgement<br />

on <strong>the</strong> 1992 Charlottetown Accord,<br />

is <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s<br />

powerful symbolism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

concomitant relative displacement<br />

of federalism as a constitutional<br />

organizing principle, are illustrated<br />

by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s central place in at<br />

Présentation<br />

À les voir tant obsédés par leur<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, un anthropologue de<br />

l’autre bout du monde doit bien<br />

penser que les Canadiens pratiquent<br />

un culte millénariste et attendent<br />

d’un processus magique la parfaite<br />

constitution qui permettra aux lions<br />

et aux agneaux canadiens de<br />

gambader côte-à-côte. C’est vrai<br />

qu’ils ont consacré au cours des<br />

trente dernières années un temps<br />

fou à l’introspection<br />

constitutionnelle. Les universitaires<br />

et les spécialistes canadiens ont<br />

souvent accompagné et tenté de<br />

guider le public et les élites<br />

politiques dans leur quête d’un<br />

nouvel équilibre constitutionnel.<br />

Autant les auteurs que les sujets des<br />

articles ici publiés font voir le<br />

contraste entre l’univers<br />

constitutionnel d’hier et celui<br />

d’aujourd’hui. <strong>La</strong> recherche<br />

constitutionnelle n’est plus<br />

l’apanage des juristes; le<br />

fédéralisme n’occupe plus la place<br />

d’honneur en tant qu’objet par<br />

excellence de la constitution écrite;<br />

et les divisions franco-anglaises<br />

(Québec-Reste du Canada)<br />

n’épuisent pas la question nationale<br />

dans le Canada contemporain.<br />

Comme ce numéro le montre bien,<br />

le réexamen de la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

suppose désormais que les<br />

intervenants oeuvrent dans<br />

plusieurs disciplines différentes,<br />

dont la science politique, la<br />

philosophie et la sociologie. C’est<br />

la variante universitaire de la<br />

récente démocratisation du débat<br />

constitutionnel canadien. Le<br />

catalyste de cette démocratisation,<br />

qui a entraîné la tenue d’un<br />

référendum sur l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown de 1992, c’est la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et<br />

libertés. Le symbolisme puissant de<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong> et le déclin relatif et


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

least a third of <strong>the</strong> following<br />

articles.<br />

<strong>The</strong> emergence of Aboriginal<br />

peoples to constitutional<br />

prominence, aspects of which are<br />

lucidly explored in two of <strong>the</strong><br />

essays, is no less revealing of <strong>the</strong><br />

kind of constitutional people(s)<br />

Canadians have become. <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

evolution from constitutional<br />

objects to constitutional participants<br />

transforms what used to be <strong>the</strong> two<br />

nations debate (French-English)<br />

into a more complex debate about<br />

<strong>the</strong> appropriate institutional <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional response to a<br />

multinational ra<strong>the</strong>r than binational<br />

Canada.<br />

Canada’s recent constitutional<br />

pilgrimage has also undermined <strong>the</strong><br />

former virtual monopoly of men<br />

over constitutional discourse <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> agenda of constitutional change.<br />

Yesterday’s constitution, although<br />

this was only dimly seen by our<br />

predecessors, was male. <strong>The</strong><br />

unsettled relation of women to <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional order, in particular to<br />

future Aboriginal self-governments,<br />

is a major constitutional issue<br />

explored in <strong>the</strong> articles that follow.<br />

<strong>The</strong> intrepid cover-to-cover reader<br />

of this volume will perhaps emerge<br />

shaken, but he or she will also have<br />

gained an appreciation of <strong>the</strong><br />

complexities of Canada’s<br />

constitutional existence, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>refore of why it is so difficult to<br />

transform aspirations for change<br />

into realized constitutional reform.<br />

It may be, as <strong>the</strong> Thomas article<br />

suggests, that Canadians would<br />

have been wiser to have asked less<br />

of <strong>the</strong> constitution, <strong>and</strong> to have<br />

understood that it is wisdom, not<br />

lack of courage, to leave some<br />

constitutional stones unturned.<br />

Unfortunately, however, <strong>the</strong><br />

momentum behind <strong>the</strong> pressure for<br />

constitutional reform is unlikely to<br />

disappear when where we are is an<br />

unacceptable resting place to many<br />

6<br />

concomitant du fédéralisme en tant<br />

que principe organisateur de la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> sont clairement<br />

illustrés par la place centrale<br />

qu’occupe la <strong>Charte</strong> dans au moins<br />

le tiers des articles du présent<br />

numéro.<br />

L’importance nouvelle des peuples<br />

autochtones dans les discussions<br />

constitutionnelles — deux essais<br />

sont consacrés à certains aspects de<br />

cette question — n’est pas moins<br />

révélatrice de l’évolution des<br />

Canadiens, tous « peuples »<br />

confondus, en matière<br />

constitutionnelle. De sujets de<br />

discussion constitutionnelle qu’ils<br />

étaient, ils sont devenus des<br />

participants essentiels, transformant<br />

ainsi un débat qui se déroulait entre<br />

deux nations (Français — Anglais)<br />

en une discussion complexe sur la<br />

solution institutionnelle et<br />

constitutionnelle qui conviendrait le<br />

mieux à l’heure d’un Canada<br />

multinational et non plus binational.<br />

Le tout dernier pèlerinage canadien<br />

en terre constitutionnelle a aussi<br />

mis à mal le quasi-monopole des<br />

hommes sur le discours<br />

constitutionnel et sur les priorités à<br />

l’ordre du jour. <strong>La</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

d’hier, même si nos prédécesseurs<br />

n’en étaient guère conscients, était<br />

mâle. L’importante question,<br />

toujours pendante, du rapport des<br />

femmes à l’ordre constitutionnel,<br />

surtout en ce qui a trait aux futurs<br />

gouvernements autochtones, est<br />

également analysée dans les articles<br />

qui suivent.<br />

Le valeureux lecteur qui lira ce<br />

numéro de la première à la dernière<br />

ligne en sortira peut-être ébranlé. Il<br />

ou elle en aura néanmoins mieux<br />

saisi la complexité de la réalité<br />

constitutionnelle et compris<br />

pourquoi il est si difficile de<br />

traduire les aspirations au<br />

changement en solutions<br />

constitutionnelles concrètes. Peutêtre,<br />

comme l’article de Thomas le


of <strong>the</strong> key actors, especially<br />

Quebecois <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal<br />

nationalists, <strong>and</strong> Alberta Senate<br />

reformers.<br />

We offer this volume to our readers<br />

on <strong>the</strong> premise that no matter how<br />

difficult a constitutional<br />

rapprochement will be, an<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> dialectic<br />

between social forces <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional arrangements is a<br />

necessary if not sufficient<br />

prerequisite for successful<br />

constitutional change.<br />

Alan C. Cairns<br />

University of British Columbia<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>Federalism</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

<strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong>, le fédéralisme et la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

conseille, les Canadiens auraient-ils<br />

été plus sages en exigeant moins de<br />

leur <strong>Constitution</strong>, car en pareille<br />

matière, la prudence — et non pas<br />

la pusillanimité — veut qu’on évite<br />

de remuer ciel et terre.<br />

Malheureusement, les pressions en<br />

faveur d’une révision<br />

constitutionnelle ne se relâcheront<br />

vraisemblablement pas, compte<br />

tenu de la situation inacceptable de<br />

nombre d’acteurs clés,<br />

particulièrement les Québécois, les<br />

nationalistes autochtones et les<br />

Albertains qui préconisent une<br />

réforme du Sénat.<br />

Bien que fort conscients des<br />

difficultés d’un rapprochement<br />

constitutionnel, nous avons préparé<br />

ce numéro dans le dessein d’aider<br />

nos lectrices et lecteurs à saisir la<br />

dialectique qui régit les rapports<br />

entre les forces sociales et les<br />

aménagements constitutionnels.<br />

Nous n’ambitionnions pas de<br />

résoudre le problème; seulement de<br />

l’éclairer.<br />

Alan C. Cairns<br />

University of British Columbia<br />

7


José Woehrling<br />

<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais *<br />

Résumé<br />

Si, en 1867, le Canada a été créé sous la forme d’une fédération plutôt que<br />

d’un état unitaire, c’était essentiellement pour faciliter la coexistence de ses<br />

deux « peuples fondateurs » : les francophones — qui ne sont majoritaires<br />

qu’au Québec — et les anglophones — qui forment la majorité dans les neuf<br />

autres provinces. Or, en 1982, malgré l’opposition du Québec et<br />

contrairement à ses intérêts, le Canada anglais a apporté d’importantes<br />

modifications à la <strong>Constitution</strong> du pays. Par la suite, le Québec a vainement<br />

tenté d’obtenir des garanties qui protégeraient son caractère distinct en tant<br />

que seule collectivité francophone sur un continent anglophone. L’échec de<br />

cette tentative de réconciliation a entraîné la plus grave crise constitutionnelle<br />

que le Canada ait connu depuis sa création. L’auteur examine l’évolution des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais, de 1867 à aujourd’hui, et<br />

analyse les perspectives d’avenir.<br />

Abstract<br />

If Canada was created in 1867 as a federation ra<strong>the</strong>r than a unitary state, it<br />

was largely to facilitate <strong>the</strong> coexistence of <strong>the</strong> two “founding peoples”:<br />

Francophones, a majority only in <strong>the</strong> province of Quebec, <strong>and</strong> Anglophones,<br />

<strong>the</strong> majority in <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada. However, in 1982, some important changes<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> were imposed by English Canada against <strong>the</strong><br />

wishes of Quebec <strong>and</strong> contrary to Quebec interests. Subsequently, Quebec has<br />

tried in vain to obtain certain guarantees to protect its distinct character as <strong>the</strong><br />

sole Francophone society on an English-speaking continent. <strong>The</strong> failure of this<br />

attempt at reconciliation has brought about <strong>the</strong> most serious constitutional<br />

crisis that Canada has known since its creation. <strong>The</strong> author examines <strong>the</strong><br />

evolution of relations between Quebec <strong>and</strong> English-speaking Canada from<br />

1867 to our day, <strong>and</strong> concludes by analyzing possible future scenarios.<br />

Le Canada et le Québec traversent actuellement l’une des pires crises<br />

constitutionnelles de leur histoire. Le réaménagement des accords politiques<br />

qui servent de cadre à leurs rapports est devenu inévitable. Dans l’introduction,<br />

nous ferons un rapide survol de l’évolution des relations entre le Québec et le<br />

Canada anglais depuis 1867, année de la Confédération, jusqu’au<br />

« rapatriement » de la <strong>Constitution</strong> en 1982, contre la volonté du Québec. Nous<br />

examinerons ensuite les circonstances et les raisons de l’échec des deux<br />

tentatives majeures qui ont été faites au cours de la dernière décennie pour<br />

réformer la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne. Ce double échec a mis en lumière<br />

l’ampleur des divergences qui existent entre les aspirations du Québec et celles<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

du Canada anglais. Nous concluerons par une analyse des différentes options<br />

qui s’offrent pour l’avenir des relations entre le Québec et le Canada anglais.<br />

Au moment de la création du Canada, en 1867, les francophones étaient déjà<br />

minoritaires partout en Amérique du Nord, sauf au Québec. Aussi<br />

favorisaient-ils l’adoption d’un système fédéral afin de s’assurer, au moins, le<br />

contrôle démocratique d’un des États membres de la fédération et de disposer<br />

d’instruments politiques susceptibles de protéger leur triple particularisme,<br />

tenant à la langue française, à la religion catholique et au droit civil. Par la<br />

suite, pendant près d’un siècle, le Québec réussit à préserver son autonomie et<br />

sa spécificité sur un mode principalement défensif dans la mesure où la société<br />

québécoise restait repliée sur elle-même et fondée sur des valeurs<br />

traditionnelles. Les Canadiens français de cette époque cultivaient une<br />

idéologie de la survivance et se cantonnaient dans un univers fermé aux<br />

influences extérieures. Sur le plan constitutionnel, l’objectif des<br />

gouvernements québécois était moins d’étendre leurs pouvoirs que de les<br />

protéger contre tout empiètement. Cette attitude changera radicalement durant<br />

la période qui va de 1955 à 1965 pendant laquelle se déroule la « Révolution<br />

tranquille ». <strong>La</strong> société québécoise connaît alors une série de transformations<br />

qui lui font rattraper en quelques années le retard qu’elle avait accumulé par<br />

rapport aux autres sociétés occidentales.<br />

À cette époque, le Québec se dote d’un appareil étatique moderne par la<br />

création de nouveaux ministères et le développement de sa fonction publique.<br />

Dans le domaine économique, les nouvelles élites québécoises cherchent à<br />

conquérir une partie du pouvoir de décision traditionnellement détenu par les<br />

anglophones. Pour y parvenir, elles utilisent les ressources et les instruments<br />

de l’État québécois pour favoriser l’émergence d’une nouvelle classe<br />

d’entrepreneurs et de capitalistes francophones. <strong>La</strong> fin des années soixante<br />

marque également la mise en oeuvre d’une véritable politique linguistique<br />

québécoise. On pouvait alors constater deux phénomènes sociaux fort<br />

inquiétants : d’une part, la désaffection des immigrants à l’égard de l’école<br />

française et, d’autre part, l’infériorité du français par rapport à l’anglais dans la<br />

vie économique, et cela, même au Québec. À partir de là, les objectifs de la<br />

politique linguistique québécoise vont s’imposer en quelque sorte d’euxmêmes<br />

: le premier sera d’amener les immigrants à fréquenter l’école française<br />

et le deuxième visera à rehausser le prestige de la langue française et son utilité<br />

dans la vie économique. Ces deux objectifs n’ont jamais été remis en cause; au<br />

contraire, ils ont été poursuivis de façon systématique par tous les<br />

gouvernements qui se sont succédés au Québec depuis 1970 : le gouvernement<br />

libéral de M. Robert Bourassa, qui a fait adopter en 1974 la Loi sur la langue<br />

officielle (ou « loi 22 »); puis le gouvernement du Parti québécois, dirigé par<br />

René Lévesque, qui a fait voter en 1977 la <strong>Charte</strong> de la langue française (ou<br />

« loi 101 »). De la loi 22 à la loi 101, les buts sont restés les mêmes, seuls les<br />

moyens et les modalités ont changé : la loi 101 est plus sévère, plus coercitive<br />

et plus « englobante » que la loi 22. En 1985, lorsqu’il est revenu au pouvoir,<br />

le gouvernement libéral de M. Bourassa a conservé la loi 101 sans y apporter<br />

de modifications très importantes. <strong>La</strong> loi régit le statut des langues dans trois<br />

secteurs principaux : les institutions publiques, la vie économique et<br />

l’éducation. Dans ces trois domaines, elle a pour objectif de rehausser le statut<br />

du français. Pour y parvenir, elle limite en partie les droits ou privilèges<br />

traditionnels des anglophones.<br />

En matière constitutionnelle, la « Révolution tranquille » a fait passer le<br />

Québec de la simple défense des pouvoirs acquis à la revendication de<br />

10


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

pouvoirs nouveaux et nombreux. Après 1960, les gouvernements québécois<br />

successifs vont tous réclamer une modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> pour obtenir<br />

les compétences supplémentaires estimées nécessaires à l’épanouissement de<br />

la société québécoise. Ils dem<strong>and</strong>eront donc soit une décentralisation générale<br />

des pouvoirs valable pour toutes les provinces, soit la création d’un « statut<br />

particulier » pour le Québec par lequel celui-ci se verrait reconnaître davantage<br />

de compétences que les autres provinces.<br />

Au fur et à mesure que le temps passe, les revendications constitutionnelles du<br />

Québec vont d’ailleurs se durcir. Le gouvernement libéral de Jean Lesage, au<br />

pouvoir entre 1960 et 1966, était resté foncièrement fédéraliste et avait adopté<br />

le slogan « Maîtres chez nous ». Par contre, avec le gouvernement de l’Union<br />

nationale de Daniel Johnson, qui s’était fait élire en 1966, le mot d’ordre était<br />

devenu « Égalité ou indépendance ». En 1967, René Lévesque quittait le Parti<br />

libéral pour créer le Parti québécois, dont le programme consiste à réaliser<br />

l’indépendance du Québec. Neuf ans plus tard, en 1976, le Parti québécois<br />

prenait le pouvoir et s’engageait à tenir un référendum sur un projet de<br />

souveraineté politique du Québec, combiné avec une association économique<br />

et monétaire avec le Canada.<br />

Le référendum eut lieu en mai 1980, le « non » obtenant 59,56 p. 100 des voix<br />

et le « oui », 40,44 p. 100. Cependant, après avoir rejeté le projet souverainiste<br />

du Parti québécois, la population devait le maintenir au pouvoir lors des<br />

élections qui suivirent, en 1981. Très rapidement, le gouvernement fédéral de<br />

M. Trudeau allait mettre à profit la situation de faiblesse dans laquelle le<br />

référendum avait placé le Québec. En 1982, avec l’appui des neuf provinces<br />

anglaises, il faisait adopter une nouvelle loi constitutionnelle, sans l’accord du<br />

gouvernement québécois et contre sa volonté clairement exprimée. Ainsi, pour<br />

la première fois depuis 1867, la <strong>Constitution</strong> était modifiée sans l’accord du<br />

Québec. En outre, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 contient un processus<br />

d’amendement permettant d’eventuelles modifications sans le consentement<br />

du Québec. Par ailleurs, les dem<strong>and</strong>es formulées par le Québec depuis 1960<br />

pour obtenir de nouveaux pouvoirs restaient insatisfaites et, pis encore,<br />

certaines dispositions de la nouvelle <strong>Constitution</strong> avaient pour effet de<br />

diminuer les pouvoirs traditionnels du Québec dans le domaine crucial de la<br />

protection de la langue française.<br />

L’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech en 1987-1990<br />

Dans un jugement du 6 décembre 1982, la Cour suprême du Canada avait<br />

déclaré à l’unanimité qu’il n’existait aucune règle de droit ou convention<br />

constitutionnelle permettant au Québec de s’objecter aux modifications de la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>. Par conséquent, l’opposition du gouvernement du Parti<br />

québécois à l’adoption de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 n’a pas empêché<br />

celle-ci de s’appliquer pleinement au Québec dès son entrée en vigueur le 17<br />

avril 1982. Cependant, le fait que la deuxième plus gr<strong>and</strong>e province du Canada<br />

— et la seule qui soit majoritairement francophone — n’adhère pas à la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> pose évidemment un problème politique grave et fait planer une<br />

menace sur l’unité du Canada.<br />

En 1985, le Parti québécois cédait le pouvoir au Parti libéral de M. Robert<br />

Bourassa, qui s’est toujours présenté comme résolument fédéraliste. Le<br />

nouveau gouvernement allait formuler cinq conditions pour donner l’accord<br />

du Québec à la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 :<br />

1) la reconnaissance du Québec comme société distincte;<br />

11


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

2) la garantie d’un rôle accru des autorités provinciales en matière<br />

d’immigration;<br />

3) la participation du gouvernement québécois à la nomination de<br />

trois des neuf juges de la Cour suprême du Canada;<br />

4) la limitation du « pouvoir de dépenser » du gouvernement fédéral<br />

(c’est-à-dire le pouvoir de ce gouvernement d’intervenir<br />

financièrement dans les domaines relevant de la compétence<br />

exclusive des provinces);<br />

5) la reconnaissance d’un droit de veto au Québec sur la réforme des<br />

institutions fédérales et la création de nouvelles provinces.<br />

Il faut souligner que ces cinq dem<strong>and</strong>es représentaient une réduction<br />

considérable des exigences traditionnelles du Québec. En effet, le<br />

gouvernement Bourassa ne revendiquait de nouveaux pouvoir que dans le seul<br />

secteur de l’immigration alors que tous ses prédécesseurs, depuis la<br />

« Révolution tranquille », exigeaient d’obtenir l’exclusivité des compétences<br />

dans de très nombreux domaines, notamment la politique familiale et celle de<br />

la main-d’oeuvre, les télécommunications, l’aménagement régional et ainsi de<br />

suite. En fait, mis à part l’immigration, les quatre autres dem<strong>and</strong>es du Québec<br />

correspondaient à des mécanismes de protection des pouvoirs provinciaux<br />

existants bien plus qu’à un quelconque élargissement de ceux-ci.<br />

En juin 1987, après deux ans de négociation, les dix provinces et le<br />

gouvernement fédéral concluaient un accord (appelé l’« Accord du lac<br />

Meech ») en vertu duquel on convenait de modifier la <strong>Constitution</strong> pour<br />

donner satisfaction au Québec. Il faut cependant souligner que sur les cinq<br />

modifications réclamées par le Québec, quatre avaient été étendues à toutes les<br />

provinces. Par conséquent, la seule modification propre au Québec était la<br />

reconnaissance du caractère distinct de la société québécoise. Par ailleurs, une<br />

modification non réclamée par le Québec avait été ajoutée à l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech, à la dem<strong>and</strong>e des provinces de l’Ouest, concernant le processus de<br />

nomination des sénateurs.<br />

Pour entrer en vigueur conformément à la procédure de modification adoptée<br />

en 1982, l’Accord du lac Meech devait être ratifié dans un délai maximal de<br />

trois ans par les deux Chambres du Parlement fédéral et chacune des dix<br />

assemblées législatives provinciales. Ce délai devait être fatal, car les critiques<br />

contre l’Accord n’ont cessé de se multiplier au Canada anglais et l’appui dont<br />

il y bénéficiait au départ a constamment diminué. Certaines de ces critiques<br />

étaient parfaitement fondées alors que d’autres, au contraire, semblent avoir<br />

découlé d’une mauvaise compréhension de l’Accord, ou même d’une<br />

intention délibérée de le faire échouer. Rappelons rapidement les griefs qui ont<br />

été faits au Canada anglais à chacun des six éléments de l’Accord pour tenter<br />

d’en évaluer le bien-fondé et mesurer l’importance des divergences qui<br />

existent entre le Québec et le reste du pays.<br />

<strong>La</strong> réforme du Sénat<br />

<strong>La</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada prévoit que les sénateurs sont nommés par le<br />

gouvernement fédéral. En pratique, depuis 1867, tous les gouvernements ont<br />

procédé à des nominations partisanes, presque toujours destinées à servir de<br />

récompense politique. Cette pratique a fait en sorte que les sénateurs, qui ne<br />

sont pas élus par la population des provinces, ne peuvent pas davantage<br />

prétendre parler au nom des gouvernements provinciaux. Par conséquent, les<br />

sénateurs ne sont investis d’aucune légitimité politique et, pour cette raison, le<br />

Sénat devrait normalement s’abstenir d’exercer les pouvoirs que la<br />

12


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> lui reconnaît en matière législative et qui sont, à peu de choses<br />

près, les mêmes que ceux de la Chambre des communes1. L’Accord du lac<br />

Meech prévoyait que les sénateurs représentant une province devraient être<br />

choisis par le gouvernement fédéral d’après une liste de c<strong>and</strong>idats établie par le<br />

gouvernement de la province en question. <strong>La</strong> réforme consistait donc à<br />

substituer au pouvoir discrétionnaire et incontrôlé du gouvernement fédéral un<br />

pouvoir de nomination conjoint qui obligerait les deux gouvernements à<br />

s’entendre sur le choix des c<strong>and</strong>idats.<br />

En fait, ce n’est pas tellement ce changement qui a provoqué la critique, car les<br />

adversaires de l’Accord du lac Meech se sont surtout attaqués aux dispositions<br />

concernant la procédure de modification constitutionnelle nécessaire pour<br />

réformer les autres caractéristiques du Sénat. En effet, avec l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech, une telle réforme deviendrait pratiquement impossible parce qu’on<br />

exigeait pour sa réalisation l’accord unanime des dix provinces. Or, depuis une<br />

dizaine d’années, les provinces de l’Ouest avaient fait de la réforme du Sénat<br />

leur cheval de bataille dans le dessein d’acquérir une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e influence sur<br />

le processus décisionnel fédéral. Faiblement peuplées, ces provinces<br />

n’envoient à la Chambre des communes qu’un trop petit nombre de députés<br />

pour pouvoir y exercer une influence comparable à celle des deux gr<strong>and</strong>es<br />

provinces du « Canada central », le Québec et l’Ontario. Les provinces de<br />

l’Ouest privilégient par conséquent la formule dite « Triple E », soit un Sénat<br />

« élu, égal et efficace » où chaque province serait représentée par le même<br />

nombre de sénateurs élus au suffrage universel direct2. En outre, ce nouveau<br />

Sénat exercerait les mêmes pouvoirs que la Chambre des communes. Ce<br />

modèle s’inspire du Sénat australien.<br />

Cependant, l’égalité de représentation de toutes les provinces au Sénat<br />

entraînerait des conséquences difficiles à accepter sur le plan démocratique.<br />

En effet, les six plus petites provinces (les quatre provinces de l’Atlantique, le<br />

Manitoba et la Saskatchewan) détiendraient ensemble 60 p. 100 des voix alors<br />

qu’elles ne représentent que 17 p. 100 de la population canadienne. Une telle<br />

formule serait au surplus inacceptable pour les Québecois à qui elle ne<br />

laisserait que le dixième des sièges. Pour tenter de convaincre le Québec<br />

d’accepter une diminution de sa proportion des sièges, certains suggèrent<br />

d’exiger, dans le cadre d’un Sénat réformé, une double majorité (celle de<br />

l’ensemble des sénateurs et des sénateurs francophones) pour l’adoption des<br />

projets de loi relatifs à la langue et à la culture françaises. Un tel système ne<br />

protégerait cependant pas le Québec pour ce qui est des questions autres que<br />

linguistiques ou culturelles. Au surplus, les sénateurs francophones ne seraient<br />

pas tous québécois, puisque certains d’entre eux devraient être désignés pour<br />

représenter les minorités francophones hors du Québec. Or, les intérêts des<br />

Québécois et des minorités francophones du Canada anglais sont loin d’être<br />

identiques par rapport aux interventions fédérales en matières culturelle et<br />

linguistique.<br />

De façon plus générale, l’élection des sénateurs au suffrage direct ne paraît pas<br />

être une bonne solution dans le cadre canadien, car pareille modalité<br />

entraînerait de graves inconvénients dans le contexte d’un système<br />

parlementaire de type britannique, caractérisé par le principe de la<br />

responsabilité ministérielle, le bipartisme et la discipline de parti. Du point de<br />

vue de la composition partisane, un Sénat élu au suffrage universel risque en<br />

effet d’être trop semblable à la Chambre des communes, ce qui lui enlèverait<br />

sa raison d’être ou, au contraire, trop différent, ce qui pourrait amener les deux<br />

Chambres à s’affronter et à se neutraliser mutuellement. En effet, dans la<br />

13


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

mesure où elles seraient pareillement élues au suffrage direct et posséderaient<br />

par voie de conséquence une même légitimité démocratique, aucune des deux<br />

Chambres ne se sentirait tenue de céder à l’autre. En outre, conformément aux<br />

règles de la discipline de parti, la loyauté des sénateurs irait aux partis auxquels<br />

ils doivent leur élection et dont dépend leur réélection plutôt qu’à la province<br />

ou à la région qu’ils représentent. Comme le montre l’exemple du Sénat<br />

australien, dont le fonctionnement est généralement dominé par la politique<br />

partisane, l’élection des sénateurs a pour conséquence d’affaiblir<br />

considérablement leur capacité d’agir en tant que représentants des États<br />

membres de la fédération. Par ailleurs, il serait illogique de donner au Sénat<br />

une forte légitimité démocratique sans lui reconnaître également des pouvoirs<br />

importants. Plus précisément, dans la mesure où le Sénat et la Chambre des<br />

communes sont l’un et l’autre élus, il est difficile de ne pas reconnaître à celuici<br />

les mêmes pouvoirs qu’à celle-là. Or, un système parlementaire exige que la<br />

Chambre basse ait des pouvoirs supérieurs à ceux de la Chambre haute, car<br />

c’est de la première qu’émane le gouvernement et, par conséquent, c’est<br />

devant elle seule qu’il est responsable.<br />

Il existe donc une incompatibilité certaine entre l’élection des sénateurs au<br />

suffrage direct, qui suppose que le Sénat ait les mêmes pouvoirs que la<br />

Chambre des communes, et la logique interne du système parlementaire, qui<br />

veut, au contraire, que la Chambre basse ait des pouvoirs supérieurs à la<br />

Chambre haute. Si, comme le réclament les tenants de la formule « Triple E »,<br />

la <strong>Constitution</strong> était modifiée pour faire élire le Sénat canadien, on se<br />

trouverait placé devant des choix difficiles. Pour maintenir l’intégrité du<br />

système parlementaire, il faudrait refuser au Sénat le pouvoir de rejeter la<br />

plupart des lois adoptées par les Communes et ne lui attribuer qu’un simple<br />

droit de veto suspensif, ce qui reviendrait à dire que les sénateurs ne<br />

représentent pas la population au même titre que les députés bien qu’ils soient<br />

élus. Mais si l’on donnait au Sénat un droit de veto absolu sur les lois<br />

présentées par le gouvernement, cela serait contraire aux principes<br />

fondamentaux du système parlementaire.<br />

Il faut également souligner qu’un Sénat doté de pouvoirs significatifs peut<br />

paradoxalement constituer un facteur de centralisation du système fédéral. En<br />

effet, l’expérience de l’Allemagne et des États-Unis tend à démontrer que les<br />

États constituants acceptent d’autant plus facilement de voir leurs<br />

compétences propres diminuer qu’ils obtiennent en contrepartie une plus<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>e participation au processus décisionnel central par le biais de la<br />

Chambre fédérale. À cet égard, il est révélateur que les provinces canadiennes<br />

qui réclament le Sénat « Triple E » soient également opposées à un<br />

affaiblissement du rôle d’Ottawa. C’est que dans la mesure où ces provinces<br />

espèrent que la réforme du Sénat leur permettra d’exercer une influence accrue<br />

au sein des institutions du pouvoir central, elles veulent que ce dernier reste<br />

fort, ou même qu’il soit renforcé. Par ailleurs, il faut voir que l’élection des<br />

sénateurs au suffrage universel risque de renforcer encore le caractère<br />

centralisateur d’une réforme du Sénat. En effet, la légitimité des autorités<br />

fédérales s’en trouverait accrue et des sénateurs fédéraux élus pourraient<br />

prétendre représenter les intérêts de la population provinciale au même titre<br />

que les politiciens provinciaux3. <strong>La</strong> procédure de nomination des juges de la Cour suprême<br />

Actuellement, les juges de la Cour suprême sont nommés de façon<br />

pratiquement discrétionnaire par le gouvernement fédéral. L’Accord du lac<br />

14


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

Meech prévoyait que celui-ci serait tenu de les nommer sur proposition des<br />

gouvernements provinciaux 4. Ne craignant pas le ridicule, certains adversaires<br />

de l’Accord du lac Meech ont prétendu que cette modification enlèverait à la<br />

Cour suprême sa neutralité en tant qu’arbitre du fédéralisme. C’est plutôt le<br />

fait que les juges soient actuellement nommés par le seul gouvernement<br />

fédéral qui enlève à la Cour toute crédibilité en tant qu’instance véritablement<br />

impartiale. On peut même penser qu’un système de nomination conjointe des<br />

juges de la Cour suprême par le gouvernement fédéral et les provinces<br />

donnerait à la Cour une légitimité fédérative, qui lui fait actuellement défaut et<br />

pourrait donc avoir pour effet paradoxal de la mettre davantage à l’abri des<br />

critiques sans véritablement modifier la portée centralisatrice de son<br />

intervention, celle-ci tenant à des facteurs économiques, sociaux et politiques<br />

bien plus profonds que les simples modalités de désignation des juges. Pour<br />

terminer, il faut souligner qu’en vertu de l’article 96 de la Loi constitutionnelle<br />

de 1867, le gouvernement fédéral nomme de façon discrétionnaire les juges<br />

des cours supérieures et des cours d’appel provinciales. Or, les membres de la<br />

Cour suprême du Canada sont désignés dans neuf cas sur dix parmi les juges de<br />

la Cour supérieure ou de la Cour d’appel. On constate donc que le fait de<br />

dresser les listes de c<strong>and</strong>idats n’aurait pas conféré aux gouvernements<br />

provinciaux une très gr<strong>and</strong>e latitude.<br />

Les ententes relatives à l’immigration<br />

Actuellement, la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada attribue des pouvoirs concurrents en<br />

matière d’immigration au Parlement canadien et aux législatures des<br />

provinces tout en prévoyant la prépondérance de la législation fédérale en cas<br />

d’incompatibilité5. Cette disposition permet donc au Parlement fédéral<br />

d’exercer une véritable hégémonie dans le domaine de l’immigration,<br />

puisqu’il lui suffirait de légiférer de façon incompatible avec les lois<br />

provinciales en vigueur pour rendre celles-ci inopérantes.<br />

L’Accord du lac Meech prévoyait la constitutionnalisation d’une entente sur<br />

l’immigration intervenue en 1978 entre le Québec et le gouvernement fédéral<br />

par laquelle ce dernier acceptait de laisser le Québec établir les critères de<br />

sélection de certaines catégories d’immigrants. L’entente en question n’était<br />

cependant valable que pour une période déterminée et pouvait être dénoncée<br />

moyennant un préavis. Aux termes de l’Accord du lac Meech, cependant, il<br />

était prévu qu’après approbation par le Parlement fédéral et celui du Québec,<br />

elle serait constitutionnalisée et ne pourrait plus être modifiée qu’avec<br />

l’assentiment de ces deux mêmes corps législatifs. En outre, le gouvernement<br />

fédéral s’engageait à négocier avec les autres provinces qui en feraient la<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>e des accords similaires et à les constitutionnaliser également.<br />

Les adversaires de l’Accord du lac Meech ont prétendu que les autorités<br />

fédérales avaient ainsi ab<strong>and</strong>onné aux mains des provinces leurs pouvoirs en<br />

matière d’immigration. Cette critique est largement exagérée si l’on tient<br />

compte du fait que l’Accord prévoyait également que pareille entente « n’a<br />

d’effet que dans la mesure de sa compatibilité avec les dispositions des lois du<br />

Parlement du Canada qui fixent des normes et objectifs nationaux relatifs à<br />

l’immigration et aux aubains, notamment en ce qui concerne l’établissement<br />

des catégories générales d’immigrants, les niveaux d’immigration au Canada<br />

et la détermination des catégories de personnes admissibles au Canada ». Par<br />

conséquent, les autorités fédérales se réservaient le pouvoir discrétionnaire de<br />

rendre inopérantes les dispositions les plus importantes des ententes<br />

15


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

susceptibles d’être conclues avec les provinces, même après que leur<br />

enchâssement dans la <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

<strong>La</strong> limitation du pouvoir fédéral de dépenser<br />

Le « pouvoir de dépenser » désigne la capacité d’un ordre de gouvernement<br />

d’affecter des ressources financières à certains objectifs. Lorsque les buts<br />

poursuivis relèvent de la compétence de l’autorité qui engage les dépenses, il<br />

n’existe aucune difficulté particulière. Par contre, le problème se pose qu<strong>and</strong><br />

les dépenses ainsi faites permettent une intervention dans les compétences de<br />

l’autre ordre de gouvernement. Comme les ressources financières fédérales<br />

sont plus importantes que celles des provinces, ce sont ces dernières qui ont à<br />

craindre l’exercice du pouvoir de dépenser du gouvernement central, plutôt<br />

que l’inverse.<br />

Dans l’exercice de son pouvoir de dépenser, le fédéral verse aux provinces des<br />

subventions qui doivent servir à des programmes précis (par opposition aux<br />

paiements de péréquation que les provinces peuvent affecter librement aux<br />

fins qu’elles déterminent). En outre, ces subventions sont souvent<br />

conditionnelles au respect de certains objectifs ou normes fixés par les<br />

autorités fédérales. Enfin, les provinces sont parfois tenues de participer<br />

financièrement au programme, qui devient alors un programme « conjoint »<br />

(ou « cofinancé »). Des vérificateurs fédéraux contrôlent la bonne marche des<br />

opérations et l’utilisation des sommes versées par Ottawa. Le fédéral a<br />

commencé à proposer de tels programmes aux provinces dès l’époque de la<br />

Première Guerre mondiale dans des domaines relevant de la compétence<br />

provinciale. Depuis lors, plus de cent programmes de ce genre ont été établis,<br />

toujours à l’initiative des autorités fédérales, certains de nature temporaire,<br />

mais la plupart avec vocation à la permanence. Il est évidemment très difficile<br />

pour les provinces de refuser d’y participer, puisque cela désavantagerait leurs<br />

ressortissants qui paient à Ottawa des impôts dont une partie sert à financer les<br />

programmes en question. Pourtant, en se pliant aux objectifs et aux normes<br />

imposés par les autorités fédérales, les provinces consentent à modifier leurs<br />

propres priorités budgétaires et à se laisser dicter la manière d’exercer les<br />

compétences que la <strong>Constitution</strong> leur attribue de façon exclusive, sans compter<br />

qu’elles risquent, au bout d’un certain temps, de voir le fédéral se retirer<br />

unilatéralement du programme ou diminuer sa participation à un moment où il<br />

n’est plus politiquement possible de le supprimer à cause des attentes et des<br />

habitudes qu’il a créées dans la population6. L’Accord du lac Meech prévoyait qu’une province qui refuserait de participer<br />

aux futurs programmes à frais partagés, créés par le gouvernement fédéral<br />

dans un domaine de compétence provinciale exclusive, recevrait une « juste »<br />

compensation, qui correspondrait, si l’on comprend bien, au montant que le<br />

fédéral aurait dépensé chez elle si elle avait accepté le programme. Les<br />

adversaires de l’Accord considéraient que cette limitation du pouvoir fédéral<br />

de dépenser menaçait la capacité d’Ottawa de créer de nouveaux programmes<br />

sociaux (par exemple, un programme national de garderies) et d’en imposer<br />

l’implantation dans toutes les provinces. Encore une fois, la crainte semble<br />

exagérée. En effet, l’Accord du lac Meech prévoyait également qu’une<br />

province qui se retirerait d’un programme à frais partagés ne recevrait une<br />

compensation financière qu’à la condition d’affecter celle-ci à « un<br />

programme ou une mesure compatible avec les objectifs nationaux ». Il est vrai<br />

que la notion d’« objectifs nationaux » était imprécise et pouvait être<br />

diversement interprétée. Il aurait donc fallu attendre que les tribunaux lui<br />

16


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

donnent une signification plus précise avant de savoir quelles contraintes le<br />

respect des « objectifs nationaux » imposait réellement aux provinces.<br />

<strong>La</strong> procédure de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

L’Accord du lac Meech apportait certains changements à la procédure de<br />

modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong>. Il prévoyait notamment que les modifications<br />

actuellement visées par l’article 42 de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 et<br />

relevant par conséquent de la procédure générale des deux tiers seraient<br />

soumises à la règle de l’unanimité énoncée à l’article 41. Ce faisant, il<br />

assujétissait notamment la réforme des institutions fédérales et la création de<br />

nouvelles provinces à l’exigence d’un accord unanime des dix provinces, alors<br />

que ces modifications ne nécessitent actuellement que l’accord du Parlement<br />

fédéral et des deux tiers des provinces (c’est-à-dire sept provinces sur dix)<br />

représentant la moitié de la population totale.<br />

Il semble que les critiques adressées à ce dernier élément de l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech étaient justifiées. L’exigence de l’unanimité aurait conféré à la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> une rigidité excessive et rendu pratiquement impossible la<br />

réforme du Sénat et l’accession des Territoires du Nord-Ouest et du Yukon au<br />

statut de province. C’est pourquoi l’opposition à ces dispositions de l’Accord<br />

fut particulièrement vive, notamment dans les territoires et dans les provinces<br />

de l’Ouest, ces dernières tenant beaucoup à une réforme du Sénat. Le sort de<br />

l’Accord du lac Meech, qui a succombé à la règle de l’unanimité, démontre en<br />

quelque sorte par l’absurde les inconvénients qu’aurait entraînés l’extension<br />

de cette règle.<br />

Les difficultés de fonctionnement de la procédure de modification qu’a mises<br />

en évidence l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech amènent actuellement le<br />

gouvernement fédéral à rechercher les moyens de simplifier cette procédure et,<br />

en particulier, de diminuer les cas où l’unanimité serait exigée. Cependant, en<br />

vertu de l’article 41(e) de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982, tout changement de<br />

la procédure de modification exige l’accord unanime des autorités fédérales et<br />

des dix provinces7. <strong>La</strong> reconnaissance de la dualité linguistique du Canada et du caractère<br />

distinct du Québec<br />

L’Accord du lac Meech contenait également des dispositions reconnaissant la<br />

dualité linguistique du Canada et le caractère distinct de la société québécoise.<br />

Ce sont ces dispositions, surtout celles relatives au caractère distinct du<br />

Québec, qui ont suscité les critiques les plus virulentes. Les adversaires de<br />

l’Accord ont prétendu tout à la fois qu’elles avaient pour effet de conférer au<br />

Québec plus de pouvoirs qu’aux autres provinces et qu’elles lui permettraient<br />

de limiter, voire de supprimer les droits et libertés garantis dans la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

canadienne. Ces craintes étaient très nettement exagérées.<br />

D’abord, en ce qui concerne le partage des compétences, l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech contenait une disposition qui empêchait de façon très claire qu’on<br />

puisse faire découler de la reconnaissance du caractère distinct du Québec<br />

quelque modification que ce soit à l’actuelle répartition des pouvoirs entre le<br />

Parlement canadien et l’Assemblée législative du Québec. Par conséquent,<br />

l’Accord n’augmentait pas les pouvoirs de la province, pas plus qu’il ne les<br />

diminuait.<br />

17


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Ensuite, il faut relativiser les dangers que l’Accord constitutionnel faisait<br />

prétendûment courir aux droits et libertés. À cet égard, il y a lieu de distinguer<br />

entre les droits individuels et les droits collectifs des minorités.<br />

Les droits individuels, universels par nature, ne semblaient guère menacés : il<br />

eût été en effet fort difficile de prouver que le caractère distinct du Québec<br />

exigeait leur limitation, puisque par définition, ils sont les mêmes partout. Par<br />

contre, les droits à portée culturelle et linguistique, de nature collective, étaient<br />

à première vue plus vulnérables, puisqu’ils portent sur les mêmes réalités que<br />

celles qui constituent le caractère distinct du Québec (la langue et la culture) et<br />

qu’ils ne sont pas eux-mêmes universels et fondamentaux, mais propres à une<br />

situation sociale et culturelle contingente. Cependant, toutes les précautions<br />

avaient été prises pour que la reconnaissance du caractère distinct du Québec<br />

ne vienne pas diminuer les droits reconnus dans la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des<br />

droits et libertés ou dans d’autres dispositions constitutionnelles aux minorités<br />

qui vivent sur le territoire québécois. Pour ce qui est des droits de la minorité<br />

anglophone du Québec, ils étaient réaffirmés par la disposition faisant de la<br />

dualité linguistique une « caractéristique fondamentale de la fédération<br />

canadienne ». Manifestement, la protection de la minorité anglophone aurait<br />

toujours priorité sur la promotion du caractère francophone distinct du<br />

Québec. Quant aux autres minorités ethniques et culturelles du Québec, elles<br />

sont protégées par l’article 27 de la <strong>Charte</strong> qui garantit « le maintien et la<br />

valorisation du patrimoine multiculturel ». Or, cet article 27 a été purement et<br />

simplement soustrait à la portée de l’Accord du lac Meech, tout comme<br />

d’ailleurs les dispositions constitutionnelles qui protègent les droits des<br />

peuples autochtones (articles 25 de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés<br />

et 35 de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982).<br />

Ce bilan rapide tend donc à démontrer que l’incidence des dispositions<br />

relatives au caractère distinct du Québec sur les droits garantis par la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, qu’ils soient individuels ou collectifs, ne pouvait être que<br />

négligeable8. Les causes de l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech<br />

Pour entrer en vigueur, l’Accord du lac Meech devait être ratifié par le<br />

Parlement fédéral et l’assemblée législative de chacune des dix provmces.<br />

Dans les deux ans qui ont suivi la conclusion de l’Accord, des élections<br />

provinciales au Nouveau-Brunswick, au Manitoba et à Terre-Neuve<br />

amenèrent au pouvoir des chefs de gouvernement qui n’avaient pas participé à<br />

la négociation et à la signature de l’Accord et qui refusèrent de le faire ratifier<br />

par leur assemblée législative ou même — dans le cas de Terre-Neuve — firent<br />

révoquer par cette dernière la résolution d’agrément qu’elle avait déjà<br />

adoptée9. L’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech s’explique en bonne partie par la<br />

« globalisation » du processus de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> qui, à<br />

l’origine, était exclusivement destiné à permettre l’adhésion du Québec à la<br />

Loi constitutionnelle de 1982. Mais la raison la plus importante de cet échec<br />

tient à l’incompatibilité profonde qui s’est manifestée entre les aspirations<br />

constitutionnelles du Québec et celles d’une gr<strong>and</strong>e partie du Canada anglais.<br />

18


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

<strong>La</strong> « globalisation » du processus de modification constitutionnelle<br />

Le processus de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong>, qui était d’abord destiné à<br />

satisfaire les conditions du Québec, s’est rapidement « globalisé ». Les trois<br />

provinces récalcitrantes liaient leur acceptation de l’Accord à une réforme du<br />

Sénat. Il faut reconnaître que cette attitude se justifiait par le fait que la réforme<br />

du Sénat serait devenue beaucoup plus difficile si l’Accord du lac Meech était<br />

entré en vigueur, puisqu’elle aurait été soumise à la règle de l’unanimité (alors<br />

qu’à l’heure actuelle, une telle réforme n’exige que l’accord des autorités<br />

fédérales et de sept provinces, représentant 50 p. 100 de la population).<br />

En outre, de nombreux groupes d’intérêt ont voulu profiter de l’occasion pour<br />

obtenir la satisfaction de leurs propres revendications constitutionnelles.<br />

Ainsi, les peuples autochtones du Canada ont vivement combattu l’Accord du<br />

lac Meech. Leur opposition était en partie motivée par les dispositions portant<br />

sur la procédure d’amendement de la <strong>Constitution</strong> qui faisaient en sorte, une<br />

fois l’Accord entré en vigueur, que la création de nouvelles provinces au<br />

Yukon et dans les Territoires du Nord-Ouest exigerait l’assentiment de toutes<br />

les provinces et non plus l’accord de sept d’entre elles comme c’est le cas à<br />

l’heure actuelle. Mais le principal grief des autochtones à l’égard de l’Accord<br />

se situait sur le plan de la symbolique constitutionnelle. En effet, de tous les<br />

groupes opposés à l’Accord du lac Meech, les autochtones étaient le seul à<br />

revendiquer d’être reconnu comme une « société distincte » parce qu’il est le<br />

seul, avec le Québec, à avoir des ambitions « nationales » ou, du moins, des<br />

revendications en matière d’autonomie gouvernementale. Les autochtones<br />

considéraient que leur reconnaissance comme « société distincte » aurait<br />

favorisé ces revendications sur un plan politique. Il faut également souligner<br />

que celles-ci avaient été présentées une nouvelle fois, quelques semaines<br />

seulement avant l’Accord du lac Meech, lors d’une conférence<br />

constitutionnelle qui avait échoué. Enfin, alors que les peuples autochtones<br />

peuvent invoquer une légitimité historique antérieure à celle des deux<br />

« peuples fondateurs » — les anglophones et les francophones — leur<br />

existence n’a pas été reconnue comme une « caractéristique fondamentale »<br />

dans l’Accord du lac Meech ni ailleurs dans la <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

L’Accord du lac Meech a également entraîné l’intervention des associations<br />

féministes du Canada anglais qui prétendaient que la limitation du pouvoir de<br />

dépenser du gouvernement fédéral empêcherait celui-ci de mettre sur pied un<br />

programme national de garderies. Ces associations craignaient également que<br />

la reconnaissance du caractère distinct du Québec ne menace le droit des<br />

femmes à l’égalité. De même, les Anglo-Québécois sont intervenus pour<br />

dénoncer l’Accord dans la mesure où ils considéraient que les dispositions<br />

reconnaissant le caractère distinct du Québec menaçaient leurs droits<br />

linguistiques. De leur côté, les francophones du Nouveau-Brunswick ont<br />

cautionné l’opposition de leur gouvernement à l’Accord du lac Meech parce<br />

qu’ils voulaient profiter du processus pour faire inscrire dans la <strong>Constitution</strong> le<br />

principe de l’égalité de statut des communautés francophone et anglophone de<br />

la province, ce qui aurait cependant pu être réalisé par simple entente entre les<br />

autorités fédérales et celles du Nouveau-Brunswick10. Enfin, de nombreuses<br />

minorités culturelles et ethniques ont eu le sentiment que l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech rabaissait le statut que leur octroyait l’article 27 de la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés qui prévoit le maintien et la promotion du<br />

multiculturalisme. C’est pourquoi ces groupes voulaient faire modifier<br />

l’Accord de façon à ce que le multiculturalisme soit également reconnu<br />

comme une « caractéristique fondamentale du Canada ».<br />

19


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

On peut donc constater que toute tentative de réforme constitutionnelle<br />

provoque désormais l’intervention quasi automatique de nombreux groupes<br />

d’intérêts. Toute légitime que soit cette tendance sur le plan démocratique, il<br />

n’en reste pas moins qu’elle augmente considérablement les difficultés de<br />

fonctionnement de la procédure de modification.<br />

Le choc des aspirations et des identités nationales du Québec et du Canada<br />

anglais<br />

Il est vrai que deux provinces seulement (le Manitoba et le Nouveau-<br />

Brunswick), représentant moins de 8 p. 100 de la population canadienne, ont<br />

finalement refusé l’Accord, les sept autres provinces anglophones l’ayant<br />

entériné. Cependant, les sondages démontrent qu’à l’intérieur de celles-ci, une<br />

large majorité — entre 60 p. 100 et 70 p. 100 de la population — était fortement<br />

opposée à l’Accord du lac Meech. En fait, la controverse autour de l’Accord a<br />

révélé les divergences profondes qui existent entre les visions et les aspirations<br />

constitutionnelles du Québec et celles du Canada anglais, qu’il s’agisse de la<br />

répartition des pouvoirs entre l’État central et les provinces, du rôle reconnu à<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong> constitutionnelle, de la politique linguistique et des droits des<br />

minorités ou encore — et surtout — de la place du Québec au sein de la<br />

fédération canadienne.<br />

<strong>La</strong> répartition des pouvoirs<br />

En ce qui concerne le partage des pouvoirs entre les deux ordres de<br />

gouvernement, il paraît clair que les Canadiens anglais, en majorité, sont<br />

désireux de voir s’établir une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e centralisation, notamment dans les<br />

domaines de l’éducation, de la culture, des télecommunications et de la<br />

politique sociale, domaines pour lesquels le Québec réclame, au contraire, une<br />

plus gr<strong>and</strong>e décentralisation. Aux yeux de nombreux Canadiens anglais, cela<br />

est nécessaire pour assurer une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e égalité entre les citoyens et<br />

consolider l’identité nationale canadienne face à l’influence des États-Unis.<br />

Cette opinion est particulièrement rép<strong>and</strong>ue chez les élites canadiennesanglaises<br />

de gauche et de centre-gauche: bien que traditionnellement<br />

sympathiques aux revendications du Québec, celles-ci se sont opposées à<br />

l’Accord du lac Meech parce qu’elles y voyaient une diminution des pouvoirs<br />

du gouvernement fédéral.<br />

Il faut également souligner que six des neuf provinces anglophones ont des<br />

revenus fiscaux inférieurs à la moyenne nationale et, par conséquent,<br />

bénéficient des paiements de péréquation et autres transferts fédéraux par le<br />

biais desquels le gouvernement central procède à une certaine redistribution de<br />

la richesse nationale. Pour la plupart de ces provinces, les versements fédéraux<br />

constituent une part fort importante de leur budget et, pour cette raison, elles<br />

sont évidemment opposées à toute réforme constitutionnelle qui affaiblirait<br />

l’État centrall1. En outre, comme on l’a mentionné précédemment, les provinces de<br />

l’Atlantique et de l’Ouest, moins peuplées que le Québec et l’Ontario, espèrent<br />

qu’une réforme du Sénat leur accordera plus de pouvoir au sein des institutions<br />

centrales; dans cette mesure, elles veulent évidemment qu’elles le deviennent<br />

davantage. Elles recherchent donc plus d’influence sur le processus politique<br />

fédéral par le biais d’une Chambre haute renforcée où elles seront mieux<br />

représentées qu’à la Chambre des communes.<br />

Enfin, il faut constater que le sentiment d’identité nationale des Canadiens<br />

anglais est davantage associé à l’État central et à ses institutions qu’aux<br />

20


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

pouvoirs publics provinciaux. Par conséquent, toute dimininution du rôle et<br />

des pouvoirs d’Ottawa est perçue comme une menace ou une attaque contre<br />

cette identité. Les Québécois, au contraire, surtout depuis la « Révolution<br />

tranquille », accordent principalement leur confiance et leur loyauté à l’État<br />

provincial, ce qui est fort compréhensible, puisque c’est le seul État qu’ils<br />

contrôlent de façon démocratique. Par conséquent, à l’inverse de ce qui se<br />

passe pour les Canadiens anglais, ce sont les visées centralisatrices qui<br />

menacent le sentiment d’identité nationale des Québécois francophones.<br />

Les attitudes à l’égard de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadiennes des droits et libertés<br />

<strong>La</strong> même divergence existe en ce qui concerne les attitudes respectives des<br />

Canadiens anglais et des Québécois francophones à l’égard de la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

constitutionnelle. Au Canada anglais, celle-ci sert désormais de symbole<br />

national. L’universalité des principes qui y sont enchâssés permet de<br />

transcender les nombreuses différences de culture et d’origine qui existent<br />

dans une population composée en gr<strong>and</strong>e partie d’immigrants venus de toutes<br />

les parties du monde. Cependant, dans la mesure précisément où les droits de la<br />

personne sont généralement considérés comme devant être appliqués et<br />

interprétés partout de la même façon, l’application d’une charte<br />

constitutionnelle commune au Canada anglais et au Québec pourrait, à la<br />

longue, avoir des effets socialement uniformisateurs et par conséquent,<br />

menacer le caractère distinct de la société québécoisel2. <strong>La</strong> mise en œuvre des<br />

droits et libertés touche des problèmes de culture et de civilisation et amène les<br />

tribunaux à se substituer au législateur pour effectuer certains « choix de<br />

société ». Or, dans le cadre de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne, cette mise en oeuvre se fait<br />

à l’echelle nationale par le truchement d’une hiérarchie judiciaire centralisée<br />

qui utilise inévitablement une approche uniforme pour interpréter les<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards constitutionnels (on a souligné précédemment que les juges des<br />

cours supérieures et des cours d’appel provinciales sont nommés de façon<br />

discrétionnaire par le gouvernement fédéral). Dans la mesure où l’application<br />

de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne est susceptible de limiter les pouvoirs et la liberté de<br />

choix des organes démocratiques de l’État québécois, on comprendra qu’elle<br />

ne suscite pas au Québec les mêmes sentiments de ferveur que dans les autres<br />

provincesl3. En cherchant à faire reconnaître le caractère distinct de la société<br />

québécoise, l’on voulait précisement se protéger contre les effets<br />

uniformisateurs de la <strong>Charte</strong> espérant que cette disposition inciterait les<br />

tribunaux à tenir compte des besoins particuliers du Québec14. En 1975, l’Assemblée nationale du Québec a adopté une <strong>Charte</strong> des droits et<br />

libertés de la personne15 qui possède une valeur « quasi constitutionnelle »,<br />

puisqu’elle a primauté sur les lois québécoises ordinaires. Les Québécois<br />

francophones considèrent généralement que cet instrument les protège<br />

adéquatement et que, s’il y a lieu de le constitutionnaliser, il devrait figurer<br />

dans une nouvelle constitution du Québec, laquelle pourrait être adoptée soit<br />

dans l’actuel cadre fédéral canadien, soit à l’occasion de l’accession du<br />

Québec à la souverainetél6. Les droits des minorités et les politiques linguistiques<br />

En ce qui concerne la politique linguistique et les droits des minorités, le<br />

Canada anglais reproche au Québec de limiter les droits de sa minorité<br />

anglophone au moment même où le statut juridique des francophones hors du<br />

Québec benéficie d’une certaine amélioration. Cette vision « symétrique »<br />

méconnaît cependant le fait que les francophones, même s’ils sont en situation<br />

de majorité au Québec, constituent une minorité en perte d’influence à<br />

21


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

l’echelle du pays. En effet, tous les efforts consentis par les autorités fédérales<br />

et certaines provinces pour améliorer le sort des minorités francophones n’ont<br />

pas réussi à freiner le taux d’assimilation de ces groupes. Même au Québec, où<br />

90 p. 100 des francophones du Canada sont désormais concentrés, le fait<br />

français n’est pas à l’abri du danger, puisque les immigrants continuent de<br />

s’assimiler de préférence à la communauté anglophonel7. Pour protéger la<br />

langue française, les autorités québécoises considèrent donc qu’il faut parfois<br />

limiter les droits traditionnels des anglophones, dans la mesure où les deux<br />

langues sont en situation de concurrence. <strong>La</strong> plupart des Canadiens anglais<br />

rejettent cependant ces arguments et considèrent que la politique québécoise<br />

de la langue française viole le « pacte linguistique » tacite auquel ils ont<br />

consenti en acceptant la politique de bilinguisme officiel du gouvernement<br />

fédéral et celle de deux provinces anglophones (le Nouveau-Brunswick et,<br />

dans une moindre mesure, l’Ontario).<br />

<strong>La</strong> place du Ouébec au sein de la fédération<br />

Enfin, l’opposition la plus radicale qui se manifeste entre le Canada anglais et<br />

le Québec concerne la reconnaissance de celui-ci comme communauté<br />

nationale distincte. Depuis 1867, mais plus encore à partir de la « Révolution<br />

tranquille », le Québec aspire à un « statut particulier », qui se traduirait par<br />

l’obtention de pouvoirs supplémentaires, considérés comme nécessaires à<br />

l’épanouissement de la société québécoise. Cependant, à cette revendication<br />

de l’égalité entre les deux « peuples fondateurs », le Canada anglais a toujours<br />

opposé le double principe de l’égalité des provinces et des individus.<br />

L’insistance mise sur l’égalité juridique de toutes les provinces empêche<br />

évidemment de reconnaître à l’une d’entre elles un statut ou des pouvoirs<br />

particuliers. Mais il s’agit là d’un principe plutôt artificiel, qui ne correspond<br />

d’ailleurs pas au droit positif, puisque la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne contient déjà<br />

plusieurs dispositions qui traitent certaines provinces différemment des autres,<br />

notamment sur le plan des droits linguistiques. Quant à l’égalité des individus,<br />

garantie par la <strong>Charte</strong> constitutionnelle, l’interprétation radicale et quelque<br />

peu simpliste qu’on lui donne parfois rend également plus difficiles les<br />

arrangements institutionnels qui reconnaîtraient au Québec un statut<br />

particulier. En effet, comme le montrent certains arguments des opposants à<br />

l’Accord du lac Meech, de tels arrangements sont considérés au Canada<br />

anglais comme accordant aux Québécois plus de droits qu’aux Canadiens des<br />

autres provinces18. On peut donc conclure en affirmant que l’opposition entre le Canada anglais et<br />

le Québec a pris les allures d’un choc entre deux « sociétés globales », deux<br />

communautés nationales distinctes, dont la coexistence ne semble plus guère<br />

possible dans le cadre des structures constitutionnelles actuelles19. Il faut alors<br />

se dem<strong>and</strong>er si une association — ou communauté — entre ces deux nations<br />

est encore possible, et sous quelle forme.<br />

Le rejet de l’Accord de Charlottetown en 1992 et l’avenir des rapports<br />

entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

Un peu plus de deux ans après l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech, un nouvel<br />

accord constitutionnel, appelé « l’Accord de Charlottetown », était conclu par<br />

les onze premiers ministres auxquels s’étaient joints cette fois les<br />

représentants des Peuples autochtones du Canada. Soumis à référendum le 26<br />

octobre 1992, l’Accord de Charlottetown a été rejeté par la population de façon<br />

décisive, tant au Québec que dans le reste du Canada. Après avoir examiné sa<br />

22


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

genèse et son contenu, puis les causes de son échec, on terminera en tentant<br />

d’analyser les options encore disponibles pour l’avenir.<br />

<strong>La</strong> genèse et le contenu de l ’Accord de Charlottetown<br />

En septembre 1990, le gouvernement Bourassa et l’opposition péquiste se sont<br />

entendus pour créer une commission parlementaire élargie (la Commission<br />

Bélanger-Campeau, du nom de ses deux coprésidents) qui a reçu le m<strong>and</strong>at<br />

d’étudier les options possibles et de proposer des solutions pour l’avenir<br />

politique et constitutionnel du Québec. <strong>La</strong> Commission a remis son rapport en<br />

mars 1991 dans lequel elle conclut que les deux seules voies de solution qui<br />

s’ouvrent pour l’avenir sont la modification en profondeur du cadre<br />

constitutionnel actuel ou, sinon, l’accession du Québec à la souveraineté avec<br />

ou sans l’accord du Canada anglais20. Les principales recomm<strong>and</strong>ations de la<br />

Commission B.-C. ont été entérinées par le gouvernement quelques mois plus<br />

tard lorsque celui-ci a fait adopter par l’Assemblée nationale la Loi sur le<br />

processus de détermination de l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du<br />

Québec21. Celle-ci prévoyait la tenue d’un référendum sur la souveraineté du<br />

Québec au plus tard le 26 octobre 1992. Entre-temps, il restait loisible au<br />

gouvernement fédéral et aux autres provinces d’offrir au Québec de nouveaux<br />

arrangements constitutionnels.<br />

Le 24 septembre 1991, le gouvernement fédéral de M. Brian Mulroney<br />

présentait ses propositions de renouvellement constitutionnel22. Un comité<br />

mixte spécial du Sénat et de la Chambre des communes était créé pour<br />

parcourir le Canada afin de recueillir les réactions à ces propositions et de<br />

suggérer, le cas échéant, des modifications. Le rapport du comité a été déposé<br />

le 28 février 199223. En outre, à partir de la fin du mois de janvier, une série de<br />

conférences fut organisée pour permettre à certains groupes d’intérêts et à des<br />

personnes choisies dans le gr<strong>and</strong> public de discuter les propositions<br />

constitutionnelles du gouvernement fédéral. Entre le 12 mars et le 7 juillet<br />

1992, les recomm<strong>and</strong>ations du comité mixte allaient servir de base de<br />

discussion lors d’une série de rencontres entre les représentants des autorités<br />

fédérales, des provinces (le Québec excepté), des territoires et des peuples<br />

autochtones. À partir du 4 août 1992, se tinrent ensuite un certain nombre de<br />

réunions des premiers ministres, fédéral et provinciaux, auxquelles accepta de<br />

participer le chef du gouvernement du Québec, M. Robert Bourassa. Elles<br />

devaient aboutir, le 28 août, à un accord constitutionnel appelé « l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown ». Cependant, ce n’est que le 9 octobre suivant que furent<br />

rendus publics les textes juridiques définitifs de l’entente, lesquels<br />

comportaient de nombreuses questions en suspens, qui devaient par<br />

conséquent faire l’objet de négociations futures. C’est sous cette forme<br />

quelque peu inachevée et programmatique que le projet de réforme<br />

constitutionnelle fut soumis à la populatlon, qui le repoussa — tant au Québec<br />

que dans cinq autres provinces — lors d’un référendum qui eut lieu le 26<br />

octobre 199224. Étant donné le rejet de l’Accord de Charlottetown, il n’est pas<br />

nécessaire d’en analyser le contenu en détail. Nous en ferons cependant une<br />

brève description pour tenter de comprendre pourquoi il a été rejeté et quelles<br />

conséquences sont susceptibles de découler de ce nouvel échec.<br />

Dans le nouveau projet de modification constitutionnelle, les dispositions<br />

relatives au caractère distinct du Québec étaient désormais inscrites dans une<br />

« clause Canada », destinée à étre placée au début de la <strong>Constitution</strong>, qui<br />

énonçait huit « caractéristiques fondamentales » avec lesquelles devrait<br />

concorder l’interprétation de la <strong>Constitution</strong>, notamment la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

23


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

canadienne des droits et libertés. Parmi les sept autres « caractéristiques<br />

fondamentales » ainsi consacrées, deux au moins risquaient d’entrer en conflit<br />

avec le caractère distinct du Québec : d’une part, le principe de l’égalité de<br />

toutes les provinces et, d’autre part, « l’attachement [commitment en anglais]<br />

des Canadiens et de leurs gouvernements à l’épanouissement et au<br />

développement des communautés minoritaires de langue officielle dans tout le<br />

pays » (c’est-à-dire, au Québec, de la minorité anglophone). Par ailleurs, le<br />

paragraphe 2 de la clause Canada affirmait que « [l]a législature et le<br />

gouvernement du Québec ont le rôle de protéger et de promouvoir la société<br />

distincte. »<br />

Toutes ces règles d’interprétation auraient eu sensiblement le même poids<br />

juridique. Par conséquent, il n’aurait pas été possible pour les tribunaux<br />

d’interpréter la <strong>Constitution</strong> de façon distincte pour le Québec, puisque cela<br />

aurait été contraire à l’égalité interprovinciale. De même, interpréter la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> comme permettant une mesure qui affecterait négativement le<br />

développement et l’épanouissement de la minorité anglo-québécoise serait<br />

allé à l’encontre de la disposition protégeant les minorités de langue officielle.<br />

Avec cette disposition, la minorité anglophone aurait même disposé d’une<br />

nouvelle arme pour contester les réglementations linguistiques québécoises<br />

considérées comme incompatibles avec la protection et l’épanouissement de la<br />

langue anglaise. Il est vrai que le Québec aurait alors pu arguer que les mesures<br />

contestées étaient necessaires pour protéger et promouvolr son caractère<br />

distinct. Les tribunaux auraient dès lors été obligés de constater qu’il y avait<br />

contradiction entre la promotion des droits de la majorité, fondée sur le<br />

caractère distinct du Québec, et l’épanouissement des droits de la minorité et<br />

auraient donc dû déterminer laquelle de ces deux « caractéristiques<br />

fondamentales » devait se voir reconnaître la primauté.<br />

Pour terminer, il faut souligner que dans l’Accord de Charlottetown,<br />

contrairement à l’Accord du lac Meech, la « société distincte » était définie<br />

comme « comprenant notamment une majorité d’expression française, une<br />

culture qui est unique et une tradition de droit civil ». Bien que n’étant pas<br />

exhaustive, cette énumération était de nature à limiter le contenu de la société<br />

distincte dans la mesure où les tribunaux auraient pu appliquer la règle voulant<br />

que seuls des éléments analogues à ceux qui sont énumérés peuvent être<br />

ajoutés par interprétation à une liste non exhaustive (règle ejusdem generis).<br />

Or, le « genre » des trois éléments mentionnés, leur trait commun, était leur<br />

caractère traditionnel : il s’agissait de caractères particuliers du Québec qui<br />

existaient déjà au moment où celui-ci était entré dans la fédération en 1867. Par<br />

conséquent, on pouvait prétendre que le caractère distinct du Québec, tel qu’il<br />

était reconnu dans la clause Canada, était lié au passé et à l’histoire. Rien ne<br />

permettait évidemment de prétendre avec certitude que les tribunaux auraient<br />

retenu ce genre d’interprétation, mais cette possibilité ne pouvait pas<br />

davantage être exclue.<br />

En tenant compte des différences qui viennent d’être mentionnées, il faut donc<br />

constater que la reconnaissance du caractère distinct du Québec dans l’Accord<br />

de Charlottetown avait perdu de sa portée par rapport à l’Accord du <strong>La</strong>c<br />

Meech.<br />

L’Accord constitutionnel de Charlottetown comprenait également des<br />

dispositions relatives à la réforme du Sénat, de la Chambre des communes et de<br />

la Cour suprême.<br />

24


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

Concernant la réforme du Sénat, l’accord constitutionnel prévoyait que celuici<br />

serait « égal », chaque province étant représentée par six sénateurs et chaque<br />

territoire par un. Dans un premier temps, la proportion des sièges du Québec au<br />

Sénat serait donc passée de 23,1 p. 100 à 9,7 p. 100. Mais elle aurait ensuite<br />

continué à diminuer. En effet, l’accord constitutionnel prévoyait également de<br />

nouvelles négociations pour ajouter des sièges au Sénat afin d’y représenter les<br />

peuples autochtones. En outre, au fur et à mesure de la créaton de nouvelles<br />

provinces, il aurait fallu à nouveau augmenter le nombre des sièges de la<br />

Chambre haute. À cet égard, il faut souligner que le Québec n’avait pas obtenu,<br />

comme il le dem<strong>and</strong>ait, un droit de veto sur la création de nouvelles provinces.<br />

Au contraire, l’Accord de Charlottetown entraînait un recul de la position<br />

provinciale sur ce plan. Alors qu’à l’heure actuelle, en vertu de la Loi<br />

constitutionnelle de 1982, il faut le consentement de sept provinces<br />

représentant 50 p. 100 de la population pour créer une nouvelle province à<br />

partir d’un des deux territoires, l’Accord de 1992 prévoyait qu’il suffirait d’un<br />

accord entre les autorités fédérales et le territoire intéressé. Il est vrai, par<br />

contre, qu’il était également prévu que les provinces existantes devraient<br />

consentir, à l’unanimité, aux modalités de participation de la nouvelle<br />

province à la procédure de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> ainsi qu’à<br />

l’augmentation de sa représentation au Sénat. Il aurait donc pu arriver, par<br />

exemple, que deux nouvelles provinces soient créées pour les Territoires du<br />

Nord-Ouest, mais qu’une ou plusieurs provinces s’opposent à l’augmentation<br />

du nombre des sénateurs, avec le résultat que le principe de l’égalité de<br />

représentation des provinces au Sénat n’aurait pas pu être respecté. Les<br />

pressions pour l’augmentation des membres de la Chambre haute seraient<br />

alors devenues très fortes et, sur un plan pratique et politique, les provinces<br />

récalcitrantes auraient eu beaucoup de difficultés à maintenir leur obstruction.<br />

Selon l’Accord de Charlottetown, les sénateurs devaient être élus soit par la<br />

population, soit par l’assemblée législative provinciale, selon ce que chaque<br />

province déciderait.<br />

En ce qui concerne les attributions législatives du nouveau Sénat, l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown distinguait quatre catégories de projets de lois. Le Sénat<br />

disposerait d’un droit de veto absolu sur les projets de loi supposant « des<br />

changements fondamentaux du régime fiscal directement lié aux ressources<br />

naturelles ». Par contre, pour les projets de loi traitant des recettes et des<br />

dépenses (les projets de loi de crédits), le nouveau Sénat n’aurait qu’un droit de<br />

veto suspensif de trente jours, la Chambres des communes pouvant réadopter<br />

le projet au bout de cette période par une majorité ordinaire. Quant aux projets<br />

de loi « touchant de façon importante à la langue ou à la culture française », ils<br />

devraient être adoptés par une majorité de tous les sénateurs et par une majorité<br />

des sénateurs francophones (les sénateurs francophones étant ceux qui se<br />

déclarent comme tels au moment de leur accession au Sénat). Enfin, pour ce<br />

qui est des projets de loi « ordinaires », c’est-à-dire n’entrant dans aucune des<br />

trois catégories précédentes, le rejet ou la modification d’un projet de loi par le<br />

Sénat déclencherait un processus de séance conjointe des deux Chambres; un<br />

vote à la majorité simple en séance conjointe déciderait alors du sort du projet<br />

de loi. Par ailleurs, le nombre des députés serait augmenté substantiellement.<br />

Par conséquent, lorsque le gouvernement aurait disposé d’une solide majorité<br />

à la Chambre des Communes, comme c’est normalement le cas, il n’aurait pas<br />

eu de difficulté à faire renverser par celle-ci le veto que le Sénat pouvait<br />

opposer à ses projets (autres que ceux portant sur la fiscalité des ressources<br />

naturelles et la langue ou la culture française). En revanche, dans les cas où le<br />

25


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

gouvernement fédéral aurait été minoritaire ou n’aurait disposé que d’une<br />

faible majorité (comme cela est quelques fois arrivé au cours des quarante<br />

dernières années), l’alliance entre les partis d’opposition aux Communes et un<br />

certain nombre de sénateurs aurait pu être fatale à de nombreux projets de loi<br />

s’ils avaient fait l’objet d’un vote en séance conjointe. Dans un tel cas, le<br />

Cabinet pouvait même être contraint de dissoudre le Parlement et de faire des<br />

élections, bien qu’en théorie, selon l’Accord constitutionnel, le nouveau Sénat<br />

ne se voyait pas reconnaître le pouvoir de renverser le gouvernement.<br />

On constate donc que la réforme du Sénat risquait de compliquer, voire<br />

d’entraver sérieusement le fonctionnement du système parlementaire<br />

canadien. On peut ajouter à cela que la réforme aurait mis en mouvement une<br />

dynamique dont il était fort difficile d’évaluer les effets futurs. Dans la mesure<br />

où les sénateurs auraient été titulaires d’une légitimité démocratique<br />

semblable à celles des députés fédéraux, ils auraient pu exercer un pouvoir<br />

politique et moral, sinon juridique, considérable (il est illogique de donner au<br />

Sénat une forte légitimité démocratique sans lui reconnaître d’importants<br />

pouvoirs). Cela risquait de susciter de fortes pressions en faveur de<br />

l’augmentation des prérogatives de la Chambre haute.<br />

L’Accord de Charlottetown accordait au Québec la garantie de n’avoir jamais<br />

moins de 25 p. 100 des sièges à la Chambre des communes sans égard à<br />

l’importance relative de sa population. Il s’agissait là d’une protection qui était<br />

loin d’être négligeable pour l’avenir. En effet, si la population québécoise<br />

représente actuellement un peu plus du quart de l’ensemble canadien, elle<br />

devrait, selon les estimations, bientôt tomber sous ce seuil et continuer de<br />

diminuer au cours du XXIe siècle. <strong>La</strong> Chambre des communes restant le<br />

principal lieu d’exercice du pouvoir législatif fédéral, il est important que le<br />

Québec y soit protégé contre une diminution de sa représentation. Cependant,<br />

il ne faut pas exagérer la portée de cette garantie. En effet, les députés sont<br />

généralement prisonniers de la discipline de parti et votent par conséquent bien<br />

plus en fonction des consignes de leur parti politique que des intérêts de la<br />

province qu’ils représentent. Par conséquent, la présence d’un fort contingent<br />

de députés québécois à Ottawa ne constitue pas nécessairement une garantie<br />

que le gouvernement fédéral respectera les orientations et les priorités du<br />

gouvernement du Québec.<br />

Concernant la nomination des juges de la Cour suprême, l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown reprenait essentiellement les dispositions de l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech. En effet, il était prévu de constitutionnaliser les dispositions de la Loi<br />

sur la Cour suprême voulant que trois des neuf juges de la Cour doivent avoir<br />

été reçus au Barreau du Québec, c’est-à-dire être des civilistes, et l’on<br />

prévoyait que le gouvernement québécois pourrait présenter la liste à partir de<br />

laquelle le gouvernement fédéral devrait nommer les juges venant du Québec.<br />

Par contre, contrairement à ce que prévoyait l’Accord du lac Meech, les<br />

modifications futures du processus de sélection des juges de la Cour suprême<br />

n’exigeraient pas le consentement de toutes les provinces (ce qui aurait donné<br />

au Québec un droit de veto), mais seulement l’accord de sept d’entre elles,<br />

représentant la moitié de la population.<br />

Au chapitre de la répartition des pouvoirs, où le Québec réclame depuis trente<br />

ans une augmentation de ses compétences dans de nombreux domaines ainsi<br />

qu’une véritable limitation du pouvoir fédéral de dépenser, l’Accord<br />

constitutionnel consacrait essentiellement une forme de statu quo<br />

« remodelé ». En outre, rappelons que l’Accord n’énonçait dans ce domaine<br />

26


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

aucune règle propre au Québec, qui se trouvait donc traité exactement comme<br />

toutes les autres provinces.<br />

En premier lieu, dans un certain nombre de domaines (forêts, mines, tourisme,<br />

logement, loisirs, affaires municipales et urbaines) où les provinces possèdent<br />

déjà les pouvoirs législatifs, ceux-ci étaient formellement réaffirmés, en même<br />

temps qu’était également consacré le pouvoir de dépenser du gouvernement<br />

fédéral, lequel s’engageait à négocier son retrait par des accords valables pour<br />

cinq ans et renouvelables.<br />

Ensuite, la compétence législative exclusive des provinces était reconnue dans<br />

le domaine du développement et de la formation de la main- d’oeuvre, le<br />

fédéral conservant cependant le droit d’établir — de concert avec les provinces<br />

— des objectifs nationaux pour le premier de ces domaines. Là encore, le nonexercice<br />

du pouvoir fédéral de dépenser devait d’abord être négociée par les<br />

provinces. En outre, le fédéral conservait sa compétence exclusive à l’égard de<br />

l’assurance-chômage, y compris le soutien du revenu et les services connexes<br />

qu’il fournit dans ce cadre.<br />

En troisième lieu, en matière de culture, l’accord prévoyait une nouvelle<br />

disposition constitutionnelle reconnaissant la compétence exclusive des<br />

provinces relativement au « domaine de la culture dans la province »; en<br />

réalité, il ne s’agissait que d’une explicitation de la solution jurisprudentielle<br />

en vigueur , qui a été développée par les tribunaux sur la base de l’article 92 de<br />

la Loi constitutionnelle de 1867. Par ailleurs, la responsabilité des autorités<br />

fédérales sur les « affaires culturelles nationales » était également confirmée,<br />

le gouvernement fédéral conservant, là encore, son pouvoir de dépenser et<br />

s’engageant seulement à négocier des ententes visant à assurer aux provinces<br />

la « maîtrise d’oeuvre » de la politique culturelle sur leur territoire. Le même<br />

engagement fédéral de négocier des ententes de coordination et<br />

d’harmonisation s’appliquait aux domaines du développement régional et des<br />

télécommunications.<br />

En matière d’immigration, l’Accord de Charlottetown reprenait la substance<br />

des dispositions de l’Accord du lac Meech, c’est-à-dire que les ententes<br />

conclues dans ce domaine entre le gouvernement fédéral et les provinces<br />

étaient « protégées » constitutionnellement, de façon à ne pouvoir être<br />

modifiés, en principe, que par entente entre les deux parties. En fait, les<br />

autorités fédérales conservaient la possibilité de les modifier unilatéralement<br />

sur certains points en adoptant des normes nationales portant notamment sur<br />

les niveaux généraux d’immigration et les catégories d’immigrants<br />

admissibles.<br />

Enfin, dans tous les autres domaines de compétence provinciale exclusive —<br />

la santé ou l’éducation —, par exemple, le gouvernement fédéral conservait<br />

son pouvoir de dépenser, les provinces se voyant seulement reconnaître,<br />

comme dans l’Accord du lac Meech, le droit de refuser de participer à un<br />

nouveau programme cofinancé que le gouvernement fédéral créerait et<br />

d’obtenir une compensation financière, mais uniquement à condition de mettre<br />

elles-mêmes sur pied un programme « compatible avec les objectifs<br />

nationaux».<br />

En résumé, le principe général qui inspirait les dispositions de l’Accord<br />

relatives à la répartition des pouvoirs semble avoir été que toutes les<br />

compétences provinciales, y compris celles que la <strong>Constitution</strong> attribue aux<br />

provinces de façon « exclusive », sont en réalité perméables à l’intervention<br />

27


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

fédérale par le biais de son pouvoir de dépenser. Lorsque le fédéral acceptait de<br />

limiter ce pouvoir, c’était toujours de façon conditionnelle par des accords<br />

temporaires qu’un nouveau gouvernement, autrement disposé, pourrait<br />

refuser de renouveller.<br />

Parmi les autres dispositions de l’Accord de Charlottetown pertinentes à notre<br />

propos, rappelons celles portant sur les droits des peuples autochtones. On y<br />

consacrait le droit « inhérent » des peuples autochtones à l’autonomie<br />

gouvernementale et la création, à cet effet, d’un troisième ordre de<br />

gouvernement. Pendant une période de cinq ans, les onze gouvernements et les<br />

intéressés auraient tenté de préciser par voie de négociation la teneur de ce<br />

droit, à défaut de quoi celui-ci deviendrait exécutoire et pourrait alors être être<br />

défini par les tribunaux. Outre le fait qu’un tel projet déléguait ainsi un pouvoir<br />

trop considérable aux tribunaux, trois autres aspects ne manquaient pas<br />

d’inquiéter. En premier lieu, il n’était pas clair dans quelle mesure les lois<br />

autochtones devaient être compatibles avec les lois fédérales et provinciales25. Ensuite, l’Accord prévoyait que les autorités autochones pourraient déroger à<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés, ce qui inquiétait vivement les<br />

femmes autochtones, qui avaient peur que l’égalité sexuelle ne soit pas<br />

toujours respectée par les futurs gouvernements autochtones. Enfin, il semble<br />

que l’Accord aurait permis aux gouvernements autochtones de refuser les<br />

droits politiques aux non-autochtones vivant sur leur territoire; il se serait donc<br />

agi de gouvernements fondés au moins en partie sur l’appartenance raciale.<br />

Les causes du rejet de l’Accord de Charlottetown<br />

Comme on vient de le constater, l’Accord de Charlottetown ne répondait<br />

aucunement aux dem<strong>and</strong>es traditionnelles du Québec en matière de répartition<br />

des pouvoirs. Par ailleurs, sur de nombreux autres points, comme par exemple<br />

la réforme du Sénat, la reconnaissance du caractère distinct du Québec, le droit<br />

de veto sur les amendements à la <strong>Constitution</strong>, l’Accord représentait un recul<br />

par rapport Meech. Non seulement, le Québec ne se voyait pas reconnaître les<br />

nouveaux pouvoirs considérés comme nécessaires à son développement, mais<br />

pis encore, il n’obtenait pas même toutes les garanties nécessaires à la<br />

protection efficace de sa position minoritaire dans le cadre des institutions<br />

fédérales. Il n’est donc pas étonnant que l’Accord est été rejeté au Québec par<br />

une majorité de 56,6 p. 100 des électeurs parmi lesquels on trouvait, bien sûr,<br />

les souverainistes, mais également un gr<strong>and</strong> nombre de fédéralistes<br />

insatisfaits.<br />

Par ailleurs, l’Accord de Charlottetown contenait une réforme de la Chambre<br />

haute qui devait fatalement mécontenter les tenants du Sénat « Triple E »,<br />

puisque si le Sénat proposé était « égal » et élu, il était loin d’être aussi efficace<br />

que ces derniers l’auraient voulu. Il n’est donc pas étonnant que l’Accord ait<br />

aussi été rejeté dans les quatre provinces de l’Ouest de façon encore plus<br />

décisive qu’au Québec (par une majorité de 63,1 p. 100 des électeurs). <strong>La</strong><br />

mesure garantissant à perpétuité au Québec 25 p. 100 des sièges de la Chambre<br />

des communes a été particulièrement mal reçue en Colombie-Britannique, qui<br />

aurait ainsi continué à avoir une proportion de sièges moindre que ne le justifie<br />

sa forte croissance démographique. Les trois seules provinces où l’Accord a<br />

été accepté par une nette majorité sont Terre-Neuve, l’Île-du-Prince-Édouard<br />

et le Nouveau-Brunswick. En Nouvelle-Écosse, il a été rejeté par une mince<br />

majorité alors qu’en Ontario, une majorité encore plus réduite l’acceptait (à<br />

l’échelle nationale, l’Accord a été rejeté par 54 p. 100 des électeurs).<br />

28


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

En fait, on peut penser que l’Accord de Charlottetown était en quelque sorte<br />

condamné d’avance, puisqu’il heurtait de front les revendications des deux<br />

principaux « dem<strong>and</strong>eurs » en matière de réforme constitutionnelle : le<br />

Québec, qui n’obtenait pas les pouvoirs qu’il réclame depuis trente ans; les<br />

provinces de l’Ouest, qui se voyaient frustrées d’un véritable Sénat « Triple<br />

E » leur principale revendication depuis le milieu des années soixante-dix.<br />

Même les peuples autochtones ont majoritairement voté contre l’Accord, ce<br />

qui est plus difficile à comprendre étant donné qu’ils avaient réalisé des gains<br />

considérables, encore impensables il y a deux ou trois ans.<br />

Avec le bénéfice du recul, on comprend que pour avoir quelque chance de<br />

succès, les rédacteurs de l’Accord de Charlottetown auraient dû accepter<br />

d’augmenter les pouvoirs du Québec de façon « asymétrique » et donner en<br />

échange satisfaction aux provinces de l’Ouest pour ce qui est du Sénat « Triple<br />

E ». Sans doute, chacun des deux camps aurait-il encore eu des raisons de<br />

s’opposer à l’entente, mais également certains motifs puissants pour<br />

l’appuyer. Bien sûr, pour en arriver là, il aurait fallu accepter d’abord le<br />

principe d’un « statut particulier » pour le Québec, ce que la majorité des<br />

Canadiens anglais ne semble pas encore disposée à faire. Pourtant, il s’agit<br />

probablement de la seule avenue de changement qui reste encore ouverte pour<br />

l’avenir, mis à part l’accession du Québec à la souveraineté.<br />

<strong>La</strong> redéfinition du statut du Québec au sein du régime fédéral canadien : le<br />

fédéralisme « asymétrique » (ou statut particulier)<br />

Au cours des discussions constitutionnelles qui ont eu lieu en 1992, certains<br />

membres de l’intelligentsia et des milieux dirigeants canadiens-anglais ont<br />

présenté l’hypothèse d’un « fédéralisme asymétrique », qui permettrait au<br />

Québec d’exercer certains pouvoirs qui ne seraient pas nécessairement<br />

étendus aux autres provinces. Ce statut particulier devait cependant être<br />

« compensé » par une diminution correspondante de l’influence du Québec au<br />

sein des institutions centrales. Ainsi, les représentants du Québec au sein du<br />

Parlement canadien — députés et sénateurs — ne voteraient plus sur les lois<br />

touchant les domaines où la compétence aurait été transférée aux autorités de<br />

la province26. De même, les ministères correspondants ne devraient plus être<br />

dirigés par des Québécois et, à toute fin pratique, ceux-ci ne pourraient plus<br />

prétendre occuper le poste de Premier ministre fédéral ou celui de chef d’un<br />

parti politique national27. Selon les modalités retenues, pareil régime pourrait constituer soit un marché<br />

de dupes pour le Québec, soit une transformation profonde du système<br />

canadien qui évoluerait ainsi vers une « quasi-confédération » à deux.<br />

Le Québec perdrait évidemment au change si le transfert de pouvoirs en sa<br />

faveur n’était que minime et, par conséquent, insuffisant pour compenser sa<br />

perte d’influence subie au sein des institutions fédérales. Pour être satisfaisant,<br />

le transfert devrait porter sur la majeure partie des pouvoirs que les<br />

gouvernements québécois successifs revendiquent avec constance depuis une<br />

trentaine d’années. <strong>La</strong> liste en est longue28. Par ailleurs, le pouvoir de dépenser<br />

des autorités fédérales devrait être aboli — ou du moins ne s’exercer qu’avec<br />

l’accord du gouvernement québécois — autant dans les nouveaux domaines<br />

transférés au Québec que dans ceux qui sont traditionnellement de sa<br />

compétence exclusive. En effet, si ce pouvoir demeurait intact, le Québec ne<br />

tirerait rien de l’acquisition de nouvelles compétences, puisque le pouvoir de<br />

dépenser permet au fédéral d’obliger les provinces à se plier aux objectifs et<br />

29


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

aux normes qu’il fixe, même dans leurs champs de compétence exclusive. En<br />

outre, le transfert au Québec de nouvelles compétences législatives devrait<br />

s’accompagner du transfert correspondant de ressources financières, sous<br />

forme de ressources fiscales. Par conséquent, les Québécois bénéficieraient<br />

d’une réduction d’impôts fédéraux, ce qui permettrait un supplément de<br />

taxation provinciale correspondant aux services désormais fournis par la<br />

province. Étant donné que le Québec est la deuxième plus importante province<br />

(25 p. 100 de la population canadienne), un tel bouleversement fiscal et<br />

financier exigerait le réaménagement du système de la péréquation. Pour ce<br />

qui est de la réforme du Sénat, l’asymétrie pourrait être poussée jusqu’au point<br />

où celui-ci ne réunirait que les représentants du Canada anglais et, dès lors,<br />

n’interviendrait plus que pour les lois ne s’appliquant uniquement qu’à<br />

l’extérieur du Québec29. En outre, la <strong>Charte</strong> constitutionnelle pourrait être<br />

déclarée inapplicable au Québec et la <strong>Charte</strong> québécoise, en échange, se voir<br />

attribuer un véritable statut constitutionnel en étant « enchâssée » par une<br />

procédure spéciale d’amendement. <strong>La</strong> Cour suprême du Canada pourrait<br />

perdre sa compétence à l’égard des affaires de droit civil québécois, la Cour<br />

d’appel du Québec devenant la juridiction de dernière instance dans ce<br />

domaine : l’on pourrait même créer au sein de la Cour suprême une chambre<br />

spécialisée en matière constitutionnelle dont les membres seraient nommés<br />

conjointement par le gouvernement fédéral et le gouvernement du Québec.<br />

Enfin, la proportion des sièges du Québec à la Chambre des communes devrait<br />

être garantie et le Québec devrait obtenir un droit de veto sur les modifications<br />

constitutionnelles affectant sa place au sein des institutions centrales ainsi que<br />

le droit de recevoir une pleine compensation financière dans tous les cas où il<br />

exercerait son droit de « désaccord » (ou droit de retrait) contre une<br />

modification constitutionnelle transférant une compétence provinciale au<br />

Parlement fédéral30. Si le « fédéralisme asymétrique » respectait ces conditions, il aurait pour effet à<br />

moyen et à long terme d’instaurer entre le Québec et le Canada anglais des<br />

relations de nature quasi confédérale, plutôt que fédérale. Le Parlement et le<br />

gouvernement canadiens pourraient en quelque sorte jouer deux rôles<br />

différents : celui d’institutions fédérales pour le Canada anglais, et celui<br />

d’institutions confédérales pour le nouvel ensemble formé par le Québec et le<br />

Canada. Le Québec et le Canada ne maintiendraient alors que le degré d’union<br />

politique nécessaire pour permettre le fonctionnement de l’union économique<br />

et monétaire et chacun d’eux pourrait poursuivre plus librement ses aspirations<br />

et développer davantage sa propre identité nationale. Il s’agirait en somme<br />

d’une forme de « souveraineté-association » avec la différence qu’elle serait<br />

négociée à partir de l’actuelle situation fédérale plutôt qu’après la séparation<br />

du Québec. C’est précisément pour cette raison qu’il est peu probable que le<br />

Canada anglais accepte cette solution à l’heure actuelle, craignant qu’elle ne<br />

constitue l’« antichambre du séparatisme ».<br />

Cependant, si la menace d’une séparation du Québec redevenait plus réelle, la<br />

solution du fédéralisme asymétrique pourrait gagner des adeptes au Canada<br />

anglais dans la mesure où elle serait alors l’unique solution de rechange à<br />

l’éclatement du Canada. En outre, le Canada anglais pourrait y trouver son<br />

compte en voyant ainsi diminuer l’influence, souvent considérée comme<br />

disproportionnée, du Québec en matière de politique fédérale. En effet, les<br />

Québécois ont tendance à voter massivement pour le même parti aux élections<br />

fédérales et décident donc souvent du résultat. Par conséquent, ils jouent<br />

également un rôle considérable au Cabinet fédéral. Comme on le sait, depuis<br />

30


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

une génération, le Premier ministre fédéral a toujours été un Québécois, sauf<br />

pendant deux brèves périodes de quelques mois. L’influence que le Québec<br />

exerce sur la politique fédérale est ainsi parfois supérieure à son poids<br />

démographique, ce qui provoque des ressentiments au Canada anglais.<br />

L’accession du Québec à la souveraineté — avec ou sans le consentement<br />

du Canada anglais<br />

Si le Québec décidait de devenir souverain, il pourrait en théorie y parvenir en<br />

utilisant la procédure de modification contenue dans la Loi constitutionnelle<br />

de 1982 à condition d’obtenir le consentement des autorités fédérales et d’un<br />

certain nombre d’autres provinces, ce qui semble peu vraisemblable31. Sice<br />

consentement lui était refusé, le Québec devrait alors s’engager dans un<br />

processus de sécession unilatérale. Une telle démarche devrait préalablement<br />

avoir été endossée par une majorité suffisante de la population québécoise, de<br />

préférence à l’occasion d’un référendum. Dans un premier temps, le Canada<br />

anglais refuserait probablement de reconnaître cette sécession illégale.<br />

Cependant, les pays ayant intérêt à la normalisation de la situation, notamment<br />

les États-Unis et la France, feraient presque certainement des pressions pour<br />

qu’Ottawa reconnaisse le nouvel État. À moyen et à long termes, si l’existence<br />

du Québec était reconnue par d’autres États et s’il était admis dans certaines<br />

organisations internationales, le Canada finirait probablement par trouver<br />

opportun de le reconnaître à son tour. À partir de ce moment, les deux<br />

gouvernements pourraient entamer les négociations relatives à la succession<br />

d’État et à toutes les autres questions restées en suspens au moment de la<br />

déclaration unilatérale d’indépendance.<br />

<strong>La</strong> sécession serait considérée comme réussie si, durant un laps de temps<br />

suffisamment long, les autorités québécoises parvenaient à exclure<br />

l’application du droit canadien sur leur territoire et, au contraire, réussissaient<br />

à y faire régner l’ordre juridique découlant de leurs propres lois et décisions. Le<br />

Québec devrait alors être considéré comme un nouvel État souverain.<br />

Si une éventuelle sécession unilatérale échouait, le Québec serait à nouveau<br />

réuni à la fédération canadienne et le problème de son intégrité territoriale se<br />

poserait dans le cadre de la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada. En vertu de celle-ci, le<br />

territoire d’une province ne peut être modifié sans le consentement de ses<br />

autorités législatives32. Si la sécession réussissait et que le Québec devenait un<br />

État souverain, le principe de l’intégrité territoriale des États et de la stabilité<br />

des frontières que pose le droit international (principe de l’uti possidetis juris)<br />

empêcherait les autres États, y compris le Canada, de porter atteinte au<br />

territoire québécois, si bien que les frontières du Québec seraient<br />

officiellement celles qui existaient au moment de son accession à la<br />

souveraineté.<br />

Cependant, une menace sérieuse contre l’intégrité territoriale du Québec<br />

pourrait résulter de l’attitude des peuples autochtones — Inuit et Amérindiens<br />

— qui habitent la partie septentrionale du Québec33. En effet, ces peuples, qui<br />

sont les premiers occupants de ces territoires, pourraient prétendre exercer leur<br />

propre droit à l’autodétermination afin de continuer à faire partie du Canada et<br />

de se séparer du Québec si celui-ci décidait de quitter la fédération canadienne.<br />

Sans doute, le Québec pourrait-il répondre, à juste titre, que certaines<br />

conditions requises pour l’autodétermination des peuples autochtones sur le<br />

plan international ne sont pas réunies, voire même qu’un tel droit n’existe<br />

tout simplement pas34. Il n’en reste pas moins que la cause des autochtones<br />

31


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

leur attirerait beaucoup de sympathie, tant au Canada qu’ailleurs dans le<br />

monde. En outre, les autorités fédérales trouveraient là une bonne raison pour<br />

affirmer le maintien de leur souveraineté sur le Nord québécois, la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> leur attribuant une responsabilité de fiduciaire à l’égard des<br />

peuples autochtones et ceux-ci considérant traditionnellement le<br />

gouvernement fédéral comme leur interlocuteur privilégié35. Comme le<br />

Canada dispose d’une armée, ce qui n’est pas le cas du Québec, le maintien de<br />

la souveraineté canadienne et l’exclusion de la souveraineté québécoise sur les<br />

territoires septentrionaux s’avéreraient aisés sur le plan militaire et, sur le plan<br />

juridique, finiraient par éteindre les droits du Québec par application du<br />

principe de l’effectivité (en vertu duquel l’exercice réel de la souveraineté est<br />

nécessaire pour conserver le titre juridique sur un territoire).<br />

Par conséquent, il apparaît que l’accession pacifique du Québec à la<br />

souveraineté, sans diminution de son assiette territoriale, serait beaucoup plus<br />

facile si elle était précédée d’un accord entre les autorités québécoises, les<br />

autorités fédérales et les peuples autochtones établis au Québec. Pour favoriser<br />

la conclusion d’une pareille entente, le Québec devrait dès maintenant<br />

s’engager à enchâsser dans une future constitution québécoise les droits des<br />

autochtones qui ne pourraient plus ensuite être modifiés qu’avec le<br />

consentement de ces derniers. Ces droit devraient être formulés, à tout le<br />

moins, de la même façon que dans l’actuelle <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne et, de<br />

préférence, plus clairement et plus généreusement en incluant notamment une<br />

certaine autonomie gouvernementale interne. Par ailleurs, les autochtones<br />

québécois craignent sans doute que l’accession du Québec à la souveraineté ne<br />

rende plus difficiles les contacts avec leurs frères et soeurs du Canada. Pour les<br />

rassurer sur ce point, l’accord tripartite entre le Québec, le Canada et les<br />

peuples autochtones pourrait prévoir la liberté de circulation des autochtones<br />

de part et d’autre de la nouvelle frontière. Un tel accord pourrait également<br />

consigner les droits des autochtones à l’égard des deux États signataires et<br />

confier à un organisme mixte canado-québécois le soin d’entendre et de<br />

trancher les litiges futurs pouvant s’élever entre le Québec ou le Canada, d’une<br />

part, et leurs peuples autochtones, d’autre part. Cela permettrait sans doute<br />

d’améliorer les rapports difficiles qui existent actuellement entre ces peuples<br />

et les deux ordres de gouvernement.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Depuis plus de trente ans, tous les gouvernements québécois, de quelque parti<br />

qu’ils soient, ont tenté d’obtenir pour le Québec les nouveaux pouvoirs<br />

considérés comme nécessaires afin de lui permettre de se développer en tant<br />

que société nationale distincte. Non seulement ces revendications n’ont eu<br />

aucun succès, mais elles se sont heurtées à une évolution en sens inverse au<br />

Canada anglais, où l’on privilégie de plus en plus l’augmentation du rôle et des<br />

pouvoirs d’Ottawa. Cet affrontement entre les aspirations du Québec et celles<br />

du reste du Canada s’est soldé, dans la dernière décennie, par une double<br />

défaite pour le Québec. <strong>La</strong> première est survenue en 1982 lorsque la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> a été « rapatriée » et modifiée contre la volonté du gouvernement<br />

de René Lévesque et la seconde, en 1990, avec l’échec de l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech, qui consacrait pourtant une réduction draconienne des dem<strong>and</strong>es<br />

traditionnelles du Québec, réduction à laquelle le gouvernement de M. Robert<br />

Bourassa avait consentie.<br />

Ces échecs répétés expliquent que les Québécois, malgré l’attachement réel<br />

que beaucoup d’entre eux continuent d’éprouver pour le Canada, rejettent<br />

32


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

désormais de façon très majoritaire le statu quo constitutionnel et, a fortiori,la<br />

tendance du Canada anglais vers une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e centralisation. L’opinion<br />

publique québécoise reste cependant hésitante dans la mesure où elle se divise,<br />

dans une proportion variable selon les sondages, entre les partisans d’un<br />

renouvellement du système fédéral et ceux de la souveraineté du Québec36.En outre, la très gr<strong>and</strong>e majorité des « souverainistes » insistait sur le maintien de<br />

l’union économique et monétaire entre le Canada et un futur Québec<br />

indépendant. Il est cependant loin d’être clair quel degré d’union politique doit<br />

être considéré comme nécessaire pour permettre le maintien de l’intégration<br />

économique à son niveau actuel. Ceux qui prônent le statu quo ou le<br />

« fédéralisme renouvelé » estiment que seules des institutions véritablement<br />

fédérales permettraient d’arriver à ce résultat alors que les tenants de la<br />

souveraineté politique du Québec — combinée avec le maintien de<br />

l’association économique avec le Canada — pensent, au contraire, qu’il<br />

suffirait pour y parvenir d’institutions de nature mixte, partiellement fédérales<br />

et partiellement confédérales, comme celles qui caractérisent actuellement la<br />

Communauté économique européenne37. Cette dernière thèse serait<br />

évidemment confirmée si l’on pouvait démontrer que le degré d’intégration<br />

économique qui unit les États de la C.E.E. est comparable à celui qui existe au<br />

Canada. De façon plutôt ironique, c’est précisément ce que prétendent de<br />

nombreux tenants du maintien du système fédéral en voulant ainsi prouver que<br />

la souveraineté du Québec irait contre le « sens de l’histoire ». Comble du<br />

paradoxe, certains promoteurs d’un système fédéral plus centralisé vont<br />

jusqu’à prétendre que l’union économique constituée par la C.E.E. est d’ores<br />

et déjà plus parfaite que celle qui existe entre les provinces canadiennes,<br />

cherchant ainsi à démontrer qu’il est nécessaire d’éliminer les barrières<br />

économiques entre celles-ci en conférant davantage de pouvoirs dans ce<br />

domaine au gouvernement central.<br />

En fait, une comparaison moins polémique entre la situation canadoquébécoise<br />

et celle de l’Europe permet de souligner que les Européens<br />

semblent actuellement tout aussi hésitants à renforcer l’union politique qui<br />

existe déjà entre leurs pays que les Québécois le sont à diminuer les liens qui<br />

les unissent au reste du Canada. C’est que ni les uns ni les autres n’échappent<br />

aux deux gr<strong>and</strong>s courants qui caractérisent l’évolution du monde en cette fin<br />

du XXe siècle, à savoir l’élargissement des espaces économiques, d’une part,<br />

et l’affirmation, ou la réaffirmation, des identités nationales d’autre part38. Ces<br />

deux tendances sont évidemment liées dans la mesure où les menaces<br />

d’homogénéisation qui accompagnent l’unification économique provoquent<br />

en réaction la défense des spécificités nationales menacées. Mais les deux<br />

mouvements sont probablement moins contradictoires qu’il n’y paraît à<br />

première vue. En effet, l’appartenance à un espace économique qui dépasse les<br />

frontières nationales n’est pas incompatible avec le maintien — ou, dans le cas<br />

du Québec, l’élargissement — de la souveraineté politique dans les domaines<br />

où existent des spécificités importantes qui distinguent les communautés<br />

nationales les unes des autres.<br />

On peut donc espérer qu’à plus long terme, la raison prévaudra et que le<br />

Québec et le reste du Canada réussiront à réaménager leurs relations de façon<br />

mutuellement bénéfique et satisfaisante. Le sens démocratique du Canada<br />

anglais devrait faire en sorte que cette transformation se produise de façon<br />

pacifique, le Québec se voyant reconnaître le droit de décider de son avenir<br />

sans être soumis à des menaces de représailles économiques, voire de<br />

diminution de son territoire. Ainsi, c’est aux Québécois eux-mêmes que<br />

33


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

reviendra le dernier mot à condition qu’ils réussissent à faire preuve d’une<br />

volonté inébranlable et clairement exprimée. Après l’échec de l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown, la lassitude de l’opinion à l’égard des questions<br />

constitutionnelles poussera vraisemblablement le Canada anglais à refuser<br />

pendant un temps plus ou moins long toutes nouvelles négociations, ce qui<br />

pourrait avoir pour effet de faire augmenter les appuis à la souveraineté au<br />

Québec. Cependant, comme on l’a mentionné, dans la mesure où de nombreux<br />

Québécois sont encore attachés au système fédéral et où la plupart d’entre eux<br />

insistent sur le maintien de l’espace économique avec le reste du Canada, il est<br />

douteux que l’accession à la souveraineté par le biais d’une séparation pure et<br />

simple, sans union économique et monétaire négociée d’avance, puisse<br />

l’emporter dans un avenir prévisible. <strong>La</strong> véritable échéance sera, semble-t-il,<br />

de nouveau reportée.<br />

Notes<br />

* Une version plus détaillée du présent article a été publiée dans l’ouvrage suivant :«<strong>La</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne et l’évolution des rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais, de<br />

1867 à nos jours », Edmonton, Centre for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies (University of Alberta),<br />

1993. En outre, le présent article reproduit les pages 543 à 553 du texte de l’auteur intitulé<br />

« L’évolution constitutionnelle du Canada et du Québec de 1867 à nos jours » qui a paru dans<br />

Les <strong>Constitution</strong>s du Canada et du Québec, du Régime français à nos jours, Éditions<br />

Thémis, Montréal, 1992. L’auteur remercie les deux éditeurs pour la permission de<br />

reproduire les extraits que reprend le présent article.<br />

1. <strong>La</strong> seule différence tient à ce que les projets de lois de nature financière doivent être d’abord<br />

déposés aux Communes, conformément à l’article 53 de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1867,<br />

L.R.C. (1985), app. II, n o 5, alors que les autres projets peuvent émaner indifféremment de<br />

l’une ou l’autre des deux Chambres. Cependant, avant d’être présenté pour la sanction<br />

royale, un projet de loi sur la finance, comme tout autre projet de loi, doit nécessairement<br />

avoir été adopté dans les mêmes termes par les deux Chambres.<br />

2. <strong>La</strong> répartition actuelle des cent quatre sièges du Sénat est la suivante : Ontario et Québec,<br />

vingt-quatre chacun; Nouveau-Brunswick et Nouvelle-Écosse, dix chacun; Île-du-Prince-<br />

Édouard, quatre; Colombie-Britannique, Alberta, Saskatchewan et Manitoba, six chacun;<br />

Terre-Neuve, six; Yukon et Territoires du Nord-Ouest, un chacun.<br />

3. Pour une étude plus systématique des problèmes soulevés par la réforme du Sénat, voir José<br />

Woehrling, « Les enjeux de la réforme du Sénat canadien », (1992) 23, Revue générale de<br />

droit, 81.<br />

4. Conformément à l’article 6 de la Loi sur la Cour suprême, L.R.C. (1985), c. S-26, au moins<br />

trois des neuf juges sont choisis parmi les juges de la Cour d’appel ou de la Cour supérieure<br />

de la province du Québec ou parmi les avocats de celle-ci; l’Accord du lac Meech prévoyait<br />

également la constitutionnalisation de cette règle.<br />

5. Loi constitutionnelle de 1867, art. 95.<br />

6. Sur le pouvoir de dépenser du gouvernement fédéral, voir Jacques-Yvan Morin et José<br />

Woehrling, Les <strong>Constitution</strong>s du Canada et du Québec. Du Régime français à nos jours,<br />

Montréal, Éditions Thémis, 1992, pp. 360 et suiv.<br />

7. Loi constitutionnelle de 1982, L.R.C. (1985), app. II, n o 44, art. 41(e). <strong>La</strong> procédure de<br />

modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne est prévue aux articles 38 à 49 de la Loi<br />

constitutionnelle de 1982. Dans certains cas, l’accord des dix provinces et du Parlement<br />

fédéral est nécessaire; dans d’autres, celui du Parlement fédéral et de toutes les provinces<br />

intéressées par la modification suffit; enfin, la procédure la plus courante exige l’accord du<br />

Parlement fédéral et d’au moins deux tiers des provinces (c’est-à-dire sept sur dix) dont la<br />

population confondue représente au moins la moitié de la population de toutes les provinces.<br />

Par ailleurs, certaines modifications qui visent la constitution interne d’une province<br />

peuvent être faites par la législature de la province intéressée et d’autres, relatives au<br />

fonctionnement des organes fédéraux, par les deux Chambres du Parlement fédéral. Pour<br />

une analyse systématique du mécanisme de la procédure de modification constitutionnelle,<br />

voir J.-Y. Morin et J. Woehrling, op. cit., note 6, pp. 487 et suiv.<br />

34


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

8. Pour une analyse plus développée de l’incidence de l’Accord du lac Meech sur les droits et<br />

libertés garantis par la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada, voir José Woehrling, « <strong>La</strong> modification<br />

constitutionnelle de 1987, la reconnaissance du Québec comme société distincte et la dualité<br />

linguistique du Canada », (1988) 29, Cahiers de droit, 3; José Woehrling, « <strong>La</strong><br />

reconnaissance du Québec comme société distincte et la dualité linguistique du Canada :<br />

conséquences juridiques et constitutionnelles » dans <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord—L’Accord du<br />

lac Meech, numéro spécial de Canadian Public Policy/Analyse de politiques, septembre<br />

1988, p. 43; José Woehrling, « L’Accord du lac Meech et l’application de la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés », dans Gérald-A. Beaudoin (dir.), Vues canadiennes et<br />

européennes des droits et libertés (Actes des journées strasbourgeoises de l’Institut canadien<br />

d’études juridiques supérieures — 1988), Cowansville, Éditions Y. Blais, 1989, p. 377; José<br />

Woehrling, « A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Distinct Society Clause’s Critics » dans Michael D. Behiels<br />

(dir.), <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer : Conflicting Views of <strong>the</strong> 1987 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord,<br />

Ottawa, University of Ottawa Press, 1989, p. 171; José Woehrling, « Les droits linguistiques<br />

des minorités et le projet de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada (l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech) » dans Paul Pupier et José Woehrling, <strong>La</strong>ngue et droit (Actes du premier congrès de<br />

l’Institut international de droit linguistique comparé), Montréal, Wilson et <strong>La</strong>fleur, 1989, p.<br />

291.<br />

9. En fait, la législature du Nouveau-Brunswick finit par adopter, quelques jours avant la date<br />

limite du 23 juin 1990, la résolution d’agrément nécessaire pour ratifier l’Accord du lac<br />

Meech. Si celui-ci échoua en fin de compte, ce fut donc à cause de l’absence de ratification<br />

par les législatures du Manitoba et de Terre-Neuve. Pour plus de détails sur les péripéties de<br />

l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech, voir J.-Y. Morin et J. Woehrling, op. cit., note 6, pp. 553 et<br />

suiv.; José Woehrling, « L’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech et l’avenir constitutionnel du<br />

Canada » dans Le Canada au seuil du 21ème siècle : réflexions européennes sur l’avenir du<br />

Canada/Canada on <strong>the</strong> Treshold of <strong>the</strong> 21st Century : European Reflexions upon <strong>the</strong> Future<br />

of Canada (Communications présentées à la première conférence paneuropéenne d’études<br />

canadiennes, <strong>La</strong> Haye, Pays-Bas, 24-27 octobre 1991), Amsterdam/Philadelphie, John<br />

Benjamins Publishing Co., 1991, p. 383; José Woehrling, « <strong>La</strong> tentative de modification<br />

constitutionnelle de 1987: la reconnaissance du Québec comme société distincte et la dualité<br />

linguistique du Canada », (1990) 39, Jahrbuch des Öffentliches Rechts, 537.<br />

10. L’article 43 de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 permet de modifier les dispositions de la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> qui n’intéressent qu’une seule province par accord entre les autorités fédérales<br />

et celles de la province intéressée.<br />

11. Ces six provinces sont le Manitoba, la Saskatchewan, le Nouveau-Brunswick, la Nouvelle-<br />

Écosse, l’Île-du-Prince-Édouard et Terre-Neuve. Le Québec bénéficie également des<br />

paiements de péréquation, mais il en est moins dépendant que les six autres provinces.<br />

L’Ontario, l’Alberta et la Colombie-Britannique ont des revenus supérieurs à la moyenne<br />

nationale et ne bénéficient donc pas de la péréquation.<br />

12. Sur les effets potentiellement uniformisateurs de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés,<br />

en particulier les dispositions relatives à l’égalité et à la non-discrimination, voir José<br />

Woehrling, « Le principe d’égalité, le système fédéral canadien et le caractère distinct du<br />

Québec », dans Pierre Patenaude (dir.), Québec—Communauté française de Belgique :<br />

autonomie et spécificité dans le cadre d’un système fédéral (Actes du colloque tenu le 22<br />

mars 1991, Faculté de droit, Université de Sherbrooke), Montréal, Wilson et <strong>La</strong>fleur, 1991,<br />

p. 119. Un certain nombre de constitutionnalistes ont prédit que l’application de la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés entraînera des effets uniformisateurs, principalement sur le<br />

droit d’origine provinciale; voir par exemple, R.R. Knopff et F.L. Morton, « Le<br />

développement national et la <strong>Charte</strong> » dans A. Cairns et C. Williams (dir.), Le<br />

constitutionnalisme, la citoyenneté et la société au Canada (vol. 33 des études comm<strong>and</strong>ées<br />

dans le cadre du progamme de recherche de la Commission royale sur l’union économique et<br />

les perspectives de développement du Canada, Ottawa, Centre d’édition du gouvernement<br />

du Canada, 1986; P.H. Russell, « <strong>The</strong> Political Purposes of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms », (1983) 61, Revue du Barreau canadien 31; A. Cairns, « <strong>The</strong> Politics of<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Conservatism », dans K. Banting et R. Simeon (dir.), And No One Cheered:<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong>, Democracy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, Toronto, Methuen, 1983, p. 28. Les<br />

professeurs Knopff et Morton et le professeur Russell considèrent même que l’objectif caché<br />

du gouvernement fédéral de M. Trudeau en faisant adopter la <strong>Charte</strong>, était précisément de<br />

35


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

provoquer une centralisation indirecte des pouvoirs qui résulterait de l’interprétation<br />

judiciaire : P.H. Russell, loc. cit., 32 et 33; R.R. Knopff et F.L. Morton, op. cit., pp. 153 et<br />

154.<br />

13. Sur les différences d’attitude à l’égard de la <strong>Charte</strong> au Québec et dans le reste du Canada,<br />

voir notamment F.L. Morton, Peter H. Russell et Michael J. Wi<strong>the</strong>y, « <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court’s<br />

First One Hundred <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights Decisions: A Statistical Analysis », (1992) 30,<br />

Osgoode Hall <strong>La</strong>w Journal, 1, 31-33 et 48.<br />

14. On peut également faire remarquer que la « rhétorique » des droits et libertés confère un<br />

caractère absolu et non débattable à des questions qui sont pourtant traditionnellement<br />

considérées comme pouvant faire l’objet de divergences légitimes entre personnes<br />

raisonnables. Ainsi, par exemple, si l’on présente la question de l’ouverture des commerces<br />

le dimanche comme un problème de politique économique et sociale ordinaire, il est évident<br />

qu’aucune solution uniforme ne s’impose d’une province à l’autre étant donné que les<br />

conditions objectives et les mentalités peuvent varier gr<strong>and</strong>ement à propos d’un tel<br />

problème. Si l’on présente la même question comme une affaire de liberté de religion, il<br />

semble nécessaire d’adopter une solution universelle et impérative, car il est difficile<br />

d’admettre que la liberté de religion soit moindre dans certaines provinces que dans d’autres.<br />

Sur la tendance à interpréter les droits de la personne de façon universaliste et, par<br />

conséquent, uniformisatrice, voir, par exemple, J. Donnely, « Cultural Relativism <strong>and</strong><br />

Universal Human Rights », (1984) 6, Human Rights Quarterly 400; A.D. Renteln, « <strong>The</strong><br />

Unanswered Challenge of Relativism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Consequences for Human Rights », (1985),<br />

Human Rights Quarterly, 514; R.R. Knopff et F.L. Morton, op. cit., note 12, pp. 164 et 165;<br />

K.E. Swinton, <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court <strong>and</strong> Canadian <strong>Federalism</strong>: <strong>The</strong> <strong>La</strong>skin-Dickson Years,<br />

Toronto, Carswell, 1990, pp. 338 et suiv.<br />

15. <strong>Charte</strong> des droits et libertés de la personne, L.R.Q. c. C-12.<br />

16. Avant d’être constitutionnalisée, la <strong>Charte</strong> québécoise devrait cependant subir certaines<br />

modifications, notamment pour limiter le pouvoir de l’Assemblée nationale du Québec de<br />

déroger aux droits et libertés. Pour certaines propositions en ce sens, voir José Woehrling,<br />

« <strong>La</strong> protection des droits et libertés et le sort des minorités », dans Alain-G. Gagnon et<br />

François Rocher (dir.), Répliques aux détracteurs de la souveraineté du Québec, Montréal,<br />

VLB éditeur, 1992, p. 131, pp. 156-161.<br />

17. Sur l’évolution des groupes linguistiques, voir Kenneth McRoberts, English Canada <strong>and</strong><br />

Quebec—Avoiding <strong>the</strong> Issue, York University Robarts Centre for Canadian Studies, 1991,<br />

pp. 13-14 et 20-21; Réjean <strong>La</strong>chapelle, « Évolution des groupes linguistiques et situation des<br />

langues officielles au Canada », dans Tendances démolinguistiques et évolution des<br />

institutions canadiennes, (Communications présentées lors d’un colloque tenu à Hull le 10<br />

février 1989), numéro spécial de la collection « Thèmes canadiens » de l’Association<br />

d’études canadiennes, Montréal, 1989, p. 7.<br />

18. On pourrait ajouter que le principe du multiculturalisme qui présuppose une certaine égalité<br />

de toutes les cultures s’oppose également aux notions de « dualité linguistique » et de « deux<br />

peuples fondateurs ».<br />

19. Sur ce point, voir notamment Simon <strong>La</strong>nglois, « Le choc de deux sociétés globales », dans<br />

Louis Balthazar, Guy <strong>La</strong>forest et Vincent Lemieux, Le Québec et la restructuration du<br />

Canada, 1980-1992, Sillery (Québec), Éditions du Septentrion, 1991, p. 95.<br />

20. Rapport de la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, Québec, mars<br />

1991, 180 pages.<br />

21. L.Q. 1991, c. 34.<br />

22. Bâtir ensemble le Canada—Propositions, Ottawa, Approvisionnements et Services Canada,<br />

1991, 60 p. Pour une analyse de ces propositions, voir J.-Y. Morin et J. Woehrling, op. cit,<br />

note 6, pp. 564-571.<br />

23. Un Canada renouvelé, Rapport du Comité mixte spécial du Sénat et de la Chambre des<br />

communes sur le renouvellement du Canada (Coprésidents : Gérald Beaudoin et Dorothy<br />

Dobie), Ottawa, Approvisionnements et Services Canada, 1992. Pour une analyse des<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>ations du comité, voir Peter H. Russell, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Odyssey. Can Canadians<br />

Become a Sovereign People?, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1992, pp. 181-189.<br />

24. En septembre 1992, la Loi sur le processus de détermination de l’avenir politique et<br />

constitutionnel du Québec, précitée, note 21, avait été modifiée pour permettre la tenue d’un<br />

36


<strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle et le réaménagement des<br />

rapports entre le Québec et le Canada anglais<br />

référendum sur l’entente constitutionnelle du 28 août 1992 plutôt que sur l’accession du<br />

Québec à la souveraineté.<br />

25. Il était prévu que les lois autochtones ne pourraient pas être incompatibles « avec les lois<br />

fédérales ou provinciales essentielles au maintien de la paix, de l’ordre et du bon<br />

gouvernement du Canada ». Cette expression n’ayant aucune signification connue dans un<br />

tel contexte, il était impossible de savoir d’avance avec quelles lois fédérales ou provinciales<br />

au juste les lois autochtones devaient être compatibles.<br />

26. Cela impliquerait évidemment de modifier les règles de mise en jeu de la responsabilité<br />

ministérielle.<br />

27. Voir, par exemple Alan C. Cairns, « <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Three Equalities », dans<br />

Ronald L. Watts et Douglas M. Brown, Options for a New Canada, Toronto, University of<br />

Toronto Press, 1991, p. 77; Tom Kent, « Une asymétrie viable et équitable », Le Réseau<br />

(Bulletin du Réseau sur la <strong>Constitution</strong>), vol. 2, n o 3, mars 1992, p. 4; K. McRoberts, op. cit.,<br />

note 17, pp. 44-46.<br />

28. En 1985, le gouvernement du Québec, alors dirigé par le Parti québécois, avait indiqué ses<br />

conditions pour adhérer à la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982. Dans le domaine du<br />

réaménagement des pouvoirs, il voulait avoir la main haute sur tout le secteur de la maind’oeuvre;<br />

exigeait d’être responsable au premier chef de l’orientation générale de son<br />

développement économique, y compris celui de ses régions; réclamait une compétence<br />

prépondérante en matière de sélection et d’établissement des immigrants ainsi qu’un<br />

accroissement important de ses pouvoirs en matière de télécommunications; ne revendiquait<br />

une compétence exclusive en matière de mariage et de divorce et, enfin, que soit reconnue,<br />

en matière internationale, la situation spécifique du Québec en tout ce qui touche à ses<br />

compétences et à son identité, notamment dans le cadre de la Francophonie. Voir Projet<br />

d’accord constitutionnel : propositions du Gouvernement du Québec, mai 1985, pp. 26-30.<br />

29. En fait, on peut se dem<strong>and</strong>er si la réforme du Sénat ne deviendrait pas inutile. En effet, le<br />

retrait des votes des 75 députés québécois à la Chambre des communes sur certaines<br />

questions importantes augmenterait considérablement le poids relatif des députés de<br />

l’Ouest, des provinces de l’Atlantique, du Yukon et des Territoires du Nord-Ouest qui<br />

compteraient alors un total de 121 voix par opposition à l’Ontario qui en aurait 99. Les<br />

régions « périphériques » obtiendraient donc, dans les cas où les députés québécois ne<br />

votent pas, la majorité des voix, ce qui satisferait leur désir d’exercer une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

influence au sein des institutions fédérales. Elles pourraient par conséquent ab<strong>and</strong>onner<br />

leurs exigences en ce qui concerne la réforme du Sénat sur le modèle « Triple E ». Sur cette<br />

question, voir Gordon <strong>La</strong>xer, « Un statut radicalement distinct pour le Québec », Le Devoir,<br />

Montréal, 28 décembre 1991, p. B-12.<br />

30. À l’heure actuelle, l’article 40 de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 ne prévoit de<br />

compensation financière que dans le seul cas où une province exerce son droit de retrait<br />

contre un amendement constitutionnel transférant au Parlement fédéral la compétence<br />

législative provinciale « en matière d’éducation ou dans d’autres domaines culturels ».<br />

31. Aucune disposition de la Partie V de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 ne prévoit<br />

expressément la sécession d’une province. Le pouvoir de modification constitutionnelle de<br />

la législature provinciale ne permet manifestement pas à celle-ci de réaliser la sécession de la<br />

province par simple loi provinciale. L’article 43, qui vise les modifications qui ne<br />

concernent que certaines provinces, ne permettrait pas davantage de réaliser la sécession<br />

d’une province par accord entre les autorités fédérales et celles de la province en cause. En<br />

effet, la sécession d’une province affecterait un gr<strong>and</strong> nombre de dispositions<br />

constitutionnelles qui concernent également d’autres provinces. Enfin, de toute évidence, le<br />

pouvoir de modification constitutionnelle du Parlement fédéral, prévu à l’article 44,<br />

n’autorise pas celui-ci à opérer la sécession d’une province. Par conséquent, seules la<br />

procédure de l’unanimité de l’article 41 et celle de la majorité des deux tiers de l’article 38<br />

restent à envisager. L’une de ces deux modalités doit forcément permettre la sécession d’une<br />

province étant donné que toute la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada peut être modifiée conformément<br />

aux pouvoirs conférés par elle. Pour plus de détails sur cette question, voir José Woehrling,<br />

« Les aspects juridiques de la redéfinition du statut politique et constitutionnel du Québec »<br />

dans Éléments d’analyse institutionnelle, juridique et démolinguistique pertinents à la<br />

révision du statut politique et constitutionnel du Québec, Commission sur l’avenir politique<br />

37


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

et constitutionnel du Québec, Document de travail n o 2, 1991, p. 1, aux pp. 57-58 [texte<br />

également reproduit dans (1991-1992) 7, Revue québécoise de droit international, 12].<br />

32. Loi constitutionnelle de 1871, L.R.C. (1985), app. II, n o 11, art. 3; Loi constitutionnelle de<br />

1982, art. 43.<br />

33. Quelque 60 000 Amérindiens et Inuit, répartis en onze nations, vivent au Québec, dont 18<br />

000 appartenant aux communautés crie et inuit dans la partie septentrionale du territoire<br />

québécois.<br />

34. Les peuples autochtones, qu’ils soient établis dans le Nord québécois ou dans la partie<br />

méridionale du territoire, ne sont pas en nombre suffisant pour remplir les conditions exigées<br />

par le droit international pour l’exercice du droit à l’autodétermination externe. Quant à la<br />

communauté anglophone, concentrée principalement à Montréal, son autodétermination<br />

externe serait impraticable dans la mesure où elle nécessiterait la création d’enclaves au sein<br />

du territoire québécois. Certains vont même plus loin et affirment qu’en vertu du droit<br />

international, les peuples autochtones et les minorités ne disposent jamais, peu important les<br />

circonstances, du droit à l’autodétermination externe; cette thèse est défendue dans un avis<br />

juridique émis par cinq spécialistes de réputation internationale appartenant respectivement<br />

aux universités de New York (New York University), Londres (London School of<br />

Economics), Paris (Institut d’études politiques), Leicester (Gr<strong>and</strong>e-Bretagne) et Bonn<br />

(Allemagne); voir Thomas Franck, Rosalyn Higgins, Alain Pellet, Malcolm N. Shaw et<br />

Christian Tomuschat, « L’intégrité territoriale du Québec dans l’hypothèse de l’accession à<br />

la souveraineté », Assemblée nationale du Québec, Commission d’étude des questions<br />

afférentes à l’accession du Québec à la souveraineté, Exposés et études, volume 1 (« Les<br />

attributs d’un Québec souverain »), 1992, p. 377 aux pp. 430-443.<br />

35. En vertu de l’article 91(24) de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1867, le Parlement fédéral est<br />

exclusivement compétent pour légiférer sur « les Indiens et les terres réservées aux Indiens ».<br />

36. Selon un sondage CROP publié par le journal <strong>La</strong> Presse, le 30 mars 1992, à la question<br />

« Voulez-vous que le Québec devienne un État souverain ? », 42 p. 100 répondaient oui et 39<br />

p. 100 disaient non, 20 p. 100 restant indécis; la marge d’erreur était de 3 p. 100. Par ailleurs,<br />

de nombreux répondants semblent avoir baigné dans la confusion, puisque 55 p. 100 d’entre<br />

eux croyaient qu’un Québec souverain continuerait à faire partie du Canada, 40 p. 100<br />

pensaient qu’advenant la souveraineté du Québec, ils pourraient néanmoins conserver la<br />

nationalité canadienne et 20 p. 100 s’imaginaient qu’ils continueraient d’élire des députés à<br />

la Chambre des communes d’Ottawa; voir Denis Lessard, « Un Québec souverain ferait<br />

toujours partie du Canada », <strong>La</strong> Presse, p. A-12.<br />

37. Une confédération est un groupement d’États habituellement établi par un traité<br />

international où les membres possèdent le droit de sécession et conservent leur souveraineté,<br />

c’est-à-dire participent chacun directement aux relations internationales. Les organes<br />

confédéraux sont composés de représentants des États membres nommés par les<br />

gouvernements de ceux-ci, en nombre généralement égal pour chaque État; ils prennent<br />

normalement les décisions à l’unanimité, chacun des États membres disposant donc d’un<br />

veto. Les décisions confédérales doivent parfois être approuvées par les États membres et<br />

leur exécution relève habituellement de ces derniers étant donné qu’il n’existe ni<br />

administration ni force publique confédérale. Il peut exister des modèles mixtes présentant à<br />

des degrés divers des caractéristiques fédérales et confédérales. <strong>La</strong> Communauté<br />

économique européenne (l’Europe des douze) constitue actuellement un tel système<br />

complexe qui présente certaines caractéristiques fédérales (par exemple, la primauté et<br />

l’applicabilité directe du droit communautaire dans les ordres juridiques des États membres)<br />

et d’autres qui sont plutôt confédérales (par exemple, la règle de l’unanimité pour certaines<br />

décisions du <strong>Conseil</strong> des ministres).<br />

38. Sur le dilemne de l’affirmation et de l’unification, de la diversité et de l’homogénéisation<br />

auquel font actuellement face les pays membres de la Communauté économique<br />

européenne, voir notamment Dominique Schnapper et Henri Mendras (dir.), Six manières<br />

d’être européen, Paris, Éditions Gallimard, 1990.<br />

38


Peter H. Russell<br />

Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in<br />

Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada: <strong>The</strong> Politics of Frustration<br />

Abstract<br />

Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada st<strong>and</strong> out among <strong>the</strong> more settled constitutional<br />

democracies in <strong>the</strong> largely fruitless efforts of <strong>the</strong>ir political elites at gr<strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional restructuring. Both countries may now experience a prolonged<br />

respite from <strong>the</strong>se macro constitutional frustrations—in Australia, through<br />

<strong>La</strong>bour’s ab<strong>and</strong>oning its ideological drive for centralization <strong>and</strong> in Canada,<br />

by <strong>the</strong> realization that cleavages in <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> political community are<br />

too deep to provide <strong>the</strong> basis for a popular consensus on its constitutional<br />

restructuring. Nei<strong>the</strong>r country has found an effective way of combining<br />

constitutional negotiations, which are inescapably elitist, with a democratic<br />

ratifying process. While <strong>the</strong> two countries have influenced each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

constitutional reform efforts have been much more profoundly shaped, in<br />

terms of both ideas <strong>and</strong> economics, by global factors.<br />

Résumé<br />

Parmi les démocraties constitutionnelles les mieux établies, l’Australie et le<br />

Canada remportent la palme pour ce qui est des efforts infructueux de leurs<br />

élites politiques pour réviser de fond en comble leur <strong>Constitution</strong>. Dans<br />

l’immédiat, l’un et l’autre pays vont vraisemblablement s’accorder un sérieux<br />

répit pour oublier leurs frustrations respectives — le Parti travailliste<br />

australien mettra sûrement en veilleuse sa volonté de centralisation, alors que<br />

le Canada devra accepter l’évidence que les clivages politiques sont trop<br />

profonds pour qu’un consensus suffisamment large puisse se faire autour de sa<br />

réforme constitutionnelle. Aucun de ces deux pays n’a trouvé une façon<br />

efficace d’associer les négociations constitutionnelles — élitistes par<br />

définition — à un processus de ratification par le peuple. S’il est vrai que ces<br />

pays se sont mutuellement influencés, ce sont des facteurs globaux de<br />

caractère idéologique et économique qui ont le plus profondément marqué<br />

leurs tentatives de réforme.<br />

Among <strong>the</strong> western constitutional democracies, Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada st<strong>and</strong><br />

out in <strong>the</strong>ir prolonged efforts at macro constitutional change. In both countries,<br />

a good deal of constitutional change has taken place through <strong>the</strong> normal<br />

processes of constitutional development: judicial decisions, informal changes<br />

in <strong>the</strong> exercise of constitutional powers (such as fiscal federalism) <strong>and</strong><br />

piecemeal reform through discrete constitutional amendments. But in both<br />

countries, influential components of <strong>the</strong> political system have been dissatisfied<br />

with <strong>the</strong>se regular forms of constitutional adaptation <strong>and</strong> have pressed for<br />

major constitutional re-structuring. <strong>The</strong>se efforts at what I call “macro<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

constitutional change” have produced very little by way of concrete results.<br />

Hence, I have dubbed <strong>the</strong>m “<strong>the</strong> politics of frustration.” 1<br />

This article is a comparative examination of <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong>se two<br />

kindred federations in <strong>the</strong> frustrating politics of macro constitutional change.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first part will provide accounts of <strong>the</strong> main developments in <strong>the</strong> two<br />

countries’ involvement in constitutional politics, concentrating on <strong>the</strong> most<br />

recent episodes. <strong>The</strong> second part will offer some reflections on what might be<br />

learned from a comparative analysis of <strong>the</strong> two countries’ experience with <strong>the</strong><br />

politics of frustration.<br />

Efforts at Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change<br />

Earlier Efforts<br />

Agitation for large constitutional restructuring by leading politicians in both<br />

federations began fairly soon after <strong>the</strong>ir founding. <strong>The</strong> first major Australian<br />

effort was <strong>the</strong> Peden Royal Commission in 1927 consisting of federal <strong>and</strong> state<br />

parliamentarians along with some prominent citizens <strong>and</strong> constitutional<br />

experts (Russell, 1988). <strong>The</strong> Commission’s report, issued in 1929, found its<br />

members divided four to three on <strong>the</strong> fundamental question of whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Australia should continue as a federation. That was followed by<br />

intergovernmental conferences during <strong>the</strong> depression <strong>and</strong> war years that<br />

endeavoured to negotiate overall changes in <strong>the</strong> structure of <strong>the</strong> federation<br />

(Sawer, 1963). In 1956, <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth Parliament struck a Joint<br />

Committee on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Revision whose final report in 1959 endorsed a<br />

wide-ranging package of constitutional proposals (Australia, Joint<br />

Committee, 1959). From 1973 to 1985, <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Convention laboured away on a total review of all aspects of Australia’s<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Convention was, in effect, a peripatetic constituent<br />

assembly made up of Commonwealth, State <strong>and</strong> municipal politicians. Over<br />

its twelve year lifespan, it met six times — once in each of <strong>the</strong> State capitals. It<br />

had its own secretariat, was assisted by expert committees <strong>and</strong> issued<br />

voluminous reports (Ryan <strong>and</strong> Hewitt, 1977; Russell, 1988).<br />

In Canada, while <strong>the</strong>re were tentative moves in <strong>the</strong> direction of macro<br />

constitutional change in <strong>the</strong> inter-provincial meeting of 1887 <strong>and</strong> again in <strong>the</strong><br />

work of <strong>the</strong> Rowell Sirois Commission at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> 1930s, <strong>the</strong> effort was<br />

not engaged in earnest until <strong>the</strong> 1960s when Quebec’s “quiet revolution”<br />

generated a dem<strong>and</strong> for a fundamental constitutional restructuring (Russell,<br />

1992). <strong>The</strong> first response to Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s was a series of<br />

intergovernmental conferences culminating in 1971 in a package of<br />

constitutional proposals called <strong>the</strong> Victoria <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> 1970s witnessed a<br />

number of efforts at macro constitutional change beginning with a Joint<br />

Committee of <strong>the</strong> federal Parliament (<strong>the</strong> Molgat/ MacGuigan Committee)<br />

that made over one hundred recommendations for constitutional change<br />

(Canada. Joint Committee, 1972). Following <strong>the</strong> election of a separatist<br />

government in Quebec in 1976, <strong>the</strong>re was ano<strong>the</strong>r flurry of attempts at<br />

wholesale constitutional revision, including a Trudeau government proposal<br />

for an entirely new <strong>Constitution</strong>, a Task Force on national unity <strong>and</strong> a series of<br />

First Ministers meetings (Cairns, 1984). <strong>The</strong> attempt to negotiate an<br />

intergovernmental agreement on a large package of constitutional proposals<br />

was resumed after <strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> separatist option in <strong>the</strong> Quebec referendum<br />

of 1980. When that failed, Prime Minister Trudeau launched his own unilateral<br />

initiative to patriate <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> with a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights, an<br />

42


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

effort which, after a negotiated agreement with all of <strong>the</strong> provinces except<br />

Quebec, produced <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982 (Milne, 1982).<br />

<strong>The</strong> one striking feature which <strong>the</strong>se earlier efforts at macro constitutional<br />

change in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada have in common is <strong>the</strong> paucity of concrete<br />

results. On <strong>the</strong> Australian side, only a few scattered constitutional<br />

amendments can be associated with <strong>the</strong> various efforts. One of <strong>the</strong> Joint<br />

Parliamentary Committee’s recommendations—to empower <strong>the</strong><br />

Commonwealth to legislate in relation to aborigines—was approved in a 1967<br />

referendum. Only three of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention’s numerous<br />

resolutions led to actual constitutional amendments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se were all on<br />

relatively minor matters: <strong>the</strong> proposals approved in <strong>the</strong> 1977 referendums on<br />

<strong>the</strong> retirement age of federal judges, territorial voting on referendums <strong>and</strong><br />

filling Senate vacancies. Five o<strong>the</strong>r constitutional proposals were approved in<br />

referendums (<strong>and</strong> thirty rejected) but <strong>the</strong>se changes were not <strong>the</strong> offspring of<br />

gr<strong>and</strong> efforts at constitutional revision (Campbell, 1989). <strong>The</strong> Australian<br />

amending process is indeed quite inhospitable to projects of macro<br />

constitutional change. It is not just that proposals must win <strong>the</strong> approval of a<br />

majority of voters nationally <strong>and</strong> of majorities in a majority (four of six) States.<br />

But constitutional proposals are put to <strong>the</strong> voters one-by-one, so that a<br />

brokered set of proposals built around cross-cutting compromises cannot be<br />

put to <strong>the</strong> people as a package deal.<br />

In Canada, too, <strong>the</strong> efforts at wholesale constitutional revision bore little<br />

tangible fruit. <strong>The</strong> 1940 constitutional amendment transferring jurisdiction<br />

over unemployment insurance did come out of <strong>the</strong> Rowell Sirois Royal<br />

Commission. <strong>The</strong> only o<strong>the</strong>r formal constitutional changes stemming from<br />

macro constitutional politics were those incorporated in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act,<br />

1982. While <strong>the</strong>re can be no doubt about <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

changes effected by this measure— especially <strong>the</strong> adoption of an all-Canadian<br />

amending process, a constitutional charter of rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

recognition of aboriginal rights—<strong>the</strong>y none<strong>the</strong>less fell well short of <strong>the</strong> total<br />

overhaul of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> aimed at by <strong>the</strong> political elites participating in <strong>the</strong><br />

macro projects. Most significantly, <strong>the</strong> 1982 constitutional changes did not<br />

accommodate <strong>the</strong> constitutional aspirations of Quebec that had originally<br />

launched <strong>the</strong> effort at constitutional revision in <strong>the</strong> 1960s (Dufour, 1990).<br />

While <strong>the</strong> impetus for <strong>the</strong>se efforts at macro constitutional change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada came from opposite directions, <strong>the</strong> results were much <strong>the</strong> same:<br />

failure to resolve <strong>the</strong> underlying source of conflict. In Australia <strong>the</strong> major<br />

impetus came from <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>bor Party’s ideological drive against federalism <strong>and</strong><br />

towards centralization, whereas <strong>the</strong> impetus for Canada’s prolonged<br />

indulgence in macro level constitutional politics has been Quebec’s drive for<br />

national status within a looser federation. In both countries, <strong>the</strong> gadflies of<br />

macro constitutional politics, far from realizing <strong>the</strong>ir objectives, aroused<br />

counter movements which deepened <strong>the</strong> constitutional conflict. In Australia’s<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention, <strong>La</strong>bour’s centralism was held in check by political<br />

forces supporting State powers <strong>and</strong> a strong Senate—but produced no<br />

consensus on constitutional change. In Canada, patriation with a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights, though a victory for <strong>the</strong> Canadian nationalist forces resisting Quebec<br />

nationalism, did not slake Quebec’s thirst for more autonomy.<br />

43


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Recent Efforts<br />

Nor did <strong>the</strong> limited results of <strong>the</strong> macro efforts slake <strong>the</strong> thirst of political elites<br />

in ei<strong>the</strong>r country for <strong>the</strong> macro constitutional game. <strong>The</strong> effort continued<br />

through one more big round in Australia <strong>and</strong> two mega rounds in Canada.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se ra<strong>the</strong>r gargantuan efforts in both countries failed to bring about any<br />

constitutional changes. But, in <strong>the</strong>ir different ways, <strong>the</strong>y succeeded in<br />

producing a constitutional truce in <strong>the</strong>ir respective polities <strong>and</strong> at least a<br />

temporary respite from <strong>the</strong> macro constitutional wars. If this period of truce<br />

proves to be more than just a pause for breath, <strong>the</strong> recent rounds of macro<br />

constitutional politics in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada will have been more decisive<br />

than ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir participants or critics appreciated.<br />

Since 1987, Canada has been through two very heavy rounds of constitutional<br />

politics, <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> so-called “Canada round” ending with<br />

<strong>the</strong> referendum on 26 October, 1992. Both, concluding as <strong>the</strong>y did with <strong>the</strong><br />

rejection of large packages of constitutional proposals, were case studies in <strong>the</strong><br />

politics of frustration.<br />

<strong>The</strong> package of proposals constituting <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, while large by<br />

any normal st<strong>and</strong>ard, was relatively small in <strong>the</strong> context of Canadian<br />

constitutional politics. Its limited size, <strong>and</strong> single-purpose shape were indeed<br />

major points of contention. Meech <strong>La</strong>ke’s singular purpose was to secure <strong>the</strong><br />

support of <strong>the</strong> Province of Quebec for <strong>the</strong> changes contained in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982. Hence, it was built around a federalist Quebec<br />

government’s five conditions for accepting <strong>the</strong> 1982 outcome (Monahan,<br />

1991). For Canadians who shared Pierre Trudeau’s constitutional vision, this<br />

agenda was entirely unnecessary, or worse, subversive of what had been<br />

achieved in 1982. For those who were willing to engage in ano<strong>the</strong>r round of<br />

constitutional change, <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke agenda was far too small as it left out<br />

constitutional issues, such as Senate reform <strong>and</strong> aboriginal self-government,<br />

of vital concern to o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong> Canadian community.<br />

If Canada’s constitutional process had remained thoroughly elitist, it is<br />

possible that <strong>the</strong> restricted nature of <strong>the</strong> Meech agenda would not have<br />

mattered. After all, <strong>the</strong> federal government <strong>and</strong> all ten provincial governments<br />

did agree to <strong>the</strong> Accord. But by <strong>the</strong> 1980s, Canada’s constitutional process<br />

could no longer be controlled by its First Ministers. Not only was <strong>the</strong>re now <strong>the</strong><br />

formal requirement of legislative ratification in <strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial<br />

legislatures but, more fundamentally, <strong>the</strong> Meech round demonstrated that a<br />

democratic mutation had taken place in <strong>the</strong> country’s constitutional culture.<br />

This transformation, of which <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights was both a cause <strong>and</strong><br />

effect, had <strong>the</strong> tendency, in Alan Cairns words, to convert a “governments’<br />

constitution” into a “citizens’ constitution” (Cairns, 1991). In negotiating <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord through closed-door meetings, <strong>the</strong>n unveiling it to a<br />

surprised <strong>and</strong> ungrateful public with <strong>the</strong> admonition that <strong>the</strong>ir elected<br />

legislatures could discuss it all <strong>the</strong>y wished so long as <strong>the</strong>y did not change a<br />

word of it, <strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial premiers showed that <strong>the</strong>y had failed to<br />

grasp <strong>the</strong> full importance of <strong>the</strong> change taking place in Canada’s constitutional<br />

culture. Nor did <strong>the</strong>y anticipate how difficult it would be to combine <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional process of executive federalism with <strong>the</strong> new requirement of<br />

legislative ratification. It was <strong>the</strong> Meech process as much as its substance that<br />

accounts for its failure (Simeon, 1990).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> end, even though <strong>the</strong>re was no referendum, public opinion was crucial in<br />

<strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. When time ran out on <strong>the</strong> Accord in <strong>the</strong><br />

44


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

spring of 1990, although it had been ratified in all but two legislatures<br />

(Manitoba <strong>and</strong> Newfoundl<strong>and</strong>), legislators in those two provinces were<br />

fortified in <strong>the</strong>ir resistance by polling data showing that <strong>the</strong> Accord was<br />

opposed by a substantial majority of Canadians outside Quebec (Cohen,<br />

1990). And while <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord may still have been supported by a<br />

majority in Quebec, it was by <strong>the</strong>n a clear second choice to Quebec<br />

sovereignty. <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round ended with <strong>the</strong> Canadian people more<br />

insistent than ever that <strong>the</strong>y must be <strong>the</strong> ultimate constitutional sovereign but<br />

more divided than ever about how <strong>the</strong>ir constitution should be changed<br />

(Russell, 1992, pp. 152-3).<br />

Even if <strong>the</strong> process of ratifying <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord had been completed in<br />

June 1990, ano<strong>the</strong>r round of macro constitutional politics would have<br />

immediately followed. That is because <strong>the</strong> conditions on which <strong>the</strong> hold-out<br />

provinces nearly agreed to ratify Meech—<strong>the</strong> so-called “son-of-Meech”<br />

agreement reached by <strong>the</strong> First Ministers on June 9, 1990—entailed a<br />

commitment to proceed with an extensive list of additional constitutional<br />

reforms including an elected Senate, aboriginal self-government <strong>and</strong> a<br />

comprehensive “Canada clause” expressing <strong>the</strong> defining features of <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian community (Russell, 1992, pp. 150-1). <strong>The</strong> post-Meech round did<br />

not begin with this agenda but with Quebec’s federalist <strong>and</strong> separatist leaders<br />

collaborating in <strong>the</strong> organization of a Quebec “estates general” (<strong>the</strong> Bélanger-<br />

Campeau Commission) to explore Quebec’s constitutional future in <strong>the</strong> wake<br />

of <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada’s rejection of Quebec’s “minimal dem<strong>and</strong>s” (Fidler,<br />

1991). None<strong>the</strong>less, it was clear that if Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada ever<br />

came toge<strong>the</strong>r in this constitutional round it would be through an agenda from<br />

which no serious constitutional aspiration or discontent in <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> could be<br />

excluded.<br />

That was not <strong>the</strong> only legacy of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke. <strong>The</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r was that <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional process in this <strong>the</strong> so-called “Canada round” would have to be<br />

far more participatory than it had ever been in <strong>the</strong> past. And this it surely was,<br />

although not in any measured, disciplined or well-planned manner. Not only<br />

was <strong>the</strong>re <strong>the</strong> two-month referendum campaign on <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord<br />

at <strong>the</strong> end, but also in <strong>the</strong> two years leading up to that Accord, through all kinds<br />

of committees <strong>and</strong> commissions, <strong>the</strong> public was “consulted” on constitutional<br />

questions perhaps more thoroughly <strong>and</strong> exhaustingly than <strong>the</strong> public in any<br />

constitutional democracy has ever been consulted (Russell, 1992).<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canada round process can be likened to a ra<strong>the</strong>r peculiar hour-glass. <strong>The</strong><br />

top part of <strong>the</strong> glass, representing <strong>the</strong> public consultation stage of <strong>the</strong> process<br />

when most of <strong>the</strong> proposals contained in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord were<br />

discussed <strong>and</strong> debated is, fairly wide. When <strong>the</strong>se proposals were h<strong>and</strong>ed over<br />

to political leaders <strong>and</strong> government officials for negotiation <strong>and</strong> refinement,<br />

<strong>the</strong> glass narrows. (Though <strong>the</strong> inclusion of territorial <strong>and</strong> aboriginal leaders<br />

made <strong>the</strong> multilateral negotiations more inclusive than <strong>the</strong>y had been in <strong>the</strong><br />

past.) It comes to its narrowest point in <strong>the</strong> summer of 1992 when <strong>the</strong> final<br />

terms of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord were hammered out in a process dominated<br />

by First Ministers. From that narrow neck, <strong>the</strong> process widened out again in <strong>the</strong><br />

referendum campaign. Indeed, this bottom part of <strong>the</strong> glass, though much<br />

shorter, is considerably wider than <strong>the</strong> upper part.<br />

<strong>The</strong> short, wide bottom <strong>and</strong> tiny neck are not <strong>the</strong> only unusual features of this<br />

hour-glass. A more serious flaw in <strong>the</strong> process is <strong>the</strong> structure of <strong>the</strong> upper-part<br />

of <strong>the</strong> glass: <strong>the</strong> public consultation, negotiation <strong>and</strong> refinement stages. <strong>The</strong><br />

45


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

process represented by this part of <strong>the</strong> glass was, for most of its length, divided<br />

into very nearly water-tight compartments: Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Rest of Canada.<br />

Following Meech, public discussions of constitutional options in <strong>the</strong> two parts<br />

of Canada were disconnected. Not only were <strong>the</strong>y different in time <strong>and</strong> in<br />

forum, but, most significantly, <strong>the</strong>y addressed different questions. In Quebec,<br />

through Bélanger-Campeau <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liberal Party’s Allaire Committee,<br />

consultations that had run <strong>the</strong>ir course by <strong>the</strong> spring of 1991, discussion<br />

focused almost exclusively on <strong>the</strong> question of what Quebec needs to fulfil its<br />

constitutional aspirations. In <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada, through <strong>the</strong> Spicer<br />

Commission (Canada, Citizens’ Forum, 1991) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> various provincial,<br />

territorial <strong>and</strong> parliamentary committees culminating in <strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie<br />

proposals at <strong>the</strong> end of February 1992 (Canada. Special Joint Parliamentary<br />

Committee, 1992), <strong>the</strong> critical question was how to reform <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in<br />

a manner acceptable to all parts of <strong>the</strong> Canadian community.<br />

As <strong>the</strong> process narrowed in <strong>the</strong> negotiating <strong>and</strong> refinement stage, <strong>the</strong> Quebec<br />

section of <strong>the</strong> glass was nearly empty. Only when it reached <strong>the</strong> narrowest<br />

point of <strong>the</strong> neck did Quebec, in <strong>the</strong> person of Premier Bourassa, engage<br />

directly in <strong>the</strong> process. By <strong>the</strong>n Bourassa confronted what was very nearly “a<br />

done deal”—a set of proposals striking a delicate balance among<br />

constitutional interests in <strong>the</strong> Rest of Canada. At this stage ano<strong>the</strong>r deal was<br />

made by literally pulling a rabbit out of a house: a guarantee to Quebec of 25%<br />

of <strong>the</strong> seats in <strong>the</strong> House of Commons in return for Quebec’s acceptance of<br />

provincial equality in an elected Senate. This proposal, though potentially a<br />

very integrative way of accommodating Quebec’s special status in Canada,<br />

was an entirely novel proposal for which <strong>the</strong> public, nei<strong>the</strong>r inside or outside<br />

Quebec, had been prepared. Is it any wonder that this accord of governments<br />

could not, in two months, be converted into an accord of peoples?<br />

<strong>The</strong>re was never much doubt that <strong>the</strong> culmination of this round would be <strong>the</strong><br />

submission of proposals to <strong>the</strong> people in a national referendum. <strong>The</strong> swelling<br />

sentiment of popular sovereignty was fortified by legislation in British<br />

Columbia <strong>and</strong> Alberta requiring referendums before legislative ratification of<br />

any constitutional proposal (Boyer, 1992). As of May 1991, Quebec was<br />

legislatively committed to having a referendum by October 26, 1992 ei<strong>the</strong>r on<br />

Quebec sovereignty or <strong>the</strong> “best offer” forthcoming from <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada.<br />

And yet it was not until June 1992 that <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government brought in<br />

federal legislation to authorize a federal referendum <strong>and</strong> not until <strong>the</strong> final<br />

signing of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown agreement that it signified its intention to submit<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord to <strong>the</strong> people. This late conversion to a referendum meant that <strong>the</strong><br />

politicians, officials <strong>and</strong> experts who were closeted toge<strong>the</strong>r negotiating <strong>the</strong><br />

Accord through <strong>the</strong> spring <strong>and</strong> summer of 1992 were never consciously<br />

working towards a referendum (Johnson, 1993). As a consequence, <strong>the</strong><br />

product of <strong>the</strong>ir labours—an agreement containing some sixty clauses<br />

sprinkled with asterisks marking unfinished business to be settled by more<br />

negotiations in <strong>the</strong> future—was not designed as a document for popular<br />

ratification. In <strong>the</strong> Canada round, elite negotiations <strong>and</strong> popular ratification<br />

came toge<strong>the</strong>r too late <strong>and</strong> too fast to provide <strong>the</strong> foundation for a genuine<br />

social contract.<br />

Though <strong>the</strong> referendum was not legally binding <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal referendum<br />

law did not specify what would constitute a definitive yes or no, <strong>the</strong> results of<br />

<strong>the</strong> October 26 referendum were not difficult to interpret. To <strong>the</strong> question “Do<br />

you agree that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> of Canada should be renewed on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong><br />

agreement reached at Charlottetown on August 28, 1992?” 54% of <strong>the</strong> voters<br />

46


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

answered “no.” Only in Ontario (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re only by a hair), New Brunswick,<br />

Prince Edward Isl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Yukon Territory did <strong>the</strong> “yes” side win<br />

majorities (Russell, 1993). Given that parts of <strong>the</strong> Accord required legislative<br />

ratification by all of <strong>the</strong> provinces <strong>and</strong> most of it by seven, an attempt to<br />

achieve legislative ratification was out of <strong>the</strong> question. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accord was dead.<br />

In rejecting <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord, Canadians demonstrated <strong>the</strong>ir capacity<br />

as a sovereign people to reach a negative result. But when one bears in mind<br />

that <strong>the</strong> primary reason for <strong>the</strong> Accord’s rejection in <strong>the</strong> rest of<br />

Canada—namely that <strong>the</strong> Accord appeared to give Quebec too much—was <strong>the</strong><br />

exact reverse of <strong>the</strong> main reason for <strong>the</strong> Accord’s rejection in<br />

Quebec—namely that <strong>the</strong> Accord did not give Quebec enough—<strong>the</strong>re are no<br />

grounds for believing that <strong>the</strong> basis exists for a positive consensus among <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian people on fundamental changes in <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional arrangements.<br />

That hard thought should cool <strong>the</strong> ardour of most politicians for yet ano<strong>the</strong>r go<br />

at <strong>the</strong> macro constitutional game.<br />

While Canada was swirling through two intense rounds of constitutional<br />

politics, Australians were subjected to one more macro constitutional effort<br />

which was followed by a much more pragmatic <strong>and</strong> reflective treatment of<br />

constitutional matters as <strong>the</strong> federation prepares for <strong>the</strong> completion of its first<br />

century. Just as <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round was generated by dissatisfaction on <strong>the</strong><br />

part of Quebec, Canada’s principal gadfly of constitutional change, with <strong>the</strong><br />

1982 constitutional settlement, Australia’s last macro round was unleashed by<br />

dissatisfaction within <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>La</strong>bour Party, Australia’s main<br />

constitutional gadfly, with <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention.<br />

Australia’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission was a major <strong>and</strong> unsuccessful effort to<br />

generate public interest in comprehensive constitutional reform. <strong>The</strong><br />

Commission was established in 1985 by <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth Government as a<br />

direct reaction to <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>bour Party’s disillusionment with <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Convention. <strong>The</strong> Convention was <strong>the</strong> one Australian effort at macro<br />

constitutional reform that was primarily State-inspired. <strong>The</strong> Commonwealth<br />

government under both Whitlam <strong>and</strong> Hawke participated but failed to<br />

persuade <strong>the</strong> Convention ei<strong>the</strong>r to ab<strong>and</strong>on proposals designed to curb<br />

Canberra’s fiscal domination of <strong>the</strong> Australian federation or to adopt <strong>La</strong>bour’s<br />

centralizing agenda. <strong>La</strong>ck of bi-partisan consensus on major issues prevented<br />

action from being taken on most of <strong>the</strong> Convention’s recommendations.<br />

Immediately following <strong>the</strong> Convention’s 1985 meeting in Brisbane, <strong>the</strong><br />

Commonwealth Attorney General, Lionel Bowen, announced <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>bour<br />

government’s intention to form a “Peoples Convention.” By going over <strong>the</strong><br />

heads of politicians to citizens “with expertise but with no political axe to<br />

grind,” he thought it would be possible to develop a program of “progressive”<br />

constitutional reform (<strong>The</strong> Australian, 30 July, 1985).<br />

From <strong>the</strong> very beginning, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission was flawed by its<br />

partisan rationale <strong>and</strong> sponsorship. By 1985, <strong>La</strong>bour’s interest in<br />

constitutional reform had cooled considerably since <strong>the</strong> 1975 crisis. But those<br />

like Lionel Bowen, who still carried <strong>the</strong> constitutional torch, continued to<br />

assume that if <strong>the</strong> people were adequately exposed to <strong>the</strong> limitations of <strong>the</strong><br />

rickety old <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>the</strong>y would, among o<strong>the</strong>r things, come to appreciate<br />

<strong>the</strong> inefficiencies of federalism, <strong>the</strong> undemocratic nature of a Senate based on<br />

<strong>the</strong> principle of State equality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Governor General’s powers, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

need for a constitutional bill of rights. This was <strong>the</strong> “progressive agenda” of<br />

47


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

constitutional reform which not only was <strong>La</strong>bour’s motive in establishing <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission but also—<strong>and</strong> this is <strong>the</strong> essential point—was seen by its partisan<br />

political opponents as <strong>the</strong> Commission’s primary purpose (Cooray, 1989). <strong>The</strong><br />

Commission’s composition did little to allay <strong>the</strong>se partisan suspicions.<br />

Though its six members included two law professors, a Federal Court judge<br />

<strong>and</strong> a former Liberal State premier, its o<strong>the</strong>r two members were prominent<br />

<strong>La</strong>bourites, former <strong>La</strong>bour Prime Minister Gough Whitlam <strong>and</strong> Sir Maurice<br />

Byers, a former Commonwealth Solicitor General, who chaired <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission.<br />

To give some semblance of reality to <strong>the</strong> notion of a “Peoples Convention,” an<br />

effort was made to broaden <strong>the</strong> Commission’s base by establishing Advisory<br />

Committees on <strong>the</strong> Distribution of Powers, Trade <strong>and</strong> National Economic<br />

Management, Individual <strong>and</strong> Democratic Rights, Executive Government <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Judicial System (Australia. <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission, 1988, Appendices<br />

A <strong>and</strong> B). <strong>The</strong> membership of <strong>the</strong>se committees included academic experts<br />

<strong>and</strong> lawyers, persons from <strong>the</strong> arts, <strong>the</strong> media <strong>and</strong> industry. <strong>The</strong> efforts of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission <strong>and</strong> its Advisory Committees to engage <strong>the</strong> people in <strong>the</strong> process<br />

of constitutional renewal were olympian—even by Canadian st<strong>and</strong>ards.<br />

Hearings were conducted throughout <strong>the</strong> country, issue papers <strong>and</strong> interim<br />

reports widely distributed (on one occasion in comic-book form, Australia.<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission, 1987) <strong>and</strong> several hundred thous<strong>and</strong> copies of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> printed for free distribution. <strong>The</strong> Commission even sponsored<br />

essay-writing contests for school children <strong>and</strong> adults on “What <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> means to us.”<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong>se strenuous public relations efforts, <strong>the</strong> public took very little<br />

interest in <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> Commission. <strong>The</strong> Commission’s survey of public<br />

attitudes to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> gives a good indication of why public interest in<br />

constitutional politics in Australia is not easily aroused: only 53.9% of<br />

Australians knew that Australia has a written <strong>Constitution</strong> (Australia,<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission, 1988, p. 43). In <strong>the</strong> end, when <strong>the</strong> Hawke<br />

government rudely pulled <strong>the</strong> rug out from under its own Commission, no hue<br />

<strong>and</strong> cry could be heard from <strong>the</strong> Australian people.<br />

And jettison <strong>the</strong> Commission’s work is exactly what <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>bour government<br />

did to its <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission. A few days after <strong>the</strong> Commission<br />

released its mammoth two-volume First Report on May 6, 1988, <strong>the</strong><br />

government introduced in <strong>the</strong> House of Representatives proposals for<br />

constitutional referendums on four proposed amendments. It has been<br />

suggested that <strong>the</strong> government’s hasty response to <strong>the</strong> Commission’s report<br />

was prompted by a desire to get <strong>the</strong> constitutional reform initiative out of <strong>the</strong><br />

way before <strong>the</strong> next general election (Sharman, 1989). Whatever <strong>the</strong><br />

explanation of <strong>the</strong> government’s action, it put paid to <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission. By <strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong> Commission’s Final Report was tabled in <strong>the</strong><br />

House of Representatives in October 1988 (Australia. <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Commission, 1988), <strong>the</strong> four proposed amendments associated had been<br />

firmly rejected by <strong>the</strong> people in <strong>the</strong> September referendum rendering <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission’s report, in <strong>the</strong> poignant words of Enid Campbell, one of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission’s hardest working members, “a document of little more than<br />

academic interest” (Campbell, 1989). 2<br />

<strong>The</strong> four proposals put to <strong>the</strong> people in <strong>the</strong> September referendum bore little<br />

relationship to <strong>the</strong> comprehensive program of constitutional reform proposed<br />

by <strong>the</strong> Commission. Three of <strong>the</strong> proposals were based on <strong>the</strong> more populist<br />

48


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

items among <strong>the</strong> Commission’s recommendations. One of <strong>the</strong>se would simply<br />

have given constitutional recognition to <strong>the</strong> existence of local government. A<br />

second was designed to overcome maldistribution in federal, State <strong>and</strong><br />

Territorial elections, while <strong>the</strong> third, ra<strong>the</strong>r than putting forward <strong>the</strong> full charter<br />

of rights proposed by <strong>the</strong> Commission, simply proposed that <strong>the</strong> three basic<br />

rights which are already in <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong> but apply only to <strong>the</strong><br />

Commonwealth—namely freedom of religion, trial by jury <strong>and</strong> “just terms” in<br />

expropriating property —become limits on State <strong>and</strong> Territorial governments.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fourth proposal, to increase <strong>the</strong> maximum term of <strong>the</strong> House of<br />

Representatives from three to four years <strong>and</strong> reduce Senators’ terms from six<br />

to four years, was a vintage piece of <strong>La</strong>bour constitutionalism similar to<br />

proposals for simultaneous elections rejected in referendums in 1974, 1977<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1988.<br />

<strong>The</strong> opposition parties attacked all four constitutional proposals just as<br />

vigorously as <strong>the</strong>y had attacked <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission throughout its<br />

existence. Although early polls showed majority support for <strong>the</strong> proposals,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were soundly rejected in <strong>the</strong> September referendum. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> four<br />

proposed amendments “suffered <strong>the</strong> worst defeat of any slate of referendum<br />

proposals ever put to <strong>the</strong> Australian people” (Galligan, 1989, p. 119). None of<br />

<strong>the</strong> four proposals was able to win an overall majority or a majority in any of<br />

<strong>the</strong> States. Thus, in abject failure, ended Australia’s latest fling at macro<br />

constitutional change.<br />

<strong>The</strong> death of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission in 1988 has not been followed by<br />

anything that could be considered ano<strong>the</strong>r effort at macro constitutional<br />

change. It is not so much that Australians are suffering from what Canadians<br />

call constitutional fatigue, but that <strong>the</strong>ir political elites have learned two things<br />

about constitutional politics: first, that constitutional restructuring cannot be<br />

achieved as a partisan political project, <strong>and</strong> second, that constitutional reform<br />

is not a necessary condition for making <strong>the</strong> federation operate more efficiently.<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al politics are proceeding accordingly, <strong>and</strong> quietly, along two<br />

tracks.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first track is linked to <strong>the</strong> completion of Australia’s first century, <strong>and</strong> is<br />

fundamentally educational <strong>and</strong> non-partisan in character. <strong>The</strong> key event in<br />

inaugurating activity along this track was a Conference held at Sydney in April<br />

1991 to celebrate ano<strong>the</strong>r centenary (Australians are very keen on centennial<br />

celebrations): <strong>the</strong> constitutional convention held in Sydney in 1891 which<br />

drafted much of what was to become <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong>. <strong>The</strong> 1991<br />

assembly was a considerably more representative body than its 1891<br />

predecessor. <strong>The</strong> 89 persons who attended came from all parts of Australia <strong>and</strong><br />

New Zeal<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> besides academics, lawyers, judges, bureaucrats, business<br />

<strong>and</strong> labour leaders, included women, aborigines <strong>and</strong> school children<br />

(Solomon, 1991). Prime Minister Hawke, <strong>the</strong> Opposition leaders <strong>and</strong> State<br />

Premiers did not join <strong>the</strong> Conference until its fourth <strong>and</strong> final day.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Sydney conference did not attempt to draft constitutional proposals.<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong>re was no consensus among its participants that constitutional<br />

reform was necessary. Instead, it identified a dozen issues “to be pursued over<br />

<strong>the</strong> course of this constitutional decade” (Australia, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary,<br />

April 1992, p. 7). This cluster of issues marked a distinct shift from <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional, constitutional, Australian agenda <strong>and</strong> a considerable convergence<br />

with constitutional concerns in o<strong>the</strong>r industrial democracies. In reforming<br />

federalism, <strong>the</strong> emphasis shifted from <strong>La</strong>bour’s interest in reducing <strong>the</strong> powers<br />

49


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> States to <strong>the</strong> broader <strong>the</strong>mes of accountability <strong>and</strong><br />

globalization. <strong>The</strong>re was “broad agreement” to reduce <strong>the</strong> vertical, fiscal<br />

imbalance in Australian federalism that separates responsibility for delivering<br />

programs from raising revenues to pay for <strong>the</strong>m. Globalization was evident in<br />

<strong>the</strong> commitment not only to streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> economic union within Australia<br />

but to explore “<strong>the</strong> constitutional implications of closer economic relations<br />

with New Zeal<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r countries.” Concern was expressed about<br />

reducing executive domination of parliament, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re was a hint of growing<br />

republicanism in <strong>the</strong> desire to review <strong>the</strong> powers <strong>and</strong> selection of <strong>the</strong> Head of<br />

State. Individual <strong>and</strong> group rights were also a major concern with<br />

commitments to move towards a “guarantee of basic rights” through a process<br />

of public education <strong>and</strong> discussion <strong>and</strong> to achieve a “reconciliation between<br />

<strong>the</strong> aboriginals <strong>and</strong> Torres Strait Isl<strong>and</strong>er peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> wider Australian<br />

community” (<strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary, April 1992, p. 8).<br />

<strong>The</strong> process for working on this agenda was decidedly low key <strong>and</strong> laid-back.<br />

Through <strong>the</strong> 1990s, Australians would consider constitutional changes that<br />

would prepare <strong>the</strong>ir country for its second century. To facilitate this<br />

constitutional review, <strong>the</strong>re would be a series of centenaries commemorating<br />

various stage in <strong>the</strong> 1890s federating process. 3 To steer this process along, a<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary Foundation was established. It is headed by former<br />

High Court judge <strong>and</strong> Governor General, Sir Ninian Stephen. <strong>The</strong> Foundation<br />

works in association with <strong>the</strong> Centre for Comparative <strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies<br />

recently established at <strong>the</strong> University of Melbourne under <strong>the</strong> leadership of <strong>the</strong><br />

Foundation’s Deputy Chair, Professor Cheryl Saunders. To ensure <strong>the</strong><br />

Foundation’s independence, its funding is to come from both levels of<br />

government, <strong>the</strong> private sector <strong>and</strong> individuals.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second track was opened up by Prime Minister Hawke’s “New<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong>” speech at <strong>the</strong> National Press Club in Canberra in July 1990, <strong>and</strong><br />

represents a return to a process of constitutional adaptation which a generation<br />

of constitutional reformers in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada have tended to spurn. <strong>The</strong><br />

objective of Hawke’s “New <strong>Federalism</strong>” was entirely functional: “to improve<br />

our national efficiency <strong>and</strong> international competitiveness.” <strong>The</strong> first task in<br />

achieving this reform was not constitutional reform but moving “by sensible,<br />

practicable steps to get better co-operation within <strong>the</strong> framework of <strong>the</strong> Federal<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> as it st<strong>and</strong>s” (Hawke, 1990, pp. 1 <strong>and</strong> 19). Hawke emphasized <strong>the</strong><br />

need for harmonizing state regulatory st<strong>and</strong>ards. Noting that by 1992 <strong>the</strong>re<br />

would be fewer impediments to <strong>the</strong> free flow of commerce among <strong>the</strong> twelve<br />

sovereign nations of <strong>the</strong> European Community than among <strong>the</strong> States of<br />

Australia, he called for a streng<strong>the</strong>ning of Australia’s economic union. While<br />

improvement at <strong>the</strong> micro-economic level was to be achieved through<br />

Commonwealth-State co-operation, at <strong>the</strong> macro-economic level—here his<br />

traditional <strong>La</strong>bor centralism showed through—“Australia must have one<br />

central level of effective economic management” (Hawke, 1990, p. 5). Even<br />

though much of <strong>the</strong> New <strong>Federalism</strong> could be accomplished through intergovernmental<br />

co-operation, Hawke still clung to <strong>the</strong> belief that, eventually,<br />

some formal constitutional change would be required. But constitutional<br />

reform would not be pushed by his government for he had come to <strong>the</strong><br />

conclusion, long obvious to most observers of Australia’s constitutional<br />

politics, “that it is almost impossible to amend our <strong>Constitution</strong> in an<br />

atmosphere of partisan controversy” (Hawke, 1990, p. 11).<br />

<strong>The</strong> process for working at <strong>the</strong> new federalism employed an instrument well<br />

known to Canadians: First Ministers’ meetings. At <strong>the</strong> first two Special<br />

50


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

Premiers’ meetings (October 1990 in Brisbane <strong>and</strong> July 1991 in Sydney),<br />

progress was made across a broad front in moving towards a more harmonious<br />

<strong>and</strong> efficient federal partnership (Intergovernmental News, November 1990,<br />

August 1991). This progress included agreements on mutual recognition of<br />

regulatory st<strong>and</strong>ards, an intergovernmental agreement on <strong>the</strong> environment,<br />

<strong>and</strong> agreements to establish a national rail corporation <strong>and</strong> a national electric<br />

grid.<br />

This happy interlude of co-operative federalism was soon overtaken by <strong>the</strong><br />

storm clouds of fiscal federalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>La</strong>bour Party politics. When Prime<br />

Minister Hawke indicated that at <strong>the</strong> next Special Premiers’ Conference<br />

scheduled for November 1991, he would be willing to discuss a proposal of <strong>the</strong><br />

State Premiers’ that <strong>the</strong>y should have a guaranteed share of <strong>the</strong> personal<br />

income tax field (6% of taxable income), Hawke’s leadership rival moved<br />

against him. Before <strong>the</strong> November conference could take place, Paul Keating,<br />

responding to <strong>La</strong>bour’s traditional centralism, took <strong>the</strong> stage at Canberra’s<br />

National Press Club to denounce Hawke’s sell-out to <strong>the</strong> States. Reducing <strong>the</strong><br />

States’ fiscal dependence on Canberra by guaranteeing <strong>the</strong>m tax-room, in<br />

Keating’s view, was pushing cooperative federalism over <strong>the</strong> line which “<strong>the</strong><br />

Federal <strong>La</strong>bour Government will not cross” (Keating, 1991, p. 1). Although<br />

denying that he was “an evangelical centralist,” Keating said he could not<br />

accept “<strong>the</strong> dismembering of <strong>the</strong> national government which would inevitably<br />

follow from surrendering revenues <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r national responsibilities to <strong>the</strong><br />

States” (Keating, 1991, p. 19). In words which have a familiar ring to Canadian<br />

ears, Keating also attacked <strong>the</strong> process of executive federalism. <strong>The</strong><br />

willingness to discuss major changes in <strong>the</strong> federation “behind <strong>the</strong> closed<br />

doors of Commonwealth-State committees” was a sorry contrast with <strong>the</strong><br />

open ways of Australia’s founders (Keating, 1991, p. 6).<br />

Hawke got <strong>the</strong> message. He was unwilling to put his shaky hold on <strong>the</strong><br />

leadership fur<strong>the</strong>r at risk <strong>and</strong> so pulled out of <strong>the</strong> November Conference. <strong>The</strong><br />

State Premiers <strong>and</strong> Territorial Chief Ministers met anyway—at Adelaide<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than Perth. <strong>The</strong> twenty-three page communique issued at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

meeting outlines an ambitious program of cooperative federalism including<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of a Council of <strong>the</strong> Federation, constituted by First<br />

Ministers, to foster <strong>and</strong> direct intergovernmental cooperation (Australia,<br />

Premiers’ <strong>and</strong> Chief Ministers’ Communique, November 1991, pp. 14-15).<br />

But <strong>the</strong> Premiers recognized that little progress could be made without <strong>the</strong><br />

participation of <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth government. That participation, it soon<br />

became clear, might not be forthcoming for quite some time. On December 19,<br />

1991, <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>bour caucus in Canberra “rolled” Bob Hawke <strong>and</strong> installed Paul<br />

Keating as Prime Minister. Keating consolidated his hold on power by leading<br />

his party to victory in <strong>the</strong> general election of March, 1993.<br />

Despite Keating’s ascendency <strong>and</strong> his centralism, <strong>the</strong> “New <strong>Federalism</strong>” is not<br />

dead in Australia. Under Keating, <strong>the</strong>re will be no marked diminution of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commonwealth government’s fiscal hegemony in <strong>the</strong> Australian federation.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>re is too much at stake in terms of global competition for Australia to<br />

ab<strong>and</strong>on its efforts at removing unnecessary federal impediments to <strong>the</strong><br />

efficient functioning of its internal, political economy. <strong>The</strong> Council of<br />

Australian Governments called for by <strong>the</strong> Premiers has survived its first<br />

meeting, a meeting in which Mr. Keating’s government participated<br />

(Intergovernmental News, December 1992). Introducing a special 1992 issue<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Australian Journal of Political Science, devoted to <strong>the</strong> new federalism,<br />

Brian Galligan writes that “Although <strong>the</strong>re remain some pressures for, <strong>and</strong><br />

51


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

advocates of greater centralization, <strong>the</strong> future is more likely to be with greater<br />

diversity <strong>and</strong> complexity coupled with co-operative arrangements for<br />

harmonization” (Galligan, 1992, p. 6).<br />

Meantime, on <strong>the</strong> constitutional reform track, <strong>the</strong>re has been some movement<br />

though <strong>the</strong> pace is far from feverish. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary Foundation<br />

has established its headquarters in Melbourne where its official launch took<br />

place on April 14, 1992. Its approach at this stage is largely educational.<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Foundation has responded to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission’s<br />

findings on Australians’ ignorance of <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>Constitution</strong> by making public<br />

education on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> one of its four priorities. <strong>The</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r priorities are<br />

parliamentary reform, <strong>the</strong> economic union <strong>and</strong> aboriginal peoples. 4 If <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

to be ano<strong>the</strong>r effort at macro constitutional change in Australia to mark <strong>the</strong><br />

country’s centenary, it will be attempted in a manner which is more organic,<br />

community-based <strong>and</strong> with much broader political support than previous<br />

efforts.<br />

Points of Comparison<br />

<strong>The</strong> Need for Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform<br />

In my study of constitutional politics, I have drawn a distinction between<br />

ordinary, piecemeal constitutional change <strong>and</strong> efforts to accomplish much<br />

larger projects of constitutional renewal (Russell, 1992, pp. 75-6). <strong>The</strong>se<br />

larger efforts at constitutional change I have termed macro or mega<br />

constitutional politics. Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada st<strong>and</strong> out among <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional democracies in <strong>the</strong> sustained attention <strong>the</strong>ir political elites have<br />

given such efforts over <strong>the</strong> last generation or so <strong>and</strong>, as <strong>the</strong> first part of this<br />

paper has shown, in <strong>the</strong> low level of positive achievement <strong>the</strong>se efforts have<br />

yielded. <strong>Constitution</strong>al politics in <strong>the</strong> two countries since 1987 indicate that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is much less need for Australia, than <strong>the</strong>re is for Canada, to indulge in<br />

macro constitutional politics. Indeed, an unkind observer might conclude that,<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Australian case, <strong>the</strong> politics of frustration has been basically a selfinflicted<br />

misery—inflicted, that is, by part of <strong>the</strong> country’s political leadership<br />

on itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> very ease with which Australia moved away from macro constitutional<br />

politics just as Canada was engaging in yet ano<strong>the</strong>r intense round supports this<br />

conclusion. One can point to periods in Canada’s recent history, too, —1971 to<br />

1976 <strong>and</strong> 1982 to 1987—when <strong>the</strong> constitutional debate simmered down for a<br />

while. But even during <strong>the</strong>se periods, forces were at work within <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

political community: <strong>the</strong> growth of a democratic Quebec separatist party, <strong>the</strong><br />

decolonization of aboriginal peoples, <strong>the</strong> development of western alienation<br />

<strong>and</strong> a growing sense of Canadian nationalism in English-speaking Canada—<br />

which would force <strong>the</strong> constitutional issue to resurface at <strong>the</strong> macro level.<br />

Indeed, I have used <strong>the</strong> term “mega constitutional politics” to capture <strong>the</strong> depth<br />

of <strong>the</strong> crisis generated by <strong>the</strong> conflicting constitutional aspirations <strong>and</strong><br />

grievances fuelling Canada’s constitutional debate (Russell, 1993). <strong>The</strong><br />

Canadian constitutional debate is fundamentally about <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

political community on which <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> is to be based. However much<br />

Canadians may weary of this debate, <strong>the</strong>y have been kept engaged in it because<br />

its terms—its contending definitions of <strong>the</strong> nation—touch <strong>the</strong>ir sense of<br />

personal identity <strong>and</strong> self-worth, <strong>and</strong> entail competing principles of political<br />

justice.<br />

52


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

In Australia, <strong>the</strong> efforts of <strong>the</strong> would-be constitutional reformers have been<br />

macro in that <strong>the</strong>y have aspired to much more than piecemeal change but not<br />

mega in that <strong>the</strong>y have not deeply engaged <strong>the</strong> people. If <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>La</strong>bour<br />

Party had continued to adhere to a socialist ideology requiring Australia’s<br />

transformation from a federal to a unitary state, <strong>the</strong> debate might well have<br />

approached <strong>the</strong> mega level. But even in Gough Whitlam’s era, <strong>La</strong>bour was<br />

making its peace with federalism. <strong>The</strong> High Court’s centralism has helped in<br />

this process (Mason, 1988). Prime Minister Hawke acknowledged this in his<br />

speech inaugurating <strong>the</strong> New <strong>Federalism</strong> when he noted that “High Court<br />

decisions have done more to alter <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> than all <strong>the</strong> referendums”<br />

(Hawke, 1990, p. 15). By <strong>the</strong> 1980s, while <strong>La</strong>bour leaders still harboured<br />

constitutional reform sentiments, <strong>the</strong>y could not <strong>and</strong> did not claim that<br />

constitutional change was needed to achieve <strong>the</strong>ir policy objectives (Galligan,<br />

1989). No doubt <strong>the</strong>re are constitutional changes which both State <strong>and</strong><br />

Commonwealth leaders would welcome, but <strong>the</strong> impressive reform agenda<br />

produced by <strong>the</strong> November 1991 Premiers’ Conference demonstrates how<br />

much could be done to operate Australian federalism more efficiently (if not<br />

more accountably) without formal constitutional change.<br />

I am not suggesting ei<strong>the</strong>r that Australia will or should forsake formal<br />

constitutional change in <strong>the</strong> foreseeable future. <strong>The</strong>re are a number of reforms<br />

whose time may soon come. As in Canada, <strong>the</strong> gravest issue of constitutional<br />

injustice in Australia is <strong>the</strong> subjugation of its indigenous peoples. Though<br />

aborigines have not advanced nearly as far as Canada’s aboriginal peoples in<br />

asserting <strong>the</strong>ir right to be governed through constitutional arrangements to<br />

which <strong>the</strong>y have consented, <strong>the</strong>re are signs of progress in that direction. In <strong>the</strong><br />

courts, at long last, Australian judges are recognizing <strong>the</strong> existence of<br />

aboriginal rights (Brennan <strong>and</strong> Crawford, 1990, Brennan, 1992), <strong>and</strong>, at <strong>the</strong><br />

political level, <strong>the</strong> establishment of a broad-based Council for Aboriginal<br />

Reconciliation in December 1991 may lead to a formal reconciliation<br />

treaty—a social contract—between aboriginal <strong>and</strong> non-aboriginal Australians<br />

(Easterbrook, 1991). <strong>The</strong>re are also signs that <strong>the</strong> Australian republican<br />

movement is livelier now than even at <strong>the</strong> height of resentment over <strong>the</strong><br />

Governor General’s sacking of Whitlam in 1975. A resolution passed at <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>La</strong>bour Party’s annual conference in 1991, committing <strong>the</strong> Party to a ten-year<br />

campaign to make Australia a Republic (Sidney Morning Herald, 26 June,<br />

1991), was followed by <strong>the</strong> founding of a new Australian Republican<br />

Movement chaired by well-known author, Tom Keneally (Sidney Morning<br />

Herald, 7 July, 1991). Paul Keating seems determined to build a republican<br />

consensus by making it a rallying point for Australian nationalism. An even<br />

stronger consensus is building for a constitutional bill of rights. It would be a<br />

mistake to interpret <strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> rights proposals in <strong>the</strong> 1988 referendum<br />

as a rejection of <strong>the</strong> idea of a full bill of rights (Galligan, Knopff <strong>and</strong> Ure,<br />

1990). That proposal’s failure probably has more to do with its partisan<br />

sponsorship <strong>and</strong> Catholic fear of <strong>the</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong> freedom of religion<br />

guarantee for state-supported religious schools than with <strong>the</strong> unpopularity of<br />

entrenching fundamental rights. A recent, in-depth study of Australian<br />

attitudes to civil liberties indicates that <strong>the</strong> level of support for a constitutional<br />

bill of rights is at 70%. 5<br />

Any of <strong>the</strong>se possible constitutional changes—<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs might be<br />

accomplished each in its own time. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, Australia’s<br />

constitutional reformers might, once again, be inclined to attempt macro<br />

constitutional reform <strong>and</strong> celebrate <strong>the</strong> country’s centennial by presenting a<br />

53


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

package of proposals to <strong>the</strong> people at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> decade. If that occurs <strong>and</strong> is<br />

successful, it will not be an example of <strong>the</strong> Banting <strong>and</strong> Simeon <strong>the</strong>ory that<br />

“[l]ack of consensus makes constitutional change necessary. <strong>The</strong> same lack<br />

makes resolution supremely difficult” (Banting <strong>and</strong> Simeon, 1984, p. 25). On<br />

<strong>the</strong> contrary, it would be a constitutional restructuring introduced not to<br />

resolve a deep cleavage in <strong>the</strong> body politic but to mark a new, non-partisan<br />

consensus on <strong>the</strong> conditions of nationhood for Australia’s second century.<br />

Canada has <strong>the</strong> dubious honour of remaining a clear example of a nation-state<br />

driven to constitutional politics at <strong>the</strong> mega level by deep dissensus. This<br />

dissensus is as much <strong>the</strong> effect as <strong>the</strong> cause of constitutional politics. It is<br />

possible that had <strong>the</strong> federal political leaders in <strong>the</strong> 1984 election not<br />

committed <strong>the</strong>mselves to constitutional changes sufficient to overcome<br />

Quebec’s repudiation of <strong>the</strong> 1982 changes, <strong>and</strong> had Robert Bourassa’s Quebec<br />

Liberal Party been able to win power without committing itself to obtaining<br />

such changes, Quebec nationalism might have lost its momentum as a serious<br />

political force, thus removing any “necessity” to continue <strong>the</strong> macro<br />

constitutional effort. We can only speculate about such historical “might have<br />

beens.” However, we do know that <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round deepened <strong>the</strong><br />

cleavages within <strong>the</strong> Canadian political community <strong>and</strong> made a fur<strong>the</strong>r round<br />

inevitable.<br />

It is too early to tell whe<strong>the</strong>r this round has produced some finality—even a<br />

decade or two—to Canada’s constitutional travails. What is clear is that <strong>the</strong><br />

present generation of Canadians will not try again to reach an accord on a broad<br />

package of constitutional changes designed to prevent a national unity crisis.<br />

Such was <strong>the</strong> effort <strong>and</strong> agony of <strong>the</strong> Canada round, that most of Canada’s<br />

politicians <strong>and</strong> most of its people have no stomach for resuming <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional struggle. If, in <strong>the</strong> near future, Canada plunges back into <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional maelstrom, it will be because <strong>the</strong>re is an actual not just an<br />

apprehended national unity crisis. Such a crisis will occur if <strong>the</strong> next Quebec<br />

election (which is due by 1994) produces a government committed to<br />

Quebec’s sovereignty <strong>and</strong> if that government wins a subsequent referendum<br />

on Quebec’s independence.<br />

In Canada, as in Australia, ab<strong>and</strong>oning efforts at macro constitutional change<br />

need not mean a constitutional deep freeze. If <strong>the</strong> Quebec majority does not<br />

push for a radical constitutional restructuring, it is just possible that Canadians<br />

might recover <strong>the</strong>ir capacity for incremental constitutional change <strong>and</strong><br />

adaptation. Such a reversion to ordinary, low key constitutional politics would<br />

require nothing less than <strong>the</strong> political class adopting what Stephen Holmes<br />

calls “gag rules” on <strong>the</strong> big mega questions of national identity <strong>and</strong> political<br />

justice (Holmes, 1988). <strong>The</strong> November 1982 referendum in <strong>the</strong> Eastern Arctic,<br />

paving <strong>the</strong> way for <strong>the</strong> self-governing, largely Inuit, region of Nunavut<br />

(Financial Post, November 17, 1992) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> quiet passage in early 1993 of a<br />

constitutional amendment recognizing New Brunswick’s dualistic nature<br />

(Canada, House of Commons Debates, 1993) provide some early indication<br />

that constitutional change, retail ra<strong>the</strong>r than wholesale, is not impossible in<br />

Canada.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Process of Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Politics<br />

In both Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada, <strong>the</strong> final stage of <strong>the</strong> constitutional amendment<br />

process requires a form of democratic ratification: in Australia direct<br />

democracy through referendums; in Canada, since patriation, indirect<br />

54


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

democracy through legislative approval. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, in Canada, <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord precedent makes it politically imperative to have a<br />

referendum before legislative ratification of major constitutional changes<br />

(Boyer, 1992, p. 236). Both countries require extraordinary majorities for<br />

ratification: in Australia, two-thirds of <strong>the</strong> States <strong>and</strong> in Canada, two-thirds or,<br />

in some cases, all of <strong>the</strong> provinces. 6 Requiring extraordinary majorities for<br />

formal constitutional change is normal for democracies practising<br />

constitutionalism. For <strong>the</strong> very essence of constitutionalism, as Jon Elster has<br />

argued, is to protect principles <strong>and</strong> minorities from simple majority rule<br />

(Elster, 1988). None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> unanimity rule in Canada, even though of<br />

limited application, is a pathological case of constitutionalism, reflecting deep<br />

distrust within <strong>the</strong> political community.<br />

<strong>The</strong> requirement of extraordinary majorities, quite properly, makes ordinary,<br />

piecemeal constitutional change a difficult task. But <strong>the</strong> difficulty is<br />

compounded mightily when macro constitutional change is attempted.<br />

Political elites in both Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada who have attempted macro<br />

constitutional change have under-estimated <strong>the</strong> difficulty. <strong>The</strong>y have not<br />

appreciated how far removed macro constitutional change is from normal<br />

constitutional reform <strong>and</strong> how close it comes to constitution-making. Among<br />

people practising a democratic form of constitutionalism, constitution-making<br />

is <strong>the</strong> supreme political challenge.<br />

<strong>The</strong> packages of constitutional reform proposals under consideration in<br />

Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada have involved negotiations among political 1eaders<br />

representing different, <strong>and</strong> sometimes conflicting, constitutional ideals <strong>and</strong><br />

aspirations. Negotiating is unavoidably an activity carried out by small<br />

numbers of people <strong>and</strong> is, in that sense, elitist. Electorates <strong>and</strong> legislatures, <strong>the</strong><br />

democratic ratifiers in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada, do not negotiate. Of course <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are degrees of elitism. A First Ministers’ meeting is more elitist than a<br />

convention of legislative delegations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter is narrower than constituent<br />

assemblies containing more than party politicians. <strong>The</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r devices<br />

(parliamentary committees <strong>and</strong> federal commissions) have been tried, but<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r country has established a negotiating process capable of producing an<br />

elite accord possessing sufficient democratic legitimacy to change <strong>the</strong> terms of<br />

<strong>the</strong> social contract. In <strong>the</strong>ir attempts at macro constitutional change nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Australia nor Canada have been able to marry an elitist drafting process to a<br />

more participatory democratic ratifying process.<br />

Although nei<strong>the</strong>r country has anything very positive to teach <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r about<br />

how to accomplish macro constitutional change, both have negative lessons to<br />

impart. <strong>The</strong> clearest lesson to be derived from Australia’s experience is that<br />

political elites with conflicting constitutional aspirations will not<br />

accommodate <strong>the</strong>ir differences within a broad-based assembly such as<br />

Australia’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention when <strong>the</strong>y are not under <strong>the</strong> pressure of<br />

a genuine national crisis. Two recent Canadian studies of constituent<br />

assemblies support that conclusion (Fafard <strong>and</strong> Reid, 1991; Monahan, Covello<br />

<strong>and</strong> Batty, 1992). <strong>The</strong>se studies would go fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> question <strong>the</strong><br />

effectiveness of any form of constituent assembly except to reorganize<br />

regimes when a breakup is ei<strong>the</strong>r imminent or actual.<br />

<strong>The</strong> principal negative lesson to be gleaned from Canada’s Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

experience is <strong>the</strong> folly of achieving a constitutional agreement through a<br />

closed, secretive process of elite accommodation before <strong>the</strong>re has been wide<br />

public discussion of constitutional alternatives. In <strong>the</strong> Canada round,<br />

55


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

politicians tried to heed this lesson by staging extensive public discussions<br />

before engaging in elite bargaining. But <strong>the</strong>ir accommodation was fatally<br />

flawed by its dependence on a proposal which had not been publicly aired.<br />

Australia, with its much longer tradition of democratic constitutionalism, may<br />

not need this Canadian lesson. However, <strong>the</strong> populist cannon-ball Mr. Keating<br />

fired across <strong>the</strong> bow of <strong>the</strong> Special Premiers’ Conferences warned of <strong>the</strong><br />

danger of moving too fast towards a reshaping of Australian federalism<br />

through a relatively closed <strong>and</strong> elitist process.<br />

As a result of <strong>the</strong>ir recent experiences, <strong>the</strong> political leadership in both countries<br />

should be older <strong>and</strong> wiser about <strong>the</strong> difficulty of putting brokered<br />

constitutional packages to <strong>the</strong> people. Australia’s <strong>Constitution</strong> requires that<br />

each “proposed law,” not packages of proposed laws, be submitted to <strong>the</strong><br />

electors. <strong>The</strong> highest number of proposals ever submitted at one time was six.<br />

This was in 1913 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y were all defeated. Even if a great pile of proposals<br />

were submitted at one time (<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission recommended<br />

over 100 amendments), <strong>the</strong>re is no guarantee that those which are adopted will<br />

maintain <strong>the</strong> balance struck in negotiating <strong>the</strong> package. In Canada’s recent<br />

referendum, many people resented that <strong>the</strong>y had to vote “yes” or “no” on <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord as a whole ra<strong>the</strong>r than on each of its elements.<br />

<strong>The</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord in <strong>the</strong> October referendum adds an<br />

important caveat to a maxim gleaned from Australia’s constitutional politics.<br />

As even Bob Hawke came to acknowledge, a positive outcome in a national<br />

referendum, particularly one requiring an extraordinary majority, is most<br />

unlikely if <strong>the</strong> proposals are opposed by a major political party. <strong>The</strong> Canadian<br />

caveat is that multi-partisan support, though a necessary condition, is not a<br />

sufficient condition for success in a referendum on fundamental constitutional<br />

change. <strong>The</strong> three major national parties—<strong>the</strong> Conservatives, Liberals <strong>and</strong><br />

NDP—all supported <strong>the</strong> Accord. Still, it failed. Here Canadian experience<br />

coincides with rejection of <strong>the</strong> Masstricht Treaty by <strong>the</strong> Danish people despite<br />

its support by that country’s major political parties.<br />

<strong>The</strong> deepest lesson would-be constitutional reformers might take from <strong>the</strong>se<br />

events is <strong>the</strong> need to have a little more reverence for <strong>the</strong>ir existing constitutions<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir peoples. <strong>Constitution</strong>al reverence need not mean total acquiesence in<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional status quo. But it should foster respect for methods of<br />

constitutional adaptation that are more incremental <strong>and</strong> less contentious than<br />

macro constitutional restructuring. In constitutional democracies worthy of<br />

<strong>the</strong> name, <strong>the</strong> people should not readily be persuaded to accept major<br />

transformations of <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional arrangements.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Globalization of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Politics<br />

As might be expected, Australian <strong>and</strong> Canadian constitutionalism show a good<br />

deal of reciprocal influence. Canada’s discussion of an Australian style “triple<br />

E” Senate <strong>and</strong> Australia’s discussion of a Canadian-style <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights are<br />

clear examples. But <strong>the</strong> care with which Australian constitutionalists study<br />

Canadian experience is not reciprocated by Canadians. Australia’s<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission, for example, in considering a constitutional bill<br />

of rights, looked carefully at Canada’s <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms,<br />

adopted <strong>the</strong> exact wording of its Section 1 (<strong>the</strong> reasonable limits clause) but<br />

split three-to-two against recommending its notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause<br />

(Australia. <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission, 1988, ch. 9). <strong>The</strong> architects of <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, in excluding elected Senators from<br />

56


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

<strong>the</strong> Cabinet, appear to have given no in-depth consideration of Australia’s<br />

experience in combining an elected Senate with a parliamentary regime.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>re are signs of a wider set of international forces influencing<br />

constitutional developments in both countries. One can certainly see this<br />

globalization at <strong>the</strong> level of ideas. <strong>The</strong> growing support in Australia for a<br />

constitutional bill of rights represents much more than <strong>the</strong> Canadian influence.<br />

Much of Alan Cairns analysis of <strong>the</strong> international influences on <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> applies to Australia—especially <strong>the</strong> international human rights<br />

movement (Cairns, 1992). 7 It is difficult to untangle <strong>the</strong> influence of American<br />

constitutionalism from this broader, world-wide interest in <strong>the</strong> codification<br />

<strong>and</strong> entrenchment of fundamental human rights. I have speculated that it is <strong>the</strong><br />

relatively greater strength of <strong>the</strong> American influence on Canada that accounts<br />

for its adopting a constitutional bill of rights earlier than its sister<br />

Commonwealth countries, Australia <strong>and</strong> New Zeal<strong>and</strong> (Russell, 1990). Even<br />

if American constitutionalism is on its way to becoming <strong>the</strong> modern analogue<br />

of Roman law, it is clear that each society stamps its own identity on <strong>the</strong><br />

adopted paradigm (Henkin <strong>and</strong> Rosenthal, 1990). This is evident in Canada’s<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> with its group rights, legislative override <strong>and</strong> absence of property<br />

rights. Australia’s constitutional bill of rights, when it comes, will no doubt<br />

have its distinguishing features. 8<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is also an important international dimension to <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>ning of<br />

aboriginal rights in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada. Aboriginal peoples from Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada have linked toge<strong>the</strong>r with indigenous peoples from o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

European-settler countries to form a world-wide movement. Through <strong>the</strong>se<br />

interactions, aboriginal peoples have stimulated one ano<strong>the</strong>r in asserting <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

rights to collective survival. Indigenous minorities have gained recognition as<br />

<strong>the</strong> “fourth world” <strong>and</strong> associated <strong>the</strong>ir political objectives with <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

process of decolonization (Manuel <strong>and</strong> Posluns, 1974). <strong>The</strong>re are many factors<br />

which account for Canada’s aboriginal peoples progressing more quickly in<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional arena than <strong>the</strong>ir Australian counterparts, but perhaps <strong>the</strong><br />

most important is <strong>the</strong> demonstration effect of Quebec nationalism in creating a<br />

political environment conducive to claims of ethnic or racial selfdetermination<br />

(Brock, 1989). Even if <strong>the</strong> macro constitutional struggle is not<br />

resumed in Canada or Australia, <strong>the</strong>re are many indications that <strong>the</strong> movement<br />

of aboriginal peoples towards self-government in both countries will continue.<br />

Globalization of <strong>the</strong> international economy has had a more tangible effect on<br />

constitutional po1itics in <strong>the</strong> two countries. In recent constitutional<br />

discussions in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada, much concern is expressed about <strong>the</strong><br />

impediments to <strong>the</strong> flow of commerce across borders within <strong>the</strong> federations<br />

being greater than those at national borders in regional trading blocks. Much of<br />

<strong>the</strong> impetus behind Australia’s new federalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic union<br />

proposals in Canada’s current constitutional round stems from a desire,<br />

particularly within <strong>the</strong> business class, to adapt <strong>the</strong> economies of <strong>the</strong> federations<br />

to <strong>the</strong> imperatives of an increasingly competitive global economy (Business<br />

Council of Australia, 1991). In both countries, this tendency is counterbalanced<br />

by a social democratic tradition concerned about protecting national<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards of social <strong>and</strong> environmental policy from <strong>the</strong> competitive pressures<br />

of a commercial union (Howse, 1992). This, in turn, puts a check on tendencies<br />

within <strong>the</strong> federations to decentralize power to governments more responsive<br />

to local majorities.<br />

57


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

As <strong>the</strong> Australian <strong>and</strong> Canadian economies become more closely integrated<br />

with neighbouring states, <strong>the</strong>se international pressures on <strong>the</strong> operation of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

federal systems will surely intensify. International trade agreements which<br />

aim at removing non-tariff barriers propel <strong>the</strong> parties, inexorably, towards<br />

homogenization of a broad range of policies. When <strong>the</strong>se international<br />

arrangements severely constrain <strong>the</strong> policy-making of both levels of<br />

government, only a strict formalist would deny <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional<br />

significance. At first, of course, <strong>the</strong> constitutional form of <strong>the</strong>se international<br />

regimes is confederal—all sovereignty being retained by <strong>the</strong> member states.<br />

But as <strong>the</strong> evolution of <strong>the</strong> European Community so clearly demonstrates, <strong>the</strong><br />

expansion of delegated authority at <strong>the</strong> centre generates a dem<strong>and</strong> for a more<br />

democratic central authority <strong>and</strong> a more federal form of political union. At this<br />

point, <strong>the</strong> question of political community <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> locus of sovereign<br />

constitutional authority is raised, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm of mega constitutional politics<br />

is entered.<br />

Canada, as it contemplates <strong>the</strong> North American Free Trade Agreement, is<br />

much closer to this international stage of constitutional politics than Australia.<br />

That may be one consolation Canadians can take from <strong>the</strong>ir having been more<br />

deeply inflicted than Australians with <strong>the</strong> frustrations of macro constitutional<br />

politics. That experience has better prepared <strong>the</strong>m to be citizens of <strong>the</strong> multinational<br />

states that lie in <strong>the</strong> future of human kind. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, a decade<br />

of quiet, non-partisan, constitutionalism with a strong emphasis on public<br />

education could produce a popular consensus on national renewal in Australia.<br />

If that were to occur, Australia will embark on its second century more secure<br />

in its national identity than Canada <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> confidence needed to take full<br />

advantage of regional integration.<br />

Notes<br />

1. In an earlier article I used this phrase to characterize constitutional politics in Australia <strong>and</strong><br />

Canada from 1900 to <strong>the</strong> mid-1980s (Russell, 1988).<br />

2. <strong>The</strong> report is indeed of academic interest. Altoge<strong>the</strong>r aside from its recommendations, its<br />

background accounts of constitutional issues in each chapter are of great value to<br />

constitutional cholars.<br />

3. <strong>The</strong>re are numerous possibilities: <strong>the</strong> 1893 Corowa Conferenœ, <strong>the</strong> 1895 Premiers’ meeting<br />

in Hobart, election of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention in 1897 <strong>and</strong> its meetings that year in<br />

Adelaide <strong>and</strong> Sydney, <strong>and</strong> in 1898 in Melbourne, <strong>the</strong> ratifying referendums in 1898, <strong>the</strong><br />

second referendum in New South Wales in 1899, <strong>the</strong> London conference in 1900, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

coming into force of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> on January 1, 1901 (<strong>La</strong> Nauze, 1972).<br />

4. Interviews with Sir Ninian Stephen, Chairman of <strong>the</strong> Foundation <strong>and</strong> Mr. Denis Tracey,<br />

Executive Director of <strong>the</strong> Foundation, Melbourne, December 1991.<br />

5. <strong>The</strong> study is being carried out by Brian Galligan <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r colleagues in Canberra using <strong>the</strong><br />

same methodology employed in <strong>the</strong> survey conducted in Canada by Paul Sniderman, Joseph<br />

Fletcher, Philip Tetlock <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> author (Galligan, 1992).<br />

6. Of course, Canada’s amending formula is considerably more complicated than this. For a<br />

full discussion see Meekison, 1988.<br />

7. On December 10, 1991, Australia took an important step in committing <strong>the</strong> country to<br />

complying with international human rights st<strong>and</strong>ards when it acceded to <strong>the</strong> First Optional<br />

Protocol to <strong>the</strong> International Covenant on Civil <strong>and</strong> Political Rights.<br />

8. A likely example is a religious freedom clause that does not threaten state-funded religious<br />

schools.<br />

Bibliography<br />

Australia, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commisssion 1987 Australia’s <strong>Constitution</strong>: Time to Update.<br />

58


Attempting Macro <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada<br />

Australia, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission 1988 Final Report.<br />

Australia, Joint Parliamentary Committee on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Review 1959 Report<br />

Australia, Special Premiers’ Conference 1991 Communique, Sidney 30 July 1991.<br />

Australia, Premiers’ <strong>and</strong> Chief Ministers’ Conference 1991 Communique, Adelaide, 21-2<br />

November, 1991.<br />

Australia, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary Foundation 1992 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary, No. 1, April<br />

1992.<br />

Banting, Keith <strong>and</strong> Richard Simeon 1985 Redesigning <strong>the</strong> State: <strong>The</strong> Politics of <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Change in Industrial Nations. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

Boyer, Patrick 1992 Direct Democracy in Canada: <strong>The</strong> History <strong>and</strong> Future of Referendums.<br />

Toronto: Dunedin Press.<br />

Brennan, Frank <strong>and</strong> James Crawford 1990 “Aboriginality, Recognition <strong>and</strong> Australian <strong>La</strong>w:<br />

Where to from Here?” Public <strong>La</strong>w Review, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 53-79.<br />

Brennan, Frank 1992 “Mabo’s Case,” <strong>Constitution</strong>al Centenary, Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 12-14.<br />

Brock, Kathy 1989 <strong>The</strong> <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> Practice of Aboriginal Self-government: Canada in a<br />

Comparative Context Ph D Dissertation, Department of Political Science, University of<br />

Toronto.<br />

Business Council of Australia 1991 Government in Australia in <strong>the</strong> 1990s. Melbourne.<br />

Cairns, Alan 1984 “<strong>The</strong> Politics of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Renewal in Canada” in Keith Banting <strong>and</strong><br />

Richard Simeon (Eds.) Redesigning <strong>the</strong> State: <strong>The</strong> Politics of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in<br />

Industrial Nations. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, pp. 95-145.<br />

Cairns, Alan 1991 Disruptions: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Struggles from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke.<br />

Toronto: McClell<strong>and</strong> & Stewart.<br />

Cairns, Alan 1992 <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong>. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.<br />

Campbell, Enid 1989 “Sou<strong>the</strong>y Memorial Lecture 1988: Changing <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>—Past <strong>and</strong><br />

Future,” Melbourne University <strong>La</strong>w Review Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 1-23.<br />

Canada, 1972 Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> House of Commons on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> of Canada. Final Report.<br />

Canada, 1991 Citizens’ Forum on Canada’s Future. Ottawa: Canadian Government Publishing<br />

Centre.<br />

Canada, 1992 Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> House of Commons 1992. A Renewed<br />

Canada.<br />

Canada, 1993 House of Commons Debates February 1, p. 15238.<br />

Cohen, Andrew 1990 A Deal Undone: <strong>The</strong> Making <strong>and</strong> Breaking of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord.<br />

Vancouver: Douglas & McIntyre.<br />

Cooray, Mark 1989 “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change” in Brian Galligan <strong>and</strong> J. R.<br />

Ne<strong>the</strong>rcote (Eds) <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1988 Referendums. Canberra:<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong> Research Centre, Australian National University.<br />

Dufour, Christian 1990 A Canadian Challenge/ Le Défi québécois. <strong>La</strong>nzville, B.C.: Oolichan<br />

Books.<br />

Easterbrook, Margaret “Move for Koori reconciliation.” <strong>The</strong> Age, December 16, 1991.<br />

Elston, Jon 1988 “Introduction” in Jon Elster <strong>and</strong> Rune Slagstad (Eds.) <strong>Constitution</strong>alism <strong>and</strong><br />

Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Fafard Patrick <strong>and</strong> Darrel R. Reid 1991 Constituent Assemblies: A Comparative Survey. Kingston:<br />

Queen’s University Institute of Intergovernmental Relations.<br />

Fidler, Richard, 1991 Canada, Adieu? Quebec Debates Its Future. <strong>La</strong>ntzville B.C.: Oolichan<br />

Books.<br />

Galligan, Brian 1989 “<strong>The</strong> 1988 Referendums in Perspective” in Brian Galligan <strong>and</strong> John<br />

Ne<strong>the</strong>rcote (Eds.) <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1988 Referendums. Canberra:<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong> Research Centre, Australian National University, pp. 118-133.<br />

Galligan, Brian 1992 “Australian <strong>Federalism</strong>: Rethinking <strong>and</strong> Restructuring,” Australian Journal<br />

of Political Science, Vol. 27, pp. 1-6.<br />

Galligan Brian, Rainer Knopff <strong>and</strong> John Ure 1989 “Australian <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Debate over a<br />

Bill of Rights.” Publius, Vol. 20, No. 4, pp. 53-67.<br />

Hawke, Robert 1990 “Towards a Closer Partnership.” Canberra: Office of <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister.<br />

Henkin, Louis <strong>and</strong> Albert Rosenthal (Eds.) 1990 <strong>Constitution</strong>alism <strong>and</strong> Rights: <strong>The</strong> Influence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> United States <strong>Constitution</strong> Abroad. New York: Columbia University Press.<br />

Holmes, Stephen 1988 “Gag rules of <strong>the</strong> politics of omission” in Jon Elster <strong>and</strong> Rune Slagstad<br />

(Eds) <strong>Constitution</strong>alism <strong>and</strong> Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 19-<br />

58.<br />

Howse, Robert 1992 Economic Union, Social Justice <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform: Towards a High<br />

But Level Playing Field. North York: York University Centre for Public <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong> Public<br />

Policy.<br />

Johnson, Richard 1993 “An Inverted Logroll: <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Referendums,”<br />

PS: Political Science & Politics, Vol. 26, pp. 43-46.<br />

Keating, Paul 1991 “<strong>The</strong> Commonwealth <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> States <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> November Special Premiers’<br />

Meeting.” Canberra: National Press Club, 22 October, 1991.<br />

59


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>La</strong> Nauze, J.A. 1972 <strong>The</strong> Making of Australia’s <strong>Constitution</strong>. Melbourne: Melbourne University<br />

Press.<br />

Manuel George <strong>and</strong> Michael Posluns 1974 <strong>The</strong> Fourth World: An Indian Reality. Toronto: Collier<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Mason, Anthony 1988 “<strong>The</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong> 1901-1988.” <strong>The</strong> Australian <strong>La</strong>w Journal,<br />

Vol. 62, pp. 752-60.<br />

Meekison, Peter 1988 “<strong>The</strong> Amending Formula” in R.D. Olling <strong>and</strong> M.W. Westmacott (Eds.)<br />

Perspectives on Canadian <strong>Federalism</strong>. Toronto: Prentice-Hall.<br />

Milne, David 1982 <strong>The</strong> New Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>. Toronto: James Lorimer.<br />

Monahan, Patrick 1991 Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: <strong>The</strong> Inside Story. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

Monahan, Patrick, Lynda Covello <strong>and</strong> Jonathan Batty (Eds.) 1992 Constituent Assemblies: <strong>The</strong><br />

Canadian Debate in Comparative <strong>and</strong> Historical Context. North York: York University<br />

Centre for Public <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong> Public Policy.<br />

Russell, Peter 1988 “<strong>The</strong> Politics of Frustration: <strong>The</strong> Pursuit of Formal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in<br />

Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada,” Australian-Canadian Studies. Vol. 6, pp. 1-32.<br />

Russell, Peter 1990 “<strong>The</strong> Diffusion of Judicial Review: <strong>The</strong> Commonwealth, <strong>the</strong> United States<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Case,” Policy Studies Journal, Vol. 19, pp. 113-21.<br />

Russell, Peter 1992 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Odyssey: Can Canadians Become A Sovereign People?<br />

Toronto: University of Toronto Press<br />

Russell, Peter 1993 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Odyssey: Can Canadians Become A Sovereign People? (2nd<br />

Edition) Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

Ryan, K.W. <strong>and</strong> H. D. Hewitt 1977 <strong>The</strong> Australian <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention. Canberra: Centre<br />

for Research on Federal Financial Relations.<br />

Sawer, Geofrrey 1963 Australian Federal Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>La</strong>w, 1929-1949. Melbourne:<br />

Melbourne University Press.<br />

Sharman, Campbell 1989 “<strong>The</strong> Referendum Results <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Context” in Brian Galligan <strong>and</strong><br />

John Ne<strong>the</strong>rcote (Eds.) <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1988 Referendums.<br />

Canberra: <strong>Federalism</strong> Research Centre, Australian National University, pp. 105-117.<br />

Simeon, Richard 1990 “Why Did <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord Fail?” in Ronald Watts <strong>and</strong> Douglas<br />

Brown (Eds.) Canada: State of <strong>the</strong> Federation 1990. Kingston: Queen’s University Institute<br />

of Intergovernmental Relations.<br />

Solomon, David 1991 “Getting a constitution fit for <strong>the</strong> future,” <strong>The</strong> Australian, 5 April, 1991.<br />

60


David M. Thomas<br />

Turning a Blind Eye: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

Abstract<br />

Mature <strong>and</strong> workable constitutions contain areas of great ambiguity <strong>and</strong><br />

imprecision that are not mere compromises between principles, or weak<br />

constitutional conventions. <strong>The</strong>se gaps in a constitution, kept in place by<br />

deliberate non-exposure, are known as abeyances. Canada’s <strong>Constitution</strong> has<br />

contained a great many such areas: <strong>the</strong> long-st<strong>and</strong>ing lack of an amending<br />

formula was one example, fraught as it was with <strong>the</strong> dangers of French-<br />

English conflict, <strong>and</strong> raising as it did o<strong>the</strong>r abeyances. <strong>The</strong> rise of Quebec<br />

nationalism forced some of our abeyances into <strong>the</strong> open. <strong>The</strong> Unity Task Force<br />

Report of 1979 shows us struggling to deal with abeyances, especially<br />

binationalism, rooted in <strong>the</strong> federal system itself. <strong>The</strong> Report was dismissed by<br />

Trudeau; his response to Quebec nationalism helped create a new<br />

constitutional, intellectual <strong>and</strong> political dynamic, married to a changing<br />

social <strong>and</strong> demographic structure. New <strong>and</strong> symbolically powerful areas of<br />

conflict now clash with <strong>the</strong> old. <strong>The</strong> amending formulae created in 1982 did<br />

not, however, resolve former abeyances; <strong>the</strong>se have been worsened in ways<br />

that were not anticipated. Elite accommodation no longer seems capable of<br />

keeping abeyances in check. <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown Accords <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

referendum of October 1992 are proof that we have exposed <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>’s<br />

anomalies, breached its abeyances (not without reason) <strong>and</strong> put in place a<br />

process that offers us slim hope that our “gaps of unsettlement” can be<br />

resolved satisfactorily.<br />

Résumé<br />

Les constitutions qui ont résisté à l’épreuve du temps comportent toutes des<br />

zones d’ambiguïté et d’imprécision qui ne résultent pas forcément de<br />

compromis entre des principes ni d’arrangements constitutionnels médiocres.<br />

Dans une constitution, ces lacunes, que l’on camoufle délibérément, sont dites<br />

« questions pendantes ». <strong>La</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne renfermait un gr<strong>and</strong><br />

nombre de ces zones, par exemple la très longue absence d’une formule<br />

d’amendement, qui risquait de soulever des conflits entre francophones et<br />

anglophones et qui créaient, elle-même, d’autres questions pendantes. <strong>La</strong><br />

montée du nationalisme québécois a mis en évidence plusieurs de nos<br />

questions pendantes. Le rapport du Groupe de travail sur l’unité canadienne,<br />

paru en 1979, s’efforçait de résoudre certaines de ces questions pendantes,<br />

notamment le binationalisme qui pousse ses racines dans le régime fédéral luimême.<br />

Ce rapport a été écarté par Trudeau, dont la réaction au nationalisme<br />

québécois a mis en branle une nouvelle dynamique constitutionnelle,<br />

intellectuelle et politique associée à une structure sociale et démographique<br />

en évolution. Aujourd’hui, de nouveaux sujets de conflit, chargés d’un<br />

symbolisme puissant, viennent s’ajouter aux anciens. <strong>La</strong> formule<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

d’amendement adoptée en 1982 n’a cependant pas résolu les questions en<br />

suspens; elle les a même envenimées d’une façon tout à fait inattendue. Les<br />

compromis entre les élites ne semblent plus capables de tenir ces questions<br />

sous le boisseau et le sort qui a été réservé à l’entente du lac Meech, à celle de<br />

Charlottetown et au référendum d’octobre 1992 montre clairement que les<br />

défauts de la <strong>Constitution</strong> sont désormais à découvert, ainsi que les questions<br />

en suspens, et que nous avons mis en marche un processus qui n’aidera guère à<br />

résoudre les contradictions et les malentendus.<br />

At <strong>the</strong> 1964 annual meeting of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science Association in<br />

Charlottetown, Pierre Elliott Trudeau presented an unfinished version of a<br />

paper entitled “<strong>Federalism</strong>, Nationalism <strong>and</strong> Reason.” 1 In <strong>the</strong> summer of 1992,<br />

<strong>the</strong> University of Prince Edward Isl<strong>and</strong> was once again hosting <strong>the</strong><br />

Association’s annual ga<strong>the</strong>ring, but now scholars were wrestling with <strong>the</strong><br />

legacy of <strong>the</strong> Trudeau era <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> results of a fur<strong>the</strong>r twenty-eight years of<br />

constitutional change, debate <strong>and</strong> frustration. It is indeed Trudeau, above all,<br />

who has been responsible for forcing us to consider some of our deepest<br />

constitutional disjunctions <strong>and</strong> incompatibilities. And he has left us, once<br />

again, with unfinished business. Not that we should lay <strong>the</strong> opening of<br />

P<strong>and</strong>ora’s constitutional box at his feet alone. Far from it. He was as clearly<br />

aware as anyone that constitutional incrementalism was preferable to activism.<br />

In 1965, one year after his Charlottetown lecture, he wrote:<br />

I should be very surprised if real statesmen, given <strong>the</strong> facts of <strong>the</strong><br />

problem, arrive at <strong>the</strong> conclusion that our constitution needs drastic<br />

revision. 2<br />

Yet this is precisely what happened. And as a result of <strong>the</strong>se changes, we now<br />

face, in extreme form, <strong>the</strong> clash of almost every constitutional principle <strong>and</strong><br />

problem imaginable.<br />

<strong>The</strong> argument presented in this paper is as follows:<br />

• Mature <strong>and</strong> “living” constitutions are capable of containing unsettled areas<br />

of great importance, or “abeyances” which <strong>the</strong>y leave well alone. <strong>The</strong><br />

Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> has contained a great many such areas; <strong>the</strong><br />

amending question is particularly illustrative of <strong>the</strong> kind of difficulties we<br />

have faced. Over <strong>the</strong> past quarter of a century, we have seemed increasingly<br />

determined to leave no abeyance undisturbed; we have been loa<strong>the</strong> to admit<br />

that such things should exist. We have tended to assume that all our<br />

constitutional problems have constitutional answers. Indeed we may also<br />

have assumed that many of our non-constitutional problems have<br />

constitutional solutions.<br />

• <strong>The</strong> period following <strong>the</strong> triumph of <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois in 1976 saw a<br />

flurry of proposals for major constitutional change. Those efforts were<br />

exemplified by Bill C-60 <strong>and</strong>, in particular, by <strong>the</strong> Report of <strong>the</strong> Task Force<br />

on Canadian Unity (<strong>the</strong> Pépin-Robarts Report). 3 It attempted to tackle<br />

matters previously left as abeyances, <strong>and</strong> well crafted <strong>and</strong> drafted though it<br />

was, it ran headlong into <strong>the</strong> problem of what abeyances to avoid or address.<br />

• <strong>The</strong> Task Force report became a “political orphan” 4 <strong>and</strong> was upstaged <strong>and</strong><br />

contradicted by Pierre Trudeau’s single-minded <strong>and</strong> consistent devotion to<br />

a different set of principles. His determination to undermine Quebec<br />

nationalists <strong>and</strong> to avoid confronting, head on, <strong>the</strong> deepest abeyance of all,<br />

namely <strong>the</strong> recognition of a special role <strong>and</strong> place for Quebec, led to<br />

64


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

changes that have had <strong>the</strong> effect of fur<strong>the</strong>r isolating Quebec <strong>and</strong> of raising<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r abeyances from <strong>the</strong>ir slumber. 5<br />

• <strong>The</strong> Trudeau vision has taken deep root <strong>and</strong> is now protected, in ways that<br />

were not anticipated, by <strong>the</strong> provisions of <strong>the</strong> amending formulae, by <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms, by a newly provincialized referendum<br />

process, by <strong>the</strong> intractable <strong>and</strong> symbolic nature of <strong>the</strong> issues, <strong>and</strong> by <strong>the</strong><br />

ways in which <strong>the</strong>y have become linked. Our abeyances have become<br />

matters of public debate; competing visions struggle to emerge victorious;<br />

one principle leads on to ano<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

It is concluded that <strong>the</strong>re is but slim hope that <strong>the</strong> abeyances that have been<br />

made <strong>the</strong> subject of so much debate can be put to rest. <strong>The</strong> rejections of <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown Accords are proof that Canadians have been<br />

unable to agree on fundamental principles: our search for clarity has breached<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>’s abeyances, exposed its anomalies, created new problems<br />

<strong>and</strong> shown our unwillingness to retreat into <strong>the</strong> ambiguous safety of<br />

constitutional uncertainty even when given <strong>the</strong> chance to do so. Our abeyances<br />

are in public view, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> referendum process recently utilized seems<br />

inherently unsuited to <strong>the</strong> avoidance or resolution of longst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong><br />

complex “gaps of unsettlement.”<br />

Macro-<strong>Constitution</strong>al Politics<br />

Our <strong>Constitution</strong> is rife with well-known contradictions <strong>and</strong> incongruities.<br />

Parliamentary sovereignty <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> conventions of cabinet government sit<br />

uneasily with federalism <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for such things as Senate reform (along<br />

U.S. lines). Binationalism <strong>and</strong> dualism confront notions of provincial equality,<br />

multi-culturalism <strong>and</strong> founding peoples. Dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> entrenchment of<br />

difference blindness clash with dem<strong>and</strong>s for difference valorization <strong>and</strong><br />

recognition. 6 <strong>The</strong> equality of citizens contends with collective <strong>and</strong> group<br />

rights; liberty <strong>and</strong> community, constitutionalism <strong>and</strong> communitarianism,<br />

collide. 7 Recent court cases raise questions about <strong>the</strong> effectiveness <strong>and</strong><br />

fairness of <strong>the</strong> system of representation. Perhaps, above all, as Peter Russell<br />

pointed out in his Presidential Address to <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science<br />

Association in 1990, we cannot decide where sovereignty resides <strong>and</strong> how it is<br />

to be exercised:<br />

Canadians have not yet constituted <strong>the</strong>mselves a sovereign people.<br />

So deep are <strong>the</strong>ir current differences on fundamental questions of<br />

political justice <strong>and</strong> collective identity that Canadians may now be<br />

incapable of acting toge<strong>the</strong>r as a sovereign people. 8<br />

To say all of this is merely to belabour <strong>the</strong> obvious; we have been deeply<br />

divided on almost every conceivable constitutional issue. It is not that we are<br />

short of answers <strong>and</strong> expert opinion. Our best <strong>and</strong> brightest have laboured for a<br />

whole generation on <strong>the</strong>se problems. One could argue that Canadian political<br />

science as a discipline has been distorted by <strong>the</strong> pull (<strong>and</strong> lure) of constitutional<br />

analysis <strong>and</strong> debate. Political scientists have been drawn to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

like moths to a flame.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re have been numerous wonderfully perceptive <strong>and</strong> critical commentaries.<br />

<strong>The</strong> MacDonald Royal Commission alone saw <strong>the</strong> production of over seventy<br />

volumes of research studies. Surely we have to recognize that it is not for lack<br />

of brainpower, patriotism, money, time or effort that we have reached such an<br />

extraordinary impasse which everyone still strives to solve in his/her own way<br />

65


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>and</strong> to such little effect? Surely no o<strong>the</strong>r country can have undergone such a<br />

rigorous yet unproductive national examination by its political scientists <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional lawyers?<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r countries have spent a long time examining certain facets of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

constitution. Australia established a <strong>Constitution</strong>al Convention (in 1973) <strong>and</strong> a<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Commission (in 1985) whose labours have brought forth<br />

referendum proposals, some of <strong>the</strong>m successful. However, <strong>the</strong> latest batch<br />

recently went down to resounding defeat. Britain has long discussed electoral<br />

<strong>and</strong> parliamentary reform. Yet <strong>the</strong>se matters are as nothing compared to <strong>the</strong><br />

efforts we have made. It has been a preoccupation for our political scientists,<br />

our political elites, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> country generally. <strong>The</strong> point is, when we put our<br />

ongoing “macro-constitutional” crises into perspective, it is not hard to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> why agreement has been so difficult to reach:<br />

Macro-constitutional politics is distinguished in two ways from<br />

ordinary or micro-constitutional politics. First, macro-constitutional<br />

politics goes beyond disputing <strong>the</strong> events of specific constitutional<br />

proposals <strong>and</strong> addresses <strong>the</strong> very nature of <strong>the</strong> political community on<br />

which <strong>the</strong> constitution is to be based ... precisely because of <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamental nature of <strong>the</strong> dispute ... macro-constitutional politics is<br />

exceptionally emotional <strong>and</strong> intense. 9<br />

Who or what is to blame? An intransigent Quebec led by professional <strong>and</strong><br />

bureaucratic elites would probably top <strong>the</strong> list. It would be followed by an<br />

obdurate, anti-nationalist Trudeau, along with self-aggr<strong>and</strong>izing provincial<br />

barons <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir courtiers. Or we could blame <strong>the</strong> Fa<strong>the</strong>rs of Confederation, <strong>the</strong><br />

BNA Act, <strong>the</strong> decentralizing actions of <strong>the</strong> imperial Judicial Committee of <strong>the</strong><br />

Privy Council, <strong>the</strong> lack of cohesion <strong>and</strong> balance in Section 91 <strong>and</strong> Section 92 of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act of 1867, <strong>and</strong> more recently, <strong>the</strong> contradictions inherent in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act 1982, <strong>the</strong> workings of executive federalism, a lack of<br />

leadership, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> vagaries of fortuna. <strong>The</strong>re is clearly no shortage of<br />

c<strong>and</strong>idates for <strong>the</strong> Governor-General’s Scapegoat of <strong>the</strong> Year awards.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with any or all of <strong>the</strong>se explanations, or with <strong>the</strong> view that it is<br />

simply <strong>the</strong> cumulative weight of such issues that now presses down upon us, is<br />

that this is still to assume that we can (a) identify <strong>the</strong> problems <strong>and</strong> (b) find a<br />

solution to what ails us. Not all have presumed this to be so. As usual, a<br />

prescient Alan Cairns noted in 1970 that “cryptically we might say that <strong>the</strong><br />

constitution has not failed us, so much as we, by our inadequate underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

of its living nature, have failed it.” 10 To this he later added, when commenting<br />

on <strong>the</strong> spate of proposals that emerged in <strong>the</strong> late 1970s, that “<strong>the</strong> patient may<br />

stagger on in a kind of half life for a long time to come. Not only is <strong>the</strong>re yet no<br />

cure. <strong>The</strong>re is also no easy way to die.” 11 Perhaps we have loved not wisely but<br />

too well. We have not been content to let matters lie, <strong>and</strong> we may, ironically,<br />

have done far too much.<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances<br />

A recent provocative <strong>and</strong> powerful work by <strong>the</strong> British scholar Michael Foley<br />

casts light on our situation, <strong>and</strong> may help explain why constitutional peace <strong>and</strong><br />

quiet have been impossible to achieve. A reading of Foley’s aptly titled <strong>The</strong><br />

Silence of <strong>Constitution</strong>s12 does not tell us what we should do, it tells us instead<br />

why what we have been doing has not succeeded, <strong>and</strong> what we should, in fact,<br />

not do. It is <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis of this paper that Foley is correct in this key<br />

66


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

respect—mature <strong>and</strong> workable constitutions contain abeyances which one<br />

approaches <strong>and</strong> disinters at one’s peril. We have been, <strong>and</strong> are, digging up <strong>the</strong><br />

entire graveyard <strong>and</strong> one doubts that <strong>the</strong>re is an abeyance left unturned.<br />

So what are abeyances, <strong>and</strong> why are <strong>the</strong>y so important? <strong>The</strong>y are, in effect,<br />

holes or gaps in a constitution. <strong>The</strong>y are areas to be avoided at all costs. One<br />

blunders into an abeyance only to retreat as quickly <strong>and</strong> quietly as possible.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are constitutional quicks<strong>and</strong>. <strong>The</strong>y exist, says Foley, in a sort of “twilight<br />

zone,” in an “intermediate layer of obscurity” between <strong>the</strong> micro workings of<br />

uncodified rules <strong>and</strong> customs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> macro world of recognized rules <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional conventions. Without this layer of obscurity a constitution may<br />

well cease to function. <strong>The</strong>y remain unwritten <strong>and</strong> obscure because:<br />

It is recognized that any attempt to define <strong>the</strong>m would be not merely<br />

unnecessary or impossible, but positively misguided <strong>and</strong> even<br />

potentially threatening to <strong>the</strong> constitution itself. This is because such<br />

“underst<strong>and</strong>ings” only remain understood as long as <strong>the</strong>y remain<br />

sufficiently obscure to allow <strong>the</strong>m to retain an approximate<br />

appearance of internal coherence <strong>and</strong> clarity, while at <strong>the</strong> same time<br />

accommodating several potentially conflicting <strong>and</strong> quite unresolved<br />

points of issue. <strong>The</strong> resolution of conflict in such cases is that of<br />

suspended irresolution—ei<strong>the</strong>r consciously secured or, far more<br />

probably, unconsciously <strong>and</strong> unintentionally acquired. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

packages of aggregated positions are preserved by studied<br />

inattention. <strong>The</strong>y may include contradictions, tensions, anomalies,<br />

<strong>and</strong> inequities, but <strong>the</strong> fragility <strong>and</strong>, at times, total illogicality of such<br />

packages are kept intact through a convention of non-exposure, of<br />

strategic oversight, <strong>and</strong> of complicity in delusion—in short, through<br />

an instinctive reversion to not breaking ranks when confronted with<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional equivalents of <strong>the</strong> emperor’s clo<strong>the</strong>s. 13<br />

This passage should strike a responsive chord in many a Canadian scholar’s<br />

heart. It is, <strong>the</strong>refore, not enough to think of such abeyances as merely<br />

encompassing <strong>the</strong> unwritten parts of a constitution. <strong>The</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard, first year<br />

undergraduate explanation of unwritten (i.e. British) <strong>and</strong> written (i.e.<br />

American) constitutions, along with a hybrid (Canada) does not suffice. In <strong>the</strong><br />

first place, such distinctions between written <strong>and</strong> unwritten constitutions do<br />

not in <strong>the</strong>mselves make much sense anyway <strong>and</strong> have long been discarded.<br />

Secondly, conventions are not abeyances, as Foley uses <strong>the</strong> term.<br />

Conventions, as discussed by Heard in his recent book on <strong>the</strong> subject, can be<br />

divided into categories which range from <strong>the</strong> fundamental conventions<br />

“supported by general agreement on <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>and</strong> value of <strong>the</strong> principle<br />

involved” through meso-conventions <strong>and</strong> semi-conventions to infraconventions,<br />

“whose existence may be hotly contested.” Finally <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

embryonic conventions, such as <strong>the</strong> non use of <strong>the</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause.<br />

Below all of <strong>the</strong>se will lie usages. 14<br />

It may be true that some of <strong>the</strong>se conventions represent <strong>the</strong> tip of <strong>the</strong> abeyance<br />

iceberg, as is <strong>the</strong> case with those surrounding parliamentary sovereignty. Yet<br />

<strong>the</strong> point is that we can argue about <strong>the</strong> strength of specific conventions<br />

without calling into question <strong>the</strong> larger issues which lurk in <strong>the</strong> shadows<br />

behind <strong>the</strong>m. It should also be noted that mere ambiguity does not in itself<br />

constitute an abeyance, useful adjunct though it may be. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms is, for example, ambiguous in some areas, but o<strong>the</strong>r areas it<br />

67


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

avoids entirely. Abeyances are thus NOT recognizable rules or compromises,<br />

nor are <strong>the</strong>y in any sense legally precise notions. <strong>The</strong>y amount to “strategic<br />

gaps” kept in place by a sort of deterrence <strong>the</strong>ory, namely <strong>the</strong> knowledge that to<br />

subject <strong>the</strong>m to public view <strong>and</strong> open debate is to court disaster, for <strong>the</strong>y are too<br />

intractable <strong>and</strong> dangerous. If <strong>the</strong>y do become <strong>the</strong> subject of conflict, Foley<br />

argues that <strong>the</strong>y are “not so much accompanied by an intense constitutional<br />

crisis, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>the</strong> essence of that crisis.” 15<br />

To students of Canadian politics, Foley’s <strong>the</strong>sis may offer some important<br />

insights. First of all, it can give us hope. Even those constitutions that are<br />

seemingly well worked out, <strong>and</strong> agreed upon, are not. In Canada, <strong>the</strong> United<br />

States’ <strong>Constitution</strong> is often held up as <strong>the</strong> very essence of constitutionalism. It<br />

is seen as clear, binding, consistent <strong>and</strong> democratic. Not so, says Foley:<br />

In reality, <strong>the</strong> U.S. <strong>Constitution</strong> is replete with anomalies, gaps, <strong>and</strong><br />

areas of utter unsettlement...judicial consistency is unknown, final<br />

authoritative judgements are unavailable. 16<br />

It leaves unresolved <strong>and</strong> unclear <strong>the</strong> issues surrounding popular sovereignty<br />

<strong>and</strong> judicial review, <strong>and</strong> it does not explain <strong>the</strong> mysteries (<strong>and</strong> myths) of<br />

Presidential power <strong>and</strong> how this is to be kept in check by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>. To Foley, it is a mark of maturity that in both Britain <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

United States <strong>the</strong>re is a desire to leave such matters in a state of “settled<br />

unsettlement,” <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>re is a deep conservatism to constitutional practice.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> British case it may be due to historical traumas, such as <strong>the</strong> Civil War,<br />

<strong>and</strong> a collective acceptance of “tradition.” In <strong>the</strong> United States, <strong>the</strong> Supreme<br />

Court has played a key role in working “creatively with ambiguity.” 17<br />

One can hope that we, too, have tolerated our abeyances: it would seem in <strong>the</strong><br />

cautious Canadian character to have done so. This is what appears to have<br />

happened until well into this century. 18 We proceeded cautiously <strong>and</strong> slowly.<br />

We appear to have recognized, implicitly, that a federal system by its very<br />

nature will embody a changing conception of roles <strong>and</strong> powers, of identities<br />

<strong>and</strong> loyalties. This federal conception, especially if it embodies assumptions<br />

about unstated prerogatives which apply to some but not all <strong>the</strong> federal units,<br />

cannot be put down on paper. A central, crucial, abeyance was, <strong>and</strong> is, <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional definition of Quebec’s place within <strong>the</strong> Canadian federal state.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r was <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> assumed equality of <strong>the</strong> provinces. <strong>The</strong>se could not <strong>and</strong><br />

cannot be written down in such a way that <strong>the</strong>y are dealt with satisfactorily. To<br />

have attempted to do so ran <strong>the</strong> risk of picking one constitutional principle over<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r, of freezing, at a particular moment, <strong>the</strong> received constitutional<br />

wisdom of <strong>the</strong> time, <strong>and</strong> of creating new <strong>and</strong> unperceived incompatibilities.<br />

Amendment<br />

A quintessentially Canadian example of a problem behind which abeyances<br />

lurked was our amending formula, <strong>and</strong> lack <strong>the</strong>reof until 1982. Clearly, most<br />

federations settle this at <strong>the</strong> outset. To those ga<strong>the</strong>red at Philadelphia, <strong>the</strong> need<br />

for a new amending process was clear, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> process that emerged clearly<br />

embodied principles that rendered it both national <strong>and</strong> federal, (although it was<br />

still held, as Calhoun was later to argue, to leave unanswered ultimate<br />

questions of sovereignty).<br />

Australia <strong>and</strong> Switzerl<strong>and</strong> likewise paid attention to <strong>the</strong> principles behind <strong>the</strong><br />

amending process. At a series of conventions, which took almost a decade,<br />

68


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

Australians devised an amending formula which, it was assumed, would prove<br />

flexible, simple, democratic <strong>and</strong> federal. 19 In Switzerl<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> drafting<br />

committee of <strong>the</strong> 1848 formula (still <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> revisions of 1874 <strong>and</strong><br />

1891), said:<br />

<strong>The</strong> committee proposes to render <strong>the</strong> constitution very easily<br />

amendable because a truly sovereign people must be able to change<br />

its fundamental law whenever it is so inclined ... in order to come into<br />

force, <strong>the</strong> Federal <strong>Constitution</strong> must be accepted by a majority of<br />

Swiss citizenry <strong>and</strong> by <strong>the</strong> majority of <strong>the</strong> Cantons. 20<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian situation was completely different. <strong>The</strong> initial procedural<br />

question was whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> Federal Cabinet could submit its request<br />

directly to Britain, without consulting <strong>and</strong> obtaining <strong>the</strong> consent of <strong>the</strong> national<br />

Parliament. What we got was an amending process that worked quite well in<br />

spite of itself. It was viewed in terms of political expediency. Jennifer Smith<br />

comments that:<br />

... as far as ratification <strong>and</strong> amendment were concerned <strong>the</strong> real<br />

question in both instances was <strong>the</strong> consent required domestically<br />

before <strong>the</strong> British parliament could be requested to act. 21<br />

Amendments were made but we left unresolved <strong>the</strong> debate over sovereignty<br />

which <strong>the</strong> amending problem created. As one shrewd American commentator<br />

has noted:<br />

When <strong>the</strong>re is no agreement on <strong>the</strong> proper allocation of authority, or<br />

(more fundamentally) no agreement on <strong>the</strong> desired level of unity<br />

within a society, as has been <strong>the</strong> case in Canada, agreement on a<br />

wholly satisfactory amendment process becomes impossible ... until<br />

a substantial consensus is reached on <strong>the</strong> underlying question of<br />

nationhood, no satisfactory agreement can be reached on a process of<br />

amendment. 22<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian system changed in some dramatic ways not via amendments but<br />

by judicial interpretation <strong>and</strong> informal federal-provincial agreements. We<br />

seemed to be verifying <strong>the</strong> point made in Livingston’s classic work <strong>Federalism</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change. 23 His assumption that federalism is “a function<br />

not of constitutions but of societies” is well known. Accompanying this is his<br />

view that societies employ what he calls “instrumentalities” to serve <strong>the</strong> needs<br />

of <strong>the</strong>ir diversity. <strong>The</strong>se instrumentalities can be procedures, institutions <strong>and</strong><br />

conventions but he also adds to <strong>the</strong> list concepts, habits <strong>and</strong> attitudes, all of<br />

which serve to “articulate <strong>and</strong> protect <strong>the</strong> diversities that constitute <strong>the</strong> psychosociological<br />

basis of <strong>the</strong> federal community.” 24 Our instrumentalities were<br />

protecting our abeyances <strong>and</strong> our lack of an amending formula.<br />

It was not until <strong>the</strong> aftermath of <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth Conference of 1926 that<br />

we launched <strong>the</strong> first of a series of federal-provincial conferences which<br />

discussed <strong>the</strong> amending problem. <strong>The</strong> 1950 conference actually managed to<br />

reach unanimous agreement of <strong>the</strong> division of <strong>the</strong> constitution into six different<br />

categories each with different rules for change—surely a Canadian approach if<br />

ever <strong>the</strong>re was one.<br />

69


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

In <strong>the</strong>se debates, we were trying to skirt our abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> questions that<br />

came with <strong>the</strong>m: did we subscribe to <strong>the</strong> compact <strong>the</strong>ory; to what extent were<br />

<strong>the</strong> provinces sovereign; should Quebec be treated differently; should any<br />

single province have a constitutional veto; could regional assent be substituted<br />

for a provincial approach; was <strong>the</strong>re to be any popular ratification; who<br />

initiated <strong>the</strong> amending process; could <strong>the</strong>re be opting out; must <strong>the</strong>re be <strong>the</strong><br />

same rules for all; how were we to reconcile popular sovereignty <strong>and</strong><br />

federalism? Thus ra<strong>the</strong>r than arguing about <strong>the</strong> substance of future<br />

amendments, <strong>the</strong> focus switched to <strong>the</strong> process itself. It became “<strong>the</strong> essence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> crisis,” <strong>and</strong> we were subjected “to a series of federal-provincial<br />

conferences which, like <strong>the</strong> woes inflicted on sinners by <strong>the</strong> God of <strong>the</strong> Old<br />

Testament, have lasted unto <strong>the</strong> third <strong>and</strong> fourth generations.” 25<br />

“A Diversity in Ignorance of Itself”<br />

A notable effort to tackle our disinterred <strong>and</strong> emergent abeyances<br />

simultaneously was made in 1979 by <strong>the</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity report<br />

entitled A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r. Better known as <strong>the</strong> Pépin-Robarts Report after its<br />

two co-chairs, it represented an inter-connected <strong>and</strong> comprehensive approach.<br />

Even its critics saw it as well written, succinct <strong>and</strong> willing to tackle deep-seated<br />

problems. Ideas from it, <strong>and</strong> individuals associated with it, have continued to<br />

play a significant part in our on going constitutional saga.<br />

It attempted to deal with dualism, regionalism, <strong>the</strong> functional distribution of<br />

power <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> national government.<br />

We have tried in this report to answer three questions: How do we<br />

secure <strong>the</strong> fuller expression of duality in all <strong>the</strong> spheres to which it<br />

relates? How do we accommodate more satisfactorily <strong>the</strong> forces of<br />

regionalism that are altering <strong>the</strong> face of Canadian society? How do<br />

we make <strong>the</strong> principle of sharing an “operational value” in our<br />

country, <strong>and</strong> within <strong>and</strong> between our governments, so that duality <strong>and</strong><br />

regionalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r features of Canadian life are given<br />

appropriate recognition? 26<br />

It thus came face to face with at least <strong>the</strong> following abeyances:<br />

• <strong>the</strong> constitutional recognition of dualism <strong>and</strong> Quebec’s distinctiveness;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> redistribution of powers;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> need for a legitimizing amending formula in which Quebec’s consent<br />

was required;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> problem of provincial equality <strong>and</strong> symmetry;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> clash between federal <strong>and</strong> parliamentary principles;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> recognition of individual as well as group rights;<br />

• <strong>the</strong> clash between judicial constitutional supremacy <strong>and</strong> democratic<br />

control.<br />

In some respects it appeared to tackle <strong>the</strong>se problems head on. It said of<br />

Quebec that:<br />

70<br />

We support <strong>the</strong> efforts of <strong>the</strong> Quebec provincial government <strong>and</strong> of<br />

<strong>the</strong> people of Quebec to ensure <strong>the</strong> predominance of <strong>the</strong> French<br />

language <strong>and</strong> culture in that province. Quebec is distinctive <strong>and</strong><br />

should, within a viable Canada, have <strong>the</strong> power necessary to protect<br />

<strong>and</strong> develop its distinctive character; any political solution short if<br />

this would lead to <strong>the</strong> rupture of Canada. 27


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

Thus, language policy was to be a provincial matter, counterbalanced by<br />

French/English educational opportunities “where numbers warrant” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

availability of federal services in both languages.<br />

It dealt with <strong>the</strong> parliamentary/federal problem by proposing a totally<br />

restructured Senate modelled on <strong>the</strong> Bundestag, <strong>and</strong> partial proportional<br />

representation for <strong>the</strong> Commons. <strong>The</strong> membership <strong>and</strong> powers of <strong>the</strong> Council<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Federation—as <strong>the</strong> restructured Senate would be called—were set out<br />

clearly; it was to comprise a maximum of 60 delegates “acting under<br />

instruction” from <strong>the</strong> provinces. <strong>The</strong>se were bold <strong>and</strong> sweeping<br />

recommendations that would have had a profound effect. <strong>The</strong> same could be<br />

said of <strong>the</strong>ir approach to <strong>the</strong> amending problem, popular sovereignty<br />

requirements, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Quebec “veto.” Along with passage by <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

Parliament, a four region referendum was proposed, Quebec being one of <strong>the</strong><br />

regions.<br />

Thus, abeyances were tackled in a way that saw <strong>the</strong> proposed solutions closely<br />

linked toge<strong>the</strong>r. At <strong>the</strong> same time, it can be argued that even Pépin-Robarts &<br />

Co. tried to skirt or fudge some of <strong>the</strong> central issues, <strong>and</strong> this was to get <strong>the</strong>m<br />

into hot water. In particular, <strong>the</strong>y tried to defuse <strong>the</strong> asymmetry versus<br />

provincial equality problem, <strong>and</strong> special status for Quebec, by allotting:<br />

... to all provinces powers in <strong>the</strong> areas needed by Quebec to maintain<br />

its distinctive culture <strong>and</strong> heritage, but to do so in a manner which<br />

would enable <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provinces, if <strong>the</strong>y so wished, not to exercise<br />

<strong>the</strong>se responsibilities <strong>and</strong> instead leave <strong>the</strong>m to Ottawa. <strong>The</strong>re are two<br />

methods for achieving this: to place <strong>the</strong>se matters under concurrent<br />

jurisdiction with provincial paramountcy, thus leaving provinces<br />

with <strong>the</strong> option whe<strong>the</strong>r to exercise <strong>the</strong>ir overriding power in <strong>the</strong>se<br />

fields; <strong>and</strong> to provide in <strong>the</strong> constitution a procedure for <strong>the</strong><br />

intergovernmental delegation of legislative powers. In our view both<br />

methods should be used. 28<br />

This particular provision illustrates clearly a desire to see how things will work<br />

out (<strong>and</strong> should sound familiar to us now!). <strong>The</strong>re was a similar vagueness in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir recommendations for a Declaration of Rights which was to include “<strong>the</strong><br />

usual political, legal, economic <strong>and</strong> egalitarian rights.” Such individual <strong>and</strong><br />

collective rights would have to be those “on which <strong>the</strong> central <strong>and</strong> provincial<br />

governments are in agreement.” Yet ano<strong>the</strong>r example of issue avoidance can<br />

be found in <strong>the</strong> discussion of native rights: <strong>the</strong>re is no mention here of native<br />

sovereignty, inherent rights or any of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r dem<strong>and</strong>s now made.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Report’s wise disinclination to provide clarity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> corollary that much<br />

remained to be worked out was, not surprisingly, seen as a major weakness in<br />

<strong>the</strong> document. It could thus be attacked for its concerted attempt to entrench<br />

intra-state federalism, popular sovereignty, <strong>and</strong> a special place for Quebec<br />

<strong>and</strong>, at <strong>the</strong> same time, for its “smorgasbord” of principles <strong>and</strong> criteria, <strong>and</strong> its<br />

p<strong>and</strong>ering to Quebec nationalism <strong>and</strong> regionalism.<br />

Alan Cairns, in a trenchant <strong>and</strong> harsh criticism of <strong>the</strong> overall Report, argued<br />

that <strong>the</strong> provision for concurrency <strong>and</strong> delegation noted above “is capable of<br />

producing two anti<strong>the</strong>tical outcomes at <strong>the</strong> opposite ends of <strong>the</strong> spectrum <strong>and</strong><br />

anything in between.” 29 In o<strong>the</strong>r words, we could have found ourselves, in<br />

future, with an extraordinarily decentralized system due to our desire to paper<br />

over <strong>the</strong> Quebec problem. Cairns also noted, amongst o<strong>the</strong>r things, that <strong>the</strong><br />

71


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Report stressed “what divides us,” it “lacked <strong>the</strong> subtlety necessary to h<strong>and</strong>le<br />

<strong>the</strong> complexities” of <strong>the</strong> national question, it utilized an “ahistorical<br />

approach,” <strong>and</strong> it suffered from “hesitation <strong>and</strong> embarrassment” on <strong>the</strong><br />

question of national identity.<br />

One cannot help but feel sorry for <strong>the</strong> authors. <strong>The</strong>y were trying to tackle<br />

abeyances that had haunted us for years. <strong>The</strong>y were prisoners of a climate of<br />

opinion that was heavily provincialist. First Ministers’ Conferences had come<br />

into <strong>the</strong>ir own. Premiers strutted <strong>the</strong>ir hour upon <strong>the</strong> stage, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> entire<br />

Pépin-Robarts Report was premised on <strong>the</strong> notion that with respect to powers<br />

<strong>the</strong>re must be “equality of status of <strong>the</strong> central <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> provincial orders of<br />

government.” 30<br />

In Pépin-Robarts, a revised <strong>and</strong> subtle version of <strong>the</strong> compact <strong>the</strong>ory had<br />

wrestled with <strong>the</strong> questions of inter- <strong>and</strong> intra-state federalism, pan-<br />

Canadianism, dualism, individual rights <strong>and</strong> founding nations. Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not<br />

Pépin-Robarts was a noble effort doomed to failure, a constitution that could<br />

have grown <strong>and</strong> matured but was strangled at birth, or a vision that was fatally<br />

flawed <strong>and</strong> rife with contradictions, became irrelevant. <strong>The</strong> Unity Task Force<br />

had tried—how it had tried—to solve <strong>the</strong>se problems imaginatively <strong>and</strong><br />

constructively, in <strong>the</strong> light of socio-political realities as well as constitutional<br />

principles. Certainly, if one considers what has happened since <strong>the</strong>ir report<br />

appeared, it is difficult to argue that we have done any better.<br />

A <strong>Constitution</strong> with Crystal Clear Principles<br />

When Pierre Trudeau returned to power in 1980, Pépin-Robarts, <strong>and</strong> its search<br />

for a “third option,” lay neglected <strong>and</strong> disparaged. Trudeau’s agenda was very<br />

different. It was to be an irony, a paradox, that Trudeau <strong>the</strong> pragmatist—<strong>the</strong><br />

cool, clear, cerebral anti-nationalist, <strong>the</strong> defender of incrementalism <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

need to establish our national identity so that it could accommodate<br />

Quebec—should end up pushing through an amending formula <strong>and</strong> a charter<br />

that forced our abeyances into <strong>the</strong> open <strong>and</strong> created new <strong>and</strong> fundamental<br />

tensions in <strong>the</strong> state.<br />

Trudeau was ra<strong>the</strong>r like <strong>the</strong> Charles I portrayed by Foley. Trudeau also had a<br />

strict legality on his side, had little regard for <strong>the</strong> legislature, was not prepared<br />

to let sleeping issues lie <strong>and</strong> was convinced, not without reason, that his logic<br />

<strong>and</strong> clarity of vision were superior to those of his opponents. In fairness, he had<br />

to act as a result of <strong>the</strong> promises made during <strong>the</strong> referendum of 1980. Once<br />

Quebec had pushed its way out of its own protective cocoon <strong>and</strong> had seen itself<br />

as an actor on a larger stage (to mix metaphors) notions such as abeyances or<br />

“stops in <strong>the</strong> mind” became almost impossible to h<strong>and</strong>le.<br />

But now <strong>the</strong> Quebec abeyance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> amending abeyance became <strong>the</strong> focal<br />

point for what Foley has called o<strong>the</strong>r “deeply embedded disjunctions.” A<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned West, led by a powerful Alberta premier, was willing to fight for<br />

provincial equality as were o<strong>the</strong>r premiers. Trudeau was adamantly committed<br />

to a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights, to official bilingualism, to streng<strong>the</strong>ning Federal<br />

institutions <strong>and</strong> to a recognition of multiculturalism. His desire for<br />

constitutional coherence, his inability <strong>and</strong> unwillingness to accept <strong>the</strong> coexistence<br />

of (seemingly) irreconcilable positions, <strong>and</strong> his acceptance of<br />

provincial equality, constituted <strong>the</strong> anti<strong>the</strong>sis of a reliance on obfuscation <strong>and</strong><br />

avoidance. In his criticism of this approach, Guy <strong>La</strong>Forest uses “Foleyian”<br />

terminology when he argues that:<br />

72


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

My point here, simply put, is that <strong>the</strong>se checks, ambiguities, <strong>and</strong><br />

blurred sovereignties between visions were necessary to <strong>the</strong><br />

flourishing of complex federalism in Canada. When all this is<br />

discarded in favour of a constitution with crystal clear principles...<br />

<strong>the</strong> very nature of our federalism becomes threatened <strong>and</strong> so does<br />

Canada. 31<br />

Many of <strong>the</strong>se issues were not new, but this time <strong>the</strong>re was a difference; <strong>the</strong>re<br />

was a Prime Minister willing to go it alone, a federal government able to claim<br />

its own Quebec m<strong>and</strong>ate, a separatist government in Quebec emasculated by<br />

<strong>the</strong> referendum of 1980, <strong>and</strong>, ga<strong>the</strong>ring force on <strong>the</strong> fringes of <strong>the</strong> debate, a<br />

growing assembly of new constitutional players pushing for change if <strong>the</strong><br />

opportunity arose.<br />

Would we have been better off opting for as limited a constitutional package as<br />

possible? Was <strong>the</strong>re a chance in <strong>the</strong> autumn <strong>and</strong> winter of 1981-82 that we<br />

could have muddled through <strong>and</strong> tolerated ambiguity? It must be admitted that,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>and</strong> now, <strong>the</strong>re is a strong case to be made for <strong>the</strong> view that constitution<br />

making does indeed require a st<strong>and</strong> on principles, for some fundamental<br />

questions cannot be ignored.<br />

But we ended up with constitutional arrangements that have made our<br />

abeyances all too apparent. Behind <strong>the</strong> oddities of <strong>the</strong> amending formulae,<br />

such as <strong>the</strong> extent of <strong>the</strong> unanimity rule, <strong>the</strong> acknowledged provincial right of<br />

rescission, <strong>the</strong> three-year time limit <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> inability to co-ordinate legislative<br />

amendment or approval, lie even larger questions. 32<br />

It could, perhaps, be argued that in 1982 certain abeyances were left alone.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re was no attempt to define Quebec’s role <strong>and</strong> place in <strong>the</strong> scheme of<br />

things. <strong>The</strong> operation of First Ministers’ Conferences was left unclear. Native<br />

claims to sovereignty were ignored. Citizens were not given a constitutional<br />

role. Never<strong>the</strong>less, we still ended up with changes that led to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong><br />

to Charlottetown, <strong>and</strong> which juxtaposed our former abeyances in ways that<br />

make <strong>the</strong>m extremely difficult to h<strong>and</strong>le.<br />

Unsettled Settlement<br />

What can be said in conclusion? Is <strong>the</strong>re hope that we can take some of our<br />

abeyances off <strong>the</strong> table? <strong>The</strong> Trudeau legacy has been extraordinary, <strong>and</strong> his<br />

view of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> has taken hold. His interventions in defence of his<br />

endeavours have been decisive. Well-known scholars can now proclaim that<br />

<strong>the</strong> end of our constitutional journey is in sight:<br />

Canada is, de facto, now a republic; <strong>the</strong> people of Canada are<br />

sovereign. Sooner or later, by law or by convention, Canada’s<br />

constitution will reflect both those realities de jure. So too will its<br />

legislators <strong>and</strong> courts. 33<br />

To argue thus assumes that our deepest abeyances are now being laid to rest:<br />

like old soldiers, <strong>the</strong>y will just fade away. Our political <strong>and</strong> constitutional<br />

culture will have changed; even Quebec, in this view, could become<br />

“charterized.” <strong>The</strong> new, demarcated, ascertainable, liberal-democratic rules of<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional <strong>and</strong> political game are seen as in place, buttressed by<br />

referendum-rooted popular sovereignty <strong>and</strong> by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> itself.<br />

73


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

This optimistic view does not accord with <strong>the</strong> recognition of <strong>the</strong> importance of<br />

abeyances. It can be argued that <strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accords, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> referendum process itself, demonstrated clearly that we have<br />

not come to terms with <strong>the</strong> idea of <strong>the</strong> need for abeyances in a general sense, or<br />

with <strong>the</strong> specific, dormant dangers we have pushed <strong>and</strong> prodded out of <strong>the</strong><br />

interstitial constitutional caves where <strong>the</strong>y were hibernating.<br />

Let us remind ourselves that Foley’s <strong>the</strong>sis holds that gaps of significant<br />

constitutional unsettlement are marks of maturity <strong>and</strong> a source of considerable<br />

strength; that constitutional incoherence can be a positive <strong>and</strong> necessary value;<br />

that legal precision is less desirable than social consensus <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> willingness<br />

to turn a blind eye to our idiosyncrasies. <strong>Constitution</strong>al cowardice is a virtue:<br />

we live to fight ano<strong>the</strong>r day.<br />

Are we prepared <strong>and</strong> able to turn our backs on <strong>the</strong> very real <strong>and</strong> dangerous<br />

sources of conflict that have surfaced so dramatically since 1982? Do we have<br />

<strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> political skills, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> leadership, to h<strong>and</strong>le our constitutional<br />

unsettlement? Will our institutional mechanisms permit us to change even if<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is widespread support for so doing?<br />

<strong>The</strong> attempt, in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, to constitutionalize Quebec’s<br />

distinctiveness, illustrates all of <strong>the</strong>se problems. Meech was an effort to go<br />

beyond de facto or implicit recognition34 that <strong>the</strong> two founding nations view<br />

“was <strong>the</strong> only form in which confederation would be ultimately acceptable to<br />

French Canada.” 35 Meech was an attempt to set it down on paper, <strong>and</strong> people<br />

wanted to know exactly what it meant. At <strong>the</strong> same time, it was raising an<br />

abeyance that was now symbolically tied to o<strong>the</strong>r intractable questions. In<br />

Patrick Monahan’s view:<br />

... (<strong>the</strong>) symbolic messages associated with <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause<br />

provide <strong>the</strong> most powerful explanation of its massive unpopularity<br />

outside of Quebec. 36<br />

Survey data on <strong>the</strong> October referendum now show that, once again, <strong>the</strong> most<br />

important issue, outside Quebec, was that Quebec was seen as getting too<br />

much. Inevitably, in Meech <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown, o<strong>the</strong>r abeyances came into<br />

play, particularly those surrounding <strong>the</strong> question of provincial equality,<br />

affecting both <strong>the</strong> amending formula, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposals for a Triple E Senate.<br />

Many seemed surprised to find out that raising what was seen as a straightforward<br />

federal principle, namely <strong>the</strong> political equality of disparate geopolitical<br />

units in a second house, trailed in its wake such a host of deep<br />

problems, old <strong>and</strong> new. Less of a surprise, perhaps, was <strong>the</strong> clash of principles<br />

surrounding who we are as citizens, <strong>and</strong> how we are to be treated, individually<br />

<strong>and</strong> collectively. <strong>The</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se questions, too, were once abeyances is<br />

revealed by Charles Taylor’s comment that in this debate over what constitutes<br />

a liberal society “aspirations which are as such perfectly compatible come to<br />

be seen as deadly rivals.” 37<br />

<strong>The</strong> left has a great deal of difficulty coming to terms with <strong>the</strong>se issues38 <strong>and</strong>,<br />

on <strong>the</strong> right, in <strong>the</strong> shape of <strong>the</strong> Reform Party, one finds certitude. Populist<br />

diagnoses seem inherently intolerant of abeyances. When Preston Manning<br />

speaks of his “New Canada” he is talking of a country that will operate<br />

according to a few seemingly straightforward principles: we will all be equal;<br />

we will all be treated equally; <strong>the</strong>re will not be a need for hyphenated<br />

Canadianism; <strong>the</strong> provinces will be equal; <strong>and</strong> our institutions will be<br />

74


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

reformed. Manning’s populism seeks to find simple answers to complex<br />

problems, <strong>and</strong> prudence is not an adjective that comes to mind in this context.<br />

Populists dislike ambiguity <strong>and</strong> equivocation, <strong>and</strong> because of that <strong>the</strong>y do not<br />

want “suspended irresolution.” Supporters see in <strong>the</strong> Reform Party <strong>the</strong> answers<br />

to what bo<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>the</strong>y want politicians to listen <strong>and</strong> be accountable to <strong>the</strong><br />

electorate, to stop p<strong>and</strong>ering to Quebec, <strong>and</strong> to stop wasting <strong>the</strong> taxpayers’<br />

money.<br />

Populism dem<strong>and</strong>s referendums, but because abeyances are “<strong>the</strong> product of<br />

long historical experience <strong>and</strong> accumulated practice of which <strong>the</strong> public is but<br />

dimly aware,” 39 <strong>the</strong>y are exceptionally difficult to deal with during a<br />

referendum campaign. <strong>The</strong> fact that a referendum was used would seem to be a<br />

vindication of <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> is an affair, ultimately, of citizens<br />

<strong>and</strong> not governments. It would thus seem to settle a longst<strong>and</strong>ing abeyance <strong>and</strong><br />

overturn <strong>the</strong> predominance of governments <strong>and</strong> of executive federalism<br />

established by <strong>the</strong> amending formulae. Matters are not this simple.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fundamental incompatibilities of <strong>the</strong> 1982 arrangements have not given<br />

way to clarity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> referendum was, in certain key ways, not an act of<br />

national public affirmation; it was a new version of inter-state federalism in<br />

which provincialized communities, ra<strong>the</strong>r than governments, spoke for<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves. It was precipitated by pre-emptive referendum legislation in three<br />

provinces: Quebec, Alberta <strong>and</strong> British Columbia. It is no coincidence that<br />

<strong>the</strong>se three provinces soundly rejected <strong>the</strong> Accord. We tackled, in part, what<br />

Jennifer Smith has called <strong>the</strong> problem of constituting power: “Process—not<br />

any process, but one that embodies consent requirements—replaces<br />

sovereignty,” 40 (i.e., as <strong>the</strong> key issue). But what has been added is <strong>the</strong><br />

provincial equality abeyance in a new guise. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, if we are to use<br />

referendums in <strong>the</strong> future “how are we to avoid drawing abeyances into <strong>the</strong><br />

public debate? How do we avoid spelling out what we know cannot be spelled<br />

out?” 41 Our old mechanisms of elite accommodation were, it would appear, by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir very nature inherently tolerant of abeyances. Consensus was to be<br />

produced due to a common desire to maintain <strong>the</strong> system <strong>and</strong> avoid undue<br />

fragmentation, whilst accommodating divergent interests <strong>and</strong> subcultures.<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al affairs were dealt with in an ordinary political way.<br />

Ra<strong>the</strong>r than being content with <strong>the</strong> virtues of “settled unsettlement,” we have<br />

got instead “unsettled settlement” of some things, <strong>and</strong> no settlement at all of a<br />

long list of o<strong>the</strong>r items, driven as <strong>the</strong>y are by political crises, values,<br />

personalities <strong>and</strong> great social <strong>and</strong> demographic change. While <strong>the</strong> rest of<br />

Canada’s values have been changing, in Quebec, in yet ano<strong>the</strong>r paradox,<br />

devotion to British traditions of representative government <strong>and</strong><br />

parliamentarianism have, if anything, increased. We have Quebec scholars<br />

who would normally “prefer specificity in constitutional matters” 42 now<br />

arguing that vagueness is desirable <strong>and</strong> that a clear vision is dangerous.<br />

Christian Dufour puts <strong>the</strong> point thus:<br />

Beyond <strong>the</strong> reality of <strong>the</strong> country, beyond <strong>the</strong> ideal, Canada is<br />

foundering in an idealism, in an ideology of <strong>the</strong> ideal, that is<br />

constraining <strong>and</strong> compulsory. This is not surprising: in politics<br />

idealism corresponds to losing touch with reality. It results from an<br />

inability to integrate some aspects of that reality. 43<br />

75


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

In sum, events from Pépin-Robarts to Charlottetown reveal how deep our<br />

“disjunctions” are (<strong>and</strong> even so, <strong>the</strong>re are still abeyances left untouched, such<br />

as those surrounding responsible government).<br />

To ask, in conclusion, whe<strong>the</strong>r we can get at least some of our key abeyances<br />

under control is to try to forecast <strong>the</strong> future. This is dangerous terrain. <strong>The</strong><br />

vagaries of <strong>the</strong> moment, <strong>and</strong> our own hopes <strong>and</strong> fears, can turn scholars into<br />

journalists; trying to gain a perspective on our past is difficult enough. Even so,<br />

if we accept <strong>the</strong> idea of abeyances, <strong>the</strong>ir role <strong>and</strong> crucial importance, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

usefulness of <strong>the</strong> concept in putting our macro-constitutional debate into a<br />

new, comparative perspective, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> question of how we are to h<strong>and</strong>le <strong>the</strong>m<br />

cannot be avoided.<br />

It may be that <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>the</strong> referendum, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> process itself, have made<br />

us realize how far apart we are. We might come to take a more resolutely Tory<br />

view of our living, evolving <strong>Constitution</strong> with its areas of contradiction <strong>and</strong><br />

imprecision, although when we were given <strong>the</strong> opportunity, in Meech, to<br />

obfuscate on “distinct society” <strong>and</strong> pass <strong>the</strong> buck to <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court, we did<br />

not take it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> metaphors of marriage <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> family have often been used to describe <strong>the</strong><br />

Quebec-“Rest of Canada” relationship. Such metaphors seem particularly<br />

applicable to abeyances. In most longst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> successful relationships<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are, (in Foleyian terms), “underst<strong>and</strong>ings”; <strong>the</strong>re is “suspended<br />

irresolution” of some matters; <strong>the</strong>re are “conventions of non-exposure”; <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>re is “complicity in delusion” so that we can, quite simply, continue to get<br />

along with each o<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong>re may well be an increasing realization of this in<br />

Quebec, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong> country.<br />

<strong>The</strong> one abeyance that might be uncoupled from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs is <strong>the</strong> question of<br />

aboriginal rights. <strong>The</strong>re could be sufficient public support for this, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

work of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples could set <strong>the</strong> scene. To<br />

say this is to be optimistic. Finally, we might hope for new <strong>and</strong> creative<br />

leadership, greater tolerance, more imagination <strong>and</strong> less certitude as we try to<br />

break free of “<strong>the</strong> late modern century.” 44 New abeyances can flourish <strong>and</strong><br />

assimilate diverse principles if we let <strong>the</strong>m do so, but first <strong>the</strong>re are grave areas<br />

of “unsettled settlement” to resolve.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Pierre Elliott Trudeau, “<strong>Federalism</strong>, Nationalism <strong>and</strong> Reason” in <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> French<br />

Canadians (Toronto: Macmillan & Company, Ltd., 1968).<br />

2. Pierre Elliott Trudeau, “Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Problem” in <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

French Canadians, op. cit., 36. Trudeau has repeated this point of view recently in his<br />

pamphlet “Fatal Tilt: Speaking Out About Sovereignty” (Toronto: Harper Collins<br />

Publishers, 1991), 14-15. He states: “I am on record since <strong>the</strong> mid-sixties as having pointed<br />

out <strong>the</strong> dangers of embarking on a constitutional voyage when <strong>the</strong> virus of consititutionitis<br />

had begun to infect <strong>the</strong> ship of state. But <strong>the</strong> provinces took matters into <strong>the</strong>ir own h<strong>and</strong>s in<br />

1967 ... surely <strong>the</strong> federal government had no choice but to accept <strong>the</strong> challenge <strong>and</strong> sail on.”<br />

3. Canada, Task Force on Canadian Unity, A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Observations <strong>and</strong><br />

Recommendations (Ottawa: Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada, 1979).<br />

4. See Cristine Andrea Beauvais De Clercy, “Holding H<strong>and</strong>s with <strong>the</strong> Public: Trudeau <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Task Force on Canadian Unity, 1977-79.” Unpublished M.A. <strong>The</strong>sis, University of<br />

Saskatchewan, 1992.<br />

5. Note in particular <strong>the</strong> discussion of <strong>the</strong> ironies of <strong>the</strong> Trudeau legacy in Kenneth McRoberts,<br />

English Canada <strong>and</strong> Quebec: Avoiding <strong>the</strong> Issue (York: Robarts Centre for <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Studies, 1991).<br />

76


Turning a Blind Eye:<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Abeyances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Experience<br />

6. Charles Taylor has presented a case for <strong>the</strong> recognition of what he calls second level or<br />

“deep” diversity. See his “Shared <strong>and</strong> Divergent Values,” a paper prepared for <strong>the</strong> Business<br />

Council on National Issues Symposium on Canada’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Options (Toronto,<br />

January, 1991), <strong>and</strong> his brief but important remarks regarding “<strong>The</strong> Politics of Recognition”<br />

in Douglas Brown, Robert Young, <strong>and</strong> Dwight Herberger, (eds.), <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Commentaries: An Assessment of <strong>the</strong> 1991 Federal Proposal. (Kingston: Institute of<br />

Intergovernmental Relations, conference paper number 10, 1991).<br />

7. See Robert C. Vipond, Liberty <strong>and</strong> Community: Canadian <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Failure of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1991). Note also Janet Ajzenstat<br />

(ed.) Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>alism 1791-1991 (Ottawa: Canadian Study of Parliament<br />

Group, 1992). This collection of essays “illustrates <strong>the</strong> origins <strong>and</strong> contours of <strong>the</strong> quarrel<br />

between <strong>Constitution</strong>alists <strong>and</strong> Communitarians that underlies today’s debate on<br />

constitutional reform.”<br />

8. Peter H. Russell, “Can <strong>the</strong> Canadians Be a Sovereign People,” Presidential Address to <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian Political Science Association (Kingston: Queen’s University, 1991), reported in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian Journal of Political Science, 24 (1991), 691-709.<br />

9. Ibid., 699-700.<br />

10. Alan C. Cairns, “<strong>The</strong> Living Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>” in Blair <strong>and</strong> McLeod (eds.), <strong>The</strong><br />

Canadian Political Tradition (Toronto: Methuen, 1987), 11.<br />

11. Alan C. Cairns, “Recent Federalist <strong>Constitution</strong>al Proposals” in Douglas E. Williams (ed.),<br />

Disruptions: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Struggles form <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke (Toronto:<br />

McClell<strong>and</strong>, Stewart, 1991), 57.<br />

12. Michael Foley, <strong>The</strong> Silence of <strong>Constitution</strong>s (London: Routledge, 1989).<br />

13. Ibid., 9.<br />

14. See Andrew Heard, Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conventions: <strong>The</strong> Marriage of <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong><br />

Politics (Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1991), ch. 7.<br />

15. Foley, op. cit., XI.<br />

16. Ibid., 126.<br />

17. Ibid., 119. See chapters three <strong>and</strong> five for a detailed discussion of British <strong>and</strong> American<br />

experience.<br />

18. See D.V. Smiley’s comment that “I can find only two major <strong>and</strong> important sets of<br />

suggestions for basic constitutional change prior to <strong>the</strong> 1960s: <strong>the</strong> report emanating from <strong>the</strong><br />

interprovincial conferences of 1887, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> highly structuralist thrust of <strong>the</strong> proposals of <strong>the</strong><br />

League for Social Reconstruction in 1935.” This is attached as a footnote to “A Dangerous<br />

Deed: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982” in Banting <strong>and</strong> Simeon And No One Cheered:<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong>, Democracy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, (Toronto, Methuen, 1983), 94.<br />

19. In Peter Russell’s view “Australia’s founding fa<strong>the</strong>rs, it would seem, were more committed<br />

federalists than Canada’s. Certainly <strong>the</strong>y knew more about federalism”. See “<strong>The</strong> Politics of<br />

Frustration; <strong>The</strong> pursuit of Formal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change in Australia <strong>and</strong> Canada” in<br />

Hodgins, Eddy, Grant <strong>and</strong> Stru<strong>the</strong>rs (eds.), <strong>Federalism</strong> in Canada <strong>and</strong> Australia: Historical<br />

Perspectives, 1920-88 (Peterborough: Trent University, 1989), 59. In practice it should be<br />

noted that this formula hasn’t been that flexible: only eight out of 42 proposed amendments<br />

have passed.<br />

20. For a classic <strong>and</strong> still extremely useful analysis of <strong>the</strong> amending problem in federal societies<br />

<strong>and</strong> states see W.S. Livingston, <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change, (Oxford: Clarendon<br />

Press, 1956), 178. This quote is used by Livingston in his discussion of <strong>the</strong> Swiss experience.<br />

21. Jennifer Smith, “Canadian Confederation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Influence of American <strong>Federalism</strong>,”<br />

Canadian Journal of Political Science, 21 (1988), 459.<br />

22. Walter Dellinger, “<strong>The</strong> Amending Process in Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States: A Comparative<br />

Perspective” in Davenport <strong>and</strong> Leach (eds.), Reshaping Confederation: <strong>The</strong> 1982 Reform of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> (Durham, Duke University Centre for International Studies, 1984), 286.<br />

23. Livingston, op. cit.<br />

24. Ibid., 305.<br />

25. Garth Stevenson, Unfulfilled Union. (Canada: Gage, 1989), 239. Stevenson unleashes a<br />

stinging criticism of <strong>the</strong> 1982 agreement, saying that “<strong>the</strong> ‘new’ Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> was<br />

an untidy collection of miscellaneous provisions reflecting sordid <strong>and</strong> undignified<br />

compromises with a variety of provincial interests,” 238.<br />

26. A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r, op. cit., 41.<br />

77


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

27. Ibid., 87.<br />

28. Ibid.<br />

29. Alan C. Cairns, “Recent Federalist <strong>Constitution</strong>al Proposals,” op. cit., 53.<br />

30. A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r, op. cit., 125.<br />

31. Guy <strong>La</strong>forest, “Interpreting <strong>the</strong> Political Heritage of André <strong>La</strong>urendeau” in Smith,<br />

Mackinnon <strong>and</strong> Courtney (eds.), After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: Lessons for <strong>the</strong> Future (Saskatoon: Fifth<br />

House Publishers, 1991), 102.<br />

32. See Alan C. Cairns, <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong>: <strong>The</strong> Dilemmas of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform<br />

(Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1992), ch. 3.<br />

33. David J. Bercuson <strong>and</strong> Barry Cooper, “From <strong>Constitution</strong>al Monarchy to Quasi Republic:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Evolution of Liberal Democracy in Canada” in Ajzenstat, op. cit., 27.<br />

34. Christopher Dunn in fact uses <strong>the</strong> phrase “<strong>the</strong> silence of <strong>the</strong> constitution” to explain<br />

Quebec’s de facto acquisition of power. See “Do Canada <strong>and</strong> Quebec Need Each O<strong>the</strong>r,”<br />

paper presented at <strong>the</strong> Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science Association,<br />

(Kingston: Queen’s University, 1991), 13.<br />

35. See Taylor, “Divergent Values,” op. cit., 16.<br />

36. Patrick Monahan, Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: <strong>The</strong> Inside Story (Toronto: University of Toronto Press,<br />

1991), 258.<br />

37. Taylor, “Divergent Values,” op. cit., 31. Taylor lists aspirations which should be<br />

compatible: duality <strong>and</strong> multiculturalism; aboriginal <strong>and</strong> Quebec claims to distinctiveness;<br />

regional equality <strong>and</strong> Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

38. A useful discussion of this problem is to be found in Serge Denis, Le Long Malentendu: Le<br />

Québec vu par les intellectuels progressistes au Canada anglais 1970-1991 (Québec: Les<br />

Éditions du Boréal, 1992).<br />

39. Roger Gibbins <strong>and</strong> David Thomas “Ten Lessons from <strong>the</strong> Referendum,” Canadian<br />

Parliamentary Review, vol. 15, No. 4. 1992-3, 6.<br />

40. See Jennifer Smith, “Representation <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform in Canada” in Smith,<br />

Mackinnon, Courtney (eds.), After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, op. cit., 78.<br />

41. Gibbins <strong>and</strong> Thomas, op. cit.<br />

42. Dunn, op. cit., 4.<br />

43. Christian Dufour, “A Canadian Challenge / Le défi québécois,” (<strong>La</strong>nzantville, B.C. <strong>and</strong><br />

Halifax, N.S.: Oolichan Books <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Institute for Research on Public Policy, 1990), 145.<br />

44. See Ged Martin’s optimistic conclusion in “<strong>The</strong> Canadian Question <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>La</strong>te Modern<br />

Century,” British Journal of Canadian Studies, vol. 7, No. 2 (1992), 215-247.<br />

78


Richard <strong>La</strong>Rue<br />

Jocelyn Létourneau<br />

De l’unité et de l’identité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un état<br />

Résumé<br />

Comment expliquer les déchirements de tous ordres qui font craindre<br />

aujourd’hui l’éclatement du Canada ? Essentiellement soucieux des<br />

tendances lourdes qui semblent pousser à la désagrégation de l’unité politique<br />

et de l’identité collective, les auteurs estiment que certains aspects du<br />

postkeynésiannisme qui caractérisent le pays entraînent une crise virtuelle sur<br />

les plans de la représentation, de la légitimation et de la régulation. Par<br />

ailleurs, cette crise serait exacerbée et infléchie diversement par trois facteurs<br />

structurels : l’épuisement du modèle politique; l’irruption de la mondialité au<br />

coeur du projet nationalitaire; et la fin des gr<strong>and</strong>s récits collectifs. Bref, cet<br />

article propose une problématique générale qui permet d’examiner dans une<br />

optique macroscopique la phase actuelle du « problème canadien ».<br />

Abstract<br />

How can we explain <strong>the</strong> divisions of every description that now threaten to<br />

rend Canada asunder? Mindful of <strong>the</strong> weighty trends that seem to be pushing<br />

toward <strong>the</strong> dissolution of political unity <strong>and</strong> collective identity, <strong>the</strong> authors<br />

believe that some of <strong>the</strong> country’s post-Keynesian characteristics are leading<br />

to a virtual crisis in representation, legitimation <strong>and</strong> regulation. As well, this<br />

crisis seems variously exacerbated <strong>and</strong> altered by three structural factors: <strong>the</strong><br />

bankruptcy of <strong>the</strong> political model; <strong>the</strong> intrusion of globalization into <strong>the</strong> heart<br />

of <strong>the</strong> national plan; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> great collective narratives. In short, this<br />

article describes a general situation that allows for a macroscopic<br />

examination of <strong>the</strong> current phase of <strong>the</strong> “Canadian problem.”<br />

Depuis sa fondation en 1867, le Canada a été marqué par des tendances à<br />

l’éclatement profondes, permanentes et invariablement vécues sous la forme<br />

de crises d’unité et d’identité. Il serait d’ailleurs instructif de se dem<strong>and</strong>er<br />

pourquoi, malgré les risques de rupture dont il a été le théâtre tout au long de<br />

son histoire, le Canada a su perdurer en tant qu’état national. En fait, la<br />

production de l’unité et de l’identité au Canada est un problème fondamental<br />

qui s’inscrit au coeur même du devenir de cet état, et les tergiversations<br />

récentes sur la question constitutionnelle n’ont fait que traduire un nouveau<br />

moment du processus pénible et perpétuel de la recherche d’une forme de<br />

régulation, de légitimation et de représentation politique qui satisfasse les<br />

aspirations de tous les groupes de la société canadienne.<br />

Cela dit, en dépit du fait que le problème de l’unité et de l’identité canadiennes<br />

soit, à cet état, structurel, sa nature est historiquement changeante, et sa facture<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

actuelle, ainsi que ses causes, ne sont plus les mêmes. Aussi paraît-il pertinent<br />

de s’interroger sur les facteurs qui, dans la présente conjoncture, favorisent<br />

l’éclatement de l’union.<br />

À cet égard, deux options sont ouvertes : nous en tenir à une analyse<br />

synchronique du débat compliqué qui, depuis le rapatriement de la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> en 1982, marque l’horizon politique canadien et, par ce biais,<br />

nous livrer à une évaluation des différentes stratégies employées par les<br />

acteurs en présence pour parvenir à leurs fins; ou, à travers une perspective<br />

diachronique, identifier un certain nombre de « tendances lourdes » qui,<br />

s’inscrivant au coeur du devenir historique de l’état canadien, posent les<br />

conditions actuelles de sa rupture « par le haut » et « par le bas ». Nous<br />

préconiserons cette seconde option en essayant de faire ressortir comment le<br />

Canada vit au fond un problème que partagent à des degrés divers nombre<br />

d’états contemporains1 : la production des sujets politiques dans les sociétés<br />

postkeynésiennes, c’est-à-dire le problème de la recherche d’une concordance<br />

entre l’unité et l’identité de la société à une époque d’inflexion et d’altération<br />

significatives des principes d’organisation et des modes d’action formels,<br />

sociaux et politiques, qui étaient propres aux états marqués et définis par ce que<br />

certains ont appelé la « régulation monopoliste » 2 — et dont le Canada était un<br />

exemple parmi bien d’autres.<br />

Dans le cadre de cet article, nous nous limiterons à présenter trois facteurs<br />

majeurs qui affectent la production de l’unité et de l’identité canadiennes en<br />

ces temps troubles et qui, ce faisant, provoquent une crise des modes de<br />

régulation, de légitimation et de représentation à l’oeuvre au sein de cet état.<br />

Avant d’en arriver là, nous formulerons cependant quelques éléments d’une<br />

problématique concernant la production des sujets politiques dans les sociétés<br />

postkeynésiennes. Pour nous interroger ensuite sur les changements et les<br />

altérations qui ont affecté le Canada à un point tel que l’on puisse en parler<br />

comme d’un état postkeynésien.<br />

Des sujets politiques dans les sociétés postkeynésiennes<br />

Dans notre esprit, le keynésiannisme ne désigne pas seulement un mode<br />

d’intégration économique des travailleurs-consommateurs dans la dynamique<br />

générale d’un régime d’accumulation du capital. Il renvoie aussi à un mode de<br />

production des sujets politiques dans lequel ceux-ci, définis en tant qu’acteurs<br />

normalisés — « comme lieu d’une synthèse identitaire unique, irréductible et<br />

absolue » — cautionnent réciproquement leurs agirs par l’acceptation des<br />

termes d’un contrat sociopolitique dont le fiduciaire et le légataire unique est<br />

l’État. Vendant en quelque sorte leur « personne privée » en contrepartie d’une<br />

identité octroyée, celle de la « personne civile », qui les assure d’une<br />

couverture tout risque (filet de la sécurité sociale) accordée par un État<br />

providentiel et bienfaiteur, les sujets politiques, en honorant les termes du<br />

contrat, s’assurent également les privilèges d’une reconnaissance et d’un<br />

endossement officiels, ceux que leur procure la nation dans laquelle ils<br />

trouvent en outre, par décret, « ancienneté » (celle-ci confondant allègrement<br />

la tradition), c’est-à-dire histoire et mémoire.<br />

<strong>La</strong> notion de postkeynésiannisme, à laquelle nous n’accolons aucun statut<br />

théorique mais que nous voulons essentiellement descriptive, cherche à<br />

résumer et à décrire certaines inflexions ou dissolutions des principes et des<br />

modes d’action formels de l’état keynésien, de même que l’altération des<br />

formes d’identité politique dominante prévalant en son sein. On pourrait<br />

82


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

longuement discuter pour savoir si le postkeynésiannisme marque une rupture<br />

ou une altération, une inflexion ou une accentuation, une intensification ou une<br />

hypertrophisation, une sophistication ou une stylisation, une radicalisation ou<br />

une exacerbation des formes politico-sociales propres au keynésiannisme.<br />

Disons qu’il est probablement tout cela à la fois, qu’il est vulnérable aux<br />

interfaces et qu’il n’échappe pas à la logique convulsive et paradoxale de<br />

l’évolution des choses. Les tendances centrifuges que l’on dit être<br />

caractéristiques du postkeynésiannisme étaient certainement déjà présentes,<br />

contenues à l’« état de possible », dans le keynésiannisme et les décentrements<br />

à l’oeuvre dans tous les pores du tissu de la société canadienne traduisent une<br />

crise — à moins que ce ne soit une mutation encore inachevée — des formes<br />

régulatrices qui agissaient au sein de la société keynésienne (envisagée ici<br />

comme un idéal-type) et qui contribuaient à la structurer en tant qu’entité<br />

productrice de puissants effets de recentrement, de massification et de<br />

nivellement.<br />

Cela dit, la question principale qui nous occupe dans le cadre de cet article est<br />

la suivante : si on postule que le postkeynésiannisme marque une transition par<br />

rapport au keynésiannisme au plan de la régulation, de la légitimation et de la<br />

représentation, quelle est, dans ce nouveau contexte, la forme existentielle que<br />

prend le sujet politique ? En d’autres termes, comment s’établit (ou ne s’établit<br />

pas encore) la concordance entre l’unité et l’identité dans la société<br />

postkeynésienne ?<br />

Pour répondre à cette question, nous profiterons de la réflexion de Michel<br />

Freitag qui, toutefois, parle plus volontiers de postmodernité que de<br />

postkeynésiannisme3. On dira ainsi que, dans la société postkeynésienne, le<br />

sujet politique est d’abord un individu qui, conscient de son identité subjective<br />

et l’assumant, cherche à l’accréditer, l’asseoir, la promouvoir et la réaliser<br />

dans toute l’extension que lui permet son inscription dans un corps social. Il y<br />

entretient des relations d’intérêts avec d’autres individus dans le cadre de<br />

mouvements sociaux fondant leur existence dans le partage d’un certain<br />

nombre de valeurs, de modèles culturels ou civilisationnels et de caractères<br />

particuliers. Il faut souligner ici l’importance de ces mouvements sociaux qui,<br />

certes, ne sont pas apparus récemment mais dont l’émergence comme force<br />

politique a considérablement changé les modalités d’expression de la<br />

citoyenneté dans la société civile. Dans la mesure où, nous dit Freitag, ces<br />

mouvements sociaux expriment la consolidation organisationnelle de toutes<br />

sortes d’intérêts particuliers (de nature corporative) qui acquièrent un statut<br />

officiel à travers leur reconnaissance publique, judiciaire et médiatique, on a<br />

vu s’instaurer un décalage croissant entre, d’un côté, l’universalisme<br />

transcendental (associé au concept d’État) et l’unité de l’identité<br />

communautaire (lié au concept de nation), et, de l’autre, la spécificité<br />

empirique de plus en plus marquée des formes de mobilisation portées par ces<br />

mouvements sociaux qui revendiquent désormais des droits au nom de leurs<br />

identités et de leurs intérêts particuliers (You are what you believe!, suggère un<br />

slogan). Ces intérêts sont fondés sur l’idée d’une reconnaissance de la<br />

différence et de l’autonomie. C’est ainsi, continue Freitag, que l’idée<br />

d’appartenance et de participation politique s’est trouvé modifiée : la<br />

citoyenneté s’est décomposée en une multitude de modalités et de degrés de<br />

participation organisationnels et corporatifs par rapport auxquels les groupes<br />

se trouvent hiérarchisés : a) selon la puissance qu’ils détiennent<br />

empiriquement dans les jeux de l’influence; b) selon la capacité qu’ils ont de<br />

mobiliser toutes sortes d’intérêts et d’identités spécifiques; et c) selon les<br />

83


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

aptitudes qu’ils déploient pour faire reconnaître au « public », de manière<br />

médiatique, la légitimité de leurs objectifs ou la valeur des finalités qu’ils<br />

poursuivent. Il n’est certes pas excessif de prétendre, dès lors, que le sujet<br />

politique dans l’état keynésien, « sujet social identitaire et synthétique », s’est<br />

complètement fragmenté en un ensemble de subjectivités catégorielles de plus<br />

en plus immédiatement concrètes et particulières, lesquelles recherchent, par<br />

le biais d’une action protectrice, la constitution de sphères singularisées<br />

d’autonomie privée en se référant, pour justifier leur prétention, aux « droits<br />

de la personne » et donc à une « liberté » définie de manière entièrement privée.<br />

Le Canada en tant qu’état postkeynésien ?<br />

Quels sont donc, pour reprendre les termes de la question plus tôt formulée, les<br />

changements et altérations qui ont à ce point affecté le Canada que l’on puisse<br />

en parler comme d’un état postkeynésien ? Sans épuiser le sujet, on exposera<br />

les idées qui suivent.<br />

Le premier changement concerne certainement le mode de représentation<br />

politique auquel aspire un gr<strong>and</strong> nombre de citoyens qui, cherchant de<br />

nouveaux lieux d’intervention et d’incorporation, contredisent la tradition de<br />

s’en remettre aux autorités politiques pour administrer, par délégation<br />

complète de pouvoir, la chose publique (la revendication pour un « Sénat triple<br />

E », portée principalement par des intervenants provenant de l’Ouest du pays<br />

lors des dernières négociations constitutionnelles, incarnait en partie cette<br />

aspiration) 4. Le deuxième changement majeur a trait à la critique de l’idée du<br />

« citoyen universel », fiduciaire d’un État exécutif qui se fait en retour<br />

bienfaiteur et protecteur, au profit du concept de « groupe opprimé » qui non<br />

seulement offre une alternative à la participation active de citoyens regroupés<br />

sur la base de la proximité et du partage de leurs conditions de vie, mais les<br />

assure aussi d’une représentation directe dans l’agora (à cet égard, certains<br />

groupes féministes ont dit que la Chambre des communes devrait être une<br />

« Chambre d’égalité » plutôt qu’une « Chambre des provinces »). Le troisième<br />

changement affectant la matérialité de l’état canadien tient à l’érosion de<br />

l’identité canadienne au profit d’autres identités plus restreintes ou plus larges.<br />

Ce phénomène confirme la tendance, observée par nombre de commentateurs,<br />

d’un délestage marqué de l’appartenance des personnes de leurs ancrages<br />

traditionnels (l’État-nation et la communauté politique territorialisée,<br />

notamment). Autrement dit, dorénavant l’importance des parcours personnels<br />

combinée à l’obtention de certaines garanties juridiques qui protègent leurs<br />

droits, permettent en quelque sorte aux personnes de désaccorder leur histoire,<br />

donc leur être politique, d’un parcours collectif qui n’est ni vécu, ni perçu<br />

comme le lieu de leur action. En termes concrets, cette déconnexion entre<br />

l’action personnelle et le parcours collectif se traduit souvent par le fait que,<br />

pour un citoyen, l’intégration à un groupe n’entraîne plus nécessairement le<br />

partage d’un seul lieu commun ni d’une seule culture. Du point de vue de la<br />

constitution de communautés d’appartenance de type national, ce phénomène<br />

constitue un problème majeur qui se vit sous la forme d’une « crise de la<br />

référence et de la symbolique nationales ». Cette crise de la représentation<br />

symbolique du lieu commun — il s’agit là d’un quatrième changement<br />

affectant structurellement l’état canadien — trouve ses conditions au niveau<br />

de la remise en cause des interprétations traditionnelles de l’histoire et des<br />

conceptions spatio-temporelles sur lesquelles elles sont fondées. À ce<br />

chapitre, les Autochtones, les femmes, les écologistes et les membres des<br />

communautés ethniques ont le plus activement contesté les paramètres connus<br />

84


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

du gr<strong>and</strong> récit historique du Canada — lequel est fondé sur une vision linéaire<br />

et progressive, libérale et patriarcale, dualiste et totalisante des choses — pour<br />

insister plutôt sur les notions de « différence », de « relativité » et<br />

d’« historicité », façon de marquer leur désir de rompre avec la trame infirme,<br />

réductive et archi-classique de cette configuration narrative du « Nous<br />

collectif ». Le cinquième changement altérant le substrat de l’état canadien<br />

découle de l’importance gr<strong>and</strong>issante acquise par les immigrants de fraîche<br />

date. Contrairement à l’idée rép<strong>and</strong>ue, ceux-ci ne « vivent » pas naturellement<br />

l’identité qui leur est octroyée par leur statut de nouveau citoyen résidant au<br />

Canada, mais l’adoptent ou la refusent, la modifient ou la recomposent dans<br />

des formes souvent originales qui, si elles élargissent singulièrement le<br />

paysage culturel de la nation, déstabilisent en même temps la théorie depuis<br />

toujours acceptée d’une société canadienne basée sur deux peuples fondateurs<br />

(ou trois si on inclut les Autochtones).<br />

<strong>La</strong> remise en cause des équilibres régulateurs existants — tant sur le plan<br />

politique et social que culturel et symbolique — à partir d’une critique de<br />

l’universalisme indifférencié et de l’égalité substantielle; la déconstruction<br />

des gr<strong>and</strong>es représentations communes; l’émergence de nouvelles identités<br />

fondées sur le particularisme culturel et sur la différenciation individuelle; et la<br />

déterritorialisation des appartenances et des visions collectives montrent que<br />

l’état canadien est entré dans une période de transition que résume bien la<br />

notion descriptive de postkeynésiannisme (suivant la définition que nous en<br />

donnons). Comment, dans ces conditions, produire un sujet politique en même<br />

temps qu’un état national (en d’autres termes, comment produire de l’unité et<br />

de l’identité dans la dissension), tel est le dilemme et telle est l’impasse du<br />

Canada. Au lieu de proposer des modalités de résolution à cette véritable<br />

équation infernale, nous tenterons plutôt de faire ressortir l’ampleur et la<br />

profondeur des germes d’implosion et d’explosion plantés au sein de l’état<br />

canadien par l’affirmation virulente des tendances que nous venons de décrire.<br />

Facteurs d’éclatement de l’unité canadienne<br />

Au début des années 1990, la production simultanée de l’unité et de l’identité<br />

devient un défi majeur. En évitant de continuellement nous référer aux<br />

données de la conjoncture actuelle, nous nous limiterons à identifier trois<br />

tendances lourdes et rampantes qui agissent au coeur de la matérialité de l’état<br />

canadien en la modifiant et qui, de ce fait, provoquent une crise majeure des<br />

modes de régulation, de légitimation et de représentation à l’oeuvre au sein de<br />

cet état.<br />

L’épuisement d’un modèle politique<br />

<strong>La</strong> production concordante de l’unité et de l’identité se révèle un gr<strong>and</strong> défi à<br />

cause de l’épuisement du modèle politique dans le cadre duquel s’est<br />

historiquement formée la nation canadienne (le fédéralisme exécutif) et a<br />

fonctionné l’état canadien depuis ses débuts. Trois causes interreliées<br />

expliquent cet épuisement.<br />

1. la dynamique à l’origine de la représentation au sein des instances<br />

décisionnelles du système politique canadien est fortement contestée par<br />

nombre d’acteurs, réunis en groupes ou associations, qui recherchent des<br />

modes d’intervention plus directs et des formes d’incorporation plus<br />

définies et plus achevées dans les structures du pouvoir — d’où l’idée de<br />

« constitutionnaliser » leurs dem<strong>and</strong>es et d’influencer les rondes de<br />

85


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

négociations pour que les intervenants à la table centrale tiennent compte<br />

de leurs intérêts spécifiques qu’ils définissent en terme d’une réforme de la<br />

représentativité et des institutions;<br />

2. la dualité fondatrice (l’idée des deux peuples fondateurs et ses incidences<br />

sur l’aménagement des équilibres internes de l’union), l’un des principes<br />

fondamentaux qui régularisent l’état canadien tant sur le plan politique que<br />

sur le plan social et culurel, est également remise en cause. Bon nombre de<br />

groupes se sentent peu concernés par ses aspects réducteurs (c’est le cas<br />

des Amérindiens et de plusieurs mouvements sociaux, par exemple celui<br />

des femmes) ou estiment que les paramètres qu’il impose à la vie politique<br />

canadienne sont inefficaces ou insuffisants pour permettre leur<br />

épanouissement en tant que collectivité agissante (c’est le cas des<br />

nationalistes québécois qui préféreraient que le Québec devienne un état à<br />

part entière, mais c’est aussi le cas des membres des communautés<br />

ethniques et raciales) 5;<br />

3. la reconnaissance des personnes comme citoyens garantie par leur accès à<br />

un vaste système de protection sociale et d’égalité des droits fondé sur<br />

l’idée de l’universalité des chances et de l’effacement des différences<br />

(« citoyen universel ») constitue un deuxième principe régulateur<br />

fondamental également débattu sous prétexte que ce système, en<br />

massifiant les perspectives (donc en homogénéisant les problèmes et les<br />

solutions) ne répond plus aux conditions d’épanouissement d’acteurs qui<br />

recherchent des réponses particulières à leurs besoins existentiels distincts<br />

tout en souscrivant à l’idée générale et généreuse de l’équité 6.<br />

On voit bien comment ces trois ordres de revendications : plus de pouvoir<br />

direct, un équilibre de l’union qui ne repose plus sur la dualité fondatrice —<br />

donc une ouverture vers la pluralité administrative — et le délestage de<br />

l’égalité formelle des individus au bénéfice de l’équité pratique entre les<br />

groupes, sont susceptibles de miner les fondements du système politique<br />

canadien et de provoquer une crise profonde de la régulation, de la légitimation<br />

et de la représentation. Il importe en effet de comprendre, pour prendre cet<br />

exemple, que l’ab<strong>and</strong>on du principe de l’égalité formelle des citoyens remet en<br />

cause, dans sa dynamique même, le mode de régulation sur la base duquel<br />

l’État central avait assis sa légitimité et bâti sa « figure providentielle » depuis<br />

le milieu des années 1930 : celui d’une gestion centralisée et homogénéisante<br />

d’individus pratiquement interchangeables et perçus comme facteurs de<br />

production qui circulent et consomment de manière optimale à l’intérieur<br />

d’une économie intégrée et pannationale 7. Il en va de même pour la<br />

revendication de l’accès au pouvoir. À cet égard, la tendance inéluctable du<br />

rétrécissement de l’espace démocratique consécutive à la centralisation qui<br />

découle des modalités d’opération de l’État-providence (et dont ont<br />

directement bénéficié les technocrates et la classe politique canadienne en<br />

s’instituant les m<strong>and</strong>ataires d’un gigantesque système de redistribution des<br />

richesses) se voit stoppée, sinon renversée, au profit de groupes en voie de<br />

légitimisation qui ne détiennent pour l’instant aucune assise politique stable ou<br />

fondée sur un consensus national. Finalement, la remise en cause de l’idée de<br />

la dualité fondatrice comme paramètre essentiel de la régulation et de la<br />

représentation de l’État canadien provoque d’angoissants vertiges à toute la<br />

classe politique canadienne, et ce, bien qu’elle démontre les ouvertures<br />

apparentes pour endosser les desiderata de certains groupes, les Autochtones<br />

notamment. En fait, remettre en question ce principe d’équilibre de la<br />

fédération canadienne — principe auquel s’accroche résolument le<br />

gouvernement du Québec pour entériner tout nouveau projet de constitution et<br />

86


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

auquel semblent également tenir bon nombre d’hommes et de femmes<br />

politiques à travers le Canada qui y trouvent leur assise et une certaine<br />

sécurité8 — crée un vide représentatif que cherchent à combler autant de<br />

groupes inspirés par l’idéologie de la rectitude politique (political<br />

correctness). Ne se définissant ni par rapport à une territorialité bien arrêtée<br />

(cas des Autochtones) ni par rapport aux catégories jusque-là admises de<br />

« personnes de langue et de culture française ou anglaise détenant des droits<br />

individuels » (cas de la plupart des groupes opprimés : femmes, personnes<br />

âgées, personnes h<strong>and</strong>icapées, pauvres, victimes de ceci ou de cela, etc.) ces<br />

groupes désirent néanmoins avoir voix au chapitre et inscrire leur historicité<br />

particulière au coeur du devenir de l’État canadien.<br />

Jusqu’ici, la crise de régulation, de légitimation et de représentation de l’État<br />

canadien a été « absorbée » par le système politique de deux manières : par la<br />

négociation continuelle (et on sait à quel point ce mode de « résolution » des<br />

conflits, peu importe qu’il retarde, englue ou fasse avancer les choses,<br />

constitue une dimension permanente de l’expérience politique canadienne); et<br />

par le recours systématique aux tribunaux de la part des intervenants, façon<br />

d’inscrire ou de faire valoir leurs droits dans les cadres du régime<br />

constitutionnel associé à l’instauration de la <strong>Charte</strong> des droits et des libertés de<br />

la personne en 1982. Cette absorption de la crise a cependant donné lieu à une<br />

digestion très difficile de ses effets pervers. D’une part, les rondes de<br />

négociation constitutionnelle, en plus d’être extrêmement onéreuses sur le<br />

plan financier et humain, ont complexifié la situation en élargissant<br />

sensiblement le débat et en faisant écho à tous les groupes qui se manifestent<br />

sur la scène publique, sans pour autant rompre avec la perspective dualiste<br />

traditionnelle — ce qui rend hasardeuse la découverte d’une « régulation »<br />

nouvelle9; d’autre part, l’utilisation fréquente des tribunaux, en plus de<br />

favoriser l’apparition d’une véritable culture institutionnalisée de la<br />

complainte, a substitué à l’incorporation des acteurs dans l’agora un mode de<br />

représentation essentiellement judiciarisée des points de vue. Cette pratique<br />

fait bien sûr la fortune des juristes mais contribue à accroître le déficit<br />

démocratique de la société canadienne.<br />

<strong>La</strong> mondialité inscrite au coeur du projet nationalitaire<br />

<strong>La</strong> production simultanée de l’unité et de l’identité au Canada s’avère un gr<strong>and</strong><br />

défi pour une deuxième raison — liée à ce que l’on pourrait appeler<br />

l’apparition de nouvelles territorialités de référence et d’appartenance — celle<br />

en particulier de la « mondialité » et de son pendant culturel<br />

« l’internationalisme » 10. Contrairement à ce que l’on pourrait croire, cette<br />

tendance est majeure, concerne une proportion importante de la population et<br />

se traduit par une remise en cause assez dramatique de l’idée d’État-nation<br />

comme espace d’intervention politique, d’allégeance et de référence — d’où la<br />

crise de légitimité qui s’ensuit pour les entités nationales.<br />

Au cours des vingt dernières années se sont en effet multipliés les groupes et<br />

les réseaux d’action pour qui la planète est le terrain d’intervention privilégié,<br />

celui à partir duquel ils se définissent une identité, celui aussi par rapport<br />

auquel ils entendent reconfigurer l’espace politique. Contribuant à ce que R.<br />

Falk a appelé des « évasions de l’État » 11, ces actions politiques d’acteurs nonétatiques<br />

qui font des problèmes globaux (écologie, sida, droits de la personne,<br />

pauvreté endémique du Tiers-Monde, etc.) leur affaire, ont inscrit dans<br />

l’agenda politique des gouvernements nationaux tout un ensemble d’items<br />

pour lesquels des solutions lucides ne peuvent être trouvées, le cas échéant,<br />

87


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

qu’en autant que les états se dissolvent dans une espèce de communauté transnationale,<br />

cédant ainsi une gr<strong>and</strong>e partie de leur souveraineté traditionnelle et<br />

amenuisant par conséquent leur capacité à se représenter comme états<br />

indépendants définissant leur autonomie, c’est-à-dire leurs propres frontières<br />

d’inclusion et d’exclusion.<br />

Au cours de cette même période de vingt ans s’est également imposée, dans<br />

l’horizon politique et symbolique des états contemporains, une nouvelle figure<br />

identitaire : celle de l’être performant dont le champ d’action est le monde et<br />

qui trouve son fondement existentiel dans les stratégies d’accumulation des<br />

entreprises, si ce n’est dans les accords commerciaux12. Ce « monde » a bien<br />

sûr une extension spatiale, littéralement celle de la planète, mais il consiste<br />

surtout en une arène de réalisation du destin individuel de personnes dont le<br />

principe vital est d’assurer leur survie (Life is short. Play hard, dit un slogan),<br />

donc de démontrer leur appartenance au clan des gagnants — façon d’acquérir<br />

une identité optimale et de se farder du look impressionniste, « bon chic bon<br />

genre », y correspondant — en prouvant leur capacité à jouer ou à déjouer la<br />

concurrence internationale. Comme l’écrivait Benjamin R. Barber dans un<br />

article récent (article dont l’argumentation s’applique tout à fait au cas<br />

canadien) 13 : « Commercial pilots, computer programmers, international<br />

bankers, media specialists, oil riggers, entertainment celebrities, ecology<br />

experts, demographers, accountants, professors, athletes — <strong>the</strong>se compose a<br />

new breed of men <strong>and</strong> women for whom religion, culture <strong>and</strong> nationality can<br />

seem only marginal elements in a working identity. » Dans un ouvrage bien<br />

connu, Robert Reich14 estimait que cette nouvelle classe internationaliste, qui<br />

diffuse ses valeurs par l’entremise de médias prestigieux dans lesquels nombre<br />

de « non-admis » trouvent leurs mirages quotidiens, comptait pour environ 10<br />

p. 100 de la population américaine.<br />

Cette figure identitaire est endossée par l’élite politique et économique<br />

canadienne, ce qui signifie un idéal existentiel particulièrement valorisé dans<br />

les sphères où on élabore les représentations symboliques qui visent à assurer<br />

une cohérence au couple État-nation. Préparant l’arrivée prochaine dans les<br />

cercles du pouvoir d’une méritocratie internationaliste aux savoir-faire<br />

performants, elle a pourtant contribué à démembrer la représentation<br />

traditionnelle de l’État national et a inscrit, au coeur même de l’appareil<br />

étatique et du projet de promotion nationalitaire, l’esprit et la trace de la<br />

mondialité, si ce n’est ceux du McWorld soul et de la « culture Benetton »<br />

(dont l’éthique et l’esthétique s’incarnent dans un slogan génialement<br />

équivoque : « Toutes couleurs unies »). Si bien que, l’enjeu mondial<br />

déstructure la capacité des états à se représenter comme lieu de convergence et<br />

d’agrégation, l’internationalisation des communications et la métaphore du<br />

« village global » ne faisant qu’accentuer l’érosion des liens culturels qui<br />

unissaient autrefois les Canadiens.<br />

L’arrimage des acteurs à cette double structure référentielle, en apparence<br />

contradictoire, de la mondialité et de la nationalité n’a pas été vécu sur le mode<br />

de la confusion. Au contraire — et le slogan à la mode Think globally, act<br />

locally en fait foi — ce double bind dans lequel ils sont pris favorise leur<br />

inscription au sein d’un espace public et médiatique dont les frontières ne<br />

coïncident pas avec le territoire national. Il ouvre de ce fait la voie à<br />

l’affirmation d’une citoyenneté mondiale dont les porte-étendards, toujours<br />

plus nombreux, cherchent à faire reconnaître la trace dans les chartes<br />

universelles et au sein des organismes internationaux.<br />

88


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

L’affirmation d’une véritable culture politique transnationale, dont l’impact<br />

premier est de faire ressortir le côté obsolète de l’idée de territorialité<br />

nationale, n’est pas un phénomène excentrique à la dynamique sociale<br />

canadienne. Suivant l’hypothèse émise par Breton et Jenson, il y a lieu plutôt<br />

de reconnaître, dans cette culture transnationale, l’expression d’un « processus<br />

social réel qui s’enracine dans des réseaux d’action et de pouvoir en voie de<br />

globalisation ». Dès lors, il faut saisir l’importance des enjeux posés par la<br />

mondialité à l’État-nation : celle-ci, par la façon dont elle est assumée et prise<br />

en charge par des groupes et des segments toujours plus nombreux de la<br />

population, porte une redéfinition spatiale des gr<strong>and</strong>s paramètres de la vie<br />

politique canadienne, si ce n’est un forum d’expression positive du citoyen qui<br />

trouve désormais ses allégeances, ses reconnaissances et ses lieux<br />

d’identification dans une arène aux dimensions supranationales.<br />

<strong>La</strong> fin des gr<strong>and</strong>s récits collectifs ?<br />

Nous avons vu dans les paragraphes précédents comment l’état canadien, à la<br />

suite de pressions venant de l’intérieur et de l’extérieur, tendait à l’implosion et<br />

à l’explosion. Un troisième facteur, qui dans les circonstances accentue la<br />

tendance plus qu’il ne la provoque, concourt également à amplifier les<br />

menaces de rupture de l’union. Il s’agit de l’inefficacité des gr<strong>and</strong>s récits<br />

d’édification de la nation à activer un sens communautaire qui, sur le plan<br />

symbolique, propose un mode de représentation de l’état satisfaisant les<br />

aspirations et les visions des groupes. En d’autres termes, l’un des défis à la<br />

production de l’unité au Canada tient au fait que l’on ne trouve plus de lieu de<br />

reconnaissance et de réciprocité (sauf celui du social conçu comme un espace<br />

de valorisation et de promotion de ses droits particuliers ou corporatisés,<br />

espace notamment créé par la <strong>Charte</strong> de 1982) et que, plus que jamais, en<br />

l’absence surtout de héros récipiendaires de la ferveur populaire (héros<br />

incarnant probablement le Sujet fictif de la société unifiée), le discours de la<br />

nation, celle qui s’étend uniformément d’un océan à l’autre sonne creux ou<br />

reste inaudible. À cet égard, il est symptomatique qu’une enquête récemment<br />

effectuée pour le compte de l’Association d’études canadiennes ait révélé que<br />

les Canadiens avaient du mal à identifier, dans l’histoire ou dans l’actualité de<br />

leur pays, plus de deux personnages ou événements qui, par leur envergure ou<br />

leur importance, pouvaient être des sources de motivation et de fierté<br />

collectives15. Cette même enquête soulignait par ailleurs le fait que, dans leur<br />

ensemble, les Canadiens croyaient impératif de mettre plus d’efforts à faire<br />

connaître l’histoire nationale, ses personnages principaux, ses événements<br />

significatifs, etc. Malheureusement, aucune question spécifique n’invitait les<br />

répondants (que l’on avait catégorisé par appartenance linguistique, par lieu de<br />

résidence et par tranche d’âge) à préciser ce qui, dans la matière du passé,<br />

devait être promu au rang d’histoire nationale. On peut raisonnablement<br />

penser que les réponses, donc que les trames historiques proposées, auraient<br />

été nombreuses et éclatées, surtout si l’on avait réalisé l’enquête auprès de<br />

« catégories sociales » moins classiques.<br />

L’inefficacité des gr<strong>and</strong>s récits d’édification de la nation à représenter une<br />

communauté de sens dans laquelle se reconnaîtraient les sujets politiques tient<br />

au fait que ces récits restent fondamentalement basés sur une conception<br />

dualiste de la destinée canadienne — ce qui fait que les moments forts de<br />

l’histoire collective concernent la saga ininterrompue des rapports conflictuels<br />

entre Francophones et Anglophones, entre l’Est et l’Ouest, entre le fédéral et<br />

les provinces — ; sur une espèce de conception naïve du Canada, éden dont la<br />

matérialité résiderait dans un ensemble d’images, de symboles ou<br />

89


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

d’institutions universelles suscitant le patriotisme de ses habitants (la beauté<br />

environnementale du pays, sa gr<strong>and</strong>eur et ses ressouces; les programmes<br />

sociaux; la possibilité de s’installer n’importe où sur un vaste territoire; etc.),<br />

ou encore sur la promotion de gr<strong>and</strong>s projets incarnant l’« esprit canadien ». Or<br />

de tels récits arrivent mal, en ces temps troubles, à aviver les consensus16.Ona vu plus tôt que la représentation dualiste de l’état canadien (et par conséquent<br />

de son histoire et de son actualité), bien qu’elle satisfasse divers intervenants<br />

sur la scène publimédiatique (pensons au gouvernement du Québec et à la<br />

classe politique canadienne), contrevenait à de nombreux autres. De même, la<br />

perspective unifiante et homogénéisante d’un Canada fondant sa matérialité<br />

dans l’idée d’une égalité formelle de ses sujets devant l’histoire et dans la<br />

primauté de ses normes nationales (ce qui implique l’existence d’un<br />

fédéralisme exécutif) s’accorde mal avec les perspectives et les visions<br />

spécifiques de bien des groupes. Enfin, comme l’affirmait Donna Dasko dans<br />

un article proposant une analyse très intéressante17, « nous n’avons pas vu,<br />

dans la dernière décennie, l’équivalent de la construction d’un chemin de fer<br />

transcontinental, de la création d’un réseau national de radio et de télévision ou<br />

de l’établissement d’un régime d’assurance-maladie, et il semble peu probable<br />

qu’un projet d’une telle envergure puisse être réalisé d’ici la fin du siècle »; en<br />

d’autres termes, c’est comme si l’on manquait de « matière » pour écrire<br />

l’histoire de l’« esprit canadien », si ce n’est pour fonder de nouveaux my<strong>the</strong>s<br />

unitaires, et force est de dire que les « gr<strong>and</strong>s projets de l’heure » (traités de<br />

libre échange; projet d’accord constitutionnel; désengagement de l’État et<br />

privatisation de sociétés publiques), en déconstruisant l’édifice dans lequel<br />

s’enracinait, se reflétait et se réalisait la nation, ne sont pas facteurs de création<br />

d’unité nationale.<br />

Pour étayer notre thèse d’une érosion graduelle de l’idée du Canada, on<br />

pourrait aussi faire état des résultats de deux sondages, l’un portant sur les<br />

symboles d’identité canadienne et l’autre mesurant le sentiment d’identité des<br />

citoyens18. Ainsi, les recherches sur l’opinion publique d’Environics révèlent<br />

un déclin de l’importance que les Canadiens attachent à virtuellement tous les<br />

symboles de l’identité canadienne mesurés entre 1985 et 1991 (le drapeau,<br />

l’hymne national, le multiculturalisme, le bilinguisme, la Société Radio-<br />

Canada et la monarchie) au profit d’un nouveau symbole d’identité, la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

des droits et des libertés de la personne, qui incorpore tout un train de valeurs<br />

(parmi lesquelles l’individualisme et le pouvoir de la personne) dont les effets<br />

fédératifs, contrairement à ce que l’on anticipait au départ, sont faibles. De<br />

même, à la lumière de la série de sondages Focus Canada, il apparaît manifeste<br />

que la préférence des Canadiens pour un gouvernement central fort s’est<br />

étiolée depuis 1979 au profit de l’idée de « compétence provinciale »,<br />

renforçant ainsi l’allégeance locale et contribuant au relâchement de l’unité<br />

canadienne.<br />

L’inefficacité des gr<strong>and</strong>s récits d’édification de la nation à construire une<br />

communauté de sens a jusqu’ici entraîné l’apparition d’un vide consensuel qui<br />

s’est rempli de ressentiments, d’antagonismes, de désirs de rectitude et de<br />

complaintes exprimés par autant d’intervenants sur la scène publimédiatique,<br />

provoquant ce que Dominique Schnapper appelle une « cohésion par le flou »,<br />

sorte de dissolution du lien social prophétisé (et craint) par les penseurs de la<br />

modernité. À première vue, une telle polyphonie peut être interprétée comme<br />

un moment fort de restructuration de l’esprit communautaire où chacun<br />

exprime librement son point de vue et fait reconnaître la valeur et la justesse de<br />

ses revendications. En réalité, c’est une véritable boîte de P<strong>and</strong>ore qui a été<br />

90


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

ouverte et, dans la mesure où le jugement et l’éthique politiques ont été<br />

remplacés par l’injonction légale et le discours des juristes, on ne sait plus<br />

comment la refermer ou en canaliser les effets générateurs. Dans cette logique<br />

de la réciprocité, un droit n’appelle pas un devoir mais advenant une réplique<br />

de l’adversaire suggère le recours à un autre droit et ainsi de suite. <strong>La</strong><br />

conséquence est évidente : au lieu de permettre le rapprochement de groupes<br />

de personnes désormais constitués en parties légales et au lieu de favoriser la<br />

recréation du sens communautaire et de l’esprit démocratique, le débat public<br />

s’enlise dans des affrontements insolubles qui atrophient davantage le<br />

politique (entendu ici comme réflexivité du vivre-ensemble et responsabilité<br />

collective des finalités de la vie sociale) 19 en plus de provoquer un<br />

recentrement des doléances vers la seule dimension groupusculaire. Ce<br />

recentrement n’entraîne aucun dépassement de la perspective des anciens<br />

récits mais, plutôt, un approfondissement de leurs limites en les remplaçant par<br />

des micro-récits qui font de l’« essentialisme » (dialectique de l’inclusion et de<br />

l’exclusion centrée sur une recherche de Soi-même en évitant la réciprocité<br />

avec l’Autre — s’agit-il du retour en force d’une sorte d’intégrisme fondée sur<br />

l’idéologie ambiguë du politically correct ? ) le point de départ et le point<br />

d’arrivée de leur rhétorique. Sous le couvert d’une richesse participative et<br />

d’un élargissement de l’espace démocratique, c’est un carnaval grotesque qui<br />

se déroule à longueur d’année, c’est une méga-inertie de l’agora qui en résulte.<br />

Triomphatrice comme jamais, la parole fragmentée (surdéterminée par la<br />

pensée légale) provoque l’aplatissement du sens civique, favorise l’avènement<br />

de l’identité narcissique et nourrit le processus techno-bureaucratique de<br />

gestion et de régulation du social qui, désormais, ne traite que des dem<strong>and</strong>es<br />

provenant d’interlocuteurs dotés de puissances variables d’intervention<br />

publique et s’étant emparés, à la suite d’une joute très compétitive et<br />

spécialisée, d’une position avantageuse au sein de l’espace discursif, puissant<br />

lieu de formation identitaire à l’ère de la société médiatique.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Nous avons parlé, tout au long de cet article, d’éclatement, de dissension et de<br />

menace de rupture du Canada. Certes, un état d’équilibre, et donc une forme<br />

d’unité et d’identité politique, celle qui s’était incarnée dans l’Étatprovidence,<br />

est en train de s’écrouler à la suite de pressions internes et externes<br />

portées par de nombreux mouvements sociaux, véritables corporations<br />

identitaires20 qui s’agitent localement, nationalement et internationalement.<br />

Cette nouvelle dynamique qui traverse l’état canadien a jusqu’ici détruit des<br />

valeurs communes et fomenté des conflits d’intérêt. Cela ne veut pas dire que<br />

toute forme d’unité soit impossible mais l’horizon semble pour l’instant<br />

bouché. Or comment sortir de l’impasse ? Sans vouloir jouer aux devins, il se<br />

pourrait bien que l’unité nouvelle du Canada se fasse dans la reconnaissance et<br />

dans l’institutionnalisation de la dissension, ce qui est une perspective assez<br />

différente de celle qui avait été préconisée sous les gouvernements de Pierre<br />

Trudeau et qui a été enchâssée dans le réaménagement constitutionnel de<br />

1982. Cette démarche de reconnaissance et d’institutionnalisation<br />

(postnationaliste?) est rendue particulièrement difficile parce que l’on<br />

s’interdit, d’un côté comme de l’autre, de réfléchir l’avenir du Canada en<br />

dehors de catégories et de modèles politiques devenus dysfonctionnels.<br />

L’insistance des participants au débat constitutionnel à recourir, pour<br />

examiner ou solutionner le « cas canadien », à des schèmes de compréhension<br />

qui renvoient à des modèles associatifs ou à des formations politiques révolues<br />

91


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

ou idéalisées (telle la Suisse par exemple), fait que l’on s’imagine pouvoir<br />

résoudre les impasses actuelles du Canada en réaménageant autrement, mais<br />

toujours dans un même cadre général, les instances d’exercice du pouvoir<br />

entre des intervenants qui, faisant fi de toute considération politique lucide,<br />

s’agitent sur la scène médiatique pour conquérir une opinion publique dopée<br />

par le charabia de constitutionnalistes eux-mêmes en voie de<br />

constitutionnalisation! À vrai dire, un tel réaménagement permettra au mieux<br />

d’aboutir à un repositionnement différent, mais toujours instable et précaire,<br />

des groupes en présence qui continueront, au-delà de tout « règlement »<br />

constitutionnel, à se livrer à des joutes de concurrence dans la logique<br />

culturelle du postkeynésiannisme. En somme, l’avenir quel qu’il soit<br />

entraînera, à moins qu’un nouveau régime politique ne soit instauré, un<br />

approfondissement des tendances à l’éclatement « par le haut » et « par le bas »<br />

de cet état. Or il importe de commencer à mesurer les effets désastreux de cette<br />

situation : l’accroissement du nombre des exclus au sein d’un pays pourtant<br />

fier de se présenter comme le premier au monde en terme de niveau de vie et de<br />

bien-être collectif; l’évincement de la parole raisonnable et du bon sens<br />

pratique par la rhétorique implacable des juristes, sophistes des temps actuels<br />

et animateurs d’une culture de la complainte institutionnalisée; et la<br />

transformation de la place publique en une arène de compétition où, munis<br />

d’une règle du calcul opportuniste, des figures rendues blafardes par la<br />

performance se rencontrent en vue de s’imposer sur des concurrents tous aussi<br />

soucieux de leur image, mirage dans lequel ils fondent … leur absence<br />

d’identité.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Nous assumons cette position. Cela dit, faute de place, nous ne procéderons pas dans cet<br />

article à une analyse comparative.<br />

2. Cf. J. Létourneau, « L’économie politique des trente glorieuses. Apport et originalité des<br />

analyses en terme de régulation », Historical Reflections/Réflexions historiques, 14, 2<br />

(1987), p. 345-379. On trouvera dans l’ouvrage de Robert Delorme et Christine André<br />

(L’État et l’économie. Un essai d’explication de l’évolution des dépenses publiques en<br />

France, 1870-1980, Paris, Seuil, 1983) une analyse historique poussée des formes de la<br />

régulation étatique dans l’occident moderne. Enfin, pour une application au cas canadien du<br />

concept de régulation monopoliste, voir les textes de François Houle « <strong>La</strong> crise et la place du<br />

Canada dans la nouvelle division internationale du travail » dans Le Canada et la nouvelle<br />

division internationale du travail, sous la dir. de D. Cameron et F. Houle, Ottawa, Éditions<br />

de l’Université d’Ottawa, 1985, p. 79-102; de Jane Jenson<br />

« Different but not Exceptional : Canada’s Permeable Fordism », Revue canadienne de<br />

sociologie et d’anthropologie, 26, 1 1989, p. 69-94; et l’ouvrage publié sous la direction de<br />

Gérard Boismenu et Daniel Drache, Politique et régulation. Modèle de développement et<br />

trajectoire canadienne, Paris/ L’Harmattan, Montréal/Méridiens, 1990, 360 p.<br />

3. Voir son article intitulé « L’identité, l’altérité et le politique. Essai exploratoire de<br />

reconstruction conceptuelle historique », Société [Montréal], n o 9 (hiver 1992), p. 1-55.<br />

4. Idée avancée par Jane Jenson dans un article inédit intitulé « Le refus de la dualité. Nouvelles<br />

revendications de la citoyenneté au Canada » à paraître dans <strong>La</strong> question identitaire au<br />

Canada francophone : récits, parcours, enjeux, hors-lieux, sous la dir. de R. Bernard et J.<br />

Létourneau, Québec, Presses de l’Université <strong>La</strong>val, 1993, coll. « Culture française<br />

d’Amérique ».<br />

5. Ibid.<br />

6. Idée développée par Gilles Breton et Jane Jenson dans un texte intitulé « Globalisation et<br />

citoyenneté : quelques enjeux actuels » publié dans L’ethnicité à l’heure de la<br />

mondialisation, sous la dir. de Caroline Andrew et al., Ottawa, ACFAS-Outaouais, 1992, p.<br />

35-55.<br />

92


De l’unité et de l’indentité au Canada.<br />

Essai sur l’éclatement d’un État<br />

7. On sait à quel point cet idéal fut porté loin par Pierre Trudeau qui, pendant tout le temps où il<br />

occupa le pouvoir, incarna l’idéal d’un nationalisme fondé sur le fédéralisme centralisateur<br />

et exécutif.<br />

8. Sous prétexte que le Canada deviendrait un pays totalement ingouvernable.<br />

9. L’ensemble du débat constitutionnel (à tout le moins la dernière ronde de négociations) est<br />

en effet envenimé par le paradigme nationalitaire qui, pour les uns et pour les autres, semble<br />

une donnée incontournable pour penser, poser et solutionner les problèmes d’aménagement<br />

des rapports politiques internes à l’union. Du côté canadien, ce nationalisme s’exprime à<br />

travers le principe de l’égalité des provinces, de l’homogénéité pancanadienne et de la<br />

primauté des normes exécutives du gouvernement central. Du côté québécois, il s’incarne à<br />

travers l’idée d’un provincialisme offensif, distinct, aux ambitions souveraines et<br />

recherchant la maîtrise d’oeuvre de sa destinée. À qu<strong>and</strong> l’avènement du post-nationalisme?<br />

10. Par culture de l’internationalisme, nous entendons cet ensemble de pratiques et de<br />

comportements, de codes de paraître et d’habitudes qui constituent autant de marqueurs<br />

distinctifs d’une élite en voie de structuration et dont le modèle existentiel, diffusé par une<br />

pléiade de media « in » allant des aéro-magazines (En Route) aux journaux d’affaires (Globe<br />

& Mail ) en passant par les revues-mode (Vogue, Uomo), définit l’horizon d’un nombre<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>issant de personnes qui s’identifient à la culture haut-de-gamme et dont le sentiment<br />

d’appartenance évolue au gré des opportunités d’investissement du capital financier,<br />

immobilier ou idéel (les idées sont en effet un capital symbolique dont la valeur se mesure<br />

désormais en terme d’« aéro-miles ») à travers le monde.<br />

11. R. Falk, « Evasions of Sovereignty » dans R.B.J. Walker et S.H. Mendlovitz, eds.,<br />

Contending Sovereignties. Redefining Political Community, Boulder/Londres, Lyne Rienne<br />

Publishers, 1990, cité dans Breton et Jenson.<br />

12. Idée développée dans J. Létourneau, « <strong>La</strong> nouvelle figure identitaire du Québécois. Essai sur<br />

la dimension symbolique d’un consensus social en voie d’émergence », British Journal of<br />

Canadian Studies, 6, 1 (1991), p. 17-38.<br />

13. « Jihad Vs McWorld », <strong>The</strong> Atlantic Monthly, vol. 269, n o 3 (March 1992), p. 53-63.<br />

14. <strong>The</strong> Work of Nations, New York, Vintage Books, 1992.<br />

15. Les résultats de cette enquête ont été publiés dans le Bulletin de l’AEC, vol. 13, n o 3 (automne<br />

1991), en même temps que les observations d’un certain nombre de commentateurs, dont les<br />

nôtres (p. 14-16).<br />

16. Pour un plaidoyer semblable mais à partir de considérations opposées, voir Michael Bliss,<br />

« Fragmented Past, Fragmented Future », University of Toronto Magazine (Winter 1991),<br />

p. 6-11.<br />

17. « Les liens qui nous unissent : l’évolution de la perception qu’ont les Canadiens du système<br />

fédéral » dans Le Réseau, vol. 2, n o 6/7 (juin-juillet 1992), p. 5-11.<br />

18. Pour plus de détails, voir l’article cité de Donna Dasko.<br />

19. Définition empruntée de Michel Freitag, op. cit.<br />

20. Aurions-nous raison d’analyser, à partir de cette idée de « corporation identitaire », le fait<br />

qu’une multitude de personnes affichent maintenant leur allégeance, leur appartenance, leur<br />

partisannerie, leurs aspirations, leurs identifications individuelles et sociales en faisant<br />

imprimer, sur les T-shirts qu’elles portent, le slogan, l’idée ou la formule-choc qui résume<br />

l’idéal, noble ou vulgaire, auquel elles croient ? Ou le fait qu’un nombre gr<strong>and</strong>issant<br />

d’entreprises, désireuses de créer chez leurs clients un sentiment d’appartenance ou de<br />

distinction fondée sur la notion de privilège, se transforment en clubs (Club Price, Club Z,<br />

Aéroplan, etc.) où l’on est formellement admis et où la détention d’une carte — d’identité<br />

corporative ? — donne droit à des avantages refusés à ceux qui n’en sont pas titulaires ?<br />

93


Richard Sigurdson<br />

Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics *<br />

Abstract<br />

Although various leading scholars have long been concerned that some<br />

aspects of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms would have an<br />

unwelcome influence upon Canada’s political institutions <strong>and</strong> processes, a<br />

recent, more ideological, academic attack on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has developed. <strong>The</strong><br />

author’s intention in this paper is to outline <strong>and</strong> discuss this new development,<br />

which can be called “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia,” <strong>and</strong> to discuss its effects on Canadian<br />

political discourse. In particular, <strong>the</strong>re are two fundamental strains of<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia—left- <strong>and</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia—that rely upon<br />

curiously similar arguments about <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> perils of<br />

judicial review. <strong>The</strong> author argues that <strong>the</strong>se critiques are unnecessarily<br />

alarmist, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes are largely unable to provide attractive<br />

reasons to believe that Canada would be better off without an entrenched<br />

charter.<br />

Résumé<br />

Ce n’est pas d’hier que des spécialistes en vue s’inquiètent des effets sur les<br />

institutions et le processus politiques canadiens de certains aspects de la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés. Depuis peu, cependant, on assiste au<br />

déferlement d’une nouvelle vague d’attaques à caractère plus idéologique<br />

originant des milieux universitaires. L’auteur de cet article entend décrire et<br />

examiner ce phénomène, qu’on peut baptiser « chartophobie », et d’en<br />

apprécier l’influence sur le discours politique au Canada. On observe deux<br />

types principaux de chartophobie — celle de gauche et celle de droite — qui,<br />

curieusement, font appel aux mêmes arguments pour décrier les effets de la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong> ainsi que les dangers de la judiciarisation. Selon l’auteur, ces critiques<br />

sont largement exagérées et les chartophobes n’offrent guère de raisons<br />

valables à l’encontre de la constitutionnalisation des droits et des libertés.<br />

One reason for <strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord that was often cited by<br />

its critics was <strong>the</strong> alleged damage it would do to <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms. <strong>The</strong>re were those, of course, who insisted that such fears were<br />

unfounded, that <strong>the</strong> Accord would do no harm to <strong>the</strong> precious <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Seldom<br />

did we hear from anyone who might say that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is not worth<br />

protecting, that it was a mistake to enter into <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>l<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> first place. For<br />

<strong>the</strong>se sorts of arguments, one has to turn to academics, many of whom are<br />

highly critical, not just of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms<br />

specifically but of <strong>the</strong> constitutional entrenchment <strong>and</strong> codification of rights in<br />

general.<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Various writers have long suggested that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s “importance in terms of<br />

Canada’s constitutional future is that it is centralizing, legalizing <strong>and</strong><br />

Americanizing” (Cheffins <strong>and</strong> Johnson, 1986: 148). And many leading<br />

scholars have been critical, or at least sceptical, of <strong>the</strong>se tendencies right from<br />

<strong>the</strong> start. For instance, Donald Smiley (1983) worried that <strong>the</strong> attempt to<br />

achieve national unity by means of a centralizing, entrenched charter would<br />

have precisely <strong>the</strong> opposite effect to <strong>the</strong> one desired. Peter Russell (1983) told<br />

us that <strong>the</strong> principal impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would be to “judicialize politics <strong>and</strong><br />

politicize <strong>the</strong> judiciary” <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> danger of this would lie not so much in <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that non-elected judges would impose <strong>the</strong>ir will in an undemocratic<br />

fashion, but that social <strong>and</strong> political questions would become transformed into<br />

abstract, technical ones that <strong>the</strong> bulk of <strong>the</strong> citizenry will feel incompetent to<br />

debate <strong>and</strong> attempt to resolve. And William Christian <strong>and</strong> Colin Campbell<br />

(1983) warned that <strong>the</strong> adoption of a charter would shift Canadian political<br />

culture away from its tory <strong>and</strong> collectivist past towards a much more<br />

individualistic, Lockean liberal focus. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, that <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms would exacerbate <strong>the</strong> trend which George<br />

Grant (1965) so eloquently lamented.<br />

In this paper I wish to take a closer look at a more recent trend in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

scholarship—one that has produced a highly normative literature, often on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of <strong>the</strong> observations noted above. My intention, <strong>the</strong>n, is to outline <strong>and</strong><br />

discuss this new, more ideological, academic attack upon <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms. I will refer to this anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> position as<br />

“<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia” because I see in it not just a scepticism about our specific<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> but a more generalized fear of, <strong>and</strong> antipathy towards, any<br />

constitutionally entrenched bill or charter of human rights in a modern, liberal,<br />

democratic state. I think that this anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> attitude is unnecessarily<br />

alarmist—that is, I can find little concrete evidence to support <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobic account of what is going on in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>l<strong>and</strong>. I will argue, as well,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes are largely unable to provide appropriate alternative<br />

methods for addressing <strong>the</strong> major social <strong>and</strong> economic concerns of a modern<br />

<strong>and</strong> diverse liberal democracy. My main strategy, however, is not to<br />

counterattack with discussions of specific provisions <strong>and</strong> cases <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

interpretation. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, I am concerned with <strong>the</strong> rhetorical significance of<br />

recent anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> scholarship <strong>and</strong> will discuss its effects on our political<br />

discourse.<br />

In particular, I will identify two fundamental strains of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia— leftwing<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia <strong>and</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia—that rely upon curiously<br />

similar arguments about <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> perils of judicial<br />

review. In fact, both left- <strong>and</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes assail <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in<br />

<strong>the</strong> way best calculated to evoke shock <strong>and</strong> horror in a society like ours—that<br />

is, <strong>the</strong>y accuse it of generating anti-democratic political consequences. As we<br />

will see, <strong>the</strong>re are some interesting points of overlap between <strong>the</strong>se two types<br />

of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia <strong>and</strong> it is worth pondering just what this tells us about <strong>the</strong><br />

persistence of certain Canadian intellectual traditions. Of course, <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

significant differences, too, <strong>and</strong> we will have to explore <strong>the</strong> arguments used to<br />

portray <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> as an instrument of anti-democracy <strong>and</strong> what each side<br />

means by “democratic”.<br />

My discussion will be presented in three parts. First, I will outline <strong>and</strong> explain<br />

<strong>the</strong> major objections to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> put forward by leading, leftist, legal<br />

scholars. Second, I will look at <strong>the</strong> critique of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> politics by<br />

conservatives, mainly in <strong>the</strong> discipline of political science. In <strong>the</strong> third section,<br />

96


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

I will review <strong>the</strong> arguments, try to show that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes have not made<br />

a convincing case, <strong>and</strong> sketch a defence—albeit a qualified one—of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, warts <strong>and</strong> all.<br />

Left-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia<br />

I shall begin with a discussion of <strong>the</strong> left-wing fear of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. This was<br />

evident during <strong>the</strong> 1981 constitutional negotiations in <strong>the</strong> position taken by<br />

Saskatchewan Premier Alan Blakeney, who feared, among o<strong>the</strong>r things, that<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would have a centralizing influence on Canadian federalism. Still<br />

smarting from recent Supreme Court decisions against his province in CIGOL<br />

(1978) <strong>and</strong> Potash (1979), Blakeney did not relish <strong>the</strong> prospect of federallyappointed<br />

courts setting uniform national st<strong>and</strong>ards, often in policy areas of<br />

exclusive provincial jurisdiction.<br />

What is more, Blakeney was certain that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would constitute a threat<br />

to <strong>the</strong> interests of organized labour. He based this opinion, in part, on his<br />

critical observations of <strong>the</strong> American experience, where <strong>the</strong> Bill of Rights has<br />

been used to strike down laws setting minimum wages, minimum hours of<br />

work, etc. (Greunding, 1990: 192). Blakeney was convinced, moreover, that<br />

his province’s progressive social programs, such as medicare, might have been<br />

struck down by a conservative court. Since he considered <strong>the</strong> state as an<br />

instrument for providing important public services while pursuing greater<br />

equity for all citizens, Blakeney could see no benefit in a charter that would<br />

restrain government in order to protect <strong>the</strong> rights of citizens to be free from<br />

state interference in <strong>the</strong>ir economic or social lives. Indeed, he was “aghast that<br />

any social democratic party would be in favour of transferring power from<br />

legislatures to courts” (Greunding, 1990: 196).<br />

An additional, more personal, dimension to Blakeney’s opposition to <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> links him to a significant British-tory streak within <strong>the</strong> tradition of<br />

English-Canadian social democracy. That is, Blakeney simply preferred <strong>the</strong><br />

tory-collectivist features of <strong>the</strong> British parliamentary tradition over <strong>the</strong> liberal<br />

individualism of <strong>the</strong> US model <strong>and</strong> its rights-based constitution. <strong>The</strong> son of a<br />

traditional Tory family in Nova Scotia, product of a Loyalist legal education at<br />

Dalhousie <strong>and</strong> a British one at Oxford, Blakeney defined himself as a “British<br />

constitutional lawyer type” who believes that rights are best protected by<br />

Parliament <strong>and</strong> not by a constitution which is interpreted by <strong>the</strong> courts. After<br />

all, he said, “<strong>the</strong> British Parliament has worked not all that badly” (Greunding,<br />

1990: 192). Not surprisingly, <strong>the</strong>n, Blakeney was an adamant champion of<br />

parliamentary sovereignty throughout <strong>the</strong> constitutional negotiations,<br />

reluctantly giving in to <strong>the</strong> pressure to accept an entrenched charter only once<br />

he was assured that <strong>the</strong>re would be a clause allowing legislatures to make laws<br />

“notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing” certain rights. And even on this matter he proved to be a<br />

tenacious <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobe, dem<strong>and</strong>ing for longer than anyone else that both <strong>the</strong><br />

gender equality provision in Section 28 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> aboriginal rights clause in<br />

Section 35 should remain within <strong>the</strong> jurisdiction of <strong>the</strong> provincial override.<br />

It must be noted, of course, that Blakeney’s position was far from being <strong>the</strong><br />

majority one within his own party, especially at <strong>the</strong> national level. Indeed,<br />

support for an entrenched charter had been party policy since <strong>the</strong> days when<br />

M.J. Coldwell was leader of <strong>the</strong> CCF. What is more, Blakeney’s opposition to<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> put him in direct <strong>and</strong> public conflict with <strong>the</strong> national party leader,<br />

Ed Broadbent, with party elders Tommy Douglas, David Lewis <strong>and</strong> Stanley<br />

Knowles, <strong>and</strong> with several groups usually supportive of <strong>the</strong> party, including<br />

97


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

civil libertarian <strong>and</strong> feminist organizations. In <strong>the</strong> end, <strong>the</strong> national party<br />

backed <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. In fact, <strong>the</strong> only NDP MP to vote against <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,<br />

Svend Robinson, did so not because it undermined parliamentary sovereignty<br />

but because it included a legislative override clause. Since <strong>the</strong>n, leftist<br />

politicians have rarely been vocal in <strong>the</strong>ir opposition to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> lately<br />

prefer a strategy of attempting to increase <strong>the</strong> list of constitutionally protected<br />

rights to include, for example, social <strong>and</strong> economic entitlements to be set out in<br />

some sort of social charter.<br />

Nowadays, <strong>the</strong>n, pure left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia is most evident in <strong>the</strong> academy,<br />

most notably in writings by Canadian legal scholars (ra<strong>the</strong>r than political<br />

scientists). <strong>The</strong> most thorough example of this can be found in Michael<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el’s book, <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Legalization of Politics in<br />

Canada (1989). Excellent examples can also be found in articles by Joel Bakan<br />

(1991) <strong>and</strong> Robert Martin (1991). But perhaps <strong>the</strong> most vociferous leftist<br />

assaults on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> have been launched by Andrew Petter, who is now<br />

British Columbia’s Aboriginal Affairs Minister, <strong>and</strong> Osgoode Hall <strong>La</strong>w<br />

School’s Alan Hutchinson (Petter, 1986, 1987, 1989; Petter <strong>and</strong> Hutchinson,<br />

1988, 1989, 1990; <strong>and</strong> Hutchinson, 1989, 1991).<br />

Simply put, <strong>the</strong>se scholars argue that despite its marketing as part of a<br />

“people’s package” <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is yet ano<strong>the</strong>r tool for <strong>the</strong> advancement of <strong>the</strong><br />

private interests of corporations, professionals, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r privileged groups at<br />

<strong>the</strong> expense of workers, <strong>the</strong> unemployed, women, aboriginals, racial<br />

minorities, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r socially <strong>and</strong> economically disadvantaged Canadians.<br />

<strong>The</strong> principal lines of argument advanced to support this conclusion involve<br />

discussions of (1) <strong>the</strong> nature of rights; (2) <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> judicial process<br />

itself, including problems with access to <strong>the</strong> judicial system <strong>and</strong> concerns with<br />

<strong>the</strong> composition of <strong>the</strong> judiciary; <strong>and</strong> (3) <strong>the</strong> Americanizing influence of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. First, left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> critics suggest that all those who supported <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> because <strong>the</strong>y saw it as a means of advancing <strong>the</strong> interests of<br />

disadvantaged Canadians failed to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> true nature of rights, i.e., that<br />

“<strong>the</strong> conferral of rights under a charter is a zero-sum ra<strong>the</strong>r than a positive-sum<br />

game” (Petter, 1986:474). Hence, exp<strong>and</strong>ing rights for some groups will result<br />

in <strong>the</strong> loss of entitlements for o<strong>the</strong>rs. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged will not be<br />

on <strong>the</strong> winning side of <strong>the</strong>se disputes because of <strong>the</strong> ideological nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

rights enshrined in our <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. As Andrew Petter puts it, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is “a 19th<br />

century document let loose on a 20th century welfare state. <strong>The</strong> rights in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are founded on <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> main enemies of freedom are not<br />

disparities in wealth nor concentrations of private power, but <strong>the</strong> state” (Petter,<br />

1987: 857).<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> rights conferred in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are largely negative rights<br />

aimed at protecting individuals from state interference ra<strong>the</strong>r than positive<br />

rights or entitlements to, say, employment, shelter or health care services. And<br />

since <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> politics is a zero-sum game, private rights are given to<br />

individuals only insofar as <strong>the</strong>y are taken away from governments <strong>and</strong> public<br />

institutions. This explains why <strong>the</strong> judicial activism of <strong>the</strong> courts has so far<br />

been confined to cases dealing with <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s legal rights provisions (e.g.,<br />

procedural rights of accused persons, prisoners <strong>and</strong> immigrants). Individuals<br />

<strong>and</strong> groups without much social power are sometimes beneficiaries of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

legal rights decisions; but, from <strong>the</strong> perspective of <strong>the</strong> legal left, <strong>the</strong> real<br />

winners are criminal lawyers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> system itself—<strong>the</strong> former benefits from<br />

more money <strong>and</strong> prestige, <strong>the</strong> latter benefits from much needed legitimation<br />

services (M<strong>and</strong>el, 1989: 128-83).<br />

98


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

Petter <strong>and</strong> his colleagues see it as ironic that <strong>the</strong> groups who supported <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> as a means of aiding <strong>the</strong> socially <strong>and</strong> economically disadvantaged are<br />

those who insist most forcefully upon <strong>the</strong> need for greater positive intervention<br />

by government. This is ironic since it is <strong>the</strong>se very groups who are likely to<br />

suffer <strong>the</strong> loss of hard-won entitlements as courts inhibit governmental ability<br />

to implement measures aimed at achieving greater social justice. Like<br />

Blakeney before him, <strong>the</strong>n, Petter fears that <strong>the</strong> power of governments to<br />

provide social services, to attempt to redistribute economic resources, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

regulate private conduct will be successfully attacked in <strong>the</strong> courts (Petter,<br />

1989: 152). Indeed, <strong>the</strong>re is already a body of evidence to suggest that some of<br />

this is now occurring—e.g., corporations are using <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to protect<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves against governmental regulation <strong>and</strong> control (M<strong>and</strong>el, 1989: 217-<br />

38; Martin, 1991: 124-25).<br />

In <strong>the</strong>ir second line of attack on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, leftist legal scholars argue that its<br />

supporters who see it as a distributive instrument are wrong because <strong>the</strong>y fail to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideological nature of <strong>the</strong> judicial framework in which <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

rights operate. “In a word,” explains Michael M<strong>and</strong>el, “<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has<br />

legalized our politics. But legalized politics is <strong>the</strong> quintessential conservative<br />

politics” (1989: 4). <strong>The</strong>re are two interrelated dimensions to this analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

adjudicative process: <strong>the</strong> first concerns <strong>the</strong> unequal access to <strong>the</strong> judicial<br />

process <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r concerns <strong>the</strong> composition of <strong>the</strong> judiciary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> biases<br />

of <strong>the</strong> courts.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> former matter, critics observe that access to <strong>the</strong> courts is extremely<br />

unequal. Although <strong>the</strong> formal equality provisions that govern <strong>the</strong> legal system<br />

entitle all to litigate, litigation is very expensive. Consequently, “oppressed<br />

<strong>and</strong> disempowered groups who are <strong>the</strong> supposed beneficiaries of progressive<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> litigation will, because of <strong>the</strong>ir lack of resources, be <strong>the</strong> least likely to<br />

have genuine access to <strong>the</strong> courts” (Bakan, 1991: 318). And even if <strong>the</strong>se<br />

groups are able to muster enough cash to get into court in <strong>the</strong> first place, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are likely to be at a competitive disadvantage since <strong>the</strong> lawyers on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

side, representing business or government, will have greater resources to fight<br />

<strong>the</strong> case. Groups representing left-wing causes are thus in a no-win situation<br />

when it comes to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: if <strong>the</strong>y resist <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> litigation <strong>the</strong>y may risk <strong>the</strong><br />

eradication of legislation beneficial to <strong>the</strong>ir interests; but if <strong>the</strong>y do succumb to<br />

<strong>the</strong> pressure to defend or promote <strong>the</strong>ir causes in court, that will mean that<br />

money, time <strong>and</strong> energy will be taken away from lobbying <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms of<br />

political action (Petter, 1987: 859; M<strong>and</strong>el, 1989: 70).<br />

As well as <strong>the</strong>se worries about unequal access, leftist scholars have raised<br />

concerns about <strong>the</strong> unrepresentativeness of <strong>the</strong> judiciary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideological<br />

biases within <strong>the</strong> judicial system. Judges in Canada are for <strong>the</strong> most part white,<br />

male <strong>and</strong> wealthy. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> legal training <strong>and</strong> work experience of judges<br />

tends to encourage affinities between <strong>the</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> beliefs of those on <strong>the</strong><br />

bench <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> interests of litigants who represent <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic elite.<br />

Thus <strong>the</strong>re exists an inevitable set of judicial biases against <strong>the</strong> economically<br />

<strong>and</strong> socially disadvantaged. By legalizing politics, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has vastly<br />

enhanced <strong>the</strong> political power of lawyers <strong>and</strong> judges who possess nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

“background, <strong>the</strong> experience, [n]or <strong>the</strong> training to comprehend <strong>the</strong> social<br />

impact of claims made to <strong>the</strong>m under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, let alone to resolve those<br />

claims in ways that promote, or even protect, <strong>the</strong> interests of disadvantaged<br />

Canadians” (Petter, 1989: 157).<br />

99


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Finally, left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes have noted that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has effected a<br />

shift from a British to an American conception of <strong>the</strong> appropriate relations<br />

between <strong>the</strong> legal profession <strong>and</strong> representative institutions. In particular, <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has promoted a redefinition of <strong>the</strong> judicial role along American lines.<br />

Unelected <strong>and</strong> unaccountable judges increasingly see <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court as<br />

<strong>the</strong> guardian of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r than simply as an adjudicator of<br />

disputes between parties. For many left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes this is an antidemocratic<br />

departure from our traditions of parliamentary supremacy. No one<br />

is more upset about this than Robert Martin, who complains that<br />

“Parliamentary government was <strong>the</strong> democratic heart of our political system.<br />

To subvert parliamentary government in Canada is, <strong>the</strong>n, to subvert<br />

democracy” (1991: 123).<br />

Martin goes on to discuss three ways in which <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been used in <strong>the</strong><br />

process of <strong>the</strong> Americanization of Canada. First, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> undermines <strong>the</strong><br />

sense of Canadian uniqueness. Now that we have a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> similar in most<br />

respects to <strong>the</strong> US Bill of Rights, we are quickly forgetting that we once had<br />

our own values, institutions <strong>and</strong> practices. And it does not help that Canadian<br />

courts, in <strong>the</strong> absence of any significant history of home-grown civil liberties<br />

case law, have relied upon American precedents to determine solutions to<br />

Canadian legal problems. This underlines <strong>the</strong> fact that large numbers of<br />

Canadians, especially students, now believe that prior to <strong>the</strong> enactment of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in 1982 Canadians enjoyed virtually no rights.<br />

Second, Martin complains that Canadian judges have taken to proclaiming <strong>the</strong><br />

social <strong>and</strong> political primacy of <strong>the</strong> individual. Not only is this contrary to our<br />

tory past, but it undermines <strong>the</strong> potential legitimacy of collectivist public<br />

policy. We are being taught to conceptualize our needs, desires <strong>and</strong> whims as<br />

rights. This rights-thinking, by its nature, is alienating <strong>and</strong> socially divisive.<br />

Michael M<strong>and</strong>el (1989: 239) agrees, adding that <strong>the</strong> individualism of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> can be damaging to subordinate groups, such as women <strong>and</strong><br />

aboriginals, who see <strong>the</strong>ir interests best served by <strong>the</strong> protection of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

collective rights ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> individual rights of <strong>the</strong>ir members. And Petter<br />

<strong>and</strong> Hutchinson (1988: 292) point out that <strong>the</strong> individualizing thrust of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

rights has allowed judges to support a mythical public/private distinction that<br />

limits <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s applicability to legislative or governmental action while<br />

excluding from <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> scrutiny <strong>the</strong> major source of inequality within our<br />

society—<strong>the</strong> maldistribution of private property entitlements among<br />

individuals.<br />

Third, Martin argues that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has encouraged <strong>the</strong> contemporary<br />

process of deligitimizing politics <strong>and</strong> worshipping economics. It does so<br />

because <strong>the</strong> negative nature of rights means that <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases almost<br />

inevitably involve an individual seeking protection against <strong>the</strong> strong arm of<br />

<strong>the</strong> state. So, Martin assumes, if rights are seen as “good,” <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> state will be<br />

seen as “bad.” This process is especially insidious in Canada, Martin worries,<br />

since here <strong>the</strong>re has traditionally been a higher acceptance rate for positive<br />

state action than in <strong>the</strong> USA. In some ways, Canadian society has been a virtual<br />

creation of state action, <strong>and</strong> state institutions have played a decisive role in <strong>the</strong><br />

development of a unique Canadian identity. Hence, “to put <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of<br />

<strong>the</strong> state in doubt is to put <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of Canada in doubt” (Martin, 1991:<br />

130).<br />

It is interesting to note, in conclusion, that <strong>the</strong> left-wing attack on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

concerns almost exclusively its promise to better protect fundamental rights<br />

100


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

<strong>and</strong> freedoms. Leftist legal scholars are largely silent on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r primary<br />

political purpose of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, as identified by Peter Russell, which “has to<br />

do with national unity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s capacity to offset, if not reverse, <strong>the</strong><br />

centrifugal forces which some believe threaten <strong>the</strong> survival of Canada as a<br />

unified country” (1983: 30). Nor do <strong>the</strong>y raise any concerns about <strong>the</strong> process<br />

that Alan Cairns has traced. In his writings, Cairns has shown how a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

that emphasizes <strong>the</strong> rights of citizens ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> powers of governments<br />

tends to transform, in his words, a “Government’s <strong>Constitution</strong>” to a “Citizens’<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>” (1991: 108-38, 199-222).<br />

Why is it that <strong>the</strong> leftist fear of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is not so great when it comes to its<br />

centralizing influence? One reason might be that socialists <strong>and</strong> social<br />

democrats in Canada have historically believed that a strong central<br />

government is necessary in order to redistribute wealth <strong>and</strong> income, to provide<br />

social security <strong>and</strong> to constrain <strong>the</strong> power of big business. To <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> actually works as a nationalizing force, <strong>the</strong>n, it is consistent with social<br />

democratic purposes. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> left is not about to lament <strong>the</strong> demise of<br />

elite accommodation (“eleven men in suits deciding <strong>the</strong> nation’s future”) if <strong>the</strong><br />

result is an increased role in <strong>the</strong> decision-making process for representatives of<br />

various citizens’ groups—e.g., women’s groups, aboriginal groups <strong>and</strong><br />

minority groups. To <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> really works to make ours more<br />

of a citizens’ constitution, <strong>the</strong>n, it is again consistent with social democratic<br />

principles.<br />

Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia<br />

Turning next to right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia, we should note that it, too, was<br />

present during <strong>the</strong> 1981 negotiations in <strong>the</strong> person of Manitoba Premier<br />

Sterling Lyon—“<strong>the</strong> stubby, irascible, Praetorian guardsman of a vanishing<br />

British Canada” (Sheppard <strong>and</strong> Valpy, 1982: 10-11). Premier Lyon expressed<br />

concerns that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would undermine <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> monarchy in Canada<br />

<strong>and</strong> that it would dictate <strong>the</strong> behaviour of provincial governments in relation to<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir religious, ethnic <strong>and</strong> ideological minorities. Most importantly, however,<br />

he saw entrenched rights as a threat to <strong>the</strong> doctrine of parliamentary<br />

supremacy. In <strong>the</strong> end, <strong>the</strong>se views held even less sway than did Blakeney’s.<br />

As we know, Lyon, who had returned to Manitoba to fight a provincial<br />

election, suffered <strong>the</strong> indignity of being shut out, along with Quebec’s<br />

representatives, of <strong>the</strong> all-night negotiations that produced a draft agreement<br />

for <strong>the</strong> patriation of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> with a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms.<br />

Lyon himself went down to electoral defeat <strong>and</strong>, since <strong>the</strong>n, conservative<br />

politicians, like <strong>the</strong>ir leftist brethren, have ceased to play leading roles in <strong>the</strong><br />

anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> movement.<br />

Nowadays one has to look to representatives of right-wing interest groups to<br />

find a concerted political attack on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> its values. For example,<br />

REAL Women argues that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is being used by feminist group elites<br />

promoting <strong>the</strong>ir own personal extremist views to force governments to allow<br />

abortion, extend rights to same sex couples, provide universal subsidized<br />

childcare, <strong>and</strong> implement pay equity <strong>and</strong> affirmative action schemes. Many<br />

concerns have been raised in <strong>the</strong> conservative media as well—i.e., that<br />

expensive social programs will be forced on governments by courts<br />

sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to <strong>the</strong> needs of various equality-seeking groups (Simpson,<br />

1992a). Ano<strong>the</strong>r fear is that <strong>the</strong> “substantive equality” (equality of results)<br />

sought by <strong>the</strong>se groups will have to come at public expense <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> costs of<br />

<strong>the</strong> idea that formal rights must be enjoyed equally by all members of<br />

101


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

society—as Clifford Lincoln would say, that “rights are rights are rights”<br />

(Simpson, 1992b: 14A).<br />

Of course, many conservative politicians have raised similar concerns about<br />

<strong>the</strong> dangers of an overtly activist court. For instance, Justice Minister Kim<br />

Campbell worried that activist Supreme Court justices might force elected<br />

politicians to spend public money against <strong>the</strong>ir wishes. She fears, moreover,<br />

that if courts become unduly activist, <strong>and</strong> parliaments lose <strong>the</strong>ir ability to make<br />

key decisions, <strong>the</strong>n politicians will use this as an excuse to abdicate <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

policy-making responsibilities <strong>and</strong> leave all difficult or controversial<br />

decisions to <strong>the</strong> courts (Campbell, 1992). O<strong>the</strong>r conservative politicians,<br />

especially in <strong>the</strong> West, adopt <strong>the</strong> position most forcefully advanced by Reform<br />

Party Leader Preston Manning that Canada should have, like <strong>the</strong> USA, a<br />

concept of rights that makes no mention of race, gender or language. In<br />

addition, many right-wing politicians in Canada wish to emulate <strong>the</strong> American<br />

model of individualism <strong>and</strong> free-enterprise by including a provision for<br />

property rights in <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, most conservative politicians today appear to accept <strong>the</strong> notion<br />

that rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms should be guaranteed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> integrity of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

defended. Indeed, Conservative Prime Minister Brian Mulroney has gone on<br />

record saying that “<strong>the</strong> constitution is not worth <strong>the</strong> paper it is written on”—but<br />

not because <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> places unnecessary limits on <strong>the</strong> power of elected<br />

parliamentarians. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong> reason for <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister’s outrage<br />

is that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> goes too far in accommodating <strong>the</strong> supremacy of Parliament<br />

(especially of provincial parliaments) since its infamous “notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

clause” allows for <strong>the</strong> override of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provisions.<br />

Quite <strong>the</strong> opposite view is expressed by those academics I will call “right-wing<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes.” <strong>The</strong> most powerful figures in this movement are political<br />

scientists ra<strong>the</strong>r than lawyers, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> most prominent among <strong>the</strong>m are<br />

University of Calgary professors Rainer Knopff <strong>and</strong> F.L. Morton. <strong>The</strong>se two<br />

have espoused <strong>the</strong>ir views on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> separately, collectively <strong>and</strong> with<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r collaborators in recent books, articles <strong>and</strong> conference papers (Knopff,<br />

1988, 1989; Morton, 1990, 1991, 1992; Morton, et al., 1990; Morton <strong>and</strong><br />

Knopff, 1990, 1992); but perhaps <strong>the</strong> most accessible single source is <strong>the</strong>ir new<br />

book, <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Politics (1992). It must be noted, however, that in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

Politics Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton take considerable pains to subordinate <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

views to <strong>the</strong> general task of clarifying <strong>the</strong> debates about <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Thus <strong>the</strong>y<br />

portray <strong>the</strong>se quarrels in terms of <strong>the</strong> opposition between “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>philes” <strong>and</strong><br />

“<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> sceptics” (of both <strong>the</strong> left <strong>and</strong> right), not between <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>philes <strong>and</strong><br />

Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong>mselves key participants in <strong>the</strong><br />

debate <strong>the</strong>y are attempting to clarify, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re can be no doubt that <strong>the</strong>ir work<br />

should be identified as a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> critique from <strong>the</strong> political right.<br />

Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton argue that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is nei<strong>the</strong>r democratic nor consistent<br />

with <strong>the</strong> traditional liberal respect for <strong>the</strong> private sphere <strong>and</strong> limited<br />

government. <strong>The</strong>ir principal lines of argument include (1) <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> promotes equality at <strong>the</strong> expense of private liberty <strong>and</strong> individual<br />

rights, <strong>and</strong> that its implementation involves a massive <strong>and</strong> unwelcome exercise<br />

in “social technology”; (2) <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> judiciary has nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

democratic legitimacy nor <strong>the</strong> political competence to justify its<br />

transformation since <strong>the</strong> introduction of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> from an adjudicative body<br />

to a policy-making one; <strong>and</strong> (3) <strong>the</strong> claim that a “court party” of feminists, civil<br />

libertarians, environmentalists, <strong>and</strong> racial <strong>and</strong> ethnic minorities have, with <strong>the</strong><br />

102


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

aid of <strong>the</strong>ir left-liberal lawyers, used <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to advance <strong>the</strong>ir own narrow<br />

(“special”) interests over <strong>and</strong> against <strong>the</strong> wishes of <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>and</strong> its duly<br />

elected servants.<br />

First, <strong>the</strong> right-wing critique of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is grounded on a <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

analysis of <strong>the</strong> shifting meanings of democracy <strong>and</strong> rights from <strong>the</strong>ir classical<br />

liberal roots to <strong>the</strong> present. That is, <strong>the</strong> original idea of democratic government<br />

emphasized political rights <strong>and</strong> formal equality of individuals, while today’s<br />

rights advocates have in mind social rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> equality of group results. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> earlier view, rights would secure a sphere of private liberty invaded only by<br />

<strong>the</strong> few limits on personal action that could be consented to by self-interested<br />

individuals in order for <strong>the</strong>m to live as safely as possible. According to this line<br />

of thought, inequality of political or legal rights would be prohibited but o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

forms of inequality were expected to flourish. Indeed, as <strong>the</strong> greatest liberal<br />

<strong>the</strong>orists all seemed to agree, <strong>the</strong> very purpose of government was not to make<br />

individuals better or to force <strong>the</strong>m to live in equal conditions, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to<br />

protect <strong>the</strong>ir unequal capacities of acquiring <strong>and</strong> enjoying property (Knopff,<br />

1989: 17-31).<br />

In contemporary rights <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> practice, however, <strong>the</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> classical<br />

liberal equation are reversed—individual liberty is restricted in <strong>the</strong> name of<br />

social equality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> private domain is whittled away in favour of increased<br />

public authority. In what Knopff calls “<strong>the</strong> new war on discrimination,” <strong>the</strong><br />

systemic deficiencies of existing society are attacked by a set of rationalist<br />

rules designed to achieve <strong>the</strong> intellectually derived criteria of “individual<br />

treatment” <strong>and</strong> “equality of result.” For Knopff, <strong>the</strong> irony of <strong>the</strong> situation is that<br />

<strong>the</strong> language of human rights, originally a bulwark of individual liberty <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy, has been appropriated by <strong>the</strong> foes of liberal democracy who use it<br />

to deny personal freedom <strong>and</strong> to suppress democratic decision making<br />

(Knopff, 1989: 213).<br />

<strong>The</strong> argument runs that today’s rights enthusiasts wish to subject essentially<br />

unplanned social processes to a variety of unrealistic <strong>and</strong> illiberal policy<br />

initiatives—e.g., anti-discrimination legislation enforced by human rights<br />

commissions, equality provisions entrenched in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> affirmative<br />

action programs. <strong>The</strong> shared characteristic of <strong>the</strong>se policy developments is<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir attempt to remake human beings by changing <strong>the</strong> social environment.<br />

According to Knopff, <strong>the</strong>se exercises at “constructivist social technology” are<br />

bound to fail since <strong>the</strong> anti-social tendencies <strong>the</strong>y seek to eradicate are rooted<br />

in nature. Consequently, “such projects in social engineering are<br />

fundamentally misconceived <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> suppression of freedom <strong>the</strong>y require will<br />

be permanent, not temporary” (Knopff, 1989: 22).<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> principal result of entrenching <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been to transfer<br />

political power from more accountable democratic institutions to relatively<br />

unaccountable judicial <strong>and</strong> quasi-judicial agencies that are under <strong>the</strong> sway of a<br />

leftist <strong>and</strong> partisan intellectual elite. That is why Morton <strong>and</strong> Knopff argue that<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is both undemocratic <strong>and</strong> illiberal. It is undemocratic because it<br />

results in a legalized politics that bypasses <strong>the</strong> traditional democratic processes<br />

of collective self-government through popular elections <strong>and</strong> responsible<br />

parliamentary government. And it is illiberal to <strong>the</strong> extent that its “most ardent<br />

partisans <strong>and</strong> practitioners are imbued with an ‘unconstrained’ vision of<br />

politics that is anti<strong>the</strong>tical to <strong>the</strong> respect for <strong>the</strong> private sphere <strong>and</strong> limited<br />

government that informs <strong>the</strong> tradition of constitutionalism” (Morton <strong>and</strong><br />

Knopff, 1992: 2).<br />

103


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

This underpins Knopff’s <strong>and</strong> Morton’s second main line of criticism of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>—that <strong>the</strong> triumph of legalized politics means that <strong>the</strong> courtroom is<br />

now more than ever a political arena <strong>and</strong> that judges are, at least potentially,<br />

“politicians in robes.” Whe<strong>the</strong>r judges will exercise this power to its full<br />

potential depends upon how <strong>the</strong>y view <strong>the</strong>ir role in <strong>the</strong> political process. Hence<br />

<strong>the</strong> crucial importance of <strong>the</strong> debates discussed in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Politics, i.e., those<br />

over <strong>the</strong> proper balance between judicial “activism” <strong>and</strong> “self-restraint,” as<br />

well as over <strong>the</strong> merits of <strong>the</strong> leading <strong>the</strong>ories of constitutional interpretation—<br />

“interpretivism” <strong>and</strong> “noninterpretivism.”<br />

Although <strong>the</strong>y are not always dogmatic on this point, Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton tend<br />

to side with restrained interpretivism over noninterpretivist activism. That is,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y prefer a court limited to enforcing original or traditional underst<strong>and</strong>ings in<br />

a restrained manner ra<strong>the</strong>r to one that boldly exerts its policy influence in order<br />

to keep political institutions relevant in rapidly changing times. It is generally<br />

felt that this sort of judicial self-restraint should impede radical policy<br />

initiatives or, at least, reduce <strong>the</strong> possibility that radical policies will be<br />

generated by a judiciary itself over-anxious to prescribe political remedies for<br />

legal problems. <strong>The</strong> usual defence of this view is a separation of power<br />

argument: <strong>the</strong>re is a division of responsibilities between <strong>the</strong> executive <strong>and</strong><br />

legislative branches on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> judicial branch on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r; to <strong>the</strong><br />

extent that judges allow <strong>the</strong>mselves to engage in courtroom politics, <strong>the</strong>y have<br />

overstepped <strong>the</strong>ir proper authority <strong>and</strong> become instruments of anti-democratic<br />

forces.<br />

Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton suggest that violations by <strong>the</strong> courts of this separation of<br />

powers doctrine have been vastly multiplied since <strong>the</strong> introduction of an<br />

entrenched charter. With its vaguely worded provisions, generally open to a<br />

variety of interpretations, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rarely involves judges in simply<br />

enforcing law-like rights against insensitive governments. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> judges<br />

are now actively involved in making laws, in creating new rights. Hence <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been a catalyst for an unprecedented style of activist judicial<br />

review. Courts are no longer content with simply invalidating, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

delaying (perhaps temporarily), policy decisions by elected representatives.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y now feel emboldened to tell <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r branches of government what <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have to do <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong>y have to do it. This is problematic for reasons <strong>the</strong> leftist<br />

critics might have advanced <strong>the</strong>mselves: (1) it is undemocratic to have<br />

appointed judges trespassing on <strong>the</strong> policy-making jurisdiction of duly elected<br />

politicians, <strong>and</strong> (2) <strong>the</strong> judges doing <strong>the</strong> trespassing have no special<br />

competence in resolving difficult social, moral <strong>and</strong> political problems.<br />

Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton object to both <strong>the</strong> consequences of an increasingly<br />

noninterpretivist activism among judges <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> general belief that helps<br />

sustain this practice—i.e., that judges <strong>and</strong> not politicians are <strong>the</strong> best oracles of<br />

what <strong>the</strong> law requires. In <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Politics, <strong>the</strong>refore, Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton<br />

ponder alternatives to <strong>the</strong> politics of <strong>the</strong> oracular courtroom. One possibility<br />

would be to restrict judicial decisions to <strong>the</strong> immediate adjudicative context.<br />

Under this scheme, judicial opinions would be persuasive but not binding on<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r branches of government (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton, 1992: 178-79). Ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

proposal, one which <strong>the</strong>y seem to endorse more heartily, would see <strong>the</strong> policy<br />

opinions of <strong>the</strong> judiciary fully integrated into an overtly political system of<br />

checks <strong>and</strong> balances. In this way, one could reject judicial finality without<br />

rejecting judicial review (even noninterpretivist activism). One way in which<br />

judicial policy-making can be integrated into a system of checks <strong>and</strong> balances<br />

involves what Peter Russell (1982: 32) has called “<strong>the</strong> legislative review of<br />

104


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

judicial review.” Although a version of this already exists in <strong>the</strong> override<br />

clause (at least for provisions in Sections 2 <strong>and</strong> 7-15), Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton point<br />

out that <strong>the</strong> existing Canadian legislative <strong>and</strong> executive institutions would<br />

have to be reformed before <strong>the</strong>y enjoyed <strong>the</strong> legitimacy necessary for <strong>the</strong>m to<br />

act as effective counterweights for <strong>the</strong> courts (1992: 232-33).<br />

In any case, replacing oracular legalism with a healthy system of checks <strong>and</strong><br />

balances would have <strong>the</strong> special merit of discouraging interest groups from<br />

using <strong>the</strong> courtroom as a political arena. If decisions by <strong>the</strong> courts are no longer<br />

final, <strong>the</strong>n interest groups will be less likely to attempt to use <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> courts to circumvent <strong>the</strong> traditional channels of policy making. Indeed, <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that so many organized interests have succeeded in doing just this is <strong>the</strong><br />

third major feature of <strong>the</strong> right-wing argument against <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton argue that “<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s main beneficiaries are special<br />

interest groups, who invoke it to persuade appointed judges to reverse <strong>the</strong><br />

decisions of democratically elected representatives” (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton,<br />

1992: 28). In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong>se groups turn to an undemocratic institution to<br />

seek victories that eluded <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong> normal arena of free <strong>and</strong> open democratic<br />

competition. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong>n, rewards losers who whine loudly enough<br />

about <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong>ir specific rights <strong>and</strong> entitlements to get a<br />

sympa<strong>the</strong>tic hearing in court. Activist judges, meanwhile, will open wide <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

courtroom doors to <strong>the</strong>se interest group litigants, even those who have no more<br />

direct stake in <strong>the</strong> outcome of <strong>the</strong> case than <strong>the</strong> ordinary citizen generally.<br />

What is more, courts will hear moot cases when interest groups convince <strong>the</strong>m<br />

that <strong>the</strong> issues posed are of sufficient public importance (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton,<br />

1992: 193).<br />

For Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton, <strong>the</strong> introduction of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has not made ours a<br />

more democratic “Citizens’ <strong>Constitution</strong>” but a constitution of special<br />

interests. <strong>The</strong> argument runs that <strong>the</strong> transfer of power from <strong>the</strong> legislatures to<br />

<strong>the</strong> courts has promoted <strong>the</strong> growth of a “court party” in Canadian politics that<br />

consists of new citizens’ interest groups, state bureaucracies, academics <strong>and</strong><br />

media elites (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton, 1992: 79-80; Morton <strong>and</strong> Knopff, 1992: 6-<br />

21). Unlike political parties that participate in elections, <strong>the</strong> “court party” is a<br />

new social movement that prefers <strong>the</strong> policy-making power of <strong>the</strong> courts to <strong>the</strong><br />

democratic world of polling booths <strong>and</strong> legislatures. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provides <strong>the</strong><br />

foundation for this “court party” to <strong>the</strong> extent that it officially recognizes a<br />

number of specific groups <strong>and</strong> interests. Women receive explicit recognition<br />

in Sections 15 <strong>and</strong> 28; racial <strong>and</strong> ethnic minorities are included in Sections 15<br />

<strong>and</strong> 27; Section 15 also bestows official status on age-based groups, <strong>and</strong> on<br />

those representing <strong>the</strong> interests of <strong>the</strong> mentally or physically h<strong>and</strong>icapped; <strong>the</strong><br />

rights of minority language groups are enshrined in Sections 16 to 23; <strong>and</strong><br />

aboriginal interests are recognized in Sections 25 <strong>and</strong> 35.<br />

<strong>The</strong> politics of <strong>the</strong> “court party” involves <strong>the</strong> calculated attempts by <strong>the</strong>se<br />

groups to maintain <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir visibility <strong>and</strong> status. <strong>The</strong> key currency<br />

here is explicit recognition as a constitutional category: “<strong>Constitution</strong>al status<br />

gives a group official public status of <strong>the</strong> highest order, <strong>and</strong> groups who enjoy<br />

it have an advantage impressing <strong>the</strong>ir claims against government over groups<br />

who do not” (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton, 1992: 82). <strong>The</strong> self interest of those groups<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s that any who are already in <strong>the</strong> “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> club” must seek to exclude<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r entrants, no matter how politically relevant. And <strong>the</strong> club members<br />

constantly fight amongst <strong>the</strong>mselves for relative power, attempting to<br />

105


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

construct pecking-orders or hierarchies of constitutionally protected interests<br />

that are to <strong>the</strong>ir own particular advantage.<br />

Needless to say, this is not a flattering picture of <strong>the</strong> role in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> politics<br />

played by contemporary citizens’ groups. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>y are portrayed as a<br />

divisive <strong>and</strong> potentially undemocratic element in our public life. Yet even<br />

right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes recognize that <strong>the</strong> formalism of legalized politics<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> biases of <strong>the</strong> judicial process have so far combined to limit <strong>the</strong> legal<br />

victories of feminist, aboriginal, social action or ethnocultural groups. Still, as<br />

Alan Cairns <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs have shown, <strong>the</strong> greatest influence of such groups has<br />

been realized in constitutional politics. This, too, is a result of <strong>the</strong>ir official<br />

recognition as <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> club members—that is, as potentially affected groups<br />

<strong>the</strong>y dem<strong>and</strong> involvement in any process that might be consequential for <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

constitutional fate. According to many right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> critics, this has a<br />

divisive ra<strong>the</strong>r than a unifying influence. Thus, in this area at least, <strong>the</strong> dreams<br />

of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> supporters to forge a national consensus around shared <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

rights is unrealized. Indeed, it may be argued that <strong>the</strong> very multiplicity of group<br />

concerns works against <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s intended success at creating a single,<br />

unifying Canadian identity.<br />

Review <strong>and</strong> Criticism<br />

As we have seen, both left- <strong>and</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes condemn <strong>the</strong> rise of<br />

legalized politics <strong>and</strong> bemoan <strong>the</strong> undemocratic consequences of judicial<br />

review of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. But as is <strong>the</strong> case in interpretations of legal decisions, <strong>the</strong><br />

important part is less <strong>the</strong> verdict than <strong>the</strong> reasons behind it. It is here that we<br />

find considerable tension between <strong>the</strong> philosophies underlying <strong>the</strong>se majority<br />

concurring decisions.<br />

<strong>The</strong> bottom line for <strong>the</strong> legal left is that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is a disaster because it is a<br />

liberal document. For <strong>the</strong>se critics, “Liberalism is a failure: it cannot pass<br />

conceptual, social, legal, or political muster. A continued reliance on its<br />

intellectual assumptions <strong>and</strong> ideological prescriptions is indefensible” (Petter<br />

<strong>and</strong> Hutchinson, 1988: 295). <strong>The</strong> immediate need is to ab<strong>and</strong>on liberal<br />

individualism <strong>and</strong> to replace it with some form of social democracy that might<br />

be capable of responding to <strong>the</strong> inequalities of economic <strong>and</strong> political power<br />

that liberalism <strong>and</strong> its disciples permit <strong>and</strong> condone. This would entail a real<br />

redistribution of power in ways contradicting <strong>the</strong> logic of <strong>the</strong> marketplace. It<br />

would mean, at a minimum, a significant expansion of <strong>the</strong> public sector <strong>and</strong> a<br />

contraction of <strong>the</strong> private sphere (M<strong>and</strong>el, 1989: 267).<br />

Needless to say, this is not a prospect to which right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes look<br />

forward with great joys of anticipation. <strong>The</strong>y are more likely to respond, in <strong>the</strong><br />

spirit of Adam Smith, that a system of private property rights is <strong>the</strong> best way to<br />

channel natural human selfishness into socially useful projects. What is more,<br />

intervention by <strong>the</strong> state on <strong>the</strong> behalf of groups who are disproportionately at<br />

<strong>the</strong> lower levels of status <strong>and</strong> class hierarchies is seen by most on <strong>the</strong> right as a<br />

violation of <strong>the</strong> democratic idea of <strong>the</strong> formal equality of rights. It should be<br />

condemned, as well, for strictly practical reasons: human nature being what it<br />

is, success in planning <strong>the</strong> lives of o<strong>the</strong>r people or of society as a whole is likely<br />

to be limited.<br />

In any event, <strong>the</strong> eradication of free market capitalism in Canada does not seem<br />

immanent. Hence, right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes are willing to take <strong>the</strong>ir chances<br />

that <strong>the</strong> ideas of M<strong>and</strong>el, Petter, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs on <strong>the</strong> anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> left will fail to<br />

capture much of a market share in any free <strong>and</strong> open democratic competition.<br />

106


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

What is more troublesome, from <strong>the</strong>ir point of view, is <strong>the</strong> ascendancy of a pro-<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, left-liberal egalitarian democracy. It is this ideology that Knopff <strong>and</strong><br />

Morton fear has taken over <strong>the</strong> legal profession <strong>and</strong> justified <strong>the</strong> granting of an<br />

unfair advantage to “special” interest groups—groups based more on gender,<br />

race <strong>and</strong> ethnicity than on class.<br />

But is <strong>the</strong>re any concrete evidence to support <strong>the</strong>se claims? I think not. First,<br />

right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes can point to few cases where <strong>the</strong>ir fears have been<br />

realized concerning activist judicial review of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> forcing<br />

governments to spend money against <strong>the</strong>ir wishes. Second, recent evidence<br />

suggests that we should not exaggerate <strong>the</strong> audacity of <strong>the</strong> courts, except<br />

perhaps in legal rights cases. After an original spurt of judicial activism, <strong>the</strong><br />

Supreme Court seems to have settled back to a more comfortable role of<br />

simply ensuring that <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights are not violated flagrantly. <strong>The</strong> Court has<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r tired of actively challenging governments’ decision-making<br />

prerogatives. One indication of this is <strong>the</strong> steep drop in <strong>the</strong> rate at which <strong>the</strong><br />

Court has been striking down legislation. It is often pointed out that in its first<br />

fifteen <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> decisions <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court upheld <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claim in a<br />

staggering nine cases—a 60% success rate for <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claimants. According to<br />

one recent count, however, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> success rate fell to 17.5% in 1989-90 (7<br />

out of 40 cases), <strong>and</strong> to a minuscule 11.8% (2 out of 17) in cases outside<br />

criminal law (Eliot: 1992). <strong>The</strong>re might be several reasons for this: <strong>the</strong><br />

changing nature of cases coming forward; <strong>the</strong> conservative influence of recent<br />

judicial appointments; or a rethinking by <strong>the</strong> justices <strong>the</strong>mselves of <strong>the</strong>ir role in<br />

<strong>the</strong> political process. In any event, <strong>the</strong> evidence seems to point to a greater<br />

acceptance of judicial self-restraint, at least since <strong>the</strong> Edwards Books decision<br />

in 1986.<br />

Of course, <strong>the</strong> numbers may not tell <strong>the</strong> whole story. <strong>The</strong> very possibility of<br />

negative judicial decisions may be forcing governments to make corrections or<br />

assessments prior to <strong>the</strong> enactment of legislation. Since politicians would<br />

inevitably rely upon lawyers within <strong>the</strong>ir Justice Departments to carry out<br />

<strong>the</strong>se assessments—to make sure that legislation is “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>proof,” to use<br />

Patrick Monahan’s phrase (1992)—political power may have gravitated<br />

towards <strong>the</strong> technical, legal experts <strong>and</strong> away from <strong>the</strong> elected politicians. This<br />

means ano<strong>the</strong>r triumph for legalized politics <strong>and</strong> raises alarms about<br />

democratic legitimacy <strong>and</strong> policy-making competence similar to those<br />

sounded by left- <strong>and</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes.<br />

But is it necessarily a bad thing that governments have learned to double-check<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir plans against <strong>the</strong> prevailing values <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provisions?<br />

Indeed, if politicians cannot convince <strong>the</strong>ir own bureaucrats that <strong>the</strong>ir policies<br />

<strong>and</strong> programs are sensible, necessary, or o<strong>the</strong>rwise “demonstrably justifiable<br />

in a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society,” <strong>the</strong>n perhaps <strong>the</strong>y have no business enacting<br />

<strong>the</strong>m, after all. And anyway, <strong>the</strong> courts are only assessing legislation according<br />

to provisions placed in a charter only recently by duly elected governments,<br />

governments that have <strong>the</strong> power to amend those provisions (or to override<br />

most of <strong>the</strong>m) in <strong>the</strong> event of overwhelming popular evidence that this is<br />

necessary. Yet Canadian governments have still failed to demonstrate that,<br />

when left to <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>the</strong>y can be trusted to make sure that <strong>the</strong>ir legislation<br />

passes <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards. This was proved during <strong>the</strong> three years allotted to<br />

<strong>the</strong>m to clean up statutes that might violate Section 15. Few governments made<br />

wise use of that time <strong>and</strong> many found <strong>the</strong>mselves having to react in a near panic<br />

situation.<br />

107


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Moreover, even <strong>the</strong> most progressive gains that have been made in <strong>the</strong> courts<br />

against <strong>the</strong> will of governments by certain individuals <strong>and</strong> groups have not, in<br />

my mind, come at <strong>the</strong> expense of any fundamental principles of Canadian<br />

democracy. Voting rights for people with disabilities, new rules about<br />

sentencing individuals found not guilty by reason of insanity, expansion of <strong>the</strong><br />

due process rights of alleged perpetrators or incarcerated persons,<br />

decriminalization of abortion, rollbacks of pay equity caps, rights to UIC<br />

benefits for those over sixty-five, limited expansion of benefits to same sex<br />

couples, abolition of discriminatory “spouse in <strong>the</strong> house rules” for social<br />

services—all of <strong>the</strong>se victories for underprivileged individuals <strong>and</strong> groups<br />

enhance, ra<strong>the</strong>r than undermine, <strong>the</strong> democratic character of our society. <strong>The</strong><br />

fact that <strong>the</strong>y were won in <strong>the</strong> courts ra<strong>the</strong>r than in <strong>the</strong> legislative arena does not<br />

make <strong>the</strong>m any less democratic.<br />

And what about <strong>the</strong> central component to <strong>the</strong> right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobic<br />

attack—<strong>the</strong> rise of a “court party”? Here, too, I see little evidence that<br />

feminists, anti-racists, multicultural activists, or any o<strong>the</strong>r special groups have<br />

pursued <strong>the</strong>ir social policy agendas in <strong>the</strong> courts to <strong>the</strong> disregard of o<strong>the</strong>r, more<br />

direct, forms of democratic politics. And even if <strong>the</strong>y did, would this not be<br />

more of a condemnation of our system of party politics that has shut <strong>the</strong>m out<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than of our legalized <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> politics?<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> very assumption that <strong>the</strong>re are “special” interest groups that<br />

somehow shun <strong>the</strong> open glare of <strong>the</strong> public stage to pursue <strong>the</strong>ir narrow<br />

interests behind <strong>the</strong> closed doors of <strong>the</strong> courtrooms conveys a distorted image<br />

of reality. First, it ignores <strong>the</strong> fact that representatives of disadvantaged<br />

individuals <strong>and</strong> groups have been extremely active for generations in a variety<br />

of political forums, though not always successfully. <strong>The</strong> advent of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

has simply increased access to <strong>the</strong> courts of Canada for a wider range of<br />

groups. This only means that now <strong>the</strong>y, too, can approach <strong>the</strong> courts as a<br />

supplement to <strong>the</strong>ir o<strong>the</strong>r forms of activity, in <strong>the</strong> exact same way more<br />

institutionalized groups—largely business -oriented ones—have done for<br />

years. What seems to disturb right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes most, <strong>the</strong>n, is <strong>the</strong> types<br />

of groups that have now gained access. Yet groups with “special”<br />

interests—those from specific provinces or regions—have always been<br />

recognized players within federal- provincial relations or federalism<br />

jurisprudence. On this score, I fail to see why <strong>the</strong> narrow focus of regional<br />

interest is proper <strong>and</strong> legitimate, while <strong>the</strong> same is not true of <strong>the</strong> shared<br />

interest of women or people of colour.<br />

More important philosophically is <strong>the</strong> argument that special-interest group<br />

activity violates democratic ideals. This is said to be so because group or<br />

collective rights contradict <strong>the</strong> formal logic of free competition between<br />

equally rights-empowered individuals, <strong>and</strong> this makes it impossible for <strong>the</strong><br />

majority will to have <strong>the</strong> final say on all public issues. Political scientist Iris<br />

Young shows how this view assumes <strong>the</strong> intrinsic value of attaining some sort<br />

of “universality of a general will that leaves difference, particularity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

body behind in <strong>the</strong> private realms of family <strong>and</strong> civil life” (Young, 1990: 97).<br />

Young demonstrates that this idea of an “impartial general will” is a myth that<br />

serves ideological functions by masking <strong>the</strong> ways in which <strong>the</strong> particular<br />

perspectives of dominant groups claim universality, thus justifying<br />

hierarchical decision-making structures. Hence, she argues that <strong>the</strong> full<br />

inclusion <strong>and</strong> participation of everyone in public discussion requires more<br />

than a formally equal right for individual participation—it requires<br />

mechanisms for group representation. Social justice <strong>and</strong> equality for members<br />

108


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

of disadvantaged groups will only be had, she says, if difference is recognized<br />

<strong>and</strong> affirmed. And this sometimes means <strong>the</strong> accommodation of special rights<br />

that attend to specific group differences in order to undermine oppression <strong>and</strong><br />

disadvantage (Young, 1989: 117-41). Our <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> certainly does not<br />

guarantee that less advantaged groups will be given <strong>the</strong> means to overcome<br />

oppression <strong>and</strong> inequality. But by recognizing <strong>the</strong> special needs of those who<br />

have historically been targets for discrimination, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> helps to prevent<br />

at least <strong>the</strong> worst rights abuses <strong>and</strong> announces our society’s commitment to a<br />

certain st<strong>and</strong>ard of decency <strong>and</strong> respect for o<strong>the</strong>rs. And contrary to <strong>the</strong><br />

suspicions of some right-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes, it does so without harming<br />

unnecessarily <strong>the</strong> privileges of those already relatively well off in terms of<br />

social <strong>and</strong> economic power.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> left, of course, <strong>the</strong> fact that some fundamental rights are<br />

protected is not enough. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong>y say, recognizes only negative <strong>and</strong><br />

not positive rights, <strong>and</strong> its formalism dem<strong>and</strong>s that rights protection be applied<br />

equally to everyone. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, whatever marginal utility is derived from<br />

rights discourse is perceived by <strong>the</strong> legal left as being had at <strong>the</strong> expense of<br />

agendas for social reform. So concerned are <strong>the</strong>se scholars that some<br />

imaginary future government’s progressive social or economic policies might<br />

be overturned by conservative judges, that <strong>the</strong>y are willing to allow existing<br />

governments to do what ever <strong>the</strong>y want.<br />

This left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobic argument exaggerates, in my view, <strong>the</strong> disutility<br />

of rights in political advancement for disadvantaged groups. It ignores (or at<br />

least downplays) <strong>the</strong> fact of a long history of Canadian legislation against <strong>the</strong><br />

interests of women, <strong>the</strong> poor, aboriginals <strong>and</strong> racial <strong>and</strong> ethnic minorities. And<br />

its argument that negative rights are disutile, even harmful, trivializes <strong>the</strong> lived<br />

experience of any person or group whose vulnerability has been truly protected<br />

by rights. As Patricia Williams, an African American legal scholar, explains:<br />

“For <strong>the</strong> historically disempowered, <strong>the</strong> conferring of rights is symbolic of all<br />

<strong>the</strong> denied aspects of <strong>the</strong>ir humanity: rights imply a respect that places one in<br />

<strong>the</strong> referential range of self <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, that elevates one’s status from human<br />

body to social being. For blacks, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> attainment of rights signifies <strong>the</strong><br />

respectful behaviour, <strong>the</strong> collective responsibility, properly owed by a society<br />

to one of its own” (1991: 153). Williams reminds us that one’s sense of<br />

empowerment defines one’s relation to <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> to rights. Hence, <strong>the</strong> male<br />

white left, already rights-empowered, may feel that rights discourse should be<br />

replaced by some sort of needs discourse that would justify positive state<br />

action on behalf of <strong>the</strong> truly needy. But those who have been historically<br />

disempowered may not trust that <strong>the</strong> replacement of a formal legal rights<br />

system by a more informal political one will lead to better outcomes.<br />

A case in point is <strong>the</strong> debate within aboriginal communities over <strong>the</strong> utility of<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights. Male Native leaders tend to want aboriginal self-governments<br />

to be exempt from <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Representatives of Native women’s<br />

associations see things differently: “Native women <strong>and</strong> children need a<br />

safeguard against <strong>the</strong> abuse of power by male leaders <strong>and</strong>,” Gail Stacey Moore<br />

says, “until an acceptable alternative is put in place, we insist on having <strong>the</strong><br />

safeguard of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” (Globe& Mail [Toronto], 29 May 1992: A6). One<br />

cannot assume that <strong>the</strong> accommodation of collective or group aspirations will<br />

include <strong>the</strong> protection of significant individual rights. Nor should we assume<br />

that <strong>the</strong> majority of citizens out in <strong>the</strong> larger world want to overcome sexism,<br />

racism <strong>and</strong> alienation ra<strong>the</strong>r than heartily embrace <strong>the</strong>m. This underscores<br />

Williams’ sense of <strong>the</strong> importance of rights: “rights are to law what conscious<br />

109


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

commitments are to <strong>the</strong> psyche. This country’s worst historical moments have<br />

not been attributable to rights assertion but to a failure of rights commitment”<br />

(1991 159).<br />

On a more empirical level, as well, <strong>the</strong> left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobic argument is a<br />

poor guide to life in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>l<strong>and</strong>. As many have pointed out since 1982, <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms includes not just negative<br />

individual rights but also a long list of collective rights <strong>and</strong> some exemptions<br />

from rights (Elkins, 1989: 699-716). Without exhausting <strong>the</strong> list, one could<br />

mention “society’s rights” as conferred in Section 1; linguistic <strong>and</strong> minority<br />

language education rights; aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights; multicultural rights;<br />

affirmative action provisions in Sections 6(4) <strong>and</strong> 15(2); provincial group<br />

rights in Sections 38(2) <strong>and</strong> (3); <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> override provision in Section 33.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> lacks some of <strong>the</strong> more individualistic concepts found<br />

in <strong>the</strong> American Bill of Rights, most importantly property rights.<br />

Consequently, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is not as liberalizing, individualizing <strong>and</strong><br />

Americanizing as some critics would suggest.<br />

Still, left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes have been right to point out that <strong>the</strong> introduction<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has highlighted some real problems in our legal system: e.g.,<br />

access to <strong>the</strong> courts is unequal <strong>and</strong> judges are unrepresentative of <strong>the</strong> general<br />

population. But is this <strong>the</strong> fault of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> or are <strong>the</strong>se structures <strong>the</strong><br />

products of social forces <strong>and</strong> of individuals who want <strong>the</strong>m this way? It is<br />

certainly true, for instance, that by making it difficult for all but <strong>the</strong><br />

economically powerful to access <strong>the</strong> courts, high litigation costs help to<br />

determine how <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> guarantees will be interpreted. This is because vague<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provisions will only be clarified through a process of judicial<br />

interpretation. If <strong>the</strong> issues <strong>and</strong> concerns of <strong>the</strong> wealthy <strong>and</strong> powerful are given<br />

disproportionate attention in <strong>the</strong> courts, <strong>the</strong>n that will shape <strong>and</strong> influence <strong>the</strong><br />

authoritative decisions about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> scope of various rights in ways<br />

that reflect <strong>the</strong>se vested interests (Petter, 1989: 156-57). Yet governments can<br />

make policy decisions that would equalize access ei<strong>the</strong>r by changing <strong>the</strong> rules<br />

to reduce litigation costs or by providing public funds to allow economically<br />

disadvantaged groups to participate in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases as litigants or as<br />

interveners. <strong>The</strong> Court Challenges Program, recently terminated by <strong>the</strong><br />

Mulroney government, is a very modest example of <strong>the</strong> latter approach. <strong>The</strong><br />

crucial point, however, is that decisions about <strong>the</strong> creation, expansion <strong>and</strong><br />

demise of this program were made by elected politicians, <strong>the</strong> representatives of<br />

<strong>the</strong> many, <strong>and</strong> not by <strong>the</strong> few who are judges or lawyers.<br />

What is more, discussions about <strong>the</strong> high costs of litigation should not<br />

overlook <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>re is also an extremely high cost associated with<br />

electoral participation or with non-judicial, interest-group activity. This works<br />

to exclude socially <strong>and</strong> economically disadvantaged individuals <strong>and</strong> groups<br />

from democratic politics just as surely as it does from legalized politics.<br />

Likewise, one should not dismiss judicial review because of <strong>the</strong><br />

unrepresentativeness of judges without looking at <strong>the</strong> reality of representation<br />

in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two branches of government. In fact, <strong>the</strong>re are more reasons to be<br />

optimistic about <strong>the</strong> possibility of greater representativeness in <strong>the</strong> judiciary<br />

than in Parliament, where <strong>the</strong> party-centred system continues to create<br />

obstacles for <strong>the</strong> advancement of females <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r disadvantaged individuals.<br />

For instance, <strong>the</strong> composition of <strong>the</strong> judiciary is closely tied to law school<br />

populations, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re have been dramatic changes in <strong>the</strong>se institutions: in<br />

1971, only nine percent of law school graduates were women; by 1991,<br />

however, a full 51 percent of law students were women. This exp<strong>and</strong>ing pool<br />

110


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

of female lawyers will no doubt have its effect on <strong>the</strong> composition of <strong>the</strong><br />

judiciary in a few years. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> very fact that so many leftist <strong>and</strong><br />

feminist scholars are now teaching in law schools bodes well for <strong>the</strong> future<br />

development of a progressive left-liberal orientation in <strong>the</strong> legal profession.<br />

This brings us to a paradoxical feature of left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia—it is in<br />

many ways <strong>the</strong> more “conservative” of <strong>the</strong> two approaches. Left-wing<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes want to “conserve” or “preserve” <strong>the</strong> parliamentary status quo,<br />

partly in order to help protect those practices <strong>and</strong> attitudes that distinguish<br />

Canadian from American political culture. Yet can we assume, as Blakeney<br />

<strong>and</strong> Martin do, that our British-style, parliamentary democratic institutions<br />

work well enough as it is? A brief glance at <strong>the</strong> historical record should dispel<br />

any notions that freedom was better protected in <strong>the</strong> past by parliamentary<br />

governments than we can expect it to be by <strong>the</strong> courts in <strong>the</strong> future.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms joins four o<strong>the</strong>r instruments that have<br />

long been part of our constitutional system: (1) <strong>the</strong> rule of law; (2) <strong>the</strong> division<br />

of jurisdiction; (3) statutory bills of rights; <strong>and</strong> (4) <strong>the</strong> institutions of<br />

Parliament. But how effective have <strong>the</strong>se been as rights protectors? <strong>The</strong> idea<br />

that <strong>the</strong> rule of law is <strong>the</strong> bulwark that protects us from arbitrary treatment from<br />

<strong>the</strong> executive was brought home dramatically by <strong>the</strong> case of Roncarelli v.<br />

Duplessis in 1959. But <strong>the</strong>re are few o<strong>the</strong>r such dramatic cases. Reference re<br />

Alberta Statutes (1937) <strong>and</strong> Switzman v.Elbling (1957) prove that when courts<br />

decide on jurisdictional matters <strong>the</strong>y can also protect rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms. But<br />

<strong>the</strong>se cases were rare <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y do not demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> violation of<br />

democratic freedoms would be beyond all legislatures, only provincial ones.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> federal government’s passage of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Bill of Rights in<br />

1960 did not usher in a bright new dawn of rights enjoyment in this country.<br />

Aside from Drybones v. <strong>the</strong> Queen (1970), <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court was notoriously<br />

unwilling to strike down legislation even when it was clear that rights or<br />

freedoms mentioned in <strong>the</strong> Bill were being denied. Finally, <strong>the</strong>re is little<br />

evidence to suggest that <strong>the</strong> institutions of Parliament also serve to protect <strong>the</strong><br />

rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms of individuals. <strong>The</strong> party system <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rules of <strong>the</strong> House<br />

of Commons help to make sure that <strong>the</strong> opposition has little weight as an<br />

important sanction against repressive laws, even if it is opposed to <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Conclusion<br />

In conclusion, <strong>the</strong>n, I remain unconvinced by <strong>the</strong> recent crop of anti-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

writers that we have taken <strong>the</strong> wrong path by adopting an entrenched charter.<br />

This does not mean that I think <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is perfect, that it cannot be<br />

improved upon. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> response from citizens <strong>and</strong> interested parties<br />

during <strong>the</strong> so-called “Canada Round” of constitutional negotiations<br />

demonstrates that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> suffers from several serious omissions. Most<br />

importantly, <strong>the</strong>re is a lack of a better recognition that, as self-governing,<br />

majority cultures, aboriginals <strong>and</strong> Quebeckers have claims to distinct rights<br />

that are different in status to claims made by, say, religious or ethnic<br />

minorities. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord would have addressed some of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

concerns by entrenching into <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> an inherent right to aboriginal<br />

self-government <strong>and</strong> by recognizing Quebec as a distinct society within<br />

Canada. What is more, <strong>the</strong>re has been a concerted effort in recent years to<br />

exp<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existing list of rights to include some social or economic rights as<br />

well. It was more difficult for governments to agree to this change, however,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord included only an unjusticiable provision<br />

111


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

committing governments to <strong>the</strong> principle of preserving <strong>and</strong> developing<br />

Canada’s social <strong>and</strong> economic union.<br />

What is more, <strong>the</strong>re are still concerns with <strong>the</strong> incompatibility between an<br />

entrenched charter <strong>and</strong> a legislative override provision. In fact, <strong>the</strong><br />

notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause—<strong>the</strong> only <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provision applauded by both right<strong>and</strong><br />

left-wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobes—remains <strong>the</strong> most unpopular element of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Consequently, <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a Renewed Canada,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee, heard pleas for <strong>the</strong> dismantling of Section<br />

33 in every city where hearings were held. Representatives from minority<br />

groups, in particular, ureed that at least Section 15 (1) should be exempted<br />

from <strong>the</strong> clause. With <strong>the</strong> legislative override still in place, <strong>the</strong>y argued,<br />

minorities <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r less advantaged Canadians remain inadequately protected<br />

from rights abuses. Any changes to this provision would require unanimous<br />

provincial consent, however, <strong>and</strong> knowing that this would be impossible, <strong>the</strong><br />

drafters of our various constitutional reform packages since 1982 have<br />

consistently left out any such change.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> end, of course, <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord was rejected in <strong>the</strong> October<br />

1992 referendum. Crucial to its defeat were <strong>the</strong> lobbying efforts made by<br />

various pro-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> constituencies, including women’s groups, social justice<br />

advocates, <strong>and</strong> groups representing ethnic <strong>and</strong> racial minorities. Governments<br />

that supported <strong>the</strong> constitutional reforms were consistently put on <strong>the</strong><br />

defensive, forced to insist that <strong>the</strong> rights recognized <strong>and</strong> protected under <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would not be infringed or denied by any of <strong>the</strong> new provisions.<br />

Canadians, it would seem, have not only become used to life after <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,<br />

but recognize <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> as a valuable <strong>and</strong> authoritative symbol of this<br />

country’s commitment to freedom, equality <strong>and</strong> human dignity.<br />

I would add, never<strong>the</strong>less, that in spite of all <strong>the</strong> ink spilled over it, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

is only a part of our political system as a whole <strong>and</strong> its nature <strong>and</strong> function will<br />

be shaped <strong>and</strong> formed within <strong>the</strong> same matrix of social <strong>and</strong> economic forces<br />

that influence <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong> system. As a result, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has not had<br />

a dramatic effect on <strong>the</strong> distribution of wealth <strong>and</strong> power or on <strong>the</strong> level of<br />

social justice in Canadian society, nor should it have been expected to on its<br />

own. As Shelagh Day notes: “It doesn’t mean that women aren’t still being<br />

beaten, it doesn’t mean that women aren’t still earning less than men”<br />

(Victoria Times-Colonist [Victoria], 12 April 1992: A5). Of course, she is<br />

right: we still have children living in poverty; we have rampant racism <strong>and</strong><br />

homophobia; <strong>and</strong> we have people with disabilities who are prevented from<br />

achieving <strong>the</strong>ir full potential or who are not institutionalized when <strong>the</strong>y ought<br />

to be.<br />

Still, <strong>the</strong> constitutional guarantees in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> have altered <strong>the</strong> way<br />

Canadians view <strong>the</strong>ir relationship with government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y argue for<br />

change. In my view, this has been for <strong>the</strong> better. Not only has <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> given<br />

women <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r disadvantaged groups access to an additional arena of<br />

democratic participation, it has also signalled to those who resist progressive<br />

change that <strong>the</strong>y cannot so easily ignore <strong>the</strong> claims of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights-holders.<br />

In this sense, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, by holding out <strong>the</strong> prospect of attainment of equality<br />

or fairness under <strong>the</strong> law, has been a fiercely motivational force for those who<br />

have not always enjoyed much hope. It is for this reason that we must be<br />

warned against debasing rights or ab<strong>and</strong>oning <strong>the</strong> project of rights protection<br />

under a charter. “In discarding rights altoge<strong>the</strong>r,” as Williams points out, “one<br />

112


Left- <strong>and</strong> Right-Wing <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>phobia in Canada:<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Critics<br />

discards a symbol too deeply enmeshed in <strong>the</strong> psyche of <strong>the</strong> oppressed to lose<br />

without trauma <strong>and</strong> much resistance” (1991: 165).<br />

Notes<br />

* An earlier version of this paper was delivered at <strong>the</strong> annual meetings of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

Political Science Association in Charlottetown, PEI, June 1992. <strong>The</strong> author would like to<br />

thank Ted Morton <strong>and</strong> Rainer Knopff for helpful comments on <strong>the</strong> text.<br />

Bibliography<br />

Bakan, Joel (1990). “<strong>Constitution</strong>al Interpretation <strong>and</strong> Social Change: You Can’t Always Get<br />

What You Want.” In <strong>The</strong> Canadian Bar Review 70: 307-328.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. (1991). Disruptions: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Struggles, from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke.<br />

Ed. Douglas E. Williams. Toronto: McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Stewart.<br />

Campbell, Kim (1992). “Opening Remarks” to <strong>the</strong> conference “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Ten Years After.”<br />

May 15-16. Simon Fraser University at Harbour Centre, Vancouver BC. Forthcoming<br />

(1993) in P. Bryden, S. Davis <strong>and</strong> J. Russell (eds.), <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Ten Years After. Toronto:<br />

University of Toronto Press.<br />

Cheffins, Ronald I. <strong>and</strong> Patricia A. Johnson (1986). <strong>The</strong> Revised Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>: Politics<br />

as <strong>La</strong>w. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.<br />

Christian, William <strong>and</strong> Colin Campbell (1983). Political Parties <strong>and</strong> Ideologies in Canada. 3rd<br />

Ed. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.<br />

Eliot, Robin (1992). “<strong>The</strong> Effect of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> on <strong>the</strong> Role of <strong>the</strong> Courts.” Forthcoming in <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Ten Years After.<br />

Grant, George (1965). <strong>La</strong>ment for a Nation. Toronto: <strong>The</strong> Carleton Library No. 50, McClell<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Stewart.<br />

Greunding, Dennis (1990). Promises to Keep: A Political Biography of Alan Blakeney. Saskatoon:<br />

Western Producer Prairie Books.<br />

Hutchinson, Alan C. (1989). “Determinacy <strong>and</strong> Democracy: An Essay on Legal Interpretation.” In<br />

University of Miami <strong>La</strong>w Journal 43: 541-76.<br />

Hutchinson, Alan C. (1991). “Waiting for Coraf (Or <strong>the</strong> Beatification of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>).” In<br />

University of Toronto <strong>La</strong>w Journal 41: 332-56.<br />

Knopff, Rainer <strong>and</strong> F.L. Morton (1992). <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Politics. Scarborough: Nelson.<br />

Knopff, Rainer (1987). “What do <strong>Constitution</strong>al Equality Rights Protect Canadians Against?” In<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian Journal of Political Science 20: 265-86.<br />

Knopff, Rainer (1988). “Parliament vs. <strong>the</strong> Courts: Making Sense of <strong>the</strong> Bill of Rights Debate.” In<br />

Legislative Studies 3:2.<br />

Knopff, Rainer (1989). Human Rights & Social Technology: <strong>The</strong> New War on Discrimination.<br />

Ottawa: Carleton University Press.<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, Michael (1989). <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Legalization of Politics in Canada.<br />

Toronto: Wall <strong>and</strong> Thompson.<br />

Martin, Robert (1991). “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Crisis in Canada.” In After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: Lessons for<br />

<strong>the</strong> Future. Ed. David E. Smith, Peter MacKinnon <strong>and</strong> John C. Courtney. Saskatoon: Fifth<br />

House.<br />

Monahan, Patrick (1992). “<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> on Government Policy-Making.”<br />

Forthcoming in <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Ten Years After.<br />

Morton, F.L. (1987). “<strong>The</strong> Political Impact of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms.” In<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian Journal of Political Science 20: 31-55.<br />

Morton, F.L. (1990). “Morgantaler vs. <strong>the</strong> Queen: A Political Analysis.” In A Time for Life,<br />

Abortion <strong>and</strong> Human Rights. Ed. Ian Gentles. Toronto: Stoddart.<br />

Morton, F.L. (1991). “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Revolution <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Court Party.” Paper prepared for<br />

“Roundtable Conference on <strong>the</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> on <strong>the</strong> Public Policy Process.” Centre<br />

for Public <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong> Public Policy. November 15-16. York University, Toronto Ontario.<br />

Morton, F.L. (1992). “Institutional Retooling: <strong>The</strong> Evolution of <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada<br />

from Adjudicator to Policy-Maker.” Paper prepared for <strong>the</strong> Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

Political Science Association. May 31. University of Prince Edward Isl<strong>and</strong>, Charlottetown<br />

PEI.<br />

Morton, F.L. <strong>and</strong> Rainer Knopff (1990). “Permanence <strong>and</strong> Change in <strong>the</strong> Written <strong>Constitution</strong>:<br />

<strong>The</strong> ‘Living Tree’ Doctrine <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights.” In Supreme Court <strong>La</strong>w Review,<br />

Second Series 1: 533-46.<br />

Morton, F.L. <strong>and</strong> Rainer Knopff (1992). “<strong>The</strong> Supreme Court as <strong>the</strong> Vanguard of <strong>the</strong><br />

Intelligentsia: <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Movement as Postmaterialist Politics.” Research Study 8.1,<br />

Occasional Papers Series, Research Unit for Socio-Legal Studies. University of Calgary.<br />

113


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Morton, F.L., G. Soloman, I. McNish <strong>and</strong> D.W. Poulton (1990). “Judicial Nullification of Statutes<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms.” In Alberta <strong>La</strong>w Review 28: 396-425.<br />

Petter, Andrew (1986). “<strong>The</strong> Politics of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.” In Supreme Court <strong>La</strong>w Review 8: 473-505.<br />

Petter, Andrew (1987). “Immaculate Deception: <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s Hidden Agenda.” In <strong>The</strong> Advocate<br />

45: 857-66.<br />

Petter, Andrew (1989). “Canada’s <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Flight: Soaring Backwards into <strong>the</strong> Future.” In Journal<br />

of <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong> Society 16: 151-65.<br />

Petter, Andrew <strong>and</strong> Alan C. Hutchinson (1988). “Private Rights/Public Wrongs: <strong>The</strong> Liberal Lie<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.” In University of Toronto <strong>La</strong>w Journal 38: 278-97.<br />

Petter, Andrew <strong>and</strong> Alan C. Hutchinson (1989). “Rights in Conflict: <strong>The</strong> Dilemma of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

Legitimacy.” In UBC <strong>La</strong>w Review 23: 531-48.<br />

Petter, Andrew <strong>and</strong> Alan C. Hutchinson (1990). “Daydream Believing: Visionary Formalism <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.” In Ottawa <strong>La</strong>w Review 22: 365-85.<br />

Russell, Peter H. (1982). “<strong>The</strong> Effect of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms on <strong>the</strong> Policy-Making<br />

Role of Canadian Courts.” In Canadian Public Administration 25: 1-33.<br />

Russell, Peter H. (1983). “<strong>The</strong> Political Purposes of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Freedoms.” In <strong>The</strong> Canadian Bar Review 61: 30-54.<br />

Sheppard, Robert <strong>and</strong> Michael Valpy (1982). <strong>The</strong> National Deal: <strong>The</strong> Fight for <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

Toronto: Fleet Books.<br />

Simpson, Jeffrey (1992). “Rights Talk: <strong>The</strong> Discourse of <strong>the</strong> 1990s.” Forthcoming in <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>:<br />

Ten Years After.<br />

Smiley, Donald (1983). “A Dangerous Deed: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982.” In And No One<br />

Cheered: <strong>Federalism</strong>, Democracy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act. Ed. Keith Banting <strong>and</strong> Richard<br />

Simeon. Toronto: Methuen.<br />

Williams, Patricia J. (1991). <strong>The</strong> Alchemy of Race <strong>and</strong> Rights. Cambridge: Harvard University<br />

Press.<br />

Young, Iris Marion (1989). “Polity <strong>and</strong> Group Differences: A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Ideal of Universal<br />

Citizenship.” In Feminism <strong>and</strong> Political <strong>The</strong>ory. Ed. Cass R. Sunstein. Chicago & London:<br />

University of Chicago Press.<br />

Young, Iris Marion (1990). Justice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University<br />

Press.<br />

114


Janet Hiebert<br />

Rights <strong>and</strong> Public Debate: <strong>The</strong> Limitations of a<br />

“Rights Must be Paramount” Perspective<br />

Abstract<br />

This paper focuses on <strong>the</strong> impact of rights-based language on constitutional<br />

debate. After a decade of entrenchment <strong>the</strong>re has been a tendency to embrace a<br />

“rights must be paramount” view of Canadian politics where protected rights<br />

are assumed to be paramount to all non-enumerated values. This perspective<br />

is criticized in <strong>the</strong> paper for its constraining effect on political debate. <strong>The</strong><br />

paper speculates that a “rights must be paramount” approach is only a<br />

transitional feature of learning to live with <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>; that <strong>the</strong> more we face<br />

conflicts between enumerated rights <strong>and</strong> non-enumerated values, <strong>the</strong> more<br />

likely we are to realize that <strong>the</strong> resolution of difficult <strong>and</strong> contentious political<br />

issues may not be amenable to assumptions about <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected<br />

rights. One example of this was <strong>the</strong> relative lack of rights-based opposition to<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in 1991 which can be explained, in part, by an<br />

implicit recognition of <strong>the</strong> limitations of a “rights must be paramount”<br />

approach in accommodating Quebec’s sense of community.<br />

Résumé<br />

Cet article traite des effets sur le débat constitutionnel d’un discours basé sur<br />

la primauté des droits. Au cours des dix années qui ont suivi leur<br />

enchâssement, on a eu tendance à considérer la politique canadienne selon<br />

une optique qui affirme la « suprématie absolue » des droits<br />

constitutionnalisés sur les valeurs non inscrites dans la <strong>Charte</strong>. Or, cette<br />

perspective gêne le déroulement du débat politique. Selon l’auteure, il ne<br />

s’agit que d’une attitude transitoire permettant d’apprivoiser la <strong>Charte</strong>. Plus<br />

les oppositions entre les droits inscrits et ceux qui ne le sont pas se<br />

multiplieront, plus nous nous rendrons compte que la solution des dossiers<br />

politiques délicats et litigieux suppose la désacralisation des droits<br />

constitutionnalisés. Soulignons, à titre d’exemple, qu’on s’est très peu opposé<br />

en 1991 à la clause de la société distincte en invoquant la <strong>Charte</strong>. Cela tient en<br />

partie au fait qu’on admet implicitement la nécessité de relativiser la « priorité<br />

absolue » des droits constitutionnalisés afin de reconnaître la personnalité<br />

collective du Québec.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms has significantly influenced <strong>the</strong> way we,<br />

as a polity, assess <strong>the</strong> priorities of competing social, political <strong>and</strong> economic<br />

values. For many, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has fundamentally altered <strong>the</strong> political system<br />

by prescribing rights which are insulated from government action. This<br />

approach is misleading because it does not recognize <strong>the</strong> role of s. 1, <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s limitation clause, in accommodating values not specifically<br />

enumerated but which are demonstrably justified <strong>and</strong> consistent with a free<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>and</strong> democratic society. 1 Never<strong>the</strong>less, an unbridled enthusiasm for <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has generated a propensity to assume a “rights must be paramount”<br />

view of Canadian politics2 which affords little scope for s. 1 in justifying<br />

values not easily accommodated in <strong>the</strong> specific rights-based provisions of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

A “rights must be paramount” perspective was evident in many of <strong>the</strong><br />

interventions on <strong>the</strong> proposed <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> before <strong>the</strong> Joint Parliamentary<br />

Committee on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in 1980-1981 which argued that <strong>the</strong> inclusion<br />

of an explicit limitation clause was not necessary because courts would impose<br />

<strong>the</strong> appropriate limits when two specific <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights collide. This implies,<br />

though, that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> itself provides exhaustive coverage of <strong>the</strong> range of<br />

values worthy of protection: that governments may not legitimately assert <strong>the</strong><br />

primacy of non-enumerated values (Hiebert, 1990, 127). A “rights must be<br />

paramount” perspective is often characteristic of <strong>the</strong> assumptions of many<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> litigants <strong>and</strong> intervenors, particularly as expressed in factums. 3 A<br />

“rights must be paramount” perspective was also assumed by some critics of<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposed distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke constitutional accord,<br />

in particular, Newfoundl<strong>and</strong> Premier Clyde Wells <strong>and</strong> some women’s groups,<br />

who argued that it was constitutionally illegitimate for non-enumerated<br />

collective values to be given primacy over protected <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights. More will<br />

be said of this later in <strong>the</strong> paper.<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> ascendency of a “rights must be paramount” perspective, <strong>the</strong> paper<br />

will argue that it is not a particularly helpful way of engaging in “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>”<br />

debate. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> paper will argue that those who assume that protected<br />

rights must at all times be paramount to o<strong>the</strong>r competing values will likely be<br />

challenged by new circumstances <strong>and</strong> conflicts which fundamentally test <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

assumptions of <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected rights. <strong>The</strong>se arguments are premised<br />

on <strong>the</strong> assumptions that 1) many provisions in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are indeterminate<br />

<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, offer incomplete guidelines on <strong>the</strong> basic values that need to be<br />

respected in <strong>the</strong> course of state action, 2) <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s emphasis on individual<br />

rights may not easily accommodate <strong>the</strong> more collective or communitarian<br />

tenets of <strong>the</strong> Canadian polity, particularly <strong>the</strong> cultural aspirations of <strong>the</strong><br />

Québécois, <strong>and</strong> 3) we are in a transitional phase of learning to live with <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

A working hypo<strong>the</strong>sis in <strong>the</strong> paper is that <strong>the</strong> more we face conflicts between<br />

protected rights <strong>and</strong> strongly held values, <strong>the</strong> more we will come to realize that<br />

not only does <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> fail to provide <strong>the</strong> necessary answers, but that<br />

resolving conflicts may involve making choices that go beyond <strong>the</strong> vindication<br />

of rights-based claims. Any polity which attempts to codify fundamental rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> values will face conflicts between <strong>the</strong>se protected values <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs which,<br />

while not specifically enumerated, may also be strongly respected. In Canada,<br />

this conflict is even more inevitable given our commitment to collective <strong>and</strong><br />

general welfare values which may not be easily accommodated in <strong>the</strong><br />

primarily individualistic language of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Yet <strong>the</strong> reluctance implicit in<br />

a “rights must be paramount” perspective to recognize that s. 1 serves a broader<br />

role than to reconcile conflicts between explicitly enumerated “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>”<br />

rights4 or serve as an emergency safety valve (Cohen) places constraints on <strong>the</strong><br />

political process. It represents <strong>the</strong> potential frustration of meaningful debate<br />

about <strong>the</strong> appropriate priorities of competing social, cultural <strong>and</strong> political values.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> decade since <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> took effect, we have faced few situations in<br />

which a judicial review of <strong>the</strong> competing values at stake challenged our<br />

118


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

intuitive, moral <strong>and</strong> political senses of what is right, just or fair, or engage us in<br />

protracted <strong>and</strong> contentious discussions of <strong>the</strong> merits of values in conflict with<br />

protected rights. <strong>The</strong> abortion debate, it might be argued, has pitted<br />

fundamentally contested views of rights-based entitlements against<br />

conflicting societal expectations; however, <strong>the</strong> full scope of this issue has yet<br />

to be addressed. 5<br />

Perhaps <strong>the</strong> best example of an issue that required a difficult choice between<br />

protected rights <strong>and</strong> non-enumerated values was <strong>the</strong> entrenchment of a distinct<br />

society clause. <strong>Constitution</strong>al recognition of Quebec as a distinct society was<br />

one of five dem<strong>and</strong>s by <strong>the</strong> Quebec government in return for participating in<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1986 constitutional renewal. Of <strong>the</strong> political issues that contributed to <strong>the</strong><br />

failure of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause most<br />

encapsulated <strong>the</strong> different perceptions of <strong>the</strong> appropriate relationship between<br />

citizens <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state <strong>and</strong> between protected rights <strong>and</strong> non-protected values.<br />

This paper will examine debate on <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> 1991 federal constitutional proposal in terms of<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re has been a movement away from a “rights must be paramount”<br />

assessment of constitutional change. <strong>The</strong> pivotal role of <strong>the</strong> distinct society<br />

clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round contrasts significantly with <strong>the</strong> comparatively<br />

minor role it played in <strong>the</strong> 1991-1992 constitutional discussions. Whe<strong>the</strong>r out<br />

of a change in commitment to <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected rights or a realization of<br />

<strong>the</strong> possible difficulties of accommodating Quebec’s sense of nationhood in a<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>- based constitutional order, <strong>the</strong> 1991-1992 constitutional debate did<br />

not demonstrate <strong>the</strong> same degree of concern to insulate protected rights from<br />

<strong>the</strong> possible implications of a distinct society clause. Before exploring this<br />

argument, we must first examine more closely how <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> affects <strong>the</strong> way<br />

<strong>the</strong> political process is viewed.<br />

Overview of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s Impact on <strong>the</strong> Political Process<br />

<strong>The</strong> language of rights promoted by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has contributed to a growing<br />

tendency to assume that non-enumerated values in conflict with protected<br />

rights are constitutionally inferior. One problem with this perspective is <strong>the</strong><br />

assumption that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is exhaustive of all fundamental values <strong>and</strong> that<br />

recourse to it offers an exclusive basis for resolving rights-based conflicts.<br />

Many commentators have observed <strong>the</strong> general <strong>and</strong> vague nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s provisions (M<strong>and</strong>el 1989; Monahan 1987). For example, <strong>the</strong><br />

wording of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> offers no clear explanation why freedom of expression<br />

should protect <strong>the</strong> ability to advertise in one’s preferred language on<br />

commercial signs or communicate for <strong>the</strong> purposes of prostitution, or why<br />

freedom of association should not protect collective bargaining. <strong>The</strong>re are no<br />

universal or self-evident “principles” that dictate <strong>the</strong>se findings; ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are <strong>the</strong> result of judicial reasoning or “policy” determinations. While courts<br />

develop judicial rules <strong>and</strong> principles to aid in <strong>the</strong> interpretation of rights (for<br />

example, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court has adopted <strong>the</strong> position that <strong>the</strong> scope of<br />

freedom of expression should not depend on <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> message) <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> itself provides little direction as to <strong>the</strong> specific circumstances that are<br />

protected by its vague <strong>and</strong> general provisions. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, even if we have <strong>the</strong><br />

utmost faith in <strong>the</strong> judicial capacity to expound, at all times, <strong>the</strong> appropriate<br />

values <strong>and</strong> circumstances protected by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (this is an assumption that<br />

many, including <strong>the</strong> author, are not prepared to make), can we be confident that<br />

<strong>the</strong> bureaucratic <strong>and</strong> political drafters of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> have captured all of <strong>the</strong><br />

119


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

fundamental values that we, our children <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir descendants will value in<br />

<strong>the</strong> future?<br />

It is not only <strong>the</strong> protected rights that are indeterminate of particular outcomes.<br />

Even more significant is <strong>the</strong> indeterminacy of <strong>the</strong> limitation clause in s. 1.<br />

Courts have assumed <strong>the</strong> responsibility of determining whe<strong>the</strong>r government<br />

policies that conflict with a protected right are never<strong>the</strong>less reasonable <strong>and</strong><br />

justified in <strong>the</strong> context of a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society. <strong>The</strong> difficulty for <strong>the</strong><br />

Court, however, is that <strong>the</strong> values integral to a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society are<br />

subject to dispute. <strong>The</strong>re is little reason to assume that nine judges are<br />

inherently more capable of expounding democratic principles than<br />

governments, political philosophers or citizens. Yet a core assumption in a<br />

“rights must be paramount” position is that <strong>the</strong> requirements of a democratic<br />

society can be readily inferred from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Some consider <strong>the</strong> reference<br />

in <strong>the</strong> limitation clause to a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual<br />

enumerated rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to be one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong><br />

specified rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> embody <strong>the</strong> rights necessary for a free <strong>and</strong><br />

democratic society6 <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, exhaust <strong>the</strong> range of values entitled to limit<br />

a protected right.<br />

<strong>The</strong> language of rights encourages <strong>the</strong> positing of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims in terms of<br />

inviolable <strong>and</strong> non-negotiable principles that supersede <strong>and</strong> surpass <strong>the</strong><br />

importance of alternative “policy” considerations. This assumption that<br />

rights-based claims immediately <strong>and</strong> unquestionably vault ahead of<br />

alternative values (often interpreted by rights claimants as little more than<br />

utilitarian, politically expedient or institutionally self-interested<br />

considerations) has significant implications on how government power is<br />

conceptualized. Those subscribing to this or some similar reading of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s impact on government, no longer consider it valid for governments<br />

to exercise discretion when determining <strong>the</strong> issues, interests, values that<br />

should shape policy, at <strong>the</strong> expense of protected rights. While conflicts<br />

between competing rights are inevitable <strong>and</strong> require resolution, many believe<br />

that entrenchment itself resolves disputes about <strong>the</strong> relative importance of<br />

competing values clearly in favour of those explicitly provided for in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

One implication of this assumption on policy development is that legislative<br />

objectives not easily accommodated within <strong>the</strong> language of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are<br />

deemed by many to lack sufficient importance to warrant limiting a protected<br />

right. This is because <strong>the</strong>se objectives relate merely to policy objectives, not<br />

matters of rights <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, are not entitled to restrict a protected right. By<br />

assuming that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is exhaustive of <strong>the</strong> most fundamental values in<br />

society <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> requirements of a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society consist<br />

primarily, if not exclusively, of <strong>the</strong> enumerated rights <strong>the</strong>mselves, this view<br />

offers little recognition that <strong>the</strong> values essential to a free <strong>and</strong> democratic<br />

society are contested.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, assumptions concerning <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected rights discourage an<br />

approach to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> which recognizes collective or general welfare values.<br />

<strong>The</strong> assumption in a “rights must be paramount” approach that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is,<br />

<strong>and</strong> should be considered, exhaustive of all fundamental values places an<br />

ideological <strong>and</strong> institutional constraint on <strong>the</strong> values that can be promoted. It<br />

excludes those values which fall outside <strong>the</strong> specific, <strong>and</strong> highly<br />

individualistic, language of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. While <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> gives limited<br />

recognition to collective rights, such as minority education rights, <strong>the</strong> extent to<br />

120


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

which <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court recognizes collective values as a protected activity<br />

depends largely on judicial assumptions about <strong>the</strong> philosophical content of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se values. A telling example of this was in <strong>the</strong> labour trilogy cases where a<br />

majority of <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court declined to recognize <strong>the</strong> collective right to<br />

strike as a protected form of freedom of association because striking did not<br />

have any individual analogy. 7<br />

<strong>The</strong> predominantly individual rights contained in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> do not address<br />

<strong>the</strong> ideological <strong>and</strong> cultural aspirations of a polity whose political culture<br />

reflects collective values generated by tory <strong>and</strong> socialist influences<br />

(Horowitz). Evidence of our hybrid political culture is suggested in strong<br />

public support for a range of collective or general welfare concerns, even when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y conflict with <strong>the</strong> individualistic assumptions of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. One such<br />

example is <strong>the</strong> attempt to promote <strong>the</strong> collective security of women through a<br />

rape shield policy (to prevent a woman’s sexual past from being raised in<br />

court) despite possible implications on individual legal rights. 8 A challenge to<br />

<strong>the</strong> primacy of individual rights also arises in public support for regulating<br />

election expenses (<strong>and</strong> hence restricting free speech) for <strong>the</strong> general welfare<br />

objective of promoting a fair <strong>and</strong> equitable election process. 9 Although <strong>the</strong>se<br />

are but two examples of collective values, <strong>the</strong>y raise important questions<br />

concerning whe<strong>the</strong>r elements of our political culture which diverge from a<br />

strictly individualistic perspective will be unduly inhibited by an approach that<br />

assumes that protected rights must invariably be paramount to all o<strong>the</strong>r values.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question of how much discretion governments should retain to impose<br />

limits on protected rights invites controversy precisely because questions of<br />

limits on rights strike at <strong>the</strong> heart of debates about <strong>the</strong> relationship between<br />

individuals <strong>and</strong> community: specifically, should <strong>the</strong> state promote a particular<br />

substantive view of <strong>the</strong> “good life” if so doing conflicts with individual rights?<br />

That <strong>the</strong>re are fundamentally contested views around this issue in Canada was<br />

particularly apparent in <strong>the</strong> controversy surrounding <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> legislative<br />

override by <strong>the</strong> Quebec government in 1988 to protect its cultural policy of<br />

promoting <strong>the</strong> French language from rights-based challenges under <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Basing his reasons on <strong>the</strong> need to protect collective rights, Premier<br />

Robert Bourassa’s assumptions about <strong>the</strong> requirements of preserving <strong>and</strong><br />

promoting <strong>the</strong> French culture clearly contradict <strong>the</strong> belief of many that <strong>the</strong><br />

protected rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, which are primarily individual based, should<br />

have primacy over all o<strong>the</strong>r policy objectives:<br />

When two fundamental values clash, someone has to make a choice,<br />

<strong>and</strong> find a balance between both. An unavoidable arbitration has to<br />

take place. Anywhere else in North America, <strong>the</strong> arbitration would<br />

have been made in favour of individual rights. . .<br />

At <strong>the</strong> end, when a choice had to be made between individual rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> collective rights, I arbitrated in favour of collective rights, by<br />

agreeing to invoke <strong>the</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause.<br />

...Iam<strong>the</strong>only head of government in North America who had <strong>the</strong><br />

moral right to follow this course, because I am, in North America, <strong>the</strong><br />

only political leader of a community which is a small minority (Globe<br />

<strong>and</strong> Mail, 1988).<br />

121


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Aside from reduced confidence in <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of governments exercising<br />

discretionary judgments about <strong>the</strong> priority of values, a “rights must be<br />

paramount” interpretation of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> potentially constrains debate. In<br />

rejecting <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of o<strong>the</strong>r values because <strong>the</strong>y lack <strong>the</strong> same status as<br />

rights, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore do not warrant constitutional protection, <strong>the</strong> language or<br />

terms of <strong>the</strong> debate are altered to an extent that compromises are more difficult<br />

to achieve. 10 How can society, after all, compromise fundamental<br />

constitutional principles?<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> powerful rhetoric of appealing to principles, if <strong>the</strong><br />

circumstances protected by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cannot be readily inferred from <strong>the</strong> text<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> values essential to a democracy are contested, it seems misdirected to<br />

assume that only those claims which can be neatly collapsed into rights-based<br />

terms are worthy of protection. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, if <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is nei<strong>the</strong>r determinate<br />

nor exhaustive of fundamental values, it is equally questionable to assume that<br />

governments <strong>the</strong>mselves should not play some role in advancing, under s. 1,<br />

values that represent reasonable <strong>and</strong> justifiable limits on protected rights. <strong>The</strong><br />

principal objection to a “rights must be paramount” position, <strong>the</strong>refore, is its<br />

assumption that governments no longer have <strong>the</strong> legitimacy to pursue <strong>and</strong><br />

promote values that conflict with protected rights. This criticism nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

presumes a particular ideological or value preference nor is motivated by<br />

disdain for <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. It must be stressed that this paper is not arguing that<br />

governments do not have an obligation to respect protected rights or that courts<br />

should defer to whatever choices governments make. Courts should be<br />

anything but deferential to legislative policies where <strong>the</strong>se do not reflect<br />

sincere attempts to debate <strong>the</strong> relative merits of competing values, or design<br />

legislation in a way which imposes as minimal an infringement on <strong>the</strong><br />

protected right as is reasonably possible. But this argument is for ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

paper. <strong>The</strong> argument here is that a “rights must be paramount” position<br />

implicitly rejects <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of governments or societies questioning <strong>and</strong><br />

challenging <strong>the</strong> parameters of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> protection. By doing so, it becomes<br />

difficult to engage in necessary <strong>and</strong> meaningful political debate about <strong>the</strong><br />

priorities that should be attached to competing values.<br />

Even if <strong>the</strong> indeterminacy <strong>and</strong> incompleteness of <strong>the</strong> values promoted by <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are accepted, many will continue to place greater trust in judicial ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than political resolutions to rights-based conflicts. This greater faith in <strong>the</strong><br />

courts is often associated with <strong>the</strong> institutional differences between courts <strong>and</strong><br />

legislatures; courts, for example, are thought to be insulated <strong>and</strong> detached from<br />

popular passions that may be hostile to minority interests. This paper does not<br />

intend to debate which institution is best equipped to protect Canadians’ rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> values. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it seeks <strong>the</strong> more modest task of questioning <strong>the</strong><br />

assumption that it is illegitimate to look beyond <strong>the</strong> specific provisions of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> or court interpretations of <strong>the</strong>m, when seeking answers to rights-based<br />

conflicts.<br />

Rights-based Criticisms of Distinct Society in Meech<br />

Opposition to <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord arose for a<br />

number of reasons. Although this paper focuses on <strong>the</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong><br />

clause on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it is difficult to disentangle <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>-based objections<br />

from broader concerns. <strong>The</strong> clause was not only debated in terms of how it<br />

would affect protected rights, but also in terms of which vision of Canada it<br />

represented. Critics argued that <strong>the</strong> clause was an invitation to re-emphasize a<br />

territorially-focused polity <strong>and</strong> a rejection of <strong>the</strong> pan-Canadian rights-based<br />

122


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

approach embodied in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Where <strong>the</strong> two fronts of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

debate intersected was on critics’ conception of <strong>the</strong> purpose of entrenched<br />

rights. One of <strong>the</strong> purposes of entrenchment was to be an instrument of nation<br />

building. By applying to all Canadians by virtue of citizenship ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

geographical residence, centralists hoped that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would streng<strong>the</strong>n<br />

national identity at <strong>the</strong> expense of regional affiliation. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, by altering <strong>the</strong><br />

political system <strong>and</strong> modifying <strong>the</strong> concept of “legislative supremacy” <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would undermine province-building. While <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> proponents, for<br />

pragmatic reasons, were quick to suggest that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> does not actually<br />

transfer power from one level of government to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, many analysts<br />

expected that <strong>the</strong> impact of judicial review would be felt more pronouncedly<br />

by <strong>the</strong> provinces (Knopff <strong>and</strong> Morton, 1985; Russell, 1983).<br />

<strong>The</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> protected rights in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> went to <strong>the</strong> heart of <strong>the</strong> debate over what vision of Canada should<br />

be promoted. Not only did <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause prescribe a shift away<br />

from <strong>the</strong> pan-Canadian model but, in <strong>the</strong> opinion of many, it also represented a<br />

rejection of our newly enacted “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> regime.” By failing to provide<br />

explicitly for <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s exemption from <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause, many<br />

feared that <strong>the</strong> clause would remodify <strong>the</strong> political system to <strong>the</strong> extent that<br />

some decisions about limiting rights in Quebec would effectively remain in <strong>the</strong><br />

h<strong>and</strong>s of governments. This view presumed that courts would have given a<br />

generous interpretation of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause, granting Quebec<br />

governments significant latitude to limit protected rights for <strong>the</strong> purpose of<br />

promoting cultural values. 11<br />

Some of <strong>the</strong> most significant rights-based objections to <strong>the</strong> distinct society<br />

clause came from women’s groups, primarily outside Quebec. In <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

hearings on <strong>the</strong> proposed constitutional amendments, five national women’s<br />

organizations argued before <strong>the</strong> Parliamentary Committee that <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

would jeopardize equality rights. 12 <strong>La</strong>nguage minority groups, especially<br />

English-speaking groups in Quebec, were also concerned that <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause would weaken protection for language rights in <strong>the</strong> province.<br />

Although it is difficult to generalize <strong>the</strong> nature of objections to <strong>the</strong> clause, a<br />

number of concerns were shared by more than one group. Women’s groups<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause could undermine women’s equality<br />

rights in essentially four ways. First, <strong>the</strong> clause could encourage courts to<br />

adopt a more restrictive interpretation of equality rights in light of possible<br />

conflicts with <strong>the</strong> objectives of a distinct society clause. Second, <strong>the</strong> clause<br />

could create a constitutionally stated justification for limiting rights. <strong>The</strong><br />

assumption was that <strong>the</strong> consideration of reasonable limits in s. 1 would<br />

become more expansive, to include cultural objectives associated with <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society clause <strong>and</strong>, as a result, provide additional grounds <strong>and</strong> greater<br />

ease for a Quebec government to promote cultural values that require limiting<br />

equality rights. Third, <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause might insulate legislation<br />

from <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> review. This would occur if courts were to define distinct society<br />

as constituting a fundamental principle of Confederation <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, of<br />

parallel constitutional importance <strong>and</strong> not subject to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. And fourth,<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinct society clause could place a lower priority on equality rights than<br />

on <strong>the</strong> collective rights of Québécois. This is because <strong>the</strong> proposed clause s. 16,<br />

which stated that multicultural <strong>and</strong> aboriginal rights in ss. 25, 27 <strong>and</strong> 35 would<br />

not have been affected by distinct society, did not explicitly exclude equality<br />

rights in ss. 15 <strong>and</strong> 28. It was argued, <strong>the</strong>refore, that equality rights could be<br />

subordinated to or affected by <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause because <strong>the</strong>y, unlike<br />

123


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

some rights, were not explicitly exempted from its ambit (Smith, 1988; Brock,<br />

1990).<br />

It would be misleading to characterize all women’s groups’ opposition to <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society clause as embodying a “rights must be paramount”<br />

perspective. A significant factor in women’s opposition to <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord was <strong>the</strong>ir frustration at not being able to engage in open <strong>and</strong> honest<br />

debate about <strong>the</strong> potential implications of a distinct society clause for equality<br />

rights (Baines, 1988). Fur<strong>the</strong>r, while many considered it illegitimate to treat<br />

collective or cultural values as being paramount to equality or o<strong>the</strong>r protected<br />

rights, o<strong>the</strong>rs called for debate on <strong>the</strong> priorities that should be attached to each<br />

(Smith, 1988). Also, for those frustrated with <strong>the</strong> traditional legislative<br />

processes, a “rights must be paramount” perspective offers an important<br />

symbolic <strong>and</strong> political position from which to challenge systemic inequalities.<br />

This is particularly true in light of <strong>the</strong> concern that equality rights, being<br />

excluded from <strong>the</strong> list of provisions exempted from <strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause, might be interpreted as of lesser importance.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se caveats notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing, many of <strong>the</strong> women’s groups’ objections to<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinct society clause shared similarities with <strong>the</strong> assumptions of a “rights<br />

must be paramount” perspective: namely, that <strong>the</strong> clause could allow for<br />

collective <strong>and</strong> non-enumerated rights to be given primacy over individual<br />

rights; that governments would continue to play a discretionary role in<br />

promoting values that conflict with protected rights; <strong>and</strong> that protection for<br />

equality rights may not be universal but ra<strong>the</strong>r might vary in <strong>and</strong> out of Quebec.<br />

While <strong>the</strong>se assumptions are legitimate depending on one’s vision of society<br />

<strong>and</strong> of governmental responsibilities, <strong>the</strong>y are limiting in <strong>the</strong>ir capacity to<br />

allow debate where disagreement exists on <strong>the</strong> priority of contested values. For<br />

example, <strong>the</strong> perception that protected rights must be insulated from<br />

government attempts to promote collective values made it difficult for non-<br />

Francophone women’s groups to reconcile <strong>the</strong>mselves to <strong>the</strong> likelihood that<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would be interpreted in <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, suspicions of any differentiation in <strong>the</strong> limits imposed on equality<br />

rights for collective purposes made it difficult to be assured by Francophone<br />

women’s claims that part of what it means for Quebec to be a distinct society is<br />

<strong>the</strong> progress made in <strong>the</strong> last couple of decades in terms of equality concerns<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> status of women (Bonenfant, 1987).<br />

Political Proponents’ Response<br />

Federal <strong>and</strong> provincial supporters of <strong>the</strong> Accord seemed impervious to<br />

women’s concerns. Early criticisms of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause were greeted<br />

with disparaging comments implying that anyone opposing <strong>the</strong> amendment<br />

was somehow “anti-Quebec.” 13 Not only did political proponents dismiss <strong>the</strong><br />

need to reassess <strong>the</strong> clause, 14 <strong>the</strong>re was little recognition that protected rights<br />

would even be affected. Instead of acknowledging <strong>the</strong> possibility that<br />

interpretations of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause could influence what activities are<br />

considered a justifiable limit on equality or o<strong>the</strong>r protected rights, political<br />

supporters of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke insisted that <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause would not<br />

“override” protected rights. 15<br />

<strong>The</strong> combined effect of a “rights must be paramount” critique of <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause <strong>and</strong> political proponents’ refusal to sincerely address rightsbased<br />

concerns was an absence of meaningful debate on <strong>the</strong> following<br />

important questions: would distinct society likely affect <strong>the</strong> interpretation of<br />

124


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

equality or o<strong>the</strong>r rights (ei<strong>the</strong>r by influencing <strong>the</strong>ir definition or, more likely,<br />

by broadening <strong>the</strong> scope of permissible limits on <strong>the</strong>m); given Quebec’s sense<br />

of community <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> importance of collective rights, are territorial-based<br />

differences in how limits on rights are interpreted acceptable; <strong>and</strong> would <strong>the</strong><br />

kind of collective values envisaged in a distinct society be consistent with a<br />

free <strong>and</strong> democratic society?<br />

Distinct Society Clause in <strong>the</strong> 1991 Federal Proposal<br />

In sharp contrast to <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke round, one interesting aspect of <strong>the</strong> 1991-<br />

1992 constitutional debate was <strong>the</strong> relative lack of contention surrounding <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society clause. Although <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>-based criticisms of <strong>the</strong> clause were<br />

raised, <strong>the</strong> level cannot be compared with <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

round.<br />

<strong>The</strong> 1991 distinct society clause would have been explicitly placed within <strong>the</strong><br />

text of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, requiring that courts interpret <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in a manner<br />

consistent with “<strong>the</strong> preservation <strong>and</strong> promotion of Quebec as a distinct society<br />

within Canada” <strong>and</strong> “<strong>the</strong> preservation of <strong>the</strong> existence of French-speaking<br />

Canadians primarily located in Quebec but also throughout Canada, <strong>and</strong><br />

English-speaking Canadians, primarily located outside Quebec but also<br />

present in Quebec.” In contrast to its vague definition in Meech, <strong>the</strong> new<br />

distinct society clause was defined to include a French-speaking majority, a<br />

unique culture <strong>and</strong> a civil law tradition (“Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r:<br />

Proposals,” 51).<br />

Placing <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause within <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> left little doubt that<br />

interpretations of protected rights would be affected. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> already<br />

recognizes <strong>the</strong> existence of collective values in <strong>the</strong> aboriginal rights <strong>and</strong><br />

multicultural heritage clauses of ss. 25 <strong>and</strong> 27. Like <strong>the</strong>se clauses, distinct<br />

society would have been an interpretive clause, providing guidelines for<br />

interpretation. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than conferring a substantive entitlement on its own, it<br />

would more likely have affected <strong>the</strong> way protected rights were interpreted <strong>and</strong>,<br />

more significantly, potentially widened <strong>the</strong> scope of permissible limitations on<br />

protected rights under s. 1. As an interpretive clause, distinct society does not<br />

appear to have been paramount to any single <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provision. Of particular<br />

concern for women, <strong>the</strong> clause seems to have been subordinate to s. 28 which is<br />

a gender “notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing” clause; s. 28 provides for equality between men<br />

<strong>and</strong> women “notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing anything in this <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” <strong>and</strong>, presumably,<br />

notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause. In contrast to <strong>the</strong> Meech clause,<br />

which exempted from its ambit certain rights but not equality rights, <strong>the</strong><br />

proposed federal clause did not lead to <strong>the</strong> same concern that a hierarchy of<br />

rights would be created.<br />

<strong>The</strong> new clause addressed some of <strong>the</strong> concerns raised in <strong>the</strong> Meech round, but<br />

not all of <strong>the</strong>m. For individuals <strong>and</strong> groups concerned about <strong>the</strong> rights-based<br />

implications of <strong>the</strong> Meech version, <strong>the</strong> 1991 version was still vulnerable in at<br />

least two respects: <strong>the</strong> clause could have affected how courts interpret <strong>the</strong><br />

scope of a protected right — what circumstances are actually protected — <strong>and</strong><br />

would likely have entered into judicial decisions about whe<strong>the</strong>r limits on<br />

protected rights are reasonable <strong>and</strong> demonstrably justified.<br />

This second role is <strong>the</strong> most significant. Judicial review of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has<br />

tended to proceed in two analytically distinct stages in which decisions about<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a right has been infringed are often distinct from <strong>the</strong> determination of<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a limit is justified. Because <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause would provide<br />

125


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

an interpretive aid when determining reasonable limits, courts could exp<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> scope of permissible limits on equality or o<strong>the</strong>r protected rights for distinct<br />

society purposes. This could include ei<strong>the</strong>r enlarging or altering <strong>the</strong> definition<br />

of what objectives are considered reasonable or worthy of limiting protected<br />

rights to include those necessary for <strong>the</strong> promotion of a distinct society. Or it<br />

could affect <strong>the</strong> way courts assess whe<strong>the</strong>r distinct society objectives meet <strong>the</strong><br />

proportionality guidelines in <strong>the</strong> Oakes test (R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103).<br />

Many have argued that judicially created guidelines for determining s. 1 issues<br />

are generally indeterminate of specific outcomes (Peck 1987; Hiebert 1991).<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, judicial discretion in determining whe<strong>the</strong>r a legislative or executive<br />

objective has been designed or administered in a manner that itself is<br />

reasonable, could be affected by judicial commitment to <strong>the</strong> objective itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> potential of <strong>the</strong> 1991 distinct society clause to influence judicial opinion<br />

on <strong>the</strong> worthiness of related objectives may have been significant for those<br />

concerned with <strong>the</strong> primacy of equality rights. It could be argued that <strong>the</strong><br />

Supreme Court has already indicated some sympathy for <strong>the</strong> promotion of a<br />

distinct society. In <strong>the</strong> Ford case (Quebec signs law), <strong>the</strong> Court went a<br />

considerable distance in reading a distinct society interpretation into <strong>the</strong><br />

limitation clause of s.1. In that case, <strong>the</strong> Court agreed with <strong>the</strong> Quebec<br />

government’s claim that protecting <strong>the</strong> French language is crucial to <strong>the</strong><br />

survival of French culture to assure <strong>the</strong> “reality of Quebec society is<br />

communicated through <strong>the</strong> visage linguistique” <strong>and</strong> that this was a justifiable<br />

objective in a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society. Its difficulty <strong>and</strong> reasons for finding<br />

<strong>the</strong> signs law invalid were not based on <strong>the</strong> objective itself but on <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

some attempt had not been made to accommodate <strong>the</strong> use of o<strong>the</strong>r languages<br />

(Ford v. Quebec [Attorney General], [1988] 2 S.C.R. at 778-779).<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> potential implications of <strong>the</strong> 1991 distinct society clause in<br />

undermining <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected rights, little concern was expressed<br />

about its rights-based implications. Most of <strong>the</strong> commentary <strong>and</strong> criticisms of<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1991 federal proposal focused on issues o<strong>the</strong>r than distinct society. And<br />

when distinct society was considered, particularly during <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

conferences, <strong>the</strong> issue was not its impact on rights but whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> concept of a<br />

distinct society should also be applied to aboriginal peoples (Renewal of<br />

Canada Conferences: Compendium of Reports, 1992).<br />

As significant as <strong>the</strong> magnitude of criticisms during <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke process<br />

was <strong>the</strong> relative absence of a sustained critique of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1991-92 discussions. Many of <strong>the</strong> women’s groups who went on record for<br />

criticizing aspects of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in Meech were noticeably<br />

silent in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 round of constitutional hearings. Only <strong>the</strong> National<br />

Action Committee on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women took a public st<strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> issue.<br />

And NAC, which endorsed <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> hearings, focused<br />

little attention on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong> clause (NAC, 1991).<br />

Unlike NAC’s response to <strong>the</strong> Meech version of distinct society, <strong>the</strong>re was no<br />

explicit criticism of <strong>the</strong> clause in terms of its potential effect on equality rights.<br />

In NAC’s view, some of <strong>the</strong> concerns of women’s organizations in <strong>the</strong> Meech<br />

<strong>La</strong>ke round had been addressed by placing <strong>the</strong> provision explicitly in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> result of this, NAC implied, was that <strong>the</strong> sexual equality clause of<br />

s. 28 would be paramount to o<strong>the</strong>r <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> provisions or interpretive clauses<br />

(Ibid.) Fur<strong>the</strong>r, NAC President Judy Rebick indicated that it may be<br />

inappropriate to require universal treatment of equality concerns; that just as<br />

126


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

sameness of treatment may not be desirable in a sexual context, it may also be<br />

undesirable in <strong>the</strong> context of cultural or aboriginal concerns:<br />

. . . (W)e underst<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> women’s movement ...that equality<br />

doesn’t mean treating everyone <strong>the</strong> same way. Equality often means<br />

special measures — that terrible word — to correct historical<br />

inequalities. . . [W]e also need special powers...forQuebec...to<br />

recognize <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>y have a disadvantage in being <strong>the</strong> only<br />

French-speaking nation or province in <strong>the</strong> whole of North America.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y need those powers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y want those powers to protect <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

language, <strong>the</strong>ir culture <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> institutions. (Rebick, 29 Oct. 1991,<br />

10:18-19).<br />

Some might object to this characterization of Quebec’s concern for special<br />

status as a measure to overcome historical disadvantages. <strong>The</strong>y may, instead,<br />

interpret Quebec’s claims for different treatment as reflecting collective<br />

values <strong>and</strong> state obligations that are <strong>the</strong> result of a political culture different<br />

from <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada. Never<strong>the</strong>less it is significant that NAC moved away<br />

from a pan-Canadian approach to protected rights. It has also indicated a<br />

significant movement away from <strong>the</strong> principle that “rights must be<br />

paramount” under all circumstances.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r significant change in support for <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause came from<br />

one of <strong>the</strong> most ardent critics of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

round, <strong>and</strong> subscriber to a “rights must be paramount” position,<br />

Newfoundl<strong>and</strong> Premier Clyde Wells. Having earlier argued that <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause should serve little purpose o<strong>the</strong>r than an historical <strong>and</strong><br />

sociological recognition of Quebec as a distinct society, Wells grudgingly<br />

accepted <strong>the</strong> principle that distinct society allows for possible variations in<br />

how protected rights are interpreted. Wells made it clear that this was not his<br />

preference but implied it was a reasonable concession to accommodate <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional concerns of <strong>the</strong> Quebec Francophone majority. 16<br />

While philosophically I personally...would prefer to see <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

apply to every part of <strong>the</strong> country <strong>and</strong> to each individual in exactly <strong>the</strong><br />

same manner, if <strong>the</strong> majority of citizens of Quebec want <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

individual charter rights to be somewhat subordinated to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

collective rights, <strong>the</strong>n it is difficult for <strong>the</strong> citizens of any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

province to say we don’t want to see that happen in Quebec...Some<br />

limited subordination of individual rights to collective rights within<br />

Quebec, if that is what <strong>the</strong> people of Quebec want, may not be an<br />

unreasonable concession to accommodate <strong>the</strong> legitimate concerns of<br />

a province that is, by reason of its culture, language <strong>and</strong> legal system,<br />

distinctly different from any o<strong>the</strong>r province in <strong>the</strong> country. (Wells, 22<br />

October 1991, 8).<br />

<strong>The</strong> comparatively minor role of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>-based criticisms of <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause does not mean all groups changed <strong>the</strong>ir opinions on <strong>the</strong><br />

legitimacy of <strong>the</strong> clause. A h<strong>and</strong>ful of smaller women’s <strong>and</strong> minority language<br />

groups continued to criticize <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause precisely because of its<br />

potential to undermine a “rights must be paramount” position. For example,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Br<strong>and</strong>on Women’s Study Group opposed <strong>the</strong> idea that women’s equality<br />

rights could be “subject to <strong>the</strong> collective interests of Quebec’s distinct<br />

society.”<br />

127


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>The</strong> issue here is not whe<strong>the</strong>r Quebec society is distinct or whe<strong>the</strong>r it<br />

should have <strong>the</strong> capacity to preserve <strong>and</strong> promote its culture; it is<br />

about whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> preservation <strong>and</strong> promotion of a collectivity<br />

should be done at <strong>the</strong> expense of individual, disadvantaged, or<br />

minority group rights. It will not help <strong>the</strong> women of Canada to have a<br />

clearly articulated statement that <strong>the</strong> interests of women must be<br />

subordinate to those of <strong>the</strong>ir national or linguistic group.<br />

...werespect <strong>the</strong> right of Quebec to claim a distinct society, but<br />

request that it does so in a way that would not override <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamental equality rights of women ...Equality rights must be<br />

maintained above any cultural, linguistic or ethnic encroachments.<br />

(Everitt, 6 Nov. 1991, 18:7-8).<br />

Similarly, ano<strong>the</strong>r women’s group, Equality Eve, raised concerns that locating<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> could “trump” protected rights. For<br />

example, it argued that had <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause been entrenched at <strong>the</strong><br />

time of <strong>the</strong> signs law decision, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court “would probably find that<br />

freedom of expression would not be violated” (Equality Eve, 1991).<br />

Concerns of how <strong>the</strong> 1991 version of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause would affect<br />

interpretations of protected rights were not confined to women’s groups.<br />

Anglophones in Quebec expressed concern, as <strong>the</strong>y did during Meech, that <strong>the</strong><br />

clause could undermine individual rights. This objection was similar to that of<br />

women’s groups — that <strong>the</strong> clause would ei<strong>the</strong>r narrow <strong>the</strong> interpretation<br />

given to protected rights or broaden <strong>the</strong> scope of permissible limits<br />

(Henderson, 1991).<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong>se objections, <strong>the</strong>re was an order of magnitude change in<br />

<strong>the</strong> criticism extended towards <strong>the</strong> clause in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 constitutional debate,<br />

despite <strong>the</strong> potential for rights-based objections. Those who opposed <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society clause in Meech, because of its potential to narrow <strong>the</strong><br />

interpretation of protected rights <strong>and</strong>, more significantly, broaden <strong>the</strong> scope of<br />

permissible limits on rights, should have had similar concerns with <strong>the</strong> 1991<br />

version. So why were <strong>the</strong>se criticisms not more vocal?<br />

An important part of <strong>the</strong> explanation for <strong>the</strong> relatively minor role <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society clause played in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 constitutional process is no doubt<br />

accounted for by <strong>the</strong> political fallout over <strong>the</strong> death of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord.<br />

Given that <strong>the</strong> clause generated significant differences between Quebec <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r women’s groups, it is not surprising that equality concerns were pursued<br />

in different forms, for instance, increasing political representation of women<br />

via a reformed Senate with a gender ra<strong>the</strong>r than territorial composition, <strong>the</strong><br />

implications of entrenching property rights, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects of decentralization<br />

on family law, among o<strong>the</strong>rs (Schneiderman, 1992).<br />

While significant, this is only part of <strong>the</strong> explanation for why rights-based<br />

criticisms of <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause did not play a more prominent role in<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1991 <strong>and</strong> early 1992 constitutional debate. This paper partly attributes <strong>the</strong><br />

relative lack of criticism to an implicit reassessment of <strong>the</strong> utility of a “rights<br />

must be paramount” approach. Considerations in 1991-92 about whe<strong>the</strong>r or<br />

not to accept an entrenched distinct society clause approximate <strong>the</strong> kind of<br />

dilemma discussed earlier, in which protected rights clash with important,<br />

although contested, non-enumerated values. Given <strong>the</strong> gulf that existed<br />

between Francophones <strong>and</strong> Anglophones on <strong>the</strong> desirability of <strong>the</strong> clause, it<br />

128


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

has become increasingly apparent that <strong>the</strong> resolution of our constitutional<br />

impasse may depend less on vindicating rights-based claims than on making<br />

difficult choices about <strong>the</strong> priorities that should be attached to competing<br />

values. In this context, <strong>the</strong> choice may be seen as having been between 1) a<br />

universal approach to rights, which would likely be rejected by Quebec <strong>and</strong> 2)<br />

possible variations on how limitations on rights are interpreted to better reflect<br />

<strong>and</strong> accommodate <strong>the</strong> different political culture of Quebec. That <strong>the</strong>re has been<br />

greater accommodation of <strong>the</strong> latter choice seems clear in NAC’s willingness<br />

to extend concern about “sameness of treatment” from <strong>the</strong> sexual equality<br />

realm to recognize Quebec’s different sense of community. In a less generous<br />

manner, Wells similarly recognized that for <strong>the</strong> sake of unity we may have to<br />

accommodate Quebec’s different underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> balance between<br />

collective <strong>and</strong> individual rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role of governments in promoting this<br />

balance.<br />

<strong>The</strong> relative lack of contention surrounding <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in <strong>the</strong><br />

1991-92 constitutional debate indicates a greater sensitivity among<br />

constitutional participants <strong>and</strong> commentators to <strong>the</strong> difficulties of<br />

accommodating Quebec’s sense of nation in a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>-based constitutional<br />

order. Whe<strong>the</strong>r out of consignment to <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> price of remaining a<br />

unified country may involve tolerating some variation in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s<br />

interpretation or recognizing that <strong>the</strong> range of Quebec’s cultural objectives is<br />

consistent with a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society, <strong>the</strong> implication is that <strong>the</strong><br />

vindication of rights-based concerns may not resolve all of our constitutional<br />

difficulties.<br />

Having argued this, however, it is premature to conclude that a “rights must be<br />

paramount” perspective no longer influences <strong>the</strong> way many assess<br />

constitutional proposals. This was made abundantly clear during debate on <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord in <strong>the</strong> fall of 1992. Unlike <strong>the</strong> 1991 federal proposal, <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord did not contain a separate distinct society clause but<br />

included it within a broader Canada clause. <strong>The</strong> Canada clause, which was an<br />

interpretive clause, defined a number of fundamental characteristics of<br />

Canada, including Canada’s parliamentary <strong>and</strong> federal system of government<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> principles of aboriginal self-government <strong>and</strong> Quebec as a distinct<br />

society. While <strong>the</strong> majority of criticisms focused on aspects of <strong>the</strong> clause o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than distinct society, 17 <strong>the</strong>y emphasized similar objections to those raised<br />

about <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause during <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debate: that <strong>the</strong><br />

Canada clause would increase <strong>the</strong> discretion given to governments to limit<br />

protected rights. <strong>The</strong> most blunt characterization of this was that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

would be “trumped” by <strong>the</strong> Canada clause (Baines, 24, 1992).<br />

Rights-based criticisms of <strong>the</strong> Canada clause speculated on <strong>the</strong> implications of<br />

Canada’s fundamental characteristics being defined in terms of certain<br />

institutional features, such as federalism, parliamentary government <strong>and</strong><br />

aboriginal self-government, while failing to specify <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong><br />

complaint was that this could undermine <strong>the</strong> relative significance of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong> judicial review of conflicts between governmental <strong>and</strong> rightsbased<br />

claims. It was also argued that <strong>the</strong> rights protected under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

might suffer because <strong>the</strong> clause provided that <strong>the</strong> entire <strong>Constitution</strong>, including<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, “shall be interpreted in a manner consistent” with <strong>the</strong>se<br />

fundamental characteristics. <strong>The</strong> concern raised was that <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> word<br />

“including” might encourage <strong>the</strong> courts to assume that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is<br />

subordinate, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore inferior, to <strong>the</strong> Canada clause:<br />

129


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

[<strong>The</strong> draft text uses] “including” which is not an ambiguous word. To<br />

<strong>the</strong> contrary, it means to treat as subsumed, as subordinated. At <strong>the</strong><br />

present time, <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> values are not subordinated to any o<strong>the</strong>r values.<br />

However, if <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown agreement is adopted, <strong>the</strong>y will be<br />

subordinated to <strong>the</strong> contents of <strong>the</strong> Canada Clause.<br />

More specifically, <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> values will be measured against <strong>the</strong> first<br />

three fundamental characteristics that are itemized in <strong>the</strong> Canada<br />

Clause. <strong>The</strong>se three are flat-out assertions of governmental <strong>and</strong><br />

federalism characteristics...Both <strong>the</strong>ir wording <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir positioning<br />

will be interpreted as indicative of <strong>the</strong> strength of <strong>the</strong> call for<br />

deference to governmental actors. (Ibid., 25).<br />

<strong>The</strong> preceding criticism of <strong>the</strong> Canada clause faulted <strong>the</strong> proposal for its failure<br />

to secure protected rights against governmental encroachments. Critics<br />

rejected <strong>the</strong> Canada clause on <strong>the</strong> basis of assumptions that governmental<br />

power <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are inherently conflictual <strong>and</strong> that governments ought<br />

not to be permitted to promote non-enumerated values that conflict with<br />

protected rights. This “rights must be paramount” critique of <strong>the</strong> clause had a<br />

constraining effect on debate. It allowed opponents to reject <strong>the</strong> Accord on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of “principle,” in that <strong>the</strong> Canada clause did not adequately insulate<br />

protected rights from government action, without addressing <strong>the</strong> following<br />

questions which would have contributed to a healthier <strong>and</strong> more vibrant<br />

debate: are <strong>the</strong>re fundamental values, in addition to those in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, that<br />

governments might promote in light of this clause; where conflicts with<br />

protected rights arise, is <strong>the</strong> wording of <strong>the</strong> clause sufficient to ensure that<br />

rights are appropriately considered; <strong>and</strong> will <strong>the</strong> clause encourage a<br />

meaningful assessment of <strong>the</strong> justification of governmental objectives in<br />

conflict with rights?<br />

A second <strong>and</strong> more compelling criticism of <strong>the</strong> Canada clause was its<br />

ambiguity regarding whe<strong>the</strong>r aboriginal women, under a system of aboriginal<br />

self-government, would be protected by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association of Canada (NWAC) sought an injunction to halt <strong>the</strong> referendum<br />

on <strong>the</strong> bases that 1) its members were excluded from <strong>the</strong> constitutional review<br />

process <strong>and</strong> 2) <strong>the</strong> Accord would undermine protection under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. This<br />

second argument is most relevant here. <strong>The</strong> concern arose from a proposal to<br />

entrench a “contextual statement” to ensure that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would not prevent<br />

aboriginal governments from safeguarding <strong>and</strong> developing <strong>the</strong>ir languages,<br />

cultures, economies, institutions <strong>and</strong> traditions. NWAC’s criticism was that<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord would confer significant discretion upon aboriginal governments<br />

to promote traditional <strong>and</strong> collective values that may undermine protection for<br />

individual women’s rights (NWAC, 3).<br />

In response to heavy pressure from aboriginal women, <strong>the</strong> drafters of <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional accord inserted a clause to address <strong>the</strong> equality of aboriginal<br />

men <strong>and</strong> women (Fine). However, <strong>the</strong> draft legal text, which was available<br />

only late in <strong>the</strong> referendum debate, contained ambiguous clauses on <strong>the</strong><br />

relationship between aboriginal policy values <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. While a<br />

proposed amendment to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act 1982 would have guaranteed <strong>the</strong><br />

rights of aboriginal peoples equally regardless of gender (s. 35(7)), <strong>the</strong> Canada<br />

clause, an interpretive clause for <strong>the</strong> entire constitution including <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,<br />

would have guaranteed aboriginal governments <strong>the</strong> “right to promote <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

languages, cultures <strong>and</strong> traditions <strong>and</strong> to ensure <strong>the</strong> integrity of <strong>the</strong>ir societies”<br />

130


<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

(s. 2(b)). <strong>The</strong>se clauses did little to address NWAC’s concern that women can,<br />

<strong>and</strong> historically have been, harmed by actions taken in <strong>the</strong> name of cultural or<br />

traditional values (NWAC, 3).<br />

It is difficult to conclude that aboriginal women’s reliance on a “rights must be<br />

paramount” framework to assess <strong>the</strong> constitution discouraged meaningful<br />

debate on <strong>the</strong> relationship between rights <strong>and</strong> aboriginal self-government. It<br />

would have been virtually impossible to engage in thoughtful debate about <strong>the</strong><br />

relative significance of collective values, given <strong>the</strong> undefined nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal for aboriginal self-government as well as <strong>the</strong> ambiguity <strong>and</strong> apparent<br />

conflict between <strong>the</strong> preceding clauses.<br />

Conclusions<br />

It is difficult to draw any sharp conclusions about whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> rights must be<br />

paramount perspective will continue to characterize constitutional debate.<br />

Despite an implicit reassessment of <strong>the</strong> utility of this approach in <strong>the</strong> 1991 <strong>and</strong><br />

early 1992 constitutional debate, rights-based assessments assumed an<br />

important role in criticisms of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord in <strong>the</strong> fall of 1992.<br />

Memories of <strong>the</strong> sharp Anglophone/Francophone division generated by <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society debate in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord likely created a reluctance to<br />

engage in a similar debate in 1991 <strong>and</strong> early 1992. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, as this paper has<br />

suggested, this ethnic/linguistic division subsequently encouraged greater<br />

sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> issue of whe<strong>the</strong>r Quebec’s more collective approach to rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> values could be accommodated within a “rights must be paramount”<br />

perspective.<br />

Rights-based assessments of <strong>the</strong> proposed constitutional amendments did not<br />

generate <strong>the</strong> same Anglophone/Francophone division in <strong>the</strong> later<br />

Charlottetown round. Secure in <strong>the</strong> knowledge of wide-spread opposition to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord (both in <strong>and</strong> out of Quebec), conveyed <strong>and</strong> reinforced by frequent<br />

public opinion polling, those with rights-based objections did not have to<br />

weigh <strong>the</strong>se principles against <strong>the</strong> risk of fur<strong>the</strong>r alienating Quebec. <strong>The</strong>re was<br />

not, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, sufficient or compelling reason to reassess <strong>the</strong> prudence of<br />

adopting a “rights must be paramount” assessment of <strong>the</strong> Accord.<br />

Given our limited experience with <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it is hardly surprising that<br />

attitudes about <strong>the</strong> relationship between citizens <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state, limits <strong>and</strong> rights<br />

or governments <strong>and</strong> courts are still adjusting to <strong>the</strong> significant societal <strong>and</strong><br />

institutional changes represented by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Aside from <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

society debate, we simply have not been compelled by circumstances to<br />

reassess uncritical assumptions about <strong>the</strong> primacy of protected rights. Fur<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

we have not yet been exposed to many fundamentally divisive judicial<br />

outcomes in which <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>-based entitlements are fundamentally at odds with<br />

deeply held values. While <strong>the</strong>re has been a h<strong>and</strong>ful of contentious judicial<br />

cases, <strong>the</strong>se have not been of <strong>the</strong> kind that fundamentally challenge our<br />

intuitive, moral <strong>and</strong> political senses of what is right, just or fair, or that engage<br />

us in protracted <strong>and</strong> contentious discussions of <strong>the</strong> merits of values in conflict<br />

with protected rights. Increasingly, as rights-based claims call into question<br />

<strong>the</strong> validity of strongly held values, we may realize that, under some<br />

circumstances, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s contribution to <strong>the</strong> political process will be less a<br />

matter of vindicating rights-based claims <strong>and</strong> more a responsibility of<br />

determining where our priorities <strong>and</strong> emphases should be placed when<br />

reconciling conflicting values. One consequence of living with <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

may be pressure to rethink <strong>the</strong> utility of a “rights must be paramount”<br />

131


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

perspective, given its inherent limitations in fostering <strong>and</strong> contributing to a<br />

meaningful debate about <strong>the</strong> priorities we assign to competing values. In light<br />

of <strong>the</strong> incompleteness <strong>and</strong> indeterminacy of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s values, it is simply<br />

no answer to argue that if a value is not explicitly mentioned in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it<br />

cannot <strong>and</strong> should not be accommodated in <strong>the</strong> constitutional order.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Nor does it recognize <strong>the</strong> potential of s. 33 as a means of reconciling non-entrenched values<br />

by temporarily limiting <strong>the</strong> applicability of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. However, <strong>the</strong> unpopularity of <strong>the</strong><br />

legislative override outside Quebec makes it difficult to engage in this discussion.<br />

2. This argument was first made by <strong>the</strong> author in “Representation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Should<br />

Rights be Paramount?” in David Smith <strong>and</strong> John Courtney (ed.), Drawing Boundaries:<br />

Legislatures, Courts <strong>and</strong> Electoral Values, 1992.<br />

3. See for example, Hiebert, “Representation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Should Rights be Paramount?”<br />

4. <strong>The</strong> word <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> here is placed in quotations to recognize <strong>the</strong> limitations of talking about<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights as opposed to protected rights. <strong>The</strong> difficulty with using <strong>the</strong> word <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in<br />

this context is that it connotes, to many, <strong>the</strong> belief that only those rights actually contained in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, as recognized by <strong>the</strong> Court, are constitutionally legitimate. But <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

being made in this paper is that by recognizing different values <strong>and</strong> policies not specifically<br />

enumerated, as a reasonable limit under s. 1, courts may provide constitutional protection to<br />

a broader range of values than those specifically enumerated. Through section 1<br />

interpretations, <strong>the</strong>refore, o<strong>the</strong>r values also receive <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> recognition. For this reason, <strong>the</strong><br />

term “protected rights” is preferable to “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights.”<br />

5. One o<strong>the</strong>r particularly controversial decision was R. v. Seaboyer; R. v. Gayme (1991) 2<br />

S.C.R. 577, in which rape shield legislation (designed to shield women from having <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

sexual histories discussed in sexual assault proceedings) was struck down. Intensive<br />

lobbying, however, resulted in revised legislation which, because it defines consent <strong>and</strong><br />

places <strong>the</strong> onus on <strong>the</strong> alleged assaulter to show intent had been given, may be viewed as a<br />

significant improvement over <strong>the</strong> previous provisions. This revised legislation has not yet<br />

been challenged under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

6. One of <strong>the</strong> clearest expressions of this position is offered by Lorraine Weinrib, “<strong>The</strong><br />

Supreme Court of Canada <strong>and</strong> Section One of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.” Supreme Court <strong>La</strong>w Review,v.<br />

19, 1988.<br />

7. <strong>The</strong> trilogy consisted of Reference re Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), (1987)<br />

1 S.C.R. 313; Government of Saskatchewan v. Retail Wholesale <strong>and</strong> Department Store<br />

Union, Locals 544, 496, 635 & 955, (1987) 1 S.C.R. 460; <strong>and</strong> R. v. Public Service Alliance of<br />

Canada (1987) 1 S.C.R. 424.<br />

8. See, for example, <strong>the</strong> intervening factums by Women’s Legal Education Action Fund in R. v.<br />

Seaboyer; R. v. Gayme (1991) 2 S.C.R. 577.<br />

9. During <strong>the</strong> public hearings of <strong>the</strong> Lortie Commission (Royal Commission on Electoral<br />

Reform <strong>and</strong> Party Financing), four-fifths of intervenors who addressed <strong>the</strong> issue of election<br />

spending limits favoured this principle. This sentiment was mirrored by <strong>the</strong> results of an<br />

attitudinal study in which 93% of respondents supported spending regulations for political<br />

parties. Reforming Electoral Democracy, v. 1, 1991, p. 334.<br />

10. Mary Ann Glendon raises similar criticisms of American “rights talk”. See Mary Ann<br />

Glendon, Rights Talk: <strong>The</strong> Impoverishment of Political Discourse, 1991.<br />

11. Critics who viewed <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause in this manner ascribed little significance to<br />

<strong>the</strong> pan-Canadian aspects of <strong>the</strong> clause; specifically, <strong>the</strong> recognition in s. 2(1)(a) of Frenchspeaking<br />

Canadians present in Quebec which are part of <strong>the</strong> fundamental characteristics of<br />

Canada.<br />

12. <strong>The</strong>se organizations were <strong>the</strong> National Association of Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>w (NAWL), <strong>the</strong><br />

Women’s Legal Education <strong>and</strong> Act Fund (LEAF), <strong>the</strong> Canadian Advisory Council on <strong>the</strong><br />

Status of Women (CACSW), <strong>the</strong> National Action Committee on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women<br />

(NAC) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ad Hoc Committee of Women on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

13. Carol Goar, “How PM Infuriated Women’s Groups,” Toronto Star, August 27, 1987, A2.<br />

132


14. <strong>The</strong> only change made was a modification of <strong>the</strong> skeleton proposal of <strong>the</strong> April 30, 1987<br />

meeting of 11 First Ministers. In that day-long session <strong>the</strong> Ministers achieved agreement in<br />

principle for <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke proposals but left, for a later date, <strong>the</strong> task of fleshing out <strong>the</strong><br />

legal text. Changes were in response to criticisms that <strong>the</strong> clause, as originally worded,<br />

promoted <strong>the</strong> notion of “two Canadas.” <strong>The</strong> original clause recognized “<strong>the</strong> existence of<br />

French-speaking Canada, centred in but not limited to Quebec, <strong>and</strong> English-speaking<br />

Canada, concentrated outside Quebec but also present in Canada.” <strong>The</strong> new phrasing<br />

reflected an attempt to eliminate <strong>the</strong> conception of two Canadas by altering <strong>the</strong> reference to<br />

“French-speaking Canada” <strong>and</strong> “English-speaking Canada.” <strong>The</strong> new wording recognized<br />

“<strong>the</strong> existence of French-speaking Canadians ...<strong>and</strong>English-speaking Canadians”. <strong>The</strong><br />

significance of <strong>the</strong> change is <strong>the</strong> clause defined groups of people ra<strong>the</strong>r than geographical<br />

regions.<br />

15. Senator Lowell Murray was particularly emphatic in his suggestion that <strong>the</strong> distinct society<br />

clause would not adversely affect protected rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Joint Parliamentary<br />

Committee, August 4, 1987, 2:50.<br />

16. While Wells was willing to consider having <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> interpreted in a manner consistent<br />

with <strong>the</strong> preservation <strong>and</strong> promotion of Quebec as a distinct society within Canada, he did<br />

express concern with <strong>the</strong> wording of <strong>the</strong> federal proposal. His recommendation was to make<br />

it clear that <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause would only affect <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> interpretations of Quebec<br />

<strong>and</strong> not federal laws. A second concern with <strong>the</strong> wording was <strong>the</strong> possibility that <strong>the</strong><br />

definition of “distinct society” might be broadened over time to include considerations o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than language, culture <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> civil law tradition.<br />

17. Some individuals <strong>and</strong> groups have continued to argue that <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause would<br />

undermine individual rights. However, like <strong>the</strong> 1991 federal proposal, <strong>the</strong> clause did not<br />

generate <strong>the</strong> same degree of opposition as during <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debate. For criticism of<br />

distinct society in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord, see Deborah Coyne <strong>and</strong> Robert Howse, No<br />

Deal: Why Canadians should reject <strong>the</strong> Mulroney <strong>Constitution</strong>, 1992.<br />

Bibliography<br />

<strong>The</strong> Limitations of a “Rights Must be Paramount”<br />

Perspective<br />

Baines, Bev. “Why <strong>La</strong>wyers Should Vote ‘No’,” Kate Su<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>, ed., Perspectives on <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord, Centre for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies, 1992.<br />

Bonenfant, Claire. Fédération des femmes du Québec, Minutes of Proceedings <strong>and</strong> Evidence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong> House of Commons on <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord, 13:44-45.<br />

Brock, Kathy L. “A M<strong>and</strong>ate Fulfilled: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Manitoba Task Force on<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke.” 1990.<br />

Canada. Reforming Electoral Democracy, v. 1, 1991.<br />

Canada. Renewal of Canada Conferences: Compendium of Reports, <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conferences<br />

Secretariat, 1992.<br />

Canada. “Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Proposals,” Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong> Services, 1991.<br />

Cohen, M. Joint Parliamentary Committee Hearings, 18 October 1980, 7:86.<br />

Dworkin, Ronald, “Liberalism,” in Michael S<strong>and</strong>el, ed., Liberalism <strong>and</strong> its Critics, 1984.<br />

Equality Eve. “<strong>The</strong> Government’s Proposals <strong>and</strong> How <strong>The</strong>y Could Affect You,” 1991.<br />

Everitt, Donna. Br<strong>and</strong>on Women’s Study Group. Special Joint Committee.<br />

Fine, Sean. “Native Women aim to block national referendum campaign in Court,” Globe <strong>and</strong><br />

Mail, Oct. 13, 1992, A10.<br />

Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, “Bourassa’s use of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> clause shows his vision of distinct Quebec”,<br />

December 22, 1988, A1, A5.<br />

Goar, Carol. “How PM Infuriated Women’s Groups,” Toronto Star, August 27, 1987, A2.<br />

Henderson, Keith. Canadians for Equality of Rights under <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Special Joint<br />

Committee, 17 December 1991, 32:34.<br />

Hiebert, Janet. “<strong>The</strong> Evolution of <strong>the</strong> Limitation Clause in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,” Osgoode Hall <strong>La</strong>w<br />

Journal, Winter 1990.<br />

Hiebert, Janet. “Representation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Should Rights be Paramount?”, David Smith <strong>and</strong><br />

John Courtney (ed.), Drawing Boundaries: Legislatures, Courts <strong>and</strong> Electoral Values,<br />

1992.<br />

Hiebert, Janet. Ph.D dissertation, “Determining <strong>the</strong> Limits of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Rights: How Much<br />

Discretion do Governments Retain?”, University of Toronto, 1991.<br />

Horowitz, G. “Conservatism, Liberalism <strong>and</strong> Socialism in Canada: An Interpretation,” Canadian<br />

Journal of Economics <strong>and</strong> Political Science, v. xxxii, 1966.<br />

133


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Knopff, Rainer <strong>and</strong> F.L. Morton. “Nation-Building <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Freedoms,” <strong>Constitution</strong>alism, Citizenship <strong>and</strong> Society in Canada, Alan Cairns <strong>and</strong> Cynthia<br />

Williams, eds., Coordinators, 1985.<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, Michael. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Legalization of Politics in Canada, 1989.<br />

Monahan, Patrick. Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>: <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court<br />

of Canada. 1987.<br />

NAC Response to Federal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Proposals. Oct. 25, 1991.<br />

Native Women’s Association of Canada, Press Release, September 21, 1992.<br />

Peck, Sidney. “An Analytical Framework for <strong>the</strong> Application of <strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms.” Osgoode Hall <strong>La</strong>w Journal, v. 25, 1987.<br />

Rebick, Judy. President National Action Committee on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women. Special Joint<br />

Committee on a Renewed Canada, 29 Oct. 1991, 10:18-19.<br />

Russell, Peter H. “Political Purposes of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,” <strong>The</strong> Canadian Bar Review, March<br />

1983.<br />

Schneiderman, David. (ed.) “Conversations Among Friends,” Proceedings of an interdisciplinary<br />

Conference on Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform, Centre for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies,<br />

Edmonton, 1992.<br />

Smith, Lynn. “<strong>The</strong> Distinct Society Clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord: Could it Affect Equality<br />

Rights for Women?” in Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions. 1988<br />

Wells, Clyde. “Commentary on <strong>the</strong> Federal Government’s Proposals, Shaping Canada’s Future<br />

Toge<strong>the</strong>r,” 22 October 1991, Presented to <strong>the</strong> Newfoundl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>La</strong>brador Committee on<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

134


Linda Cardinal<br />

Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne<br />

des droits et libertés*<br />

Résumé<br />

Cet article propose une analyse critique de trois modes d’interprétation quant<br />

à la portée de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés : la judiciarisation de<br />

la politique; la prédominance des droits individuels sur les droits collectifs; et,<br />

enfin, les rapports entre démocratie et citoyenneté. Bien que ces modes aient<br />

donné le ton aux débats sur les possibilités de changement dans la société<br />

canadienne, leur validité est loin d’être démontrée. En conclusion, l’article<br />

tente d’élucider les rapports entre les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong>.<br />

Abstract<br />

This article offers a critical analysis of three ways of interpreting <strong>the</strong> scope of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms: <strong>the</strong> judicialization of politics;<br />

<strong>the</strong> predominance of individual over collective rights; <strong>and</strong>, lastly, <strong>the</strong> ties<br />

between democracy <strong>and</strong> citizenship. Although <strong>the</strong>se interpretations have set<br />

<strong>the</strong> tone of debate over possibilities for change in Canadian society, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

validity is far from proven. In conclusion, <strong>the</strong> article attempts to elucidate <strong>the</strong><br />

ties between social movements <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

L’éclosion, dans les années 1980, de mouvements sociaux avant tout<br />

préoccupés de la précarité des droits de la personne semble avoir favorisé<br />

l’émergence à l’échelle mondiale des conditions nécessaires à l’action sociale<br />

et politique (Cairns, 1986). Sc<strong>and</strong>alisés par le totalitarisme de plusieurs pays<br />

dits démocratiques et populaires, des gens de divers horizons ont entrepris de<br />

remettre en cause la problématique révolutionnaire (Ferry et Renault, 1985), si<br />

bien que l’idée d’une transformation « radicale » de la société ne se posera plus<br />

réellement (Keane, 1988). Désormais, le changement découlera davantage de<br />

l’action de groupes à l’intérieur de mouvements qui deviendront, eux, des<br />

lieux d’appartenance et des espaces de rassemblement (Melucci, 1983).<br />

Le Canada n’a pas échappé à ce courant. Soucieux de protéger les citoyennes et<br />

citoyens contre les abus, le gouvernement fédéral adopte en 1982 la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés, ce qui devait entraîner l’apparition au pays<br />

d’un « mouvement social » voué à la défense des droits de la personne.<br />

Quoique fragmenté, ce mouvement en vient à constituer une force bien<br />

supérieure à celle de tout groupe particulier. <strong>La</strong> nouvelle loi constitutionnelle<br />

ouvre en outre aux mouvements sociaux des champs d’action en faveur des<br />

personnes directement touchées par la <strong>Charte</strong> : femmes, autochtones,<br />

personnes h<strong>and</strong>icapées, membres des minorités raciales, ethniques et<br />

linguistiques. Elle encourage la politisation de leurs revendications,<br />

notamment en matière d’avortement, d’action positive, de droits des<br />

autochtones et des minorités de langue française de l’extérieur du Québec. Si,<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

en un sens, la <strong>Charte</strong> ne fait qu’accompagner des changements qui étaient déjà<br />

en marche avant 1982, son adoption marque toutefois un moment important<br />

pour les mouvements sociaux. Elle les amène à sortir leurs revendications du<br />

domaine des questions spécifiques pour en faire des questions de droits de la<br />

personne en même temps que des enjeux politiques reliés à la définition de la<br />

citoyenneté au Canada, leur permettant d’acquérir en corollaire une légitimité<br />

politique sans précédent au pays.<br />

Cette situation fait du Canada un cas intéressant en vue d’une réflexion sur les<br />

mouvements sociaux d’aujourd’hui, puisque la <strong>Charte</strong> nous oblige à<br />

reconsidérer le rapport entre les intervenants sociaux et l’espace politique.<br />

Malheureusement, on n’a guère étudié l’incidence de la <strong>Charte</strong> sur les<br />

mouvements sociaux au Canada. Nous savons que les groupes, notamment le<br />

mouvement des femmes (Gotell, 1991), ont pris part au débat menant à<br />

l’adoption de la <strong>Charte</strong>, mais peu d’analyses ont porté sur l’utilisation qu’ils en<br />

ont fait par la suite. À l’exception de certaines études de cas, réalisées surtout<br />

par les féministes (Fudge, 1987; Brodsky et Day 1989; Razack, 1991; Brodie<br />

et al., 1992), presque tout reste à faire1.<br />

On s’en est tenu jusqu’ici à débattre ses effets sur la société canadienne, se<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>ant, par exemple, si elle ne condamnait pas le Canada à suivre la voie<br />

des États-Unis dans l’utilisation que l’on pourra faire de la référence aux droits<br />

de la personne. Certaines, certains ont décrit de nouveaux phénomènes qui<br />

confirmeraient cette hypothèse : la judiciarisation2 de la politique (M<strong>and</strong>el,<br />

1989) et la prédominance des droits individuels sur les droits collectifs<br />

(Bourque, 1990). D’autres ont cherché à comprendre comment la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

permettait de repenser les rapports entre la démocratie et la citoyenneté<br />

(Cairns, 1986; Taylor, 1986).<br />

Sans porter directement sur les mouvements sociaux, ces différents modes<br />

d’interprétation ont cependant donné le ton aux débats sur les possibilités de<br />

changement aujourd’hui, agissant ainsi sur l’articulation du lien entre les<br />

groupes et la <strong>Charte</strong>. Or, aussi bien sur les plans théorique qu’empirique, la<br />

validité des hypothèses qu’on nous propose reste à démontrer, surtout<br />

lorsqu’elles intéressent les mouvements sociaux. Comme, par ailleurs, la<br />

sociologie s’oriente depuis 1982 vers l’analyse de l’action des groupes, une<br />

lecture critique des modes d’interprétation de la <strong>Charte</strong> s’impose donc. Qui<br />

plus est, nous tenterons dans ce texte d’articuler les deux domaines en vue de<br />

repenser les mouvements sociaux en fonction de la <strong>Charte</strong>.<br />

Il s’agira, dans un premier temps, de procéder à un bref rappel de la sociologie<br />

des mouvements sociaux afin d’en préciser l’expression et de situer nos propos<br />

dans le temps avant de nous livrer à une lecture critique des différentes<br />

interprétations de la portée de la <strong>Charte</strong> sur la société canadienne. Pour<br />

conclure, nous reprendrons ces analyses pour mieux revenir à notre<br />

questionnement : définir le rapport des actrices et acteurs à l’espace politique<br />

et tenter d’esquisser les gr<strong>and</strong>es lignes de notre compréhension de la<br />

pertinence de la <strong>Charte</strong> dans l’étude des mouvements sociaux et du<br />

changement.<br />

Parce qu’elle repose essentiellement sur l’efficacité de notre dialectique et, en<br />

bout de ligne, sur nos opinions, pareille entreprise a des limites évidentes,<br />

notamment celle de ne pas éclairer la portée de la <strong>Charte</strong> sur le plan empirique.<br />

Néanmoins, elle nous apparaît nécessaire dans la mesure où nous sommes<br />

138


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

insatisfaite de ce que nous proposent les interprètes de la <strong>Charte</strong>, surtout<br />

lorsqu’ils interpellent les mouvements sociaux.<br />

<strong>La</strong> sociologie des mouvements sociaux<br />

Nous rattachons notre étude du cas canadien à la sociologie des mouvements<br />

sociaux, car notre intérêt principal est le changement social contemporain tel<br />

qu’il a été étudié dans ce champ. Alain Touraine (1974), qui a donné le ton aux<br />

analyses sur la question, a réussi à créer un consensus autour de la définition de<br />

mouvement social, définition que son collaborateur Michel Wieviorka résume<br />

ainsi :<br />

...une action conflictuelle, inscrite dans un rapport structurel de<br />

domination, portée par un acteur capable de se reconnaître dans une<br />

identité sociale et d’en reconnaître une à son adversaire, capable<br />

également de se situer sur un terrain qui est le même pour l’acteur<br />

auquel il s’oppose — et donc d’agir pour le contrôle des mêmes<br />

enjeux, des mêmes ressources culturelles. (1991 : 154)<br />

Depuis les années soixante-dix, la sociologie des mouvements sociaux<br />

s’appuie largement sur cette définition et ses analyses portent principalement<br />

sur les protagonistes, leurs projets, leurs luttes, leur culture politique et leur<br />

capacité à limiter le pouvoir de l’État (Castoriadis, 1975, 1979; Maheu, 1983;<br />

Touraine, 1978, 1980, 1981, 1984). Pendant les années quatre-vingts, nous<br />

avons aussi été amenés à nous dem<strong>and</strong>er si les mouvements étaient porteurs<br />

d’une stratégie de radicalisation de la démocratie (<strong>La</strong>clau et Mouffe, 1985),<br />

d’une politique de radicalisme auto-limitatif (Cohen 1985), d’une action en<br />

vue du développement d’une société civile démocratique et socialiste (Keane<br />

1988) ou de pratiques individuelles et collectives mondiales (Hégédus, 1989).<br />

Au Canada, les analyses des mouvements sociaux ont accordé une gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

importance à la société civile (Briskin, Adamson et McPhail, 1988; Gagnon et<br />

Rioux, 1988; Magnusson, 1990; Thériault, 1985).<br />

Ces quelques références montrent que la sociologie des mouvements sociaux a<br />

beaucoup été préoccupée par les fins, c’est-à-dire par l’option politique, se<br />

caractérisant par une approche de type volontariste selon laquelle les acteurs<br />

seraient au centre des changements sociaux (Skocpol, 1985). Par conséquent,<br />

elle s’est moins intéressée au rapport entre les protagonistes et le contexte<br />

politique et ses institutions. Au Canada, avant comme après l’adoption de la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong>, la sociologie s’est peu penchée sur la façon dont, par exemple, l’État<br />

(les pouvoirs législatif, exécutif et judiciaire) a contribué au développement et<br />

à la structuration de l’action.<br />

De surcroît, la sociologie des mouvements sociaux n’a pas encore, à notre<br />

connaissance, proposé de repères d’ordre théorique susceptibles de nous<br />

éclairer sur la question des droits. Elle est demeurée relativement silencieuse<br />

sur la signification des revendications en matière notamment d’avortement,<br />

d’égalité, de paix, d’autodétermination3. Elle a plutôt pensé les mouvements<br />

sociaux à l’extérieur de la problématique des droits pour analyser leurs visées<br />

de changement plus radical.<br />

Également, elle a étudié les mouvements sociaux en postulant essentiellement<br />

que l’État ne pouvait que s’employer à les contrôler (Keane, 1988; Ng, 1990).<br />

Or, au Canada, les gouvernements ont, jusque pendant les années quatrevingts,<br />

joué un rôle relativement important dans la mobilisation des groupes<br />

139


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

sociaux, que ce soit au moyen de programmes visant à encourager la<br />

participation démocratique des citoyennes et des citoyens au développement<br />

communautaire4, de commissions royales d’enquête5 ou de subventions<br />

directes à des groupes donnés.<br />

Ces quelques observations montrent que nous n’avons pas suffisamment de<br />

moyens pour expliquer la part qui revient aux mouvements sociaux dans le<br />

changement contemporain. Nous savons qu’ils sont des espaces de<br />

rassemblement et de débats, qu’ils soulèvent des enjeux importants et qu’ils<br />

font avancer les mentalités. L’absence d’études de cas pouvant nous éclairer<br />

sur la question traduit toutefois la nature plutôt générale à ce jour des analyses à<br />

ce sujet. Notre intérêt pour la <strong>Charte</strong> provient donc de ce fait qu’elle oblige la<br />

sociologie à situer l’action des groupes sur le plan politique6 et à comprendre<br />

son développement.<br />

<strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong><br />

Rappelons rapidement que la <strong>Charte</strong> vient remplacer la Loi canadienne sur les<br />

droits de la personne promulguée en 1960, laquelle n’avait aucune portée<br />

constitutionnelle ni effet dans les champs de compétence provinciaux. À cet<br />

égard, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 va beaucoup plus loin, reconnaissant,<br />

entre autres, certains droits à caractère collectif et la légitimité des mesures<br />

d’accès à l’égalité (affirmative action). Ainsi, l’article 15 (1), par exemple,<br />

stipule que :«<strong>La</strong>loinefait acception de personne et s’applique également à<br />

tous, et tous ont droit à la même protection et au même bénéfice de la loi,<br />

indépendamment de toute discrimination, notamment des discriminations<br />

fondées sur la race, l’origine nationale ou ethnique, la couleur, la religion, le<br />

sexe, l’âge ou les déficiences mentales ou physiques », t<strong>and</strong>is que le<br />

paragraphe (2) du même article exempte expressément les mesures visant à<br />

« améliorer » la situation des groupes des effets restrictifs des dispositions<br />

relatives à l’égalité formelle7. L’article 27 consacre le principe du multiculturalisme de la société canadienne<br />

alors que l’article 28 précise que la <strong>Charte</strong> s’applique également aux hommes<br />

et aux femmes8. De plus, ses articles 16 à 20 consacrent la nature bilingue du<br />

pays et l’article 23 garantit les droits à l’éducation dans la langue maternelle<br />

des membres des minorités linguistiques.<br />

T<strong>and</strong>is que la Loi canadienne sur les droits de la personne donne lieu à peu<br />

d’activisme juridique en ce qui a trait à la défense des droits civils, la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

inaugure un important processus de révision judiciaire. Mis à part les cas<br />

relevant du Code criminel qu’on attendait de régler avec l’entrée en vigueur de<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong>, les mouvements sociaux, tout particulièrement, choisiront de<br />

soumettre aux tribunaux diverses questions touchant les droits à incidence<br />

collective, comme ceux des femmes et des minorités. Pour faciliter ce<br />

processus, le Secrétariat d’État créera la Commission des droits de la personne<br />

qui subventionnera les groupes désireux d’emprunter la voie judiciaire pour<br />

faire reconnaître leurs droits. Jusqu’en 1992, le gouvernement canadien<br />

finance aussi un programme de contestation judiciaire dont le budget de plus<br />

de 8 millions de dollars servira à appuyer financièrement « la contestation<br />

devant les tribunaux judiciaires de causes types reliées, entre autres, aux litiges<br />

de nature linguistique » (1991 : 1). Ce programme soutenait aussi les causes<br />

touchant le droit des groupes (femmes, autochtones, personnes h<strong>and</strong>icapées et<br />

minorités visibles) à l’égalité.<br />

140


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

De plus, certains groupes créent leur propre fonds pour « financer des<br />

contestations découlant de la <strong>Charte</strong> » (Knopff et Morton, 1986 : 175) et<br />

intervenir dans des causes types afin de faire avancer la jurisprudence dans ces<br />

dossiers9. Signalons, entre autres, l’Association canadienne pour les libertés<br />

civiles, le Comité canadien d’action sur le statut de la femme (CCA),<br />

l’Association nationale des femmes et du droit (ANFD), le Women’s Legal<br />

Education <strong>and</strong> Action Fund (LEAF). Pour leur part, les juges, sous le nouveau<br />

régime de 1982, ont eu à prendre des décisions importantes en ce qui a trait, par<br />

exemple, au choix en matière d’avortement (Morgentaler, 1988), à la Loi 101<br />

au Québec (Brown, 1990), ou à la gestion scolaire en milieu francophone<br />

minoritaire (Mahé, 1990).<br />

Manifestement, la <strong>Charte</strong> a poussé les mouvements sociaux sur la voie de<br />

l’activisme juridique et du changement institutionnel. Elle a aussi eu pour effet<br />

de les sortir du modèle traditionnel de gestionnaires de la revendication sociale<br />

pour devenir des gestionnaires de droits qui favorisent l’avènement de<br />

titulaires de nouveaux droits et donc de nouveaux protagonistes<br />

constitutionnels. Or, si la sociologie s’est peu intéressée à ce phénomène, des<br />

interprètes de la <strong>Charte</strong> n’ont pas tardé à faire connaître leurs vues sur ses<br />

effets. En se dem<strong>and</strong>ant si la <strong>Charte</strong> contribuait à l’américanisation de la<br />

société, à la prédominance des droits individuels sur les droits collectifs et à la<br />

remise en cause de la démocratie politique, ils ont indiqué des pistes de<br />

réflexion fécondes pour une sociologie des mouvements sociaux qui tente de<br />

comprendre le politique. D’où l’intérêt que nous leur portons.<br />

<strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong> et ses interprétations<br />

Trois types d’interprétation de la <strong>Charte</strong> et de sa portée sur les groupes et, de<br />

façon plus large, sur le développement de la société canadienne, soit la<br />

citoyenneté méritent d’être examinés. Un premier discours, formulé par<br />

Michael M<strong>and</strong>el (1989) et la gauche canadienne-anglaise, juge que la Loi<br />

constitutionnelle de 1982 relève d’actions non démocratiques servant à<br />

dépolitiser le débat sur les questions sociales. Elle aurait pour effet de réduire<br />

la politique au juridique accélérant ainsi le mouvement, déjà en cours,<br />

d’américanisation de la société canadienne. Un deuxième, tenu par Gilles<br />

Bourque (1990) et les nationalistes québécois, estime que la <strong>Charte</strong> consacre<br />

la prédominance des droits individuels sur les droits collectifs, ce qui<br />

accentuerait également l’américanisation de la société canadienne et<br />

renverrait à l’histoire toute vision de la nation fondée sur la communauté. Une<br />

troisième approche, adoptée par Alan Cairns (1986) et une certaine élite<br />

libérale canadienne-anglaise, concentre son analyse sur les objectifs initiaux<br />

de la <strong>Charte</strong> : la protection des droits des citoyennes et des citoyens et<br />

l’épanouissement de la nation canadienne (le « nation-building »).<br />

Les deux premières interprétations interpellent les mouvements sociaux parce<br />

qu’elles supposent que la <strong>Charte</strong> les condamne à participer à l’américanisation<br />

de la société canadienne. Aux yeux des tenants de la troisième interprétation, la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong> favoriserait plutôt « la reconnaissance de clivages sociaux au pays à<br />

partir desquels la capacité de la <strong>Charte</strong> à contribuer à l’unité canadienne<br />

semble plus difficile à réaliser que prévu. » En effet, selon Cairns, « du point<br />

de vue de la démocratie, le problème est le suivant : la politisation des divisions<br />

sociales, jointe à la multiplication des différentiations typiques de la société<br />

moderne, érode notre identité de citoyens préoccupés par la totalité de la<br />

société » (1986 : 92). De plus, le rapprochement de l’État et des groupes pour<br />

structurer l’action de ces derniers mène à l’établissement d’un rapport patron-<br />

141


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

client, ce qui rend encore plus difficile l’identification de ces groupes à une<br />

vision commune de la citoyenneté.<br />

Ainsi, les objectifs politiques de la <strong>Charte</strong> interpellent les mouvements<br />

sociaux dans la mesure où ils seraient, selon cette dernière interprétation,<br />

devenus la cinquième roue du carosse. Doit-on conclure que les mouvements<br />

sociaux entravent la réalisation des objectifs d’unité nationale ou d’une<br />

redéfinition de la citoyenneté au Canada ? <strong>La</strong> thèse de Cairns porte à réfléchir<br />

sur cette dernière question, et c’est ici qu’une sociologie des mouvements<br />

sociaux devrait permettre de la valider ou non. De surcroît, elle pourra aussi se<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>er si les mouvements sont l’objet d’une manipulation politique au<br />

profit d’une américanisation de la société ou encore des besoins de légitimité<br />

de l’État canadien. Nous allons, dans les pages qui suivent, tenter de jeter un<br />

certain éclairage théorique sur ces questions.<br />

L’hypothèse de la judiciarisation de la politique<br />

<strong>La</strong> première hypothèse, nous l’avons déjà dit, a été formulée largement par<br />

l’intelligentsia canadienne-anglaise (de gauche), notamment par Michael<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, auteur du livre <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Legalization of Politics<br />

of Canada (1989). Selon lui, la <strong>Charte</strong> est une initiative non démocratique<br />

relevant d’un mouvement qui vise la judiciarisation de la politique au Canada<br />

et qui est, de surcroît, au service du plus fort. Ainsi, les individus et les groupes<br />

concernés par la <strong>Charte</strong> deviendraient des victimes de garanties<br />

constitutionnelles qui devaient, en principe, les protéger contre les abus des<br />

plus forts.<br />

Évidemment, nous ne pouvons nier le fait que la <strong>Charte</strong> encourage une<br />

certaine judiciarisation des débats politiques au Canada et l’avènement d’un<br />

gouvernement des juges qui peuvent désormais se substituer aux législateurs.<br />

Les juges interviennent dans les débats en vertu de leur autorité et du pouvoir<br />

qui leur est conféré, ce qui peut parfois inquiéter même dans les cas où ils<br />

décideraient en faveur des « plus faibles ». Mais à l’opposé des tenants de<br />

l’hypothèse de la judiciarisation, nous estimons que cette situation est<br />

antérieure à 1982. À titre d’exemple, de 1969 à 1988, le débat sur le droit des<br />

femmes en matière d’avortement a été fortement caractérisé par l’intervention<br />

des juges chargés d’interpréter la loi existante. Par contre, en 1988, le jugement<br />

de la Cour suprême du Canada dans l’affaire Morgentaler se démarque de cette<br />

tendance en déclarant la Loi sur l’avortement inconstitutionnelle. Ainsi, les<br />

juges renvoient aux femmes et aux hommes politiques la responsabilité de<br />

légiférer sur la question. Ils s’abstiennent également de recomm<strong>and</strong>ations en la<br />

matière, indiquant clairement à la classe politique leur refus d’assumer son<br />

rôle. Pour sa part, le gouvernement Mulroney tire profit du fait que ce soit les<br />

juges qui tranchent la question de l’avortement, évitant ainsi de se mettre à dos<br />

une partie de l’électorat. De fait, le débat sur le droit des femmes en cette<br />

matière illustre bien comment, au Canada, les législateurs et le gouvernement<br />

veulent confier aux juges le soin de décider de quel côté il faut pencher10 !De<br />

plus, le droit qui se projette comme un moyen de transformation sociale est ici<br />

perçu comme une échappatoire.<br />

Néanmoins, les questions qui hantent la société canadienne — avortement,<br />

droits linguistiques et équité—ainsi que les débats n’en sont pas pour autant<br />

dépolitisés et les mouvements démobilisés. Aussi, l’idée de la judiciarisation<br />

de la politique semble bien constituer un prétexte pour faire valoir une vision<br />

142


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

manichéenne du pouvoir : celle des « forts » contre les « faibles », celle du<br />

pouvoir juridique contre le pouvoir politique.<br />

Cependant, la critique selon laquelle la judiciarisation du politique se<br />

produirait au détriment du lien communautaire qui unit les membres d’un<br />

groupe ne manque pas d’intérêt (Thériault, 1988). Elle vise à comprendre<br />

l’incidence du droit sur le développement des communautés francophones et<br />

acadiennes du Canada tout en permettant de contextualiser le recours au droit<br />

au lieu de le dénoncer. Selon Thériault (1990), il faut reconnaître que les luttes<br />

judiciaires francophones pour le droit à l’éducation se situent dans la<br />

mouvance actuelle de l’individualisme en ce qu’elles libèrent « l’individu des<br />

pesanteurs du social » (1990 : 141). Cela lui permet d’entretenir une relation<br />

légale avec le monde plutôt qu’un rapport organique. Et plus une société se<br />

posera la question des droits, plus on assistera à un élargissement de son espace<br />

juridique11. Ainsi, le phénomène de la judiciarisation de la politique fait appel<br />

à une réflexion plus large sur le droit comme facteur de modernisation des<br />

sociétés.<br />

Cette analyse rejoint celle de Taylor (1986 : 253) selon qui on ne peut, en effet,<br />

nier la pertinence du droit ou des droits dans la société moderne. Il nous ramène<br />

néanmoins à la question de l’américanisation de la société canadienne en<br />

proposant de situer le droit dans le contexte de la démocratie. Le Canada,<br />

précise-t-il, est une société davantage fondée sur un modèle politique de<br />

participation que sur celui des droits individuels. Aussi, une société qui prône<br />

un modèle de droits individuels comme les États-Unis reconnaît aux groupes<br />

ou particuliers la possibilité d’affirmer leurs droits contre l’opinion de la<br />

majorité (1986 : 237). On doit donc conclure que le choix du droit comme<br />

moyen de faire avancer la situation des groupes sociaux défavorisés peut<br />

conduire à l’américanisation de la société. Or, il n’en demeure pas moins que<br />

l’utilisation qu’en ont fait, par exemple, les femmes et les minorités<br />

linguistiques a enfin permis d’actualiser des droits que la majorité<br />

reconnaissait en principe.<br />

Des droits qui s’affrontent<br />

<strong>La</strong> question de la judiciarisation de la politique déborde sur une autre<br />

interprétation selon laquelle la <strong>Charte</strong> conduit à renforcer la prédominance des<br />

droits individuels sur les droits collectifs. Cette idée, soutenue tout<br />

particulièrement par les nationalistes québécois, a été formulée<br />

principalement par Gilles Bourque (1990) puis étudiée par Robert V<strong>and</strong>ycke<br />

(1990).<br />

Selon Bourque, « la <strong>Charte</strong> tend à provoquer une véritable régression des<br />

aspects communautaires de la représentation du monde12 » (1990 : 158),<br />

ajoutant qu’elle produit « un net rétrécissement de la communauté nationale<br />

minoritaire » (159). Pourtant, certaines de ses dispositions, notamment celles<br />

portant sur l’action positive (affirmative action) reconnaissent l’existence de<br />

groupes même s’il est vrai qu’elle n’enchâsse pas le droit des Québécoises et<br />

des Québécois à l’autodétermination, lequel correspondrait à un droit collectif.<br />

Mais la <strong>Charte</strong> ne peut être réduite, comme dans le cas des jugements par les<br />

dispositions de la Loi 101 en matière d’affichage, à certaines interprétations de<br />

juges qui auraient accordé la priorité au droit individuel d’afficher en anglais<br />

sur les droits collectifs des Québécoises et des Québécois. L’accent que le<br />

Québec met sur les droits collectifs peut donner l’impression que celui-ci est<br />

prêt à sacrifier les droits individuels de sa population alors que la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

143


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

québécoise des droits et libertés reconnaît elle aussi des droits individuels à ses<br />

citoyennes et citoyens.<br />

L’interprétation selon laquelle la <strong>Charte</strong> fait prédominer les droits individuels<br />

sur les droits collectifs participe elle aussi d’une vision manichéenne du<br />

pouvoir : celle des Canadiens anglais contre les Québécois francophones et<br />

vice-versa. <strong>La</strong> distinction entre les deux notions de droits individuels et de<br />

droits collectifs relève plutôt de la confusion. On mélange, comme l’écrit<br />

Marie (1988 : 191-200), « le titulaire des droits de l’homme » et « les<br />

conditions de réalisation de ceux-ci en réduisant le sujet au mode d’exercise de<br />

ses droits ». Droits individuels et droits collectifs ne sont pas nécessairement<br />

des synonymes mais, selon Marie, « le droit des peuples à l’auto-détermination<br />

a souvent été présenté, tant lors de l’élaboration de pactes qu’après l’adoption<br />

de ces instruments, comme la condition indispensable du respect des droits de<br />

l’homme » (194).<br />

Nous pourrions citer longuement ce spécialiste des droits de la personne qui a<br />

réussi à clarifier les ambiguïtés « sémantiques » et « méthodologiques » qui<br />

caractérisent les notions de droits individuels et de droits collectifs13. En effet,<br />

le Québec reconnaît dans sa propre <strong>Charte</strong> la question des droits individuels et<br />

le Canada, nous l’avons vu précédemment, fait de même pour les droits<br />

collectifs. D’ailleurs, l’actualisation des droits, que l’on parle de droits à portée<br />

individuelle ou collective, est identique dans les deux cas.<br />

Tout comme Thériault (1990), nous insistons sur le fait que les droits, qu’ils<br />

soient individuels ou collectifs, remettent en question l’espace de la<br />

communauté et ses fondements historico-génétiques, et c’est en cela qu’ils<br />

sont intéressants. Le droit permet aux individus de se projeter dans l’avenir à<br />

partir d’une discussion sur leur devenir et de participer à une communauté ou à<br />

des mouvements sur une base volontaire. Ainsi, le droit rejoint les aspirations<br />

des mouvements sociaux d’une société qui vise l’autonomie individuelle et<br />

collective. Autrement, ils sont condamnés à fonder leur appartenance au<br />

monde sur une communauté empirique et inscrite dans une autre réalité,<br />

notamment biologique, alors que le rejet du naturalisme est justement un de<br />

leur cheval de bataille14. Comme cas d’espèce, le conflit entre francophones et anglophones correspond<br />

plutôt à une incompatibilité d’idéologies politiques justifiée par la référence<br />

symbolique aux droits individuels par rapport aux droits collectifs qu’à des<br />

réalités nécessairement contradictoires15. Il faudrait voir davantage le jeu de<br />

l’idéologie dans le contexte de la <strong>Charte</strong> afin de mieux comprendre pourquoi<br />

des groupes peuvent se prévaloir de certains droits alors que cela est<br />

impossible pour d’autres, comme c’est le cas pour les Québécoises et les<br />

Québécois par rapport au Canada16. Sila<strong>Charte</strong> contribue à la dépolitisation<br />

des débats, elle révèle d’emblée sa nature politique. Par contre, affirmer<br />

qu’elle aurait été conçue, comme le veut le sens commun nationaliste, en vue<br />

de remettre le Québec à sa place dans la Confédération relève autant de la<br />

théorie de la conspiration que de dire qu’elle ne sert que le droit du plus fort. On<br />

confond l’effet avec la cause.<br />

Vers une nation éclatée ?<br />

<strong>La</strong> troisième interprétation fait porter son analyse sur les objectifs politiques de<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong>, soit la protection des droits et libertés des citoyennes et citoyens<br />

canadiens et le rafermissement de l’unité nationale. Alan Cairns,<br />

principalement, s’intéressera aux objectifs politiques de la <strong>Charte</strong> pour<br />

144


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

constater que « les processus politiques complexes qui en ont permis<br />

l’émergence ont fait en sorte que maints clivages et divisions internes ont été<br />

reconnus, et parfois même stimulés » (1986 : 73). Et il ajoutera :<br />

...ce qui surprend davantage, et qui révèle la politisation d’une<br />

gamme toujours plus étendue de clivages et d’identités, c’est la<br />

mesure avec laquelle la <strong>Charte</strong> complète sa reconnaissance de base de<br />

droits individuels en établissant des distinctions à l’égard d’un<br />

certain nombre de groupes particuliers, lesquels font l’objet d’une<br />

reconnaissance constitutionnelle spéciale.<br />

Cairns s’intéressera à la façon dont la <strong>Charte</strong> amorcera l’avènement d’un<br />

« mouvement social » des droits de la personne au Canada, mouvement dont<br />

l’influence risque, selon lui, de remettre en cause la réalisation de l’unité<br />

nationale. Ainsi, les mouvements sociaux seront-ils directement interpellés<br />

par les objectifs politiques de la <strong>Charte</strong> sur la question de la citoyenneté. Or, ils<br />

seront aussi, par le fait même, les premiers à être véritablement concernés par<br />

les attentes vis-à-vis l’État que la <strong>Charte</strong> contribuera à susciter chez les<br />

groupes en question. Entre autres, l’État devra participer à la mise en place de<br />

mesures visant à garantir le bien-être de certains groupes qui totalisent, par<br />

ailleurs, pratiquement 70 p. 100 de la population du pays. On intègrera de<br />

nouveaux groupes sociaux à l’État-providence, non seulement sur la base de<br />

leur situation socio-économique, mais sur celle de la reconnaissance de la<br />

nécessité de mesures spéciales visant à réparer des erreurs et à rompre avec la<br />

discrimination.<br />

Cette situation amènera Alan Cairns à conclure également que les<br />

mouvements sociaux se retrouveront dans un rapport de clients à patron par<br />

rapport à l’État (1986 : 75). Selon lui, la <strong>Charte</strong> aura contribué à l’avènement<br />

d’une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e proximité des groupes avec l’État et une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

intégration au processus bureaucratique. Devenus des professionnels de la<br />

négociation et de la consultation, les groupes s’installeront dans le rapport<br />

clients-patron au détriment de leur lien avec la communauté et ses membres.<br />

Le réseau associatif francophone est un bon exemple d’un mouvement<br />

propulsé dans la négociation et la consultation avec les gouvernements et qui,<br />

au détriment de leur base et de leur référence au développement<br />

communautaire, se muera en groupe d’intérêts. Au nom de la « participation »,<br />

les groupes auront à évaluer des lois, des projets, des programmes. Ainsi, l’État<br />

garantira le financement d’une certaine bureaucratie d’expertes et d’experts<br />

détachés de leur base et bénéficiera du fait que le rapport clients-patron<br />

contribuera à maintenir les clivages entre les groupes. En effet, chacun viendra<br />

défendre ses intérêts particuliers et non une vision commune de la nation. Nous<br />

confirmons donc les inquiétudes de Cairns.<br />

Par contre, les groupes gagneront de ne pas avoir à se justifier politiquement.<br />

Ils représentent, et cela semble suffire pour engager le dialogue avec l’État. Or,<br />

qui parle et à quel titre ou au nom de quel « nous » ? Qui parmi les<br />

organisations nationales des groupes de femmes au Canada sont les plus<br />

représentatives de la population féminine canadienne ? En quoi, les<br />

regroupements autochtones sont-ils représentatifs de leur base ? Quelle est la<br />

place du processus démocratique et de la représentation au sein des<br />

mouvements sociaux ? Ces questions semblent plus ou moins importantes. Les<br />

groupes sont, en partie, devenus des groupes d’intérêts dont on ne remet pas en<br />

cause la représentativité, car, en bout de ligne, ils confèrent une légitimité à<br />

145


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

l’État. Or, si la démocratisation de la société est inévitablement accompagnée<br />

d’une certaine bureaucratisation (Turner, 1986), ce processus ne se déroule-til<br />

pas au détriment d’une reconstruction des mouvements sociaux comme lieu<br />

de socialisation politique (Urry, 1981) ? <strong>La</strong> bureaucratie devient une forme de<br />

vie en soi, détachée de son contexte, d’où la démobilisation des groupes et<br />

l’avènement d’une oligarchie de militants professionnels. D’où aussi la<br />

vulnérabilité de ces groupes devant l’État.<br />

En résumé, largement intégrés à l’État, les mouvements sociaux semblent<br />

contraints à ne rien faire d’autre que de négocier, voire de surveiller le<br />

processus de reconnaissance de leurs droits. L’État devient un mal pour le<br />

meilleur ou pour le pire et cela risque même d’avoir une portée sur la parole<br />

politique des groupes, notamment sur leur capacité de proposer une vision<br />

commune de la nation.<br />

Citoyenneté et mouvements sociaux : une autre hypothèse<br />

Selon Alan Cairns, nous l’avons vu plus haut, le rapprochement entre l’État et<br />

la société civile vient exacerber les différences nationales et risque de porter<br />

atteinte à l’unité nationale. <strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong> aurait contribué à politiser différentes<br />

formes d’identité constitutives du tissu social canadien, mais peu de groupes<br />

seraient en mesure de donner un contenu universel à leur situation particulière.<br />

« Du point de vue de la démocratie, affirme-t-il, le problème est le suivant : la<br />

politisation des divisions sociales, jointe à la multiplication des<br />

différentiations typiques de la société moderne, érode notre identité de<br />

citoyens préoccupés par la totalité de la société » (1986 : 92). Bref, la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

entraînerait une sorte de balkanisation des spécificités sociales.<br />

Par ailleurs, Cairns (1992) reconnaît que l’on ne peut plus négliger les intérêts<br />

des nouveaux « citoyens de la <strong>Charte</strong> », — le cas des francophones hors du<br />

Québec qui insistent sur le fait qu’ils ont des intérêts divergents d’avec ceux du<br />

Québec est ici pertinent. Quoiqu’il en soit, on voit mal pourquoi cette situation<br />

empêcherait les mouvements sociaux de se projeter politiquement dans une<br />

nouvelle définition de la citoyenneté ? <strong>La</strong> sociologie des mouvements sociaux<br />

n’a-t-elle pas réussi à démontrer qu’ils constituent des espaces de<br />

rassemblement (Melucci, 1983), de discussion et de politisation (Keane, 1988;<br />

<strong>La</strong>clau et Mouffe, 1985) et non pas de simples extensions des gouvernements<br />

? Aussi ne faudrait-il pas voir comment cette dimension de leur réalité est ou<br />

n’est pas (ou n’est plus) à l’oeuvre dans le rapport des groupes à l’espace<br />

politique. C’est ici que s’impose aussi une autre réflexion sur l’État et le droit<br />

pour approfondir l’analyse des mouvements sociaux comme actrices, acteurs<br />

constitutionnels participant, à ce titre, au débat politique sur la citoyenneté au<br />

lieu de jouer un rôle plus passif au niveau du processus d’institutionnalisation<br />

de leurs revendications. Notre hypothèse est que le droit a fait avancer la cause<br />

des groupes et, contrairement aux hypothèses de l’américanisation de la<br />

société et de la difficulté du « nation-building », que les mouvements sociaux<br />

contribuent plutôt à un renouvellement du débat sur la citoyenneté. À titre<br />

d’exemple, le droit de gestion scolaire accordé aux francophones vivant en<br />

milieu minoritaire a permis de faire passer l’importance de la culture dans le<br />

droit (Bastarache, 1986). Aussi, les interventions du Women’s Legal <strong>and</strong><br />

Education Action Fund ont permis d’exposer les inégalités entre les hommes et<br />

les femmes dans les jugements des différents tribunaux (Razack, 1992).<br />

Grâce à la fonction de socialisation politique des mouvements sociaux, nous<br />

assistons en vérité à l’avènement d’un discours sociologique dans le droit qui<br />

146


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

force la reconnaissance de réalités collectives et montre que tous les groupes<br />

n’ont pas également accès à la citoyenneté. Ce discours met à nu le pouvoir de<br />

domination d’un groupe sur l’autre sans pour autant tomber dans<br />

l’essentialisme ou le génétique. Concurremment, le droit oblige la<br />

communauté ou le groupe à se départir de ses fondements historicogénétiques,<br />

donc à dénaturaliser le social. Rappelons-le, le droit, nous dit<br />

Thériault, « libère l’individu des pesanteurs du social » (1990 : 141); il lui<br />

permet d’entretenir une relation légale et non plus seulement organique avec le<br />

monde. Ainsi, les groupes deviennent des représentants de catégories<br />

politiques et de sujets agissant au sein de l’espace public. Même s’ils sont aussi<br />

toujours un peu l’« autre », ces sujets s’affirment puisqu’ils résistent à la<br />

totalisation17. Les mouvements sociaux participent à la construction d’un<br />

« nous » articulé autour d’un principe d’équivalents démocratiques, c’est-àdire<br />

d’un principe qui reconnaît l’égalité de chaque élément. Chantal Mouffe<br />

(1992), à qui nous empruntons l’expression d’équivalents démocratiques<br />

définit celui-ci comme « un principe d’articulation qui touche l’agent dans ses<br />

différentes situations de sujet en même temps qu’il lui permettrait une pluralité<br />

d’allégeance particulière et la liberté individuelle18. » À travers ce principe,<br />

une nouvelle vision « commune » de la citoyenneté respecterait la pluralité des<br />

groupes et des individus. Il n’y aurait donc plus d’identité qui dominerait<br />

l’ensemble des identités.<br />

Nous n’avons pas le choix, semble-t-il. Pour contrer ce que Cairns appelle une<br />

balkanisation des particularismes sociaux encouragée par l’État, il faut<br />

repenser la citoyenneté commune à partir de ce nouveau langage de<br />

« l’équivalence démocratique ». Autrement dit, si la citoyenneté sert à traduire<br />

notre appartenance à la société politique canadienne, elle devra s’articuler<br />

autour d’une nouvelle définition de l’égalité, qui doit se fonder sur une<br />

reconnaissance des groupes. Et si l’État exerce un certain contrôle sur les<br />

groupes par le truchement du processus de négociation et de bureaucratisation,<br />

rien n’indique qu’il puisse orienter de façon décisive le débat sur la<br />

citoyenneté.<br />

En somme, à notre avis, la <strong>Charte</strong> donne enfin la possibilité aux Canadiennes<br />

et aux Canadiens de se retrouver autour d’un ensemble de valeurs communes<br />

redéfinissant la problématique de l’égalité sans pour autant tomber dans<br />

l’essentialisme et le génétisme ni entraîner l’américanisation de la société. Ce<br />

discours, les mouvements sociaux en sont les principaux porte-parole, et la<br />

légitimité qu’ils ont gagnée depuis 1982 leur permet de l’exprimer sur la scène<br />

politique. Certes, il est simultanément restreint par le jeu politique et<br />

l’omniprésence de l’État dans la gestion de leurs droits, ce qui montre à quel<br />

point le changement est un processus complexe qui n’est pas régi par la seule<br />

volonté des groupes ou de l’État.<br />

Ainsi, l’analyse du versant proprement politique de la <strong>Charte</strong> nous oblige à<br />

relativiser ou à contextualiser davantage la capacité des mouvements à<br />

participer au changement sans pour autant tomber dans le volontarisme des<br />

acteurs ou le déterminisme des structures. <strong>La</strong> sociologie des mouvements<br />

sociaux a tout à gagner d’un passage par l’analyse du politique. Or, des<br />

analyses de la <strong>Charte</strong> que nous proposent les Cairns, M<strong>and</strong>el, etc., aucune ne<br />

nous permet de voir comment la <strong>Charte</strong> est porteuse d’avenir pour la société<br />

canadienne. Le pessimisme aurait-il plus de crédibilité que l’optimisme, ou<br />

est-ce justement la frontière entre la sociologie et la politique qui fait que les<br />

uns s’occupent trop de la volonté des acteurs et les autres, des forces<br />

incontrôlables ? En fait, c’est à une étude du jeu d’équilibre entre le juridique et<br />

147


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

le politique, les mouvements sociaux et l’État, la socialisation et la<br />

bureaucratisation que nous sommes aujourd’hui conviés. Alors que le contexte<br />

politique participe à la structuration de l’action des groupes, l’étude du jeu<br />

d’équilibre entre l’État et le droit permettrait de voir si les acteurs peuvent<br />

jouer un rôle dans le débat sur la citoyenneté.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Nous avons tenté dans ce texte de passer en revue les différentes<br />

interprétations de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés pour déterminer<br />

leur apport à l’analyse des mouvements sociaux actuels, nous arrêtant à<br />

chacune d’elles. Ainsi, nous avons commenté les thèmes de la judiciarisation<br />

de la société, de son américanisation, de la prédominance des droits<br />

individuels et de l’éclatement d’une vision commune de la nation. Notre<br />

analyse critique nous a aussi conduite à une autre interprétation de la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

selon laquelle la question des droits collectifs pouvait nous porter à repenser<br />

favorablement la question de la citoyenneté.<br />

Quant à la sociologie des mouvements sociaux, elle acquiert, de ce passage par<br />

l’analyse politique, une approche dynamique et complexe de la place du<br />

politique, notamment de l’État et du droit, dans la structuration de l’action.<br />

Elle doit s’ouvrir au droit qui s’ajoute aux modes d’action des groupes et leur<br />

donne une relative efficacité malgré l’omniprésence de l’État. <strong>La</strong> sociologie<br />

des mouvements sociaux doit aussi examiner davantage la question de<br />

l’égalité dans ses rapports avec la citoyenneté : elle a tout à gagner en<br />

reconnaissant que les mouvements vivent à l’heure des droits et des choix,<br />

bref, qu’ils ont eux aussi droit à une certaine légèreté de l’être !<br />

Notes<br />

* Une première version de ce texte a été présentée en 1991, à Madrid, au colloque « Le Canada,<br />

un défi ». Nous tenons à remercier Anne-Andrée Denault, Carole Dion, Martine Perrault,<br />

Marie-Blanche Tahon ainsi que les évaluateurs anonymes pour leurs commentaires et<br />

suggestions de révisions. Nous remercions aussi Danielle Juteau pour ses précieux conseils.<br />

Cet article a pu être rédigé grâce à une subvention du <strong>Conseil</strong> de recherche en sciences<br />

humaines du Canada.<br />

1. Un des évaluateurs de ce texte nous a fait remarquer qu’une analyse de la littérature portant<br />

sur les mouvements sociaux dans d’autres pays « pourrait peut-être laisser entrevoir que ce<br />

qu’on impute à la <strong>Charte</strong> sont des phénomènes très semblables à ce qu’on retrouve ailleurs. »<br />

On pourrait aussi poser la question autrement et dem<strong>and</strong>er pourquoi, au Canada, il a fallu<br />

l’avènement de la <strong>Charte</strong> pour que l’on assiste à certains changements, certes en marche<br />

avant 1982, alors que dans d’autres pays, les mouvements sociaux n’ont pas eu besoin<br />

d’invoquer un tel document pour faire avancer leur cause ? Une sociologie comparée des<br />

trajectoires des mouvements sociaux dans des pays qui possèdent une <strong>Charte</strong> et d’autres qui<br />

n’en ont pas permettrait de vérifier cette hypothèse. Malheureusement, nous ne pouvons pas<br />

nous consacrer à cette question dans ce texte.<br />

2. En anglais, le terme legalization traduit bien l’idée selon laquelle le politique est soumis au<br />

juridique. En français, nous utiliserons le néologisme « judiciarisation » pour exprimer la<br />

même chose.<br />

3. Claude Lefort, dans L’invention démocratique (1981), propose une réflexion des plus<br />

pertinentes sur la question, sauf qu’elle n’a pas vraiment réussi à trouver sa place dans les<br />

analyses sur les mouvements sociaux.<br />

4. À titre d’exemple, en 1968, le gouvernement fédéral mettait sur pied un programme au sein<br />

du Secrétariat d’État en vue de contribuer au développement des communautés<br />

francophones vivant en milieu minoritaire. À la même époque, le ministère de l’Emploi et de<br />

l’Immigration implantait des programmes devant contribuer au développement<br />

communautaire. Les groupes sociaux ont fortement bénéficié de ces programmes. Nous<br />

148


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

pensons ici aux groupes de femmes qui ont réussi par ce moyen à embaucher des animatrices<br />

sociales qui les ont aidées à s’organiser, à faire du recrutement et à se mobiliser. Ces<br />

quelques exemples montrent que l’État n’était pas qu’au service de ses propres intérêts<br />

« absolutistes ». Il a contribué à la mobilisation des groupes au sein de la société civile. Qu’il<br />

ait récupéré les groupes comme le veut le sens commun est une autre question qu’il ne faut<br />

pas négliger. Mais alors que le sens commun veut que la question de la récupération ou de<br />

l’intégration soit perçue comme la cause ultime de l’engagement étatique dans le<br />

changement social, la sociologie des mouvements sociaux devrait proposer une analyse plus<br />

dynamique qui articule le rapport État-société dans toute sa complexité.<br />

5. Nous n’avons qu’à penser à la façon dont la Commission royale d’enquête sur le bilinguisme<br />

et le biculturalisme au Canada (Commission <strong>La</strong>urendeau-Dunton, 1963) a mobilisé la<br />

population canadienne de même que la Commission royale d’enquête sur le statut de la<br />

femme au Canada (Commission Bird, 1971), pour prendre conscience du rôle important joué<br />

par les gouvernements dans le développement des mouvements. Il est maintenant courant de<br />

voir les théoriciennes du mouvement des femmes se rapporter à la Commission Bird comme<br />

catalyseur du féminisme au Canada. Voir notamment Jeri Wine et Janice Ristock (1991).<br />

6. On pourrait objecter qu’une sociologie des groupes d’intérêts réalise déjà ce type d’analyse.<br />

En réalité, une telle sociologie ne s’intéresse pas au développement de l’action mais à la<br />

capacité d’influence de certains groupes sur le processus de formulation des politiques ou de<br />

l’opinion publique. À l’opposé, une sociologie qui analysera le développement de l’action<br />

devra plutôt faire apparaître la situation qui contribue à l’action et voir comment les groupes<br />

sont différemment situés et motivés politiquement. Elle devra s’intéresser au déroulement<br />

de l’action et voir si les résultats sont ce que les groupes escomptaient.<br />

7. L’article 15 (2) se lit comme suit :<br />

Le paragraphe (1) n’a pas pour effet d’interdire les lois, programmes ou activités destinés à<br />

améliorer la situation d’individus ou de groupes défavorisés, notamment du fait de leur race,<br />

de leur origine nationale ou ethnique, de leur couleur, de leur religion, de leur sexe, de leur<br />

âge ou de leurs déficiences mentales ou physiques.<br />

8. Cette disposition a été incluse à la suite d’une campagne intensive de démarchage politique<br />

de la part des groupes de femmes auprès du gouvernement et des partis politiques. Cette<br />

revendication faisait partie d’un ensemble de garanties que les féministes n’ont pas pu<br />

décrocher, notamment la garantie à«laliberté de reproduction » ainsi que la protection<br />

contre toute discrimination fondée sur le statut marital et l’orientation sexuelle (Hosek,<br />

1983).<br />

9. Pour plus de détails, voir l’étude du groupe LEAF par Sherene Razack dans Canadian<br />

Feminism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>w. <strong>The</strong> Women’s Legal Education <strong>and</strong> Action Fund <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pursuit of<br />

Equality. Toronto, Second Story Press.<br />

10. Pour plus de détails, voir l’ouvrage de Janine Brodie, Shelley A.M. Gavigan et Jane Jenson,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Politics of Abortion, Toronto, Oxford University Press, 1992.<br />

11. Le phénomène de différentiation sociale a été largement étudié par Talcott Parsons, Le<br />

système des sociétés modernes, Paris, Dunod, 1973. Il a vu ce mouvement bien en place dans<br />

le système américain, système qui était, selon lui, le plus moderne. Il accorde une place<br />

centrale à l’individu et fonctionne de façon autonome selon le mode du pluralisme social et le<br />

développement de sphères précises de compétence : juridique, politique, sociale,<br />

économique, culturelle. D’où l’équation entre États-Unis et modernité, bien que ce<br />

phénomène se pose pour l’ensemble des systèmes sociaux qui épousent ce mode de<br />

fonctionnement. D’où aussi l’idée selon laquelle la société canadienne s’américaniserait<br />

continuellement.<br />

12. Voir aussi, sur cette même question, J.-Yvon Thériault dans « Individualisme, nationalisme<br />

et universalisme : l’affaire Durham », communication présentée au colloque Québec-Brésil,<br />

à Montréal, 1991.<br />

13. Voir Marie (1988 : 195) :<br />

Si l’on peut éventuellement parler « de droits individuels », c’est seulement en raison de<br />

« l’individualité » qui caractérise le sujet des droits de l’homme, et non parce que ceux-ci se<br />

trouveraient restreints à une sphère imaginée comme un vase clos où l’individu évoluerait<br />

dans un superbe isolement... Au sens strict, il n’existe sans doute pas plus de « droits<br />

individuels » qu’il n’existe de « droits collectifs » en matière de droits de l’homme, ou plutôt<br />

149


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

tous les droits sont « individuels » par leur titulaire et tous sont « collectifs » par leur<br />

processus de reconnaissance, leur mode d’exercice et leur méthode de protection.<br />

14. Pour plus détails, voir Danielle Juteau, « Visions partielles, visions partiales : visions (des)<br />

minoritaires en sociologie », Sociologie et sociétés, vol. XIII, n o 2, 1981, 33-49.<br />

15. Sur cette question, nous rejoignons Yvon Thériault dans « Individualisme, nationalisme et<br />

universalisme », op. cit.<br />

16. L’entente constitutionnelle de Charlottetown, rejetée par la population canadienne le 26<br />

octobre 1992, montre à nouveau la réalité de cette incompatibilité de vision entre le Canada<br />

qui revendique l’égalité des provinces et le Québec qui se reconnaît comme le pôle central<br />

d’affirmation de l’existence politique d’une société particulière francophone.<br />

17. Pour Hannah Arendt, le sujet est aussi un paria soit, « l’irréductible, le non assimilable,<br />

l’anti-conformiste, celui dont l’étrangeté résiste à l’anonymat du social » (Colin, 1986 : 60).<br />

En tant que paria (Arendt était juive), le sujet ne peut que s’affirmer comme autre (58);<br />

« sujet qui s’il n’est pas auteur de ses actes n’en est pas moins l’agent, ou l’acteur » (58).<br />

18. Notre traduction de:«Itisanarticulating principle that affects <strong>the</strong> different subject positions<br />

of <strong>the</strong> social agent while allowing for a plurality of specific allegiances <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> respect of<br />

individual liberty » (1992 : 32). Cette idée rappelle aussi les réflexions de Georges Gurvitch<br />

sur le pluralisme juridique dans Déclaration des droits sociaux, 1944.<br />

Bibliographie<br />

Adamson, Nancy, Linda Briskin et Margaret McPhail. Feminist Organizing for Change. <strong>The</strong><br />

Contemporary Women’s Movement in Canada. Toronto : Oxford University Press, 1988.<br />

Arendt, Hannah. Condition de l’homme moderne. Paris : Calmann-Lévy, 1961.<br />

Bastarache, Michel. Les droits linguistiques au Canada. Montréal : Éditions Yvon Blais, 1986.<br />

Bourque, Gilles. « <strong>La</strong> sociologie, l’État, la nation », Cahiers de recherche sociologique, n o 14,<br />

1990.<br />

Brodie, Janine, Shelley A.M. Gavigan et Jane Jenson. <strong>The</strong> Politics of Abortion. Toronto : Oxford<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

Brodsky, Gwen et Shelagh Day. <strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne et les droits des femmes, progrès ou recul?<br />

Ottawa : <strong>Conseil</strong> consultatif canadien sur la situation de la femme, 1989.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. « L’État omniprésent : les relations entre l’État et la société au Canada » dans Keith<br />

Banting, L’État et la société : le Canada dans une optique comparative. Ottawa : ministère<br />

des Approvisionnements et Services, 1986.<br />

________. <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Dilemmas of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform. Montréal et<br />

Kingston : McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1992.<br />

Castoriadis, Cornélius. L’institution imaginaire de la société. Paris : Seuil, 1975.<br />

________. Le contenu du socialisme. Paris : Éditions Générales, 1979.<br />

Colin, Françoise. « Du privé et du public », Les cahiers du GRIF, n o 33, 1986.<br />

Ferry, Luc et Alain Renaut. <strong>La</strong> pensée 68. Paris : Gallimard, 1986.<br />

Fudge, Judy. « <strong>The</strong> Public\Private Distinction: <strong>The</strong> Limits of <strong>the</strong> Use of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Litigation To<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r Feminist Struggles », Osgoode Hall <strong>La</strong>w Journal, n o 25, 1987.<br />

Gagnon, Gabriel et Marcel Rioux. À propos d’autogestion et d’émancipation. Québec : IQRC,<br />

1988.<br />

Gotell, Lise. <strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement, Equality Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Ottawa :<br />

ICREF, 1990.<br />

Gurvitch, Georges. Déclaration des droits sociaux. Paris : Éditions de la Maison Française, 1944.<br />

Hégédus, Zsuzsa. « Social Movements <strong>and</strong> Social Change in Self-Creative Society: New Civil<br />

Initiatives in <strong>the</strong> International Arena », International Sociology. vol. 4, n o 1, 1989.<br />

Juteau, Danielle. « Visions partielles, visions partiales : visions (des) minoritaires en sociologie »,<br />

Sociologie et Sociétés, vol. XIII, n o 2, 1981.<br />

Keane, John. Civil Society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State. London : Verso, 1988.<br />

Knopff, Rainer et F.L. Morton. <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Politics. Scarborough : Nelson Canada, 1992.<br />

________. « Le développement national et la <strong>Charte</strong> » dans Alain C. Cairns et Cynthia Williams,<br />

Le constitutionnalisme, la citoyenneté et la société au Canada. Ottawa :<br />

Approvisionnements et Services, 1986.<br />

<strong>La</strong>clau, Ernesto et Chantal Mouffe. Hegemony <strong>and</strong> Socialist Strategy. London : Verso, 1985.<br />

Magnusson, Warren. « Critical Social Movements: Decentering <strong>the</strong> State » dans Alain G. Gagnon<br />

et James Bickerton, Canadian Politics. Peterborough : Broadview Press, 1990.<br />

Maheu, Louis. « Les mouvements de base et la lutte contre l’appropriation étatique du tissu<br />

social », Sociologie et Sociétés, vol. 15, n o 1, 1983.<br />

________. « Mouvements sociaux et politiques. Les enjeux d’une articulation entre gr<strong>and</strong>es<br />

problématiques du politique » dans Gérard Boismenu, Pierre Hamel et Georges <strong>La</strong>bica, Les<br />

150


Les mouvements sociaux et la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits<br />

et libertés<br />

formes modernes de la démocratie. Montréal/Paris : L’Harmattan/Les Presses de<br />

l’Université de Montréal, 1992.<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, Michael. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Legalization of Politics in Canada. Toronto :<br />

Wall & Thompson Inc, 1989.<br />

Marie, Jean-Bernard. « Relations entre droits des peuples et droits de l’homme : distinctions<br />

sémantiques et méthodologiques », L’annuaire canadien des droits de la personne. Ottawa,<br />

Université d’Ottawa, n o 5, 1988.<br />

Melucci, Alberto. « Mouvements sociaux, mouvements post-politiques », Revue internationale<br />

d’action communautaire, 10/50, 1983.<br />

Morton, F.L. « <strong>The</strong> Political Impact of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedom », Canadian<br />

Journal of Political Science, 20 : 31, 1987.<br />

Mouffe, Chantal. « Citizenship <strong>and</strong> Political Identity », October, n o 61, 1992.<br />

Ng, Roxana, Gillian Walker et Jacob Muller (éd.). Community Organization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

State. Toronto : Garamond Press, 1990.<br />

Parsons, Talcott. Le système des sociétés modernes. Paris : Dunod, 1973.<br />

Pentney, William F. « Les principes généraux d’interprétation de la <strong>Charte</strong> » dans <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés, 2 e édition (sous la dir. de Beaudoin et Ratushny).<br />

Montréal : Wilson et <strong>La</strong>fleur ltée, 1989.<br />

Programme de constestation judiciaire. Rapport annuel. Ottawa, 1991.<br />

Razack, Sherene. Canadian Feminism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>w. <strong>The</strong> Women’s Legal Education <strong>and</strong> Action<br />

Fund <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pursuit of Equality. Toronto : Second Story Press, 1991.<br />

Russell, Peter H. Leading <strong>Constitution</strong>al Decisions,3 e édition. Ottawa, Carleton University Press,<br />

1982.<br />

________. « <strong>The</strong> Political Purposes of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms », Canadian<br />

Bar Review, 61 : 30, 1983.<br />

Skocpol, <strong>The</strong>da. États et révolutions sociales. Paris : Fayard, 1985.<br />

Taylor, Charles. « Des avenirs possibles : la légitimité, l’identité et l’aliénation au Canada à la fin<br />

du XX e siècle » dans Le constitutionnalisme, la citoyenneté et la société au Canada (sous la<br />

dir. de A. Cairns et C. Williams). Ottawa : ministère des Approvisionnements et Services,<br />

1986.<br />

Thériault, J.-Yvon. « Individualisme, nationalisme et universalisme : l’affaire Durham »,<br />

communication présentée dans le cadre du colloque Québec-Brésil, UQAM, 1991.<br />

________. « Lourdeur et légèreté du devenir de la francophonie hors Québec », 1990.<br />

________. « Pays réel, pays légal : le fait minoritaire entre la communauté et le droit »,<br />

communication présentée dans le cadre du colloque annuel de l’ACSALF, Université de<br />

Moncton, 1988.<br />

________. « Mouvements sociaux et nouvelle culture politique », Politique, vol. 12, 1987.<br />

Touraine, Alain. <strong>La</strong> production de la société. Paris : Seuil, 1974.<br />

________. Le retour de l’acteur. Paris : Fayard, 1984.<br />

Touraine, Alain, François Dubet, Zsuzsa Hégédus et Michel Wieviorka. Lutte étudiante. Paris :<br />

Seuil, 1978.<br />

________. <strong>La</strong> prophétie anti-nucléaire. Paris : Seuil, 1980.<br />

________. Le Pays contre l’État. Paris : Seuil, 1981.<br />

Turner, Brian. Citizenship <strong>and</strong> Capitalism. <strong>The</strong> Debate Over Reformism. London : Allen &<br />

Unwin, 1986.<br />

Urry, John. <strong>The</strong> Anatomy of Capitalist Societies. <strong>The</strong> Economy, Civil Society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State. New<br />

Jersey, Humanities Press, 1981.<br />

V<strong>and</strong>ycke, Robert. « <strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong> constitutionnelle et les droits économiques, sociaux et culturels »,<br />

L’annuaire canadien des droits de la personne. Ottawa : Presses de l’Université d’Ottawa,<br />

1990.<br />

Wieviorka, Michel. L’espace du racisme. Paris : Seuil, 1991.<br />

Wine, Jeri et Janice Ristock. Women <strong>and</strong> Social Change. Feminist Activism in Canada. Toronto,<br />

James Lorimer, 1991.<br />

151


Andrew D. Heard<br />

Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights *<br />

Abstract<br />

Many Québécois initially viewed <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights with<br />

hostility, since it was part of <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong>Constitution</strong> Act enacted over <strong>the</strong><br />

objections of <strong>the</strong> Québec government <strong>and</strong> legislature. This paper studies <strong>the</strong><br />

subsequent treatment of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong> reported decisions of<br />

Québec’s Appeal Court <strong>and</strong> Superior Court in order to examine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

Québécois have treated <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in any manner remarkably different than<br />

that found in o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions. <strong>The</strong> results demonstrate that Québec litigants<br />

have frequently relied on <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> reception given<br />

to it by Québec judges falls within comparable patterns seen elsewhere.<br />

Résumé<br />

À l’origine, nombre de Québécois furent hostiles à la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des<br />

droits et libertés parce qu’elle faisait partie intégrante de la Loi<br />

constitutionnelle de 1982, promulguée en dépit des objections du<br />

gouvernement et de l’Assemblée nationale du Québec. Cet article examine les<br />

décisions publiées qui ont été rendues par la Cour d’appel et la Cour<br />

supérieure de la province dans des causes s’appuyant sur la <strong>Charte</strong>, afin de<br />

déterminer si les Québécois se sont comportés en cette matière d’une façon<br />

nettement différente des autres juridictions. Les résultats indiquent qu’au<br />

Québec, les plaideurs ont fréquemment invoqué la <strong>Charte</strong> et que les décisions<br />

judiciaires correspondent grosso modo à celles qui ont été prises par les<br />

autres tribunaux canadiens.<br />

While <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms is intended as a national<br />

rights document, it came into force without <strong>the</strong> consent of <strong>the</strong> Québec<br />

government, legislature or people. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Québec legislature objected to<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1981 federal-provincial accord that led to <strong>the</strong> 1982 Canada Act, through<br />

which <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> came into being. 1 Once <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> took effect, <strong>the</strong> Parti<br />

Québécois quickly ushered a bill through <strong>the</strong> National Assembly that inserted<br />

a clause into all provincial legislation exploiting <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

clause to <strong>the</strong> full. Every existing statute was declared to operate independently<br />

of Sections 2 <strong>and</strong> 7 through 15 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>; a similar provision was later<br />

added to each new bill introduced prior to <strong>the</strong> 1985 election. 2 <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was<br />

seen by many in Québec as an unwanted development foisted upon <strong>the</strong>m by<br />

English Canada.<br />

With this hostile genesis in mind, an examination is long overdue of <strong>the</strong><br />

subsequent treatment by <strong>the</strong> Québécois of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights.<br />

One might suspect that <strong>the</strong> citizens of Québec would turn <strong>the</strong>ir backs on this<br />

piece of “legal imperialism” from English Canada, or that Québec judges <strong>and</strong><br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

lawyers would try to develop a distinctive Québécois jurisprudence whenever<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was raised. After all, much has been made in many<br />

contexts of <strong>the</strong> fact that Québec operates under its own Code civil <strong>and</strong> that its<br />

traditional values purport to favour collective over individual interests. <strong>The</strong><br />

fear of an antagonistic treatment of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has fuelled much of <strong>the</strong><br />

animosity towards a “distinct society” clause outside Québec since <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord.<br />

<strong>The</strong> aim of this study is to provide an insight into how <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights has fared in Québec through an empirical analysis of <strong>the</strong> reported<br />

judgments delivered by <strong>the</strong> Québec Court of Appeal <strong>and</strong> Superior Court<br />

between 1982 <strong>and</strong> 1989. To gain some appreciation of how <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been employed in Québec, a variety of issues need to be explored.<br />

A broad view of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s use emerges from examining who has resorted to<br />

it <strong>and</strong> which particular rights have been raised. However, <strong>the</strong> best insight into<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s reception in Québec is revealed by <strong>the</strong> way in which<br />

Québec judges have dealt with <strong>the</strong>se claims. <strong>The</strong> use made of precedents from<br />

outside <strong>the</strong> province gives an indication of <strong>the</strong> acceptance of <strong>the</strong> national<br />

values that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> supposedly embodies. <strong>The</strong> interplay between <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> Québec’s own <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Human Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms<br />

may also reveal <strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s interpretation in<br />

Québec is rooted in <strong>the</strong> province’s distinctive legal culture.<br />

While <strong>the</strong> focus of this paper remains Québec, references will be made where<br />

possible to research on approaches to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions. A<br />

previously compiled identical data set for Nova Scotia will be used to make<br />

many comparisons between <strong>the</strong>se two provinces. 3 <strong>The</strong> Québec experience<br />

will also be compared to <strong>the</strong> results of o<strong>the</strong>r studies on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in<br />

Saskatchewan, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada <strong>and</strong> Ontario, as well as one paper<br />

based on national data. 4 This comparative perspective is crucial to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> significance of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s particular treatment in Québec.<br />

<strong>The</strong> manner in which <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has already been dealt with in<br />

Québec has an important bearing on current constitutional disputes. Much<br />

public debate has raged over whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> force of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would<br />

in some way be diminished if references to Québec’s distinct society were<br />

included in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>. Although uncertainties about future<br />

interpretations cannot be dispelled, evaluations of <strong>the</strong> impact of a distinct society<br />

clause should be based upon an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how distinctively <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has already been treated in Québec.<br />

Data Collection<br />

<strong>The</strong> data for this study were collected from 216 Appeal <strong>and</strong> Superior Court<br />

judgments published in two sources, <strong>the</strong> Québec Appeal Cases <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Recueil<br />

de jurisprudence du Québec, all delivered by <strong>the</strong> end of 1989. 5 Data for a<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r 49 unreported Superior Court judgments were compiled from <strong>the</strong><br />

reported decisions of <strong>the</strong>ir later appeals.<br />

A reliance upon published judgements poses particular problems for empirical<br />

research such as this, since only a subset of all judgments end up in print. A far<br />

smaller portion of Québec court decisions is published in comparison with<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions, presumably because of <strong>the</strong> smaller market for <strong>the</strong>se<br />

expensive volumes. Most substantive Appeal Court judgments are published,<br />

but only a selection of trial decisions are reported. <strong>The</strong> inferential reliability of<br />

generalizing trends in Québec courtrooms from <strong>the</strong> sample used here depends<br />

154


Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

upon all cases having a relatively equal chance of being reported; this is<br />

believed to be <strong>the</strong> case with <strong>the</strong> present sample set. <strong>The</strong> Société québécoise<br />

d’information juridique receives <strong>and</strong> reviews copies of all Superior Court<br />

judgments, <strong>and</strong> publishes those considered to be <strong>the</strong> most important. Although<br />

not ideal from a methodological viewpoint, this selection process does ensure<br />

that all judgments have had a chance to be included in <strong>the</strong> data set. Since <strong>the</strong><br />

reported cases form <strong>the</strong> vast majority of those cited as precedents in later cases,<br />

this data set depicts <strong>the</strong> working reality of Québec courts.<br />

This study includes any case where an attempt was made to raise a claim under<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> judge refused to consider <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

or decided <strong>the</strong> case on o<strong>the</strong>r grounds, since even <strong>the</strong>se cases involve a judge’s<br />

discretionary reaction to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. A case is deemed to result in a successful<br />

claim only if some remedy is granted. In a number of cases, judges find that a<br />

right has been infringed but offer no remedy—ei<strong>the</strong>r because <strong>the</strong> infringement<br />

is saved by ano<strong>the</strong>r section of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> or because <strong>the</strong> infringement is not<br />

serious enough to warrant a remedy; <strong>the</strong>se are not regarded as successful<br />

claims in this study.<br />

Players, Claims <strong>and</strong> Outcomes<br />

Despite hostile reactions by Québec’s provincial politicians to <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights, little evidence indicates that this antipathy carries over into<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s treatment in Québec courts. Québec litigants have frequently<br />

launched claims based on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, with no overt reluctance by judges to<br />

consider or allow <strong>the</strong>m. A broad cross section of Québec society has advanced<br />

claims under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in a variety of contexts, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> overall rates of<br />

acceptance are consistent with those of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims in o<strong>the</strong>r Canadian<br />

jurisdictions. Never<strong>the</strong>less, some variations emerge when <strong>the</strong> particular use<br />

made of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in Québec is compared to o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions.<br />

One measure of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s general acceptance among <strong>the</strong><br />

Québécois is <strong>the</strong> proportion of Québec cases that involve <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong><br />

easiest way to estimate <strong>the</strong> relative use of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is to calculate <strong>the</strong><br />

percentage of reported Appeal Court decisions involving <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> first 30 volumes of <strong>the</strong> Québec Appeal Cases, covering mid-1986<br />

to 1989, contain 1,035 fully reported cases, 56 of which raise <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims. 6<br />

Thus, 5.4% of <strong>the</strong> Québec Appeal Court’s workload in this period involved<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases. This is somewhat less than <strong>the</strong> 8.4% of such cases heard by <strong>the</strong><br />

Nova Scotia Appeal Court between 1986 <strong>and</strong> 1989. Given <strong>the</strong>se low<br />

percentages it is difficult to infer whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> fewer <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases heard in<br />

Québec indicate a reluctance to use <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, or whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> mix of cases<br />

reflects different procedural rules; <strong>the</strong> Nova Scotia Appeal Court was unable to<br />

refuse leave to a substantial number of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> appeals that were only minor<br />

variations of criminal cases it had already dealt with. A more difficult issue is<br />

<strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>the</strong> blanket use of <strong>the</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause has reduced<br />

<strong>the</strong> number of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases in Québec. While some diminution must be<br />

attributed to this factor, a number of challenges to <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong><br />

notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause added to total number <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases in Québec.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> data do not indicate that Québec litigants were strikingly<br />

hesitant to raise <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

During <strong>the</strong> period from 1982 to 1989, <strong>the</strong> judges of Québec’s two most senior<br />

courts granted some remedy in 27.5% of all cases involving claims under <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. As with o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions, <strong>the</strong> Appeal Court accepted<br />

155


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

fewer claims than did <strong>the</strong> superior trial court (24.4% <strong>and</strong> 29.1% respectively).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se rates of acceptance are quite consistent with those of o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions,<br />

as indicated by <strong>the</strong> following table of <strong>the</strong> success rates of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims in<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r appellate courts.<br />

Table 1 7<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Success Rates<br />

Appeal Court Percentage of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Cases<br />

with Successful Claims<br />

Québec – 1982-89 24.4<br />

Nova Scotia – 1982-90 17.4<br />

Ontario – 1982-89 25.7<br />

Saskatchewan – 1982-87 19.6<br />

Supreme Court of Canada – 1982-89 31.4<br />

Thus, Québec judges do not demonstrate any greater reluctance to grant<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims than <strong>the</strong>ir colleagues in o<strong>the</strong>r Canadian jurisdictions. Indeed,<br />

Appeal Court judges in Nova Scotia <strong>and</strong> Saskatchewan rejected far more<br />

claims than Québec Appeal Court judges.<br />

Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> data do not permit a reliable analysis of <strong>the</strong> individual<br />

voting patterns of particular judges. O<strong>the</strong>r work has demonstrated that<br />

individual judges evolve widely differing track records in <strong>the</strong>ir acceptance of<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims. 8 Although 90 <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> decisions of <strong>the</strong> Québec Appeal Court<br />

were reported during <strong>the</strong> period under study, <strong>the</strong> division of <strong>the</strong> sixteen-judge<br />

court into three- or five-judge panels means that too few judges have dealt<br />

singly with a sufficient number of cases to allow a detailed analysis of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

voting behaviour. However, <strong>the</strong> data indicate that Québec judges are likely to<br />

be as individualistic in <strong>the</strong>ir approach as o<strong>the</strong>r judges. For example, two of <strong>the</strong><br />

Appeal Court judges with <strong>the</strong> most <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> experience show quite different<br />

rates of claim acceptance: Valler<strong>and</strong> granted a remedy in only two of <strong>the</strong><br />

sixteen <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases he heard, while Chouinard accepted claims in seven of<br />

his seventeen cases.<br />

Significant differences of opinion among Québec Appeal Court judges emerge<br />

in <strong>the</strong> frequency with which members of a panel hearing a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> case<br />

disagreed with each o<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong> following table presents this information with<br />

comparative data from o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions.<br />

156


Table 2<br />

Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

Rate of Agreement on <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Claims Among Panel Members<br />

in Senior Appellate Courts<br />

Percentage of<br />

Cases Decided Québec Ontario Nova Scotia Supreme Court<br />

of Canada<br />

Unanimously<br />

With Concurring<br />

51.1 92.9 94.1 48.8<br />

Opinions<br />

With Dissenting<br />

39.6 4.9 2.2 38.0<br />

Opinions 17.7 7.1 7.2 30.6<br />

Clearly, members of Québec’s Appeal Court hold significantly different views<br />

on ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> general outcome of a case or <strong>the</strong> reasons for that outcome, or at<br />

least are much more willing to express those differences than judges in Nova<br />

Scotia or Ontario. However, <strong>the</strong> behaviour of Québec Appeal Court judges is<br />

more consistent with that of Supreme Court of Canada judges; both courts<br />

have low rates of unanimity, although Québec judges dissent less frequently<br />

than Supreme Court judges. Some of <strong>the</strong> differences between Québec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Nova Scotia or Ontario appeal courts may relate to institutional traditions.<br />

Until <strong>the</strong> mid-1980s, all judges who sat on Québec Appeal Court panels<br />

consistently delivered <strong>the</strong>ir own opinions, even if only a few brief paragraphs<br />

to say <strong>the</strong>y agreed with one or both of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r opinions. Since <strong>the</strong>n, Québec<br />

judges have followed closer in line with <strong>the</strong>ir common law counterparts, with<br />

<strong>the</strong> more regular delivery of a single opinion for <strong>the</strong> panel or <strong>the</strong> majority.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Québec cases studied, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was raised by individuals in 73.6% of<br />

cases; <strong>and</strong> by corporations, unions <strong>and</strong> media groups in 21.1% of cases. This<br />

indicates a much broader use of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> than in Nova Scotia, where<br />

individuals accounted for 94% of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claimants compared to only 5%<br />

involving unions, media or o<strong>the</strong>r corporations. 9 Part of this discrepancy may<br />

relate to <strong>the</strong> presence of many more corporate head offices in Québec than<br />

Nova Scotia, as well as <strong>the</strong> relative prosperity of Québec companies <strong>and</strong><br />

unions; one would expect that Ontario might exhibit a pattern closer to<br />

Québec’s than Nova Scotia’s.<br />

One important finding relates to <strong>the</strong> infrequent permission to participate<br />

granted to intervenors by Québec judges. In only 3% of Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases<br />

were ei<strong>the</strong>r individuals or groups allowed to participate as intervenors, which<br />

is similar to Nova Scotia’s record of 2.2% of cases with private intervenors.<br />

This low participation rate is largely due to <strong>the</strong> very restrictive rules governing<br />

permission to intervene that discourage such participation. 10 <strong>The</strong> closed<br />

nature of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> litigation has important policy implications, since <strong>the</strong> courts<br />

hear only from a very small number of interested parties before reaching <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

decisions. This contrasts with <strong>the</strong> parade of groups <strong>and</strong> individuals who testify<br />

before legislative committees examining policy issues that may later be<br />

challenged in court. <strong>The</strong> situation in Québec <strong>and</strong> Nova Scotia appears to differ<br />

somewhat from <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada, where a higher proportion of<br />

157


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

hearings (6.6%) involve submissions by private intervenors. It is quite<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>able that interest groups would participate in a larger number of<br />

Supreme Court cases, since <strong>the</strong> high costs of preparing <strong>and</strong> arguing a case<br />

likely encourage groups with scarce resources to concentrate on <strong>the</strong> most<br />

important hearings by <strong>the</strong> nation’s top court.<br />

As with o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is most likely to be referred to in<br />

Québec by parties facing prosecution for federal or provincial offenses; 57.7%<br />

of <strong>the</strong> cases studied were criminal cases. However, this figure is significantly<br />

lower than <strong>the</strong> 80.9% of Nova Scotia’s 1982 to 1990 cases that involved<br />

criminal charges, 80% in Saskatchewan from 1982 to 1987, <strong>and</strong> 77% which<br />

Morton <strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y found nationally between 1982 <strong>and</strong> 1985. 11 <strong>The</strong> lower<br />

proportion of criminal cases in Québec appears to reflect <strong>the</strong> greater use made<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> by <strong>the</strong> Québec media <strong>and</strong> trade unions, who rarely were charged<br />

with offenses.<br />

Québec has displayed a distinctive pattern in its relative use of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> for<br />

different types of rights. Table 3 indicates that Québec litigants raised fewer<br />

claims under <strong>the</strong> legal rights of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> than did Nova Scotians,<br />

considerably more fundamental rights claims, <strong>and</strong> fewer claims for equality;<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r province saw many claims under <strong>the</strong> sections involving language<br />

education rights.<br />

Table Three 12<br />

Type of Right Claimed Jurisdiction<br />

Québec Nova Scotia<br />

Fundamental 13.6 5.5<br />

Mobility 4.5 2.5<br />

Legal 70.7 75.7<br />

Equality 9.3 14.3<br />

<strong>La</strong>nguage Education<br />

Percentage of all claims in s96 (1982-89)<br />

1.9 1.9<br />

<strong>The</strong> greater emphasis on fundamental freedoms in Québec appears to arise<br />

from <strong>the</strong> larger overall involvement of corporations, <strong>the</strong> media <strong>and</strong> trade<br />

unions. <strong>The</strong>se litigants accounted for 55% of Québec cases in which<br />

fundamental freedoms were raised, compared to only 11% of such cases in<br />

Nova Scotia.<br />

<strong>The</strong> use made of individual sections of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> reveals <strong>the</strong> most striking<br />

differences among jurisdictions. <strong>The</strong> three most frequently litigated sections in<br />

Québec were s7, s11d <strong>and</strong> s8, which were respectively involved in 33.5%,<br />

22.3% <strong>and</strong> 15.1% of all cases. 13 This mix of rights differs considerably from<br />

<strong>the</strong> top three rights in Nova Scotia: s10b, s7, <strong>and</strong> s15(1). 14 But two of <strong>the</strong> three<br />

rights most frequently argued in Québec are among <strong>the</strong> top three that Morton<br />

<strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y found in <strong>the</strong>ir national study of <strong>the</strong> 1982 to 1985 period: s7, s8, <strong>and</strong><br />

s10b. <strong>The</strong> surprising difference is <strong>the</strong> virtual absence in Québec of s10b claims<br />

to <strong>the</strong> right to counsel on arrest or detention. While this right was a recurrent<br />

158


subject in Nova Scotia <strong>and</strong> nationally, less than 5% of Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases<br />

involved this section. Possible explanations for <strong>the</strong> paucity of s10b cases<br />

include: very meticulous work by Québec police officers, <strong>the</strong> unlikely<br />

possibility that lawyers are overlooking a good argument, or some problem in<br />

<strong>the</strong> reporting of Québec cases.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re were also different success rates for <strong>the</strong> various groups of rights. <strong>The</strong><br />

following table indicates <strong>the</strong> success rates of <strong>the</strong> three most frequently litigated<br />

groups of rights.<br />

Table 4 15<br />

Success Rates<br />

Most Litigated Types of Rights<br />

Type of Right Jurisdiction<br />

Québec Nova Scotia Nationally<br />

Fundamental 21 46 24<br />

Legal 26 17 28<br />

Equality 11 32 25<br />

Que & N.S.: s96 courts; National: all<br />

Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

Québec judges accepted more claims to legal rights, <strong>and</strong> fewer claims to<br />

fundamental freedoms or equality rights, than did Nova Scotia’s judges;<br />

Québec judges fell only slightly below <strong>the</strong> national average seen in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

three years of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> for legal <strong>and</strong> fundamental claims, but accepted<br />

significantly fewer claims for equal treatment under s15 than did courts across<br />

<strong>the</strong> country during <strong>the</strong> initial period of this section’s enactment. <strong>The</strong> low<br />

success rate of equality claims largely reflects <strong>the</strong> failure of cases arguing<br />

discrimination against particular professional groups by regulatory schemes or<br />

disciplinary procedures; <strong>the</strong>se represented one-quarter of all equality cases,<br />

<strong>and</strong> all but one were rejected. 16<br />

In some respects, <strong>the</strong> general objects of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims were quite similar in<br />

Québec <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions. More challenges involved <strong>the</strong> actions of<br />

officials (75%) than legal rules (37%); <strong>the</strong>se figures were 75% <strong>and</strong> 33%<br />

respectively for Nova Scotia between 1982 <strong>and</strong> 1990, while Morton <strong>and</strong><br />

Wi<strong>the</strong>y found <strong>the</strong> national aggregate proportions to be 66% <strong>and</strong> 34%<br />

respectively between 1982 <strong>and</strong> 1985. 17<br />

However, Québec courts produced a fairly distinctive pattern of outcomes<br />

with very similar success rates for cases involving laws <strong>and</strong> actions. This<br />

relative uniformity contrasts with o<strong>the</strong>r provincial jurisdictions, with<br />

challenges to legal rules being much less successful than claims against an<br />

official’s actions, as <strong>the</strong> following table illustrates.<br />

159


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Table 5 18<br />

Success Rates of<br />

Challenges to <strong>La</strong>ws <strong>and</strong> Actions<br />

Jurisdiction Challenge to:<br />

<strong>La</strong>w Action<br />

Québec (1982-89) 27 29<br />

Nova Scotia (1982-90) 22 32<br />

Ontario & Federal Courts (1982-86) 26 34<br />

Nationally<br />

Percentage of cases with successful claims<br />

28 33<br />

<strong>The</strong> approach by Québec judges to <strong>the</strong>se two kinds of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases is<br />

interesting; one would anticipate a substantially higher success rate for<br />

challenges to actions for two reasons. First, <strong>the</strong> construction of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is<br />

such that any infringement by a law of a right may be saved under s1, if it is<br />

found to be “demonstrably justified in a free <strong>and</strong> democratic society.”<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>re is no such general saving provision for officials’ actions; only<br />

when <strong>the</strong> exclusion of evidence is sought must a judge overtly decide whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>the</strong> infringement is serious enough to warrant a remedy. Secondly, <strong>the</strong> nature<br />

of <strong>the</strong> historic relationships between <strong>the</strong> three branches of government would<br />

suggest that <strong>the</strong> judiciary is less reluctant to overrule executive actions than<br />

legislation; <strong>the</strong> courts perform judicial oversight of officials in many contexts<br />

outside <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> litigation.<br />

Québec produces a fur<strong>the</strong>r surprise within <strong>the</strong> group of cases that challenged<br />

legislation. In o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions, more claims have been made against federal<br />

than provincial legislation. In Québec, however, 59 challenges related to<br />

provincial statutes, while only 21 cases involved federal laws. <strong>The</strong><br />

preponderance of challenges to provincial statutes may seem a little<br />

astonishing, given that <strong>the</strong> sweeping use of <strong>the</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause (s33)<br />

should have greatly reduced <strong>the</strong> number of <strong>the</strong>se cases. But <strong>the</strong> employment of<br />

s33 became <strong>the</strong> object of many challenges itself. Even though Jules Deschênes<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Superior Court upheld <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong> original use of s33 in an April<br />

1983 decision, litigants continued to attack its general use on <strong>the</strong> grounds that<br />

exempting all legislation violated <strong>the</strong> intent of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. O<strong>the</strong>r Superior<br />

Court judges followed <strong>the</strong>ir Chief Justice’s lead, until <strong>the</strong> Court of Appeal<br />

overturned his decision in June 1985. 19 In all, sixteen cases during <strong>the</strong> period<br />

studied in Québec involved s33. By <strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada<br />

eventually upheld <strong>the</strong> blanket use of <strong>the</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause in <strong>the</strong> 1988<br />

Ford case, <strong>the</strong> original amendments to pre-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> legislation had reached<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir five-year limit <strong>and</strong> expired. 20 This course of events may help explain <strong>the</strong><br />

many challenges to Québec statutes; following a number of initial challenges<br />

to <strong>the</strong> use of s33, <strong>the</strong> existing statutes amended by <strong>the</strong> 1982 blanket use<br />

reverted back to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s authority between 1985 <strong>and</strong> late 1988. In any<br />

event, it is quite clear that Québec residents have not hesitated to challenge<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own laws under <strong>the</strong> national values embodied in <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights.<br />

160


Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

Québec judges have accepted a lower proportion of challenges to provincial<br />

legislation to federal law: 22% as opposed to 28.6%. One may be tempted at<br />

first to say that this deference to provincial legislation illustrates an attempt to<br />

protect <strong>the</strong> provincial political system from <strong>the</strong> centralizing influences of <strong>the</strong><br />

national <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. However, such speculation is complicated since <strong>the</strong> lack of<br />

success in challenges to provincial laws is augmented by ten cases in which a<br />

notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause precluded any judgment of <strong>the</strong> merits of <strong>the</strong><br />

legislation. When <strong>the</strong>se cases are excluded, <strong>the</strong> success rate of challenges to<br />

provincial laws rises to 26.5%.<br />

<strong>The</strong> comparative data on <strong>the</strong> relative vulnerability of federal <strong>and</strong> provincial<br />

legislation shows ra<strong>the</strong>r mixed patterns. However, Québec judges acted in a<br />

somewhat similar fashion to Ontario judges, who allowed fewer challenges to<br />

provincial than federal statutes. 21 Nova Scotia’s Appeal Court, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, showed virtually identical treatment of federal <strong>and</strong> provincial statutes;<br />

roughly 17% of challenges to ei<strong>the</strong>r set of laws were accepted.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Use of Precedents<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> wording of much of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights is vague, judicial<br />

decisions play a key role in giving substance to particular sections of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Only through judicial decision-making do we come to know just what<br />

sort of activities are protected by any one of <strong>the</strong> rights enunciated in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, as well as what kinds of limitations on those rights are acceptable. As<br />

<strong>the</strong> body of court decisions on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> grows, judges have more material at<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir disposal to solve <strong>the</strong> dilemmas of a case at h<strong>and</strong>. However, a certain<br />

amount of latitude is available to lawyers <strong>and</strong> judges in choosing which past<br />

decisions are considered in a particular case. While lower court judges are<br />

bound by <strong>the</strong> decisions of higher courts in <strong>the</strong> same jurisdiction, <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

Supreme Court of Canada, <strong>the</strong>y are very free to draw from decisions h<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

down by courts in o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions. With so many <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> decisions<br />

available, judges have considerable discretion in choosing <strong>and</strong> applying<br />

precedents to a current case. Just how often judges in one jurisdiction consider<br />

precedents from o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions is an indication of how much crosspollination<br />

of values may result from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Considerable use of<br />

precedents from o<strong>the</strong>r provinces or from <strong>the</strong> national courts could lead to a<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ning of uniform values; indeed, early speculation about <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

centred on its potential as a centralizing force on <strong>the</strong> political <strong>and</strong> legal cultures<br />

across Canada that had evolved so differently under our federal structures. 22<br />

In order to gain some idea of how autonomously Québec judges have been<br />

interpreting <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, a record was kept of which jurisdictions<br />

judges drew <strong>the</strong>ir precedents from in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases. <strong>The</strong> following table shows<br />

<strong>the</strong> distribution of precedents considered by Québec judges <strong>and</strong> by Nova<br />

Scotian judges for comparison purposes.<br />

161


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Table 6<br />

Percentage of Reported Cases Citing Precedents From:<br />

Jurisdiction23 Québec Nova Scotia<br />

NFLD 3.2 2.8<br />

NS 3.2 46.2<br />

PEI 0.5 2.4<br />

NB 1.9 2.4<br />

QUE 47.7 2.1<br />

ONT 32.9 45.2<br />

MAN 6.9 11.0<br />

SASK 7.4 17.6<br />

ALTA 13.4 11.0<br />

BC 14.4 16.2<br />

FED CT 9.7 3.8<br />

SCC 65.7 54.1<br />

USA 6.5 11.0<br />

UK 7.4 4.8<br />

Several important points emerge from this table concerning <strong>the</strong> breadth of<br />

sources which Québec judges rely upon. 24 First, Québec judges consider<br />

precedents from <strong>the</strong>ir own jurisdiction as frequently as Nova Scotian judges.<br />

Secondly, <strong>the</strong> two sets of data reveal a rough similarity in <strong>the</strong> geographic<br />

distribution of <strong>the</strong> precedents considered. Within <strong>the</strong>se corresponding<br />

patterns, however, a couple of differences emerge: Québec judges rely more<br />

heavily on Supreme Court of Canada decisions <strong>and</strong> less on Ontario precedents<br />

than Nova Scotian judges. <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court of Canada clearly enjoys a<br />

tremendous influence in <strong>the</strong> shaping of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> decisions in Québec. In 16% of<br />

reported cases where <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> issue is substantively addressed, only<br />

precedents from <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada are considered; by contrast,<br />

7.4% of <strong>the</strong>se cases considered Québec decisions alone. <strong>The</strong> greater use of<br />

Supreme Court precedents in Québec than in Nova Scotia may be partially<br />

explained by <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court having decided seventeen appeals from<br />

Québec but only four from Nova Scotia by <strong>the</strong> end of 1989. Ontario also<br />

emerges as a very strong influence on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s interpretation in o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

provinces; <strong>the</strong> sheer volume of reported Ontario decisions allows that province<br />

to play a leading role. Québec judges have clearly depended upon values<br />

shaped by a national dialogue in order to interpret <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

While judges in Québec may be drawing from <strong>the</strong> national debate on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it is quite apparent that judges in o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions pay very little<br />

attention to judicial interpretations of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in Québec. Nova Scotian<br />

judges considered Québec precedents in just over 2.1% of <strong>the</strong>ir <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases.<br />

Peter McCormick has established that <strong>the</strong> appeal courts of both Saskatchewan<br />

<strong>and</strong> Manitoba have also referred to very few Québec precedents. In analyses of<br />

all (not just <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>) decisions in 1987, McCormick found that Québec Appeal<br />

Court precedents were referred to in only 1.1% of Manitoba’s Appeal Court<br />

162


Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

decisions, <strong>and</strong> in only 0.8% of Saskatchewan’s Appeal Court judgments. 25<br />

Thus, Québec’s judges are interpreting <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> with full consideration of<br />

precedents from across <strong>the</strong> country, but judges in <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada are<br />

reaching <strong>the</strong>ir decisions in blissful ignorance of most developments in Québec.<br />

This state of affairs is probably due to <strong>the</strong> fact that most Québec judges <strong>and</strong><br />

lawyers are functionally bilingual, <strong>and</strong> can readily use judicial decisions<br />

written in English, while judges <strong>and</strong> lawyers in <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada are<br />

predominantly unilingual. Since only a tiny fraction of Québec decisions are<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r written in English or later translated, most Canadian courts operate<br />

without <strong>the</strong> benefit of <strong>the</strong> important <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> interpretations being delivered in<br />

Québec.<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence of this linguistic divide challenges <strong>the</strong> established line of judicial<br />

reasoning that has not required judicial decisions to be translated. <strong>The</strong> right to<br />

use French <strong>and</strong> English in Québec <strong>and</strong> New Brunswick courts has been<br />

interpreted to mean that litigants <strong>and</strong> judges have <strong>the</strong> choice of language, not<br />

that all proceedings <strong>and</strong> judgments must be conducted <strong>and</strong> written in both<br />

languages. This is quite different from <strong>the</strong> duties imposed on <strong>the</strong> executive <strong>and</strong><br />

legislature to publish laws <strong>and</strong> regulations in both languages. 26 It seems<br />

strange to require that statutes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> regulations exp<strong>and</strong>ing or defining <strong>the</strong>m<br />

be in both languages, while <strong>the</strong> court decisions that ultimately give substance<br />

to <strong>the</strong>se statutes <strong>and</strong> regulations can be in only one language. Even more<br />

peculiar is that litigants across Canada who try to make a claim under one of<br />

<strong>the</strong> rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> may be deprived of key judicial decisions simply<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y, <strong>the</strong>ir lawyers, or <strong>the</strong> judges hearing <strong>the</strong> case are unilingual.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Human Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms<br />

One distinguishing feature of <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in Québec courts<br />

is <strong>the</strong> frequent, simultaneous submission of claims under Québec’s own<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Human Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms. 27 <strong>The</strong> provincial <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> came into<br />

force in 1975, but initially lay little used. However, <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois<br />

government greatly streng<strong>the</strong>ned <strong>the</strong> provisions of <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> around<br />

<strong>the</strong> time that <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> came into effect. 28 During <strong>the</strong> 1980s, many<br />

more claims have been launched under <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>; indeed, <strong>the</strong>re is an<br />

almost identical number of cases in <strong>the</strong> first 30 volumes of <strong>the</strong> Québec Appeal<br />

Cases (covering mid-1986 to 1989) that involve ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

Claims under <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> have been raised in 34.7% of <strong>the</strong> cases in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been argued. In most instances, <strong>the</strong> provincial<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is simply a reinforcement of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, since several of<br />

both <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s provisions are very similar. In o<strong>the</strong>r cases, however, <strong>the</strong> Québec<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> claims are additional or complimentary to those made under <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Where claims are made under both <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>s, <strong>the</strong> outcome of<br />

<strong>the</strong> claims is identical 81.5% of <strong>the</strong> time, with both sets of claims ei<strong>the</strong>r being<br />

accepted or rejected. In only 15.2% of <strong>the</strong> dual-<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases are <strong>the</strong><br />

provincial claims accepted <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> national ones rejected; most of <strong>the</strong>se would<br />

involve cases where <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was excluded because of <strong>the</strong> use of a<br />

notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing clause.<br />

<strong>The</strong> frequent use of <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> could conceivably have led to a more<br />

distinctive interpretation of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, with precedents from <strong>the</strong><br />

provincial <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> affecting interpretations of <strong>the</strong> national <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. This<br />

direction of influence was extremely rare, however, whereas precedents from<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are frequently used to interpret <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. As a<br />

163


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

result, <strong>the</strong> national values of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights have strongly<br />

shaped <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. However, <strong>the</strong> actual extent of <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> precedents’ influence on <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cannot be<br />

ascertained without a full study of all cases involving <strong>the</strong> provincial <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. If<br />

any nationalist aversion exists in Québec to <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it would<br />

likely occur among those who have chosen to make claims under <strong>the</strong> Québec<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> Canadian one. Unfortunately, this factor cannot be<br />

measured without determining how many of <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases involve<br />

claims that could also have been argued under <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, but were<br />

not.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> results of this empirical study clearly indicate that <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights has become an integral element of Québec’s legal culture. <strong>The</strong><br />

Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been relied upon frequently <strong>and</strong> by a wide range of<br />

Québec litigants. Québec judges have shown no reluctance to entertain or<br />

accept claims under <strong>the</strong> national <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> overall success rates of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

claims in Québec are well within <strong>the</strong> range seen in o<strong>the</strong>r jurisdictions where<br />

comparable data are available. While <strong>the</strong> cases studied reveal that a different<br />

mix of particular rights has been argued in Québec, <strong>and</strong> with varied results,<br />

each jurisdiction for which <strong>the</strong>re is data enjoys its own distinctive patterns as<br />

well. Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most telling evidence of Québec’s absorption of national<br />

values through <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is seen in <strong>the</strong> geographical range of<br />

precedents considered by Québec judges, as well as <strong>the</strong> interpretation of <strong>the</strong><br />

Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> through <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. While <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of<br />

Rights may have had a controversial political origin, it has since been widely<br />

accepted in Québec.<br />

Notes<br />

* <strong>The</strong> author wishes to express his gratitude to <strong>the</strong> Social Sciences <strong>and</strong> Humanities Research<br />

Council of Canada, whose funding of a Canada Research Fellowship has made this research<br />

possible.<br />

1. One of <strong>the</strong> objections listed in <strong>the</strong> resolution was aimed at <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights, where<br />

Québec wanted an override in any matter within provincial jurisdiction. See: Sheilagh M.<br />

Dunn, <strong>The</strong> Year in Review 1981: Intergovernmental Relations in Canada, (Kingston:<br />

Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, 1982), 35-36.<br />

2. Loi Concernant la Loi <strong>Constitution</strong>nelle de 1982, L.Q. 1982, c.21. This Act removed<br />

3.<br />

Québec legislation from <strong>the</strong> purview of <strong>the</strong> sections of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> that provide<br />

fundamental freedoms, legal rights <strong>and</strong> equality rights.<br />

Some of <strong>the</strong> results were included in: “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights in Nova Scotian Courts, 1982-<br />

1990,” a paper presented at <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science Association meeting in Kingston,<br />

June 1991.<br />

4. <strong>The</strong> results of this research on Québec may be compared to those examining <strong>the</strong> treatment of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in Ontario <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Federal Court [Patrick Monahan, Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, (Toronto: Carswell, 1987) at 33-49], Saskatchewan [Saskatchewan <strong>La</strong>w<br />

Review Editorial Board, “<strong>The</strong> Saskatchewan Court of Appeal <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” (1988), 52<br />

Saskatchewan <strong>La</strong>w Review 191; Peter McCormick, “Case-Load <strong>and</strong> Output of <strong>the</strong><br />

Saskatchewan Court of Appeal: An Analysis of 12 Months of Reported Cases” (1989), 53<br />

Saskatchewan <strong>La</strong>w Review 341], <strong>and</strong> Manitoba [Peter McCormick, “Caseload <strong>and</strong> Output of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Manitoba Court of Appeal: An Analysis of Twelve Months of Reported Cases” (1990),<br />

19 Manitoba <strong>La</strong>w Journal 31]. McCormick’s studies of Saskatchewan <strong>and</strong> Manitoba<br />

involve <strong>the</strong> whole range of <strong>the</strong> appeal courts’ caseload, ra<strong>the</strong>r than just relating to <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court of Canada’s <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> record has been examined in: Andrew D.<br />

Heard, “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada: <strong>The</strong> Importance of Which Judges<br />

164


Québec Courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

Hear an Appeal” (1991), 24 Canadian Journal of Political Science 287; <strong>and</strong>, F.L. Morton,<br />

Peter H. Russell, <strong>and</strong> Michael J. Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Judging <strong>the</strong> Judges: <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court’s First<br />

One Hundred <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Decisions,” in Paul W. Fox <strong>and</strong> Graham White (eds), Politics:<br />

Canada, 7th ed., (Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson, 1991). A national of study of <strong>the</strong> use<br />

made of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> has been published in: F.L. Morton <strong>and</strong> Michael J. Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Charting<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, 1982-1985: A Statistical Analysis” (1987), Canadian Human Rights Yearbook<br />

65.<br />

5. <strong>The</strong>se two report series are <strong>the</strong> principal sources for reports of full judgments of Québec<br />

cases. Digest summaries of many more cases can be found in Jurisprudence express, but <strong>the</strong><br />

information in <strong>the</strong>se summaries was insufficient to be used in this study.<br />

6. <strong>The</strong>se <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases included two which were decided in 1990, <strong>and</strong> are thus not included in<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r analyses in this paper.<br />

7. In this <strong>and</strong> following tables, data are from original research except where o<strong>the</strong>rwise noted.<br />

Data for Saskatchewan is calculated from Saskatchewan <strong>La</strong>w Review Editorial Board, “<strong>The</strong><br />

Saskatchewan Court of Appeal <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,” 193.<br />

8. See: Morton, Russell, <strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Judging <strong>the</strong> Judges: <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court’s First 100<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Decisions,” 73-75; <strong>and</strong> Heard, “<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada.”<br />

9. In Québec, <strong>the</strong> figures for <strong>the</strong>se litigants are: media 6.4%, non-media corporations 11.3%,<br />

trade unions 3.4%; in Nova Scotia <strong>the</strong> comparable breakdown of litigants is: 0.4%, 3.5%,<br />

<strong>and</strong> 0.9% respectively.<br />

10. An indication of how narrow <strong>the</strong> rules are is seen in <strong>the</strong> only case where LEAF was allowed<br />

to intervene: R. c. Caron [1988] 20 QAC 45.<br />

11. Saskatchewan <strong>La</strong>w Review Editorial Board, “<strong>The</strong> Saskatchewan Court of Appeal <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,” 193; Morton <strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Charting <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, 1982-1985,” 73.<br />

12. All data are from original research.<br />

13. Section 7 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> states: “Everyone has <strong>the</strong> right to life, liberty <strong>and</strong> security of person<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> right not to be deprived <strong>the</strong>reof except in accordance with <strong>the</strong> principles of<br />

fundamental justice.” <strong>The</strong> provision in s8 reads: “Everyone has <strong>the</strong> right to be secure against<br />

unreasonable search <strong>and</strong> seizure.” Section 11d provides, “Any person charged with an<br />

offence has <strong>the</strong> right to be presumed innocent until proven guilty according to law in a fair<br />

<strong>and</strong> public hearing by an independent <strong>and</strong> impartial tribunal.”<br />

14. Section 10b stipulates, “Everyone has <strong>the</strong> right on arrest or detention to retain <strong>and</strong> instruct<br />

counsel without delay <strong>and</strong> to be informed of that right.” Equality rights are protected in<br />

s15(1): “Every individual is equal before <strong>and</strong> under <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> has <strong>the</strong> right to equal<br />

protection <strong>and</strong> equal benefit of <strong>the</strong> law without discrimination <strong>and</strong>, in particular, without<br />

discrimination based on race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age or mental or<br />

physical disability.”<br />

15. National data are from: Morton <strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Charting <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, 1982-1985,” 71.<br />

16. <strong>The</strong> exception was a case which allowed a challenge to <strong>the</strong> differing benefits due under<br />

worker’s compensation to various occupational groups: Coulombe c. Commission d’appel<br />

en matière de lésions professionnelles, (1987) R.J.Q. 1822 (C.S.).<br />

17. Morton <strong>and</strong> Wi<strong>the</strong>y, “Charting <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, 1982-1985,” 72.<br />

18. National data are from Ibid., 72; data for Ontario s96 courts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Federal Court combined<br />

are from: Monahan, Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, 38. <strong>The</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r data are from original<br />

research.<br />

19. Deschênes’ decision was given in: Alliance des professeurs de Montréal c. P.G. du Québec,<br />

(1985) CS 1272. <strong>The</strong> judgment of <strong>the</strong> Appeal court which overturned this case is found at:<br />

(1985) CA 376.<br />

20. Ford v Quebec (Attorney General), [1988] 2 SCR 712.<br />

21. Monahan, Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, 38.<br />

22. See some early discussion of this topic in: Donald Smiley, <strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms, 1981 (Toronto: Ontario Economic Council, 1981) at 56-61; Peter H. Russell,<br />

“<strong>The</strong> Political Purposes of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms” (1983), 61<br />

Canadian Bar Review 30. A later discussion of <strong>the</strong> effects of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> can be found in:<br />

F.L. Morton, G. Solomon, I. McNish, <strong>and</strong> D.W. Poulton, “Judicial Nullification of Statutes<br />

under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms, 1982-1989” (1990) 28 Alberta <strong>La</strong>w Review 396-<br />

427.<br />

165


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

23. Québec decisions are for all reported decisions of s96 courts where <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was<br />

substantively considered; Nova Scotia figures are for all levels of courts.<br />

24. It is worth noting that <strong>the</strong> civil law setting in Québec appears to have virtually no bearing on<br />

<strong>the</strong> treatment of precedents in <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases. At an impressionistic level, no differences<br />

could be seen in <strong>the</strong> way in which Nova Scotian <strong>and</strong> Québec judges considered <strong>and</strong> applied<br />

precedents. In 16.2% of Québec cases, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> issues were settled without referring to<br />

any previous cases, while 17.6% of Nova Scotian cases were similarly decided.<br />

25. McCormick, “Caseload <strong>and</strong> Output of <strong>the</strong> Manitoba Court of Appeal,” p.47; McCormick,<br />

“Caseload <strong>and</strong> Output of <strong>the</strong> Saskatchewan Court of Appeal,” p.356.<br />

26. <strong>The</strong>se rights are found in several sources. Québec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal government are bound by<br />

s133 of <strong>the</strong> 1867 <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, while <strong>the</strong> New Brunswick <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal government are<br />

bound by sections 16 to 20 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights. Judicial decisions are routinely<br />

translated in <strong>the</strong> Federal Court <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of Canada. Some key decisions on<br />

<strong>the</strong>se rights are: A.G. Quebec v Blaikie (No.1), [1979] 2 SCR 1016; A.G. Quebec v Blaikie<br />

(No.2), [1981] 1 SCR 312; Société des Acadiens v. Association of Parents, [1986] 1 SCR<br />

549; Pilote c. Corporation de l’Hôpital Bellechasse, (1988) RJQ 380 (C.S).<br />

27. R.S.Q. c.C-21.<br />

28. For more information on <strong>the</strong> Québec <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> see: J.-Y. Morin, “<strong>La</strong> constitutionnalisation<br />

progressive de la <strong>Charte</strong> des droits et libertés de la personne,” (1987) 21 Revue juridique<br />

Thémis 25; André Morel, “<strong>La</strong> coexistence des <strong>Charte</strong>s canadiennes et québécoise:<br />

problèmes d’interaction,” (1986) Revue de droit, Université de Sherbrooke 49.<br />

166


François Rocher<br />

Daniel Salée<br />

Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique 1<br />

Résumé<br />

Comme on a pu l’observer, aussi bien les représentants des groupes d’intérêts<br />

qu’une majorité de citoyens ont violemment critiqué le caractère non<br />

démocratique du processus de révision de la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne. Le<br />

présent article analyse les propos à cet égard des uns et des autres avant<br />

d’examiner l’approche des intellectuels afin de voir si ces derniers ont<br />

renouvelé la pensée sur la démocratie en des termes différents de ceux utilisés<br />

par les élites politiques et sociales au Canada.<br />

Enfin, en opposant au discours constitutionnel que l’on nous a servi une vision<br />

de la démocratie qui se veut large et ancrée dans le social, les auteurs<br />

démontrent qu’aucune tentative de penser l’imbrication du corps politique et<br />

de la société civile à la lumière de concepts aussi fondamentaux que liberté,<br />

égalité, autorité ou obligation n’a jamais véritablement marqué les exercices<br />

de révision constitutionnelle.<br />

Abstract<br />

Both <strong>the</strong> representatives of interest groups <strong>and</strong> a majority of Canadians have<br />

harshly criticized <strong>the</strong> undemocratic nature of <strong>the</strong> Canadian constitutional<br />

review process. This article analyzes statements in this regard by <strong>the</strong> various<br />

parties concerned, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n proceeds to examine <strong>the</strong> approach taken by<br />

intellectuals, to determine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y have reopened <strong>the</strong> discussion of<br />

democracy in different terms than those used by Canada’s political <strong>and</strong> social<br />

elites.<br />

<strong>La</strong>stly, by comparing <strong>the</strong> constitutional discourse already presented to us with<br />

a broad, socially-centred vision of democracy, <strong>the</strong> authors demonstrate that<br />

<strong>the</strong> process of constitutional review has never truly attempted to situate <strong>the</strong><br />

body politic <strong>and</strong> civil society within such fundamental ideas as freedom,<br />

equality, authority or obligation.<br />

À l’instar des sociétés occidentales, le Canada vit actuellement l’épuisement<br />

du modèle de développement hérité des années d’après-guerre. Cet<br />

épuisement, on le sent à travers une certaine crise de légitimité socioinstitutionnelle<br />

qui, si elle n’est pas toujours manifeste dans le comportement<br />

quotidien des Canadiens, n’en est pas moins en train d’affaiblir le tissu social.<br />

Un sondage réalisé par le Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail en octobre 1990 indiquait que<br />

seulement 4 p. 100 des répondants estimaient que le régime actuel fonctionnait<br />

bien. Par contre, 34 p. 100 réclamaient une « refonte complète » du système<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

alors que 32 p. 100 souhaitaient des « changements considérables » et 29<br />

p. 100, « certains changements » (Dobell et Berry, 1992 : 19). Une compilation<br />

des sondages effectués depuis quinze ou vingt ans sur la satisfaction des<br />

Canadiens à l’égard de leurs institutions politiques montre un net déclin de la<br />

confiance et du respect vis-à-vis le système, le gouvernement et les élus<br />

(Dobell et Berry, 1992 : 5-12). Le rapport Spicer faisait d’ailleurs écho à ce<br />

désenchantement en notant la « perte de la foi envers le système politique » et<br />

le « désir unanime d’un changement profond » (Panitch, 1991 : 19).<br />

Le processus intense de révision constitutionnelle dans lequel le<br />

gouvernement a engagé le pays depuis l’Accord du lac Meech ne peut faire<br />

abstraction de ce mécontentement et du malaise socio-politique qui marquent<br />

cette fin de siècle. Alors que cela aurait pu être un moment privilégié de<br />

réflexion collective sur les paramètres de l’existence sociale, sur les valeurs et<br />

les normes qui doivent régir les rapports socio-économiques mutuels et la<br />

reconfiguration même de la communauté, les débats sur la <strong>Constitution</strong> ont<br />

souvent été un vain exercice de rhétorique politique et juridique dominé par les<br />

experts et les politiciens.<br />

Faut-il s’en étonner ? Reg Whitaker n’observait-il pas, il y a dix ans, que toute<br />

réflexion sur la nature de la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne ou sur les réformes qu’il y<br />

aurait peut-être lieu d’y apporter a toujours eu tendance à mettre l’accent sur<br />

les rapports entre les différents ordres de gouvernement plutôt qu’entre l’État<br />

et la population ou entre les divers agents sociaux. Avec pour résultat que la<br />

révision constitutionnelle n’a jamais abordé la question pourtant cruciale de<br />

l’imbrication du corps politique et de la société civile à la lumière de concepts<br />

tels que la liberté, l’égalité, l’autorité ou l’obligation (Whitaker, 1992 : 207).<br />

Ce texte participe de la conviction que peu de choses ont changé depuis dix<br />

ans. En dépit des dénonciations de l’approche exclusiviste qui a présidé à la<br />

négociation de l’Accord du lac Meech (11 hommes blancs réunis à huis clos<br />

décidant de l’avenir du pays), en dépit aussi de l’engagement maintes fois<br />

réitéré après son échec de solliciter l’avis de la population et d’inclure les<br />

représentants des divers groupes dans le processus de renouvellement<br />

constitutionnel, les débats sur la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne et les propositions de<br />

réforme qui en émanent restent étrangement confinés à la mécanique de<br />

partage de pouvoirs administratifs et à la reconfiguration des institutions<br />

parlementaires. Même les groupes dont on aurait pu espérer qu’ils forcent un<br />

déplacement vers des questions de fond sont le plus souvent cooptés par la<br />

logique institutionnaliste du discours sur la <strong>Constitution</strong> et s’enferment eux<br />

aussi dans ses paramètres étroits.<br />

Bizarrement, personne ne semble s’être encore attardé de manière sérieuse aux<br />

fondements sociétaux sur lesquels devrait reposer, au moins théoriquement,<br />

toute refonte de la <strong>Constitution</strong>. Peu d’intervenants réalisent que le débat<br />

constitutionnel est aussi un débat de société et que l’État et la société n’existent<br />

pas en vase clos, indépendamment l’un de l’autre. Nous soutiendrons dans ce<br />

texte que c’est là une erreur eu égard aux exigences de la démocratie. Tout le<br />

débat autour de la <strong>Constitution</strong> s’est fait en fonction d’une conception étroite<br />

de la démocratie, comme si des garanties institutionnelles suffisaient pour<br />

maintenir un niveau acceptable de démocratie en assurant un modus vivendi<br />

non seulement entre les institutions parlementaires et politiques, mais aussi et<br />

surtout des interactions multiples et variées entre les agents sociaux. L’enjeu<br />

véritable des réformes constitutionnelles ne doit pas se limiter aux seules<br />

168


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

modifications institutionnelles; il réside aussi dans un vouloir vivre collectif,<br />

dans la capacité d’empathie, de solidarité et de réciprocité.<br />

Le but du présent texte est de démontrer que le discours autour de la réforme<br />

constitutionnelle canadienne, tant celui des experts que celui des politiciens et<br />

des divers autres intervenants, n’a fait que reconduire les catégories<br />

traditionnelles de la démocratie parlementaire et les principes de base sur<br />

lesquels le fédéralisme canadien s’est historiquement constitué et développé.<br />

Dans un premier temps, il s’agira de relever les propos tenus par les<br />

représentants de différents groupes ou par les particuliers qui se sont<br />

prononcés sur les pratiques démocratiques de l’exercice constitutionnel, soit<br />

pour en dénoncer les carences ou pour en justifier les mécanismes existants.<br />

Depuis 1987, les Canadiens ont eu de nombreuses occasions de faire valoir<br />

leurs points de vue sur les modalités de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong>. Nous<br />

avons particulièrement retenu les opinions exprimées devant les comités<br />

parlementaires pertinents : le comité Tremblay-Speyer, le comité Beaudoin-<br />

Edwards ainsi que sur les propositions déposées par le gouvernement fédéral<br />

en septembre 1991 (comité Beaudoin-Dobbie). Nous croyons que ces<br />

différents moments permettent de saisir la multiplicité des positions<br />

défendues. Dans un second temps, nous nous pencherons sur la manière dont<br />

les experts, les universitaires et les intellectuels ont envisagé la problématique<br />

de la démocratie. <strong>La</strong> question qui se pose est de savoir dans quelle mesure ils<br />

ont renouvelé la pensée sur la démocratie en des termes différents de ceux mis<br />

de l’avant par les élites politiques et les figures de proue des mouvements<br />

sociaux au Canada. Finalement, en opposant au discours constitutionnel que<br />

l’on nous a servi jusqu’à maintenant une vision de la démocratie qui se veut<br />

large et ancrée dans le social, nous tenterons de démontrer combien l’exercice<br />

actuel de réforme de la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne participe d’une fiction<br />

institutionnelle qui risque en fait de nous éloigner d’une pratique au<strong>the</strong>ntique<br />

de la démocratie.<br />

<strong>La</strong> démocratie parlementaire et le fédéralisme exécutif au banc des<br />

accusés<br />

Nombre de gens ont reproché au processus qu’a mené à l’Accord du lac Meech<br />

un caractère élitiste et oligarchique qui favorisait le secret et écartait<br />

délibérément la participation du public. Aux yeux de plusieurs, le mépris des<br />

politiciens à l’endroit des principes démocratiques exigeait une remise en<br />

question des mécanismes politiques présidant aux modifications<br />

constitutionnelles. Si ces critiques avaient toutes en commun un certain<br />

désenchantement à l’égard de la conduite des affaires publiques par les<br />

politiciens, elles ne partagaient pas une identité de point de vue quant aux<br />

origines du mal à circonscrire et aux moyens à mettre en oeuvre pour y arriver.<br />

Il importe donc de jeter un regard critique sur les doléances formulées à<br />

l’endroit du processus pour saisir la vision de la démocratie qui les alimente.<br />

On peut classer les points de vue soulevés en deux catégories : d’une part, ceux<br />

ayant trait à la représentation de certaines catégories de la population dans le<br />

cadre des négociations constitutionnelles formelles et, d’autre part, ceux<br />

touchant la participation du public aux diverses étapes du processus. D’un côté<br />

comme de l’autre, il s’agit d’une remise en cause de la démocratie<br />

parlementaire et du fédéralisme exécutif tels que pratiqués au Canada.<br />

Ce sont surtout les représentants des groupes autochtones et de femmes qui ont<br />

protesté contre leur absence à la table des négociations. Pour les premiers, la<br />

169


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

structure politique du Canada et le principe de la majorité électorale<br />

contribuent à marginaliser les peuples autochtones (Canada, 1987, 9 : 29) et ne<br />

leur permettent pas de vraiment participer à la Confédération canadienne. Ils<br />

réclamèrent donc d’être partie prenante aux conférences des premiers<br />

ministres afin de pouvoir veiller à la protection de leurs droits et oeuvres à une<br />

refonte de la <strong>Constitution</strong> qui leur soit favorable (Canada, 1991a, 26 : 32).<br />

Quant aux représentantes des groupes de femmes, elles ont reproché aux<br />

gouvernements leur exclusion du processus (Canada, 1987, 15 : 154) et exigé<br />

d’être présentes lorsque leurs droits font l’objet de discussions, car aucun autre<br />

intervenant n’était mieux en mesure que les femmes elles-mêmes de faire<br />

valoir leur point de vue avec l’angle d’approche qui est le leur (Canada, 1992,<br />

10 : 26). En somme, chez les autochtones comme chez les femmes, on voulait<br />

participer au processus afin d’infléchir le cours des événements : pour les<br />

premiers, en vertu de leur statut de minoritaires; pour les seconds, à cause<br />

d’une absence de sensibilité aux problématiques des femmes. Les<br />

représentantes des groupes de femmes soutenaient même que les députées<br />

étaient moins en mesure qu’elles de défendre la cause des femmes étant donné<br />

que leurs groupes avaient jusqu’alors été les porte-parole de leurs intérêts<br />

auprès des institutions politiques (Maillé, 1992).<br />

Leur inclusion respective à la table des discussions répondrait, pour une large<br />

part, aux critiques formulées à l’endroit du processus des négociations<br />

constitutionnelles. Il faut toutefois faire remarquer que, ce faisant, c’est<br />

l’économie générale des institutions politiques et de la démocratie formelle<br />

qui en aurait été modifée, et ce, pour deux raisons.<br />

D’une part, l’ajout de nouveaux intervenants sociaux dans les mécanismes<br />

traditionnels de négociations issus du fédéralisme exécutif mettrait face à face<br />

des porte-parole dont la légitimité ne repose pas sur les mêmes bases. Les<br />

premiers ministres tiennent leur autorité de leur élection et du m<strong>and</strong>at qu’ils<br />

ont reçu d’une pluralité d’électeurs. <strong>La</strong> légitimité des représentants de groupes<br />

d’intérêts repose davantage sur la nature des liens qui les unit à leurs groupes<br />

respectifs. Ces leaders doivent bien entendu rendre des comptes, mais sur la<br />

base d’une obligation de résultats touchant à des aspects beaucoup plus<br />

restreints. Élus à partir d’un vaste programme, les politiciens sont les<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ataires de la volonté populaire qui s’est exprimée à l’occasion d’élections<br />

générales.<br />

<strong>La</strong> participation des groupes d’intérêts aux négociations soulève donc la<br />

question de leur représentativité. Dans le cadre d’une démocratie<br />

parlementaire, les élus sont des fondés de pouvoir pour l’ensemble des<br />

électeurs. L’arrivée de nouveaux intervenants peut être interprétée comme un<br />

aveu d’incapacité de la part du régime politique traditionnel de représenter<br />

certains intérêts particuliers. Dans le cas des autochtones et des femmes, leurs<br />

situations respectives expliquent en gr<strong>and</strong>e partie leur insatisfaction à l’égard<br />

d’une démocratie qualifiée de tyrannie de la majorité. Toutefois, l’inclusion de<br />

leurs représentants constituerait une reconnaissance implicite de l’illégitimité<br />

des politiciens à les représenter et confirmerait même l’incapacité de ces<br />

derniers à comprendre les tenants et aboutissants de leurs revendications et<br />

signifierait qu’ils ne parlent désormais que pour une portion de plus en plus<br />

congrue de la population, tous les autres clivages étant confondus.<br />

<strong>La</strong> remise en question du processus de négociation de la <strong>Constitution</strong> a soulevé<br />

un second ordre de critiques faisant référence à l’absence ou à la faible<br />

participation de la population. Suite à Meech, on a reproché au processus de<br />

170


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

manquer de transparence et de favoriser indûment le secret. En d’autres<br />

termes, Meech fut pris à partie pour avoir été concocté en catimini, entériné par<br />

onze premiers ministres sans consultation publique préalable et présenté<br />

comme intouchable jusqu’à sa ratification finale, qui n’eût d’ailleurs jamais<br />

lieu (Canada, 1987, 3 : 92; 13 : 27; 15 : 139; Canada, 1991a, 25 : 81). Certains<br />

ont même accusé les gouvernements d’avoir délibérément privilégié<br />

l’exclusion du public. <strong>La</strong> démocratie parlementaire et le fédéralisme exécutif<br />

ont été dénoncés comme favorisant la complicité des élites sans égard aux<br />

attentes de la population (Canada, 1991a, 31 : 48), renforçant le pouvoir d’une<br />

« oligarchie » constituée des premiers ministres (Canada, 1991a, 15 : 47),<br />

illustrant la manipulation du public par les élites et, par le fait même, niant les<br />

principes du gouvernement responsable (Canada, 1991a, 31 : 38). On y<br />

stigmatise le fédéralisme exécutif, lequel n’exige aucune participation de la<br />

population au processus (Canada, 1991a, 10 : 70). Ce phénomène est<br />

parfaitement bien illustré par la formule d’amendement qui est définie<br />

uniquement dans la perspective du fédéralisme, laissant de côté les dimensions<br />

démocratique et populaire de la gouverne politique. En somme, au fédéralisme<br />

exécutif on oppose la souveraineté populaire. On soutient que la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

appartient d’abord au peuple et qu’elle ne saurait être modifiée sans que celuici<br />

n’ait eu l’occasion de se prononcer sur le nouveau contrat social négocié par<br />

les élites, que ce soit par le biais de la convocation d’une assemblée<br />

constituante ou par la tenue d’un référendum (Canada, 1991a, 29 : 60-61 et 9 :<br />

37). Pour plusieurs, la modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> pourrait se réaliser non<br />

plus en ayant recours au fédéralisme exécutif, mais par la convocation d’une<br />

assemblée constituants chargée d’en rédiger une nouvelle. Manifestement,<br />

pareille idée s’oppose au pouvoir des élites politiques traditionnelles qui ne<br />

seraient pas investies du m<strong>and</strong>at de transformer la loi fondamentale du pays.<br />

Les pourfendeurs de la démocratie parlementaire ne sont pas moins virulents.<br />

Selon eux, le principe du gouvernement responsable serait entaché par la règle<br />

de la discipline de parti qui écarte l’idée que les gouvernements sont d’abord<br />

élus à titre de représentants de la population et doivent démissionner ou obtenir<br />

un nouveau m<strong>and</strong>at s’ils perdent la confiance du public. Dans les faits,<br />

soutiennent-ils, le gouvernement responsable et représentatif est une vue de<br />

l’esprit. Encore ici, la formule d’amendement constitutionnel illustre bien<br />

l’exclusion de la population du processus politique (Canada, 1991a, 2 : 88-89).<br />

C’est donc toute la légitimité du processus qui est remise en cause. Pour les<br />

uns, comme Cairns, il importe d’abord et avant tout d’y incorporer les<br />

principaux groupes sociaux:«lalégitimité du processus et son utilité à long<br />

terme pour les Canadiens dépend de l’incorporation d’une pluralité d’intérêts<br />

incluant les gouvernements, les groupes visés par la <strong>Charte</strong>, les peuples<br />

autochtones et un nombre important d’autres groupes qui restent souvent sur la<br />

touche » (Canada, 1991a, 23 : 22-23). Cette nécessité découle non seulement<br />

de la nouvelle réalité politique qui s’est mise en place au Canada depuis 1982 et<br />

de l’adoption de la <strong>Charte</strong> des droits et libertés, comme le prétend Cairns, mais<br />

traduit aussi un sentiment de déception, pour ne pas dire d’animosité, à<br />

l’endroit des politiciens. Certains en sont même venus à accorder une<br />

crédibilité équivalente, sinon supérieure, aux représentants des groupes<br />

sociaux (Canada, 1991a, 26 : 25). Pour d’autres, comme Brad Morse, il s’agit<br />

plutôt d’accorder une plus large place aux citoyens et de les consulter tout au<br />

long du processus, ne serait-ce que pour leur donner l’impression qu’ils<br />

participent aux changements constitutionnels (Canada, 1991a, 3 : 67).<br />

171


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Derrière cet ensemble de critiques se profile la volonté exprimée par plusieurs<br />

intervenants de donner à la population l’occasion de se prononcer à un moment<br />

ou à un autre du processus de négociation constitutionnelle. <strong>La</strong> démocratie est<br />

perçue d’abord sous sa forme institutionnelle. <strong>La</strong> question posée est celle de<br />

savoir quels mécanismes permettraient une meilleure participation populaire.<br />

Ou cherche en partie à atténuer le cynisme des citoyens à l’égard de leurs<br />

politiciens et du système politique en suggérant une foule de propositions en<br />

vue d’accroître cette participation, allant de l’assemblée constituante à un<br />

référendum national.<br />

Comme l’a fait remarquer Ka<strong>the</strong>rine Swinton, il faut distinguer au moins trois<br />

étapes dans le processus de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> : l’élaboration des<br />

modifications proposées, leur négociation et, enfin, leur ratification (Canada,<br />

1991a, 9 : 37). Le type de participation peut donc varier en fonction de chacune<br />

des étapes. Les promoteurs de l’idée de la convocation d’une assemblée<br />

constituante, dont la composition et le rôle variaient selon les intervenants,<br />

visaient surtout à accroître la participation du public lors de la première étape.<br />

Ce mécanisme est présenté comme le seul véritablement démocratique dans la<br />

mesure où il garantit la présence des citoyens dans le processus, regroupe des<br />

individus plus représentatifs de la société canadienne, limite la partisanerie qui<br />

entrave la représentation et la possibilité d’établir un consensus et rend<br />

légitime les propositions aux yeux des Canadiens (Canada, 1991b : 47). Ceuxci<br />

sont tenus de représenter les points de vue de ceux qui les ont élus.<br />

Le référendum, quant à lui, correspond à l’étape de la ratification des<br />

modifications proposées. Pour Vincent Lemieux, c’est le meilleur moyen de<br />

faire participer la population; à cet égard, il est supérieur aux audiences<br />

publiques ou aux commissions parlementaires (Canada, 1991a, 2 : 86-87).<br />

Toutefois, la formule du référendum n’est pas en soit miraculeuse. Certains ont<br />

exprimé la crainte que les résultats sèment la discorde en révélant des clivages<br />

nationaux ou régionaux préjudiciables à la recherche ou la consolidation de<br />

l’unité nationale. Un référendum ne saurait contredire la nature fédérale du<br />

régime politique et être utilisé pour faire l’économie d’une entente entre les<br />

premiers ministres (Canada, 1992, 38 : 24).<br />

Force est de constater qu’à travers toutes ces récriminations à l’endroit du<br />

processus et de son caractère plus ou moins démocratique, on ne retrouve<br />

aucune réflexion approfondie sur le sens de la démocratie. On s’est surtout<br />

penché sur le caractère formel de l’exercice (possibilité plus ou moins gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

de participation). Cela étant, il était facile à certains observateurs de faire<br />

remarquer, comme l’a fait Swinton, que « les négociations constitutionnelles<br />

du lac Meech ont sans doute été les plus démocratiques de notre histoire si tant<br />

est que la démocratie se mesure au degré de participation du pouvoir<br />

législatif » (Canada, 1991a, 9 : 37). Au sens strict, il n’est pas faux de faire<br />

remarquer que si l’élaboration du projet de réforme a été le fait du pouvoir<br />

exécutif, la participation du pouvoir législatif a été sans précédent, car toutes<br />

les assemblées législatives se devaient d’entériner l’Accord. En ce sens,<br />

l’échec de Meech s’explique en gr<strong>and</strong>e partie par l’opposition d’une forte<br />

majorité de la population canadienne qui a trouvé écho au sein de deux<br />

assemblées législatives plus récalcitrantes que d’autres. Paradoxalement,<br />

certains pourraient même soutenir que l’échec de Meech confirme le succès de<br />

la démocratie, vue comme la manifestation de la volonté populaire.<br />

De la même manière, d’un point de vue instrumental, on peut arguer que la<br />

formule actuelle de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> n’a pas besoin d’être<br />

172


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

changée pour permettre une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e participation du public. Il s’agirait<br />

seulement de généraliser la tenue d’audiences publiques pour que la<br />

population ait davantage d’occasions de faire valoir ses attentes (Brock, 1991).<br />

<strong>La</strong> transparence du processus pourrait être assurée par une meilleure<br />

information du public sur les progrès accomplis et les consensus atteints. De<br />

plus, il est loin d’être certain que la formule de l’assemblée constituante<br />

produirait les effets attendus. L’élection des participants ne pourrait être<br />

impartiale compte tenu des intérêts partisans en jeu. Plutôt que d’être ouverts<br />

aux compromis, les élus de ces assemblées pourraient bien s’en tenir à la<br />

position défendue au moment de leur élection, insufflant dans le processus<br />

plus de rigidité qu’il n’y en a à l’heure actuelle (Canada, 1991b : 51).<br />

D’autres ont soutenu, comme Richard Simeon et J. Peter Meekison, que le<br />

processus ayant conduit à Meech n’était pas illégitime. Cette entente n’a pas<br />

été conçue subitement au cours des quelques heures de négociations en mai et<br />

juin 1987. Au contraire, les éléments qui s’y sont retrouvés ont fait l’objet de<br />

débats approfondis pendant de nombreuses années et l’ordre du jour fut établi<br />

publiquement. On rappelle que le gouvernement conservateur avait fondé une<br />

partie de sa campagne électorale sur cette question (Canada, 1987, 5 : 74, 87 et<br />

10 : 41).<br />

Il importe de faire remarquer qu’en dépit de l’omniprésence des discours sur la<br />

démocratie dans les critiques à l’endroit du processus de révision<br />

constitutionnelle, les intervenants — groupes sociaux ou particuliers — s’en<br />

sont essentiellement tenus au caractère instrumental de la pratique de la<br />

démocratie. On n’y retrouve pas de véritable remise en question du mode<br />

d’insertion des individus et des groupes marginalisés au sein de la société<br />

canadienne. En vérité, le débat constitutionnel a tourné autour de questions<br />

relativement techniques : les modalités de nomination des participants à une<br />

assemblée constituante, les bienfaits de la tenue d’un référendum, les<br />

mécanismes devant présider à la conduite des audiences publiques, etc. Bien<br />

sûr, certains n’ont pas manqué de souligner au passage les lacunes du<br />

fédéralisme exécutif et de la démocratie parlementaire, mais toujours pour<br />

faire ressortir l’absence d’une véritable participation des citoyens. Cette<br />

approche fait l’économie d’une réflexion approfondie sur les faiblesses de la<br />

pratique démocratique, une réflexion qui mettrait l’accent sur les principes de<br />

solidarité sociale et les conditions de la citoyenneté. Au contraire, tout se passe<br />

comme si les individus et les groupes s’opposaient les uns aux autres à travers<br />

les institutions formelles du système politique, recherchant à la fois protection<br />

et promotion de leurs droits, définis sur la base de catégories sociales<br />

déterminées.<br />

Le fédéralisme comme fondement de la démocratie et de la<br />

citoyenneté ?<br />

Reg Whitaker, qui réfléchit depuis longtemps à la problématique de la<br />

démocratie dans le cadre fédéral canadien (1992 : 165-230, 283-328), a été<br />

l’un des premiers à prévoir la dénonciation du caractère antidémocratique du<br />

processus constitutionnel. Son analyse fine des sources politiques et<br />

idéologiques de la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne indique la nature profondément<br />

élitiste et antidémocratique de ses fondements et des pratiques politiques<br />

qu’elle a soutenues. Certes, avec le temps, reconnaît-il, la notion britannique<br />

de souveraineté incarnée par le « Gouverneur en conseil » de même que la<br />

doctrine à la fois rivale et complémentaire de suprématie parlementaire se sont<br />

quelque peu étiolées sous l’action combinée de l’extension du suffrage<br />

173


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

universel et de la montée des partis politiques. Mais c’est plutôt du côté du<br />

fédéralisme, non pas en tant que système administratif de partage de pouvoir<br />

mais comme appui de la démocratie, que Whitaker propose de regarder pour<br />

élargir le champ de la pratique démocratique. Le fédéralisme moderne,<br />

soutient-il, permet d’éviter que l’expression de la volonté de la majorité<br />

nationale agisse comme seule base légitime de législation. Le cadre fédératif<br />

empêche que la majorité nationale s’impose comme seul critère de la<br />

souveraineté, cette dernière se répartissant entre diverses souverainetés<br />

régionales. Certes, Whitaker admet que les particularités du système électoral<br />

canadien peuvent parfois diluer le potentiel démocratique du fédéralisme : au<br />

Canada, la majorité nationale n’équivaut bien souvent à rien de plus que la<br />

suprématie d’une province ou d’une région sur les autres. Quoi qu’il en soit,<br />

Whitaker n’en proclame pas moins la compatibilité du fédéralisme et de la<br />

démocratie en ce que l’un et l’autre se renforcent mutuellement. Le<br />

fédéralisme, prétend-il, offre les garanties institutionnelles d’une citoyenneté<br />

plus complexe et plus large. Cela peut, bien sûr, conduire à une multiplicité<br />

d’expressions politiques, de volontés contradictoires de représentation et de<br />

loyautés identitaires antagoniques qui constituent autant de défis à la pratique<br />

démocratique, mais qui l’obligent aussi à se renouveler.<br />

Whitaker symbolise en quelque sorte le malaise et l’ambiguïté actuels de la<br />

pensée sur la démocratie au Canada. En posant le fédéralisme comme un<br />

fondement important de la démocratie, il montre combien sa conception de la<br />

démocratie est finalement dépendante de l’appareillage institutionnel qui en<br />

permet l’exercice. On cherchera en vain chez Whitaker une définition précise<br />

des éléments constitutifs de la citoyenneté préalable à la pratique<br />

démocratique. L’intérêt du fédéralisme à cet égard tient au fait que sur le plan<br />

institutionnel, il assure une représentation plus juste et égalitaire des droits des<br />

individus contre la tyrannie de la majorité. Whitaker nous met peut-être sur<br />

une piste intéressante, car dans sa forme pure et absolue, le fédéralisme permet<br />

en effet une décentralisation de la souveraineté. Cependant, dans la mesure où<br />

les paramètres d’insertion des particularismes restent indéfinis, on ne peut se<br />

rallier complètement à Whitaker. En bout de piste, la position qu’il défend<br />

approuve la démocratie de représentation — surtout si elle est tempérée par des<br />

codes de libertés fondamentales qui protègent les opinions minoritaires — et<br />

se range à l’intérieur de la conception territoriale traditionnelle de la politique<br />

canadienne qui ne cherche finalement qu’à assurer la protection des volontés<br />

régionales. Whitaker n’offre aucune vision sociétale de la démocratie, dont la<br />

problématique s’identifie aux mécanismes de la gouverne.<br />

En fait, Whitaker compte peut-être parmi les rares à avoir cherché quelque sens<br />

démocratique à la quête constitutionnelle canadienne. De façon générale, les<br />

experts, les universitaires et les intellectuels qui s’intéressent au dossier et qui<br />

ont exprimé leur avis durant ou en marge des débats ont rarement poussé leur<br />

pensée jusque sur le terrain d’une reconceptualisation du sens de la<br />

démocratie. Dans presque tous les cas, ils ou elles se sont conformés au cadre<br />

étroit de réflexion imposé par les élites politiques. Il suffit pour s’en<br />

convaincre de consulter les procès-verbaux des audiences des diverses<br />

commissions sur la <strong>Constitution</strong> qui ont sondé les Canadiens au cours des<br />

dernières années. Que ce soit dans le cadre des ces commissions lors de forums<br />

publics ou semi-publics, ces gens n’ont jamais tenté de renouveler le discours<br />

sur la démocratie. Tout comme les groupes, associations et particuliers qui ont<br />

présenté des mémoires, l’intelligentsia canadienne s’est surtout attachée à<br />

relever les faiblesses institutionnelles qui menacent l’exercice de la<br />

174


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

démocratie sans se préoccuper des conditions sociales essentielles à la<br />

démocratie ou encore des paramètres idéaux d’une citoyenneté élargie. Elle est<br />

tombée, elle aussi, dans le panneau des discussions de plomberie<br />

institutionnelle. À lire l’imposante documentation sur la question (à titre<br />

indicatif voir Behiels, 1989; Barrie, 1988; Smith, 1991; Cairns, 1992a; Silipo,<br />

1991), on s’aperçoit vite que c’est d’abord la démocratisation du processus de<br />

réforme constitutionnelle qui retient l’attention des experts et non pas le<br />

contenu même de la démocratie. En cela, leurs propos ne s’écartent guère des<br />

multiples positions exprimées devant les comités parlementaires. Certes, il<br />

n’est pas inutile de chercher les moyens d’une juste représentation, mais<br />

l’élargissement de la démocratie ne tient pas aux seuls mécanismes de la<br />

représentation.<br />

Alan Cairns (1988) fournit les éléments d’une explication à cette espèce<br />

d’obsession institutionnelle. D’après lui, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982<br />

marquait une rupture dans la façon d’aborder la chose constitutionnelle au<br />

Canada et dans la manière surtout de s’y sentir partie prenante.<br />

L’enchâssement d’une charte des droits et libertés dans la <strong>Constitution</strong> a créé,<br />

d’après Cairns, une <strong>Constitution</strong> de citoyens encourageant les groupes et les<br />

individus historiquement exclus de la dynamique politique à prendre la place<br />

qui leur revient de droit. Alors que les discussions relatives à la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

ont toujours été le moment de tractations entre élites bureaucratiques et<br />

politiques, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 a invité les citoyens à se considérer<br />

aussi comme acteurs à part entière. Ce changement important dans la culture<br />

politique du pays pose inévitablement tout le problème de la participation et de<br />

la représentation et donc des modalités d’insertion institutionnelle des intérêts<br />

multiples et antagoniques appelés à se manifester (Fortin, 1992 : 5-6). L’échec<br />

de l’Accord du lac Meech tiendrait en partie à ce qu’on avait compté sans la<br />

réaction des groupes et citoyens nouvellement « accrédités » par la <strong>Charte</strong>, qui<br />

n’auront pas accepté de n’avoir pas été inclus dans le processus (Cairns, 1991 :<br />

19).<br />

Dans un texte récent (1992), Jane Jenson a bien retracé cette dynamique<br />

qu’elle lie à l’évolution du sens de la citoyenneté et aux modifications du<br />

contenu identitaire au Canada. Durant presque toute la première moitié du 20e siècle, observe-t-elle, la région et la culture ont défini les clivages politiques<br />

les plus importants. Les groupes dont l’action se réclamaient de l’identité<br />

régionale utilisaient le système de partis pour obtenir d’Ottawa un partage<br />

équitable des ressources socio-économiques. De même, ceux qui se<br />

mobilisaient sur la base de l’appartenance culturelle utilisaient à la fois les<br />

canaux provincial et fédéral pour faire valoir leurs revendications. Jusqu’à la<br />

Deuxième Guerre mondiale, les intérêts régionaux et ethnoculturels<br />

s’exprimeront essentiellement à travers la représentation partisane et<br />

ministérielle. Après 1945, c’est dans le cadre de négociations<br />

intergouvernementales surtout que se manifesteront les prétentions à la<br />

citoyenneté. Toujours selon Jenson, depuis l’entrée en vigueur de la <strong>Charte</strong>,<br />

cependant, l’action des groupes tend à se situer en dehors du système partisan<br />

et des mécanismes intergouvernementaux. Ainsi, l’échec de Meech manifeste<br />

l’échec des institutions représentatives de la démocratie libérale, à savoir le<br />

système de partis et le fédéralisme exécutif. Le processus de prise de décision<br />

fut dénoncé parce qu’il niait les principes de la souveraineté parlementaire<br />

ainsi que les nouvelles formes de représentation des mouvements sociaux et<br />

des groupes d’intérêts. Ces nouvelles formes de représentation offrent une utre<br />

voie au secteur populaire qui ne compte plus sur le système de partis pour faire<br />

175


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

valoir ses intérêts (Breton et Jenson, 1991 : 201). L’espace politique vital de<br />

ces groupes serait autrement défini : leur identité est intimement liée à leur<br />

préférence pour des formes nouvelles de démocratie politique. Jenson soutient<br />

que l’émergence de nouveaux mouvements sociaux, de même que la récente<br />

prééminence politique de groupes tels que les autochtones, marquent le point<br />

de départ d’une reformulation de la démocratie au Canada. Leurs positions et<br />

revendications particulières remettraient en cause le « déficit » démocratique<br />

que représentent la définition de la <strong>Constitution</strong> et l’opération des institutions<br />

intergouverne- mentales et partisanes. En fait, Jenson n’est pas loin de<br />

suggérer que ces nouveaux mouvements sociaux pourraient constituer les<br />

fondements d’une pratique élargie de la démocratie au Canada.<br />

Notre lecture de la situation n’est pas aussi enthousiaste que celle de Jenson.<br />

Sur la base des préoccupations exprimées devant les comités parlementaires,<br />

nous croyons plutôt que les revendications des nouveaux mouvements sociaux<br />

participent d’abord d’un désir de reconnaissance institutionnelle et ne<br />

remettent pas en cause les paramètres fondamentaux actuels du système<br />

politique et de la citoyenneté. D’après ce que nous avons pu déceler, rares sont<br />

les groupes qui essaient d’amener le débat sur le terrain d’une conception qui<br />

transcenderait leur intégration aux mécanismes institutionnels tels qu’ils<br />

existent à l’heure actuelle. Ainsi, ils ne remettent pas en question les<br />

fondements usuels de la citoyenneté et de la démocratie. Bien sûr, certains<br />

groupes se sont montrés fort critiques à l’endroit du mode de fonctionnement<br />

de la démocratie et ont souligné avec véhémence la faible participation de la<br />

population au processus constitutionnel. <strong>La</strong> mise en application de leurs<br />

suggestions aurait certes pour effet de modifier les institutions, mais en suivant<br />

toujours les principes de la démocratie parlementaire. De plus, leur volonté<br />

d’être entendus ou représentés, d’une manière ou d’une autre, à la table<br />

constitutionnelle, ne modifie que marginalement le fédéralisme exécutif et le<br />

recours à l’accommodation des élites comme lieu de prise de décision comme<br />

l’a pertinemment rappelé Smith (1991 : 80).<br />

Mais au-delà de ces critiques et de ces suggestions, les groupes et les nouveaux<br />

mouvements sociaux dont parle Jenson ont adopté une posture étroitement<br />

individualiste en cherchant simplement à obtenir la parité de leurs droits avec<br />

ceux des autres groupes. Leur conception de la citoyenneté se limite en fait à<br />

leur seule inclusion dans l’appareil institutionnel existant. Pire, leurs<br />

inquiétudes quant à la défense de leurs intérêts propres ne se manifestent bien<br />

souvent qu’en fonction des pertes ou des gains relatifs à la plus ou moins<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>e centralisation du fédéralisme canadien. Par exemple, les groupes de<br />

femmes considèrent souvent que le gouvernement fédéral offre de meilleures<br />

garanties de respect des principes d’universalité et d’accessibilité aux soins de<br />

santé que les provinces, d’où leur attachement à l’adoption de normes<br />

nationales (McLellan, 1992 : 10). Mais pour plusieurs, la réflexion s’arrête là.<br />

Toute la problématique est toujours posée selon l’axe traditionnel<br />

centralisation- décentralisation alors que le problème de la santé des femmes a<br />

un caractère éminemment social qui va au-delà des calculs renvoyant<br />

uniquement à la mécanique administrative et institutionnelle du partage des<br />

compétences. Ces questions sont, certes, pertinentes. Mais limiter la réflexion<br />

à ces seules balises réduit la complexité du problème et fait peu pour situer le<br />

débat à l’extérieur des institutions gouvernementales et partisanes comme le<br />

soutient Jenson. De plus, cette façon d’aborder la question ne contribue que<br />

marginalement à une redéfinition plus globale de la citoyenneté.<br />

176


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

En raison de leur « obsession institutionnaliste, » les représentants des groupes<br />

et des nouveaux mouvements sociaux ne contribuent pas véritablement au<br />

changement de la culture politique qui assurerait un renouvellement de la<br />

pratique démocratique au Canada. Alors que ces groupes pourraient être le<br />

ferment de valeurs nouvelles à la base d’une citoyenneté et d’une pratique<br />

démocratique renouvelée, leurs actions et leurs intérêts respectifs semblent les<br />

diviser. En d’autres termes, la démarche privilégiée par certains groupes peut<br />

les amener à opposer leurs intérêts et leurs droits à ceux mis de l’avant par<br />

d’autres. Par exemple, on peut s’interroger sur la complémentarité entre la<br />

reconnaissance du principe de l’autonomie gouvernementale réclamée par les<br />

chefs autochtones et le respect des droits des femmes autochtones. Celles-ci<br />

n’avaient-elles pas dem<strong>and</strong>é un siège à la table constitutionnelle craignant<br />

l’édulcoration de leurs droits contenus dans la <strong>Charte</strong> ?<br />

L’attention des intervenants socio-politiques et des spécialistes qui se sont<br />

penchés sur notre problématique s’est essentiellement portée sur les modalités<br />

d’une participation accrue sans qu’il ne soit question des fondements<br />

théoriques de la <strong>Charte</strong>. En d’autres termes, les interrogations ne portent pas<br />

sur les valeurs qui l’animent, sinon pour reprendre les gr<strong>and</strong>s principes du<br />

libéralisme. Or, il nous faut nous dem<strong>and</strong>er si ces valeurs sont suffisantes pour<br />

garantir l’exercice d’une véritable démocratie. C’est maintenant cette question<br />

qui va faire l’objet de nos propos.<br />

Repenser la démocratie<br />

Selon la conception généralement acceptée dans les sociétés occidentales,<br />

l’exercice de la démocratie relève de la dimension politico-administrative de<br />

la vie sociale; la démocratie n’a de sens et d’existence propres qu’à travers les<br />

manifestations directes et indirectes des institutions parlementaires. <strong>La</strong><br />

démocratie est d’abord une question de droits politiques consentis aux<br />

individus et le progrès en la matière se mesure à l’aune de la protection qu’une<br />

société est prête à garantir à ces mêmes droits. <strong>La</strong> démocratie s’appuie ainsi sur<br />

les préceptes du libéralisme individualiste qui pose comme prémisses<br />

ontologiques fondamentales la défense et la promotion de la liberté<br />

individuelle. Elle participe d’un concept négatif de la liberté, puisque celle-ci<br />

apparaît d’abord comme l’absence de contraintes ou d’interférences<br />

extérieures à l’individu. Dans ce cadre, le rôle de l’État se limite à protéger<br />

l’individu contre les menaces à sa liberté et surtout contre toute atteinte à son<br />

droit inaliénable à la propriété privée. <strong>La</strong> tradition libérale en ce domaine ne se<br />

préoccupe guère d’objectifs de coopération, de justice ou d’égalité sociale;<br />

légiférer de tels objectifs porterait ombrage à la liberté que doit avoir l’individu<br />

de faire ses propres choix.<br />

L’émergence de l’État-providence et la primauté accrue accordée à la<br />

promotion de l’égalité socio-économique ont démontré en un sens<br />

l’inadéquation d’une application stricte du libéralisme individualiste à la<br />

démocratie. L’expérience welfariste des sociétés occidentales au cours des<br />

quarante ou cinquante dernières années prouve que la démocratie se joue aussi<br />

en dehors des frontières de la sphère politique. Les revendications constantes<br />

pour la reconnaissance de droits sociaux et économiques, les luttes pour<br />

l’égalité non pas simplement politique mais aussi sociale montrent que pour<br />

plusieurs, la démocratie n’est pas qu’affaire de droits politiques et de libertés<br />

civiles. Au cours des années récentes, plusieurs penseurs ont remis en question<br />

les principes traditionnels de fonctionnement de la démocratie libérale. Non<br />

seulement s’inscrivent-ils souvent en faux contre l’adéquation qui est<br />

177


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

généralement faite entre libéralisme et démocratie ou encore entre<br />

parlementarisme et démocratie (Mouffe, 1992a; 1992b), mais encore ils<br />

cherchent à déborder les confins institutionnels étroits dans lesquels on<br />

enferme aussi l’exercice de la démocratie. On s’oriente ainsi vers une<br />

reconceptualisation plus globale, plus sociétale de la démocratie (<strong>La</strong>bica,<br />

1992) qui permettrait la création d’espaces publics de participation qui ne<br />

tiendrait pas seulement aux critères de la représentation, mais aussi et peut-être<br />

surtout au désir d’inclusion sociale et économique. Cette vision « alternative »<br />

ne cherche pas la reviviscence de la démocratie dans le remaniement<br />

cosmétique des institutions en place, elle lie le renouvellement de la<br />

démocratie à la reconfiguration du rapport salarial, à la transformation des<br />

rapports sociaux, au recul des hiérarchies, au respect de l’égalité dans la<br />

différence et à la mise en place de nouvelles formes de solidarité et de<br />

mécanismes de représentation plus organiques (Lipietz, 1992 : 283-284). Bref,<br />

le renouvellement de la démocratie tiendrait dans la capacité des sociétés<br />

modernes d’opter pour une remise en question du paradigme démocratique<br />

dominant.<br />

Dans la pratique sociale, le plein développement de la démocratie n’est<br />

possible que si l’on consent à en camper l’exercice, par-delà le formalisme<br />

parlementaire et représentatif, dans le champ beaucoup plus global et généreux<br />

d’un dialogue ouvert entre tous ceux et celles dont l’épanouissement personnel<br />

est à la merci des conditions sociales et matérielles. Or, il ne peut y avoir<br />

épanouissement de la personne sans coopération sociale, sans solidarité entre<br />

les individus, sans réciprocité; c’est un préalable. <strong>La</strong> garantie sociale d’un<br />

bien-être matériel et moral pour tous sans exception représente la condition<br />

nécessaire à l’épanouissement de la personne et, de manière concomitante, à<br />

l’expansion de la démocratie (Gould, 1988; Guttman, 1988; Doyal et Gough,<br />

1991).<br />

Le projet démocratique exige l’égalité entre les individus. Il ne s’agit pas ici<br />

d’une égalité formelle ou de principe, mais d’une égalité d’accès aux<br />

conditions sociales et matérielles d’épanouissement individuel. Le droit égal<br />

pour tous de participer aux décisions relatives aux activités communes liées à<br />

l’épanouissement individuel doit constituer une facette incontournable de la<br />

démocratie. Ces aires communes de décision ne relèvent pas seulement du<br />

domaine politique; elles doivent aussi s’insérer dans tous les domaines de la<br />

vie sociale et économique. Vivre la démocratie, c’est donc dépasser la tyrannie<br />

de la majorité pour aller vers des formes plus consensuelles où les minoritaires<br />

ne sont pas exclus d’emblée des choix de société. C’est également travailler à<br />

combler les écarts socio-économiques qui éloignent et polarisent les divers<br />

segments de la société. Vivre la démocratie, c’est penser une société fondée sur<br />

le partage des biens, des obligations et du savoir, une société axée sur la<br />

possibilité offerte à tous de participer aux mécanismes du devenir collectif.<br />

Vivre la démocratie, c’est finalement investir l’espace public et exercer<br />

pleinement les responsabilités de la citoyenneté.<br />

Mais de quelle citoyenneté s’agit-il ? L’idée de citoyenneté a historiquement<br />

été élaborée et comprise dans son sens universel et général. Elle repose d’abord<br />

et avant tout sur la présence de traits communs, presque toujours<br />

institutionnels, auxquels peuvent s’identifier les agents sociaux, sans égard à<br />

ce qui les différencie. L’universalisme du concept classique de souveraineté<br />

conduit à la mise en place de lois et de règles socio-institutionnelles qui se<br />

répercutent sur tous et chacun indistinctement. Les lois et les règles qui<br />

émanent de la citoyenneté traditionnelle ne tiennent pas compte des<br />

178


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

particularités individuelles et des différences socio-économiques qui<br />

distinguent et opposent même les agents et les groupes sociaux. Dans son<br />

acception actuelle, la citoyenneté équivaut ni plus ni moins à un déni de<br />

l’existence de réalités sociales multiples. Le véritable défi de la réflexion sur la<br />

démocratie à l’aube du 21e siècle consiste à penser la citoyenneté non plus<br />

comme un idéal universel et général — essentiellement défini par les classes<br />

dominantes et auquel tous se doivent d’adhérer — mais bien comme un<br />

objectif politique tangible qui viserait à donner la parole aux groupes socioéconomiques<br />

qui ont été historiquement exclus du processus socio-politique et<br />

des mécanismes institutionnels et administratifs et qui continuent d’être<br />

relégués à la marge des lieux de pouvoir et laissés pour compte dans<br />

l’élaboration de projets de société (Young, 1990).<br />

En clair, il ne saurait y avoir de projet véritablement démocratique sans<br />

solidarité ni réciprocité, mais surtout sans l’apport de tous à la définition de<br />

l’architecture sociale et de l’économie générale de la société. Les sociétés<br />

libérales se sont toujours cachées derrière l’illusion rassurante qu’offre la<br />

représentation parlementaire : l’exercice régulier du droit de vote n’est-il pas la<br />

preuve la plus tangible, le signe le plus irrévocable de la citoyenneté ? Rien<br />

n’est moins clair aujourd’hui alors que le processus électoral se confond bien<br />

souvent avec pratique civique ritualisée, passive et sans substance. Le système<br />

électoral simule la citoyenneté; il ne permet pas l’engagement direct et critique<br />

de l’électorat au processus de formulation et de discussion des politiques<br />

publiques. Certes, le pluralisme bon teint dont se targuent les sociétés libérales<br />

offre l’image d’une démocratie sereine et enviable. Dans les faits, la<br />

consultation, par élection ou sondage, des citoyens participe de l’illusion<br />

démocratique. Non seulement reconduit-elle, quelle que soit sa forme, le<br />

système socio-politique dans toute sa conformité, jamais elle ne fait vraiment<br />

participer le citoyen. Spectacles orchestrés par des élites socio-économiques<br />

qui ne cherchent qu’à assurer leur propre dominance sociale et politique, ces<br />

coups de sonde ne servent plus qu’à entretenir l’impression de la démocratie<br />

auprès de populations repoussées à la marge et que l’on entend surtout<br />

maintenir là. Et ainsi se reproduit le cercle vicieux du désengagement politique<br />

: éventuellement persuadées qu’il leur est impossible d’agir sur le système, ces<br />

populations ne voient plus l’utilité de s’informer et de revoir la légitimité du<br />

système; leur apathie et leur ignorance confirment en bout de piste l’idée<br />

qu’entretiennent les élites politiques au sujet de l’incapacité du peuple à se<br />

gouverner lui-même (Lyon, 1992 : 125).<br />

Au Canada, fédéralisme et démocratie sont généralement associés. On sait<br />

aujourd’hui que l’un n’est pas garant de l’autre (Whitaker, 1992) et qu’ici, ils<br />

ne l’ont jamais été. Pourtant, l’on persiste à penser que le fédéralisme à la<br />

canadienne est porteur de démocratie. <strong>La</strong> crise constitutionnelle actuelle<br />

reflète en gr<strong>and</strong>e partie l’insatisfaction croissante face à la nature même du<br />

régime démocratique que prétend être le fédéralisme canadien. <strong>La</strong> gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

problématique qui ressort des différentes consultations relatives à la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> porte dans presque tous les cas sur l’inadéquation ressentie par les<br />

individus, les groupes ou les associations des mécanismes de représentation et<br />

d’inclusion dans les processus décisionnels. Que ce soit pour des questions de<br />

représentativité territoriale, ethnique, linguistique, sociale, économique ou<br />

sexuelle, les doléances de tous et chacun témoignent de l’incapacité du<br />

fédéralisme canadien et des institutions parlementaires qui le soutiennent<br />

d’assurer une place et un rôle équivalents dans la formulation des politiques<br />

179


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

publiques et des décisions politico-administratives qui influent sur la vie des<br />

citoyens.<br />

À certains égards, le processus de fragmentation du tissu social et la tendance<br />

vraisemblablement irrévocable à la personnalisation du social (Lipovetsky,<br />

1983) qui caractérisent la dynamique sociétale de cette fin de siècle sonnent le<br />

glas des institutions politiques traditionnelles. L’emprise croissante sur le<br />

discours politique des revendications en faveur des droits individuels et la<br />

multiplication des regroupements d’êtres identiques pour la reconnaissance<br />

publique de leur différence ou simplement pour partager leur vécu rend<br />

obsolète un système politique comme celui du Canada, attaché qu’il reste à<br />

l’idée d’un État territorial souverain et centralisé.<br />

Dans un tel contexte de transformation des valeurs, des normes et des<br />

paramètres de la vie sociale, le système politique devient inapte à répondre aux<br />

exigences et aux attentes d’une partie croissante de la population. Au Canada,<br />

cela se vérifie d’autant plus que la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 a donné voix<br />

aux chapitre aux groupes et aux individus qui avaient été historiquement<br />

exclus du processus politique. Forts de la caution juridique que leur offre la<br />

<strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés, ceux-ci exigent plus que jamais la<br />

reconnaissance de leur différence et de leur particularité, exerçant du même<br />

coup des pressions auxquelles ni le système politique ni les élites ne peuvent<br />

donner suite (Cairns, 1988; Rocher et Salée, 1991; Whitaker, 1992). Force est<br />

de constater que la structure institutionnelle et administrative du fédéralisme<br />

canadien est en train de céder parce qu’elle est de plus en plus inapte à combler<br />

les aspirations démocratiques suscitées à la fois par la nouvelle donne imposée<br />

par la <strong>Charte</strong>, le mouvement général de personnalisation du social et la<br />

redéfinition concomitante de la citoyenneté.<br />

<strong>La</strong> tradition théorique qui anime le système politique canadien (c’est celle en<br />

fait sur laquelle se fonde toute la conceptualisation de l’organisation politique<br />

en Occident et qui puise dans la pensée des Bodin, Hobbes et Machiavel) est<br />

ancrée dans la conviction que la fonction de régie (governance) est l’objet<br />

privilégié du politique. Suivant cette optique, l’élaboration de projets de<br />

société passe d’abord par la mise au point des mécanismes de régie; les<br />

impératifs de la raison d’État conditionnent et stabilisent la société. Or, vivre la<br />

démocratie en ces temps de fragmentation sociale, c’est tenter de dépasser<br />

cette vision du politique qui n’a de sens finalement qu’en contexte de gr<strong>and</strong>e<br />

homogénéité sociale. Vivre la démocratie, c’est tenter de réorganiser la société<br />

non plus en fonction du pouvoir de l’État et d’un idéal institutionnel et<br />

instrumental, mais bien en fonction de la société elle-même, c’est-à-dire des<br />

réalités multiples et variées qui la composent et des volontés d’autonomie qui<br />

la traversent (Hueglin, 1992). Ces questions n’ont malheureusement pas<br />

alimenté le débat sur le nécessaire arrimage entre la transformation de la<br />

pratique démocratique et la transformation des mécanismes de négociations<br />

constitutionnelles au cours des dernières années.<br />

On peut d’ailleurs se permettre d’être sceptique quant à la possibilité<br />

d’enregistrer à plus ou moins long terme quelque progrès à cet égard , tant et<br />

aussi longtemps que l’on continuera d’agir à l’intérieur des mécanismes<br />

institutionnels actuels.<br />

Au-delà des raisons particulières et souvent partisanes qui ont poussé une<br />

majorité de Canadiens à rejeter l’entente de Charlottetown, l’issue du<br />

référendum d’octobre 1992 traduit aussi un désaccord populaire assez profond<br />

face au processus même de révision constitutionnelle, un certain cynisme<br />

180


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

quant au potentiel de développement démocratique qu’aurait pu contenir une<br />

telle révision, de même qu’un désenchantement à peine voilé face à la classe<br />

politique canadienne. Il serait étonnant que le débat constitutionnel soit<br />

rouvert dans un avenir rapproché. Les tribulations constitutionnelles et<br />

référendaires des dernières années ont conduit à l’écoeurement politique des<br />

Canadiens qui, à court terme tout au moins, refuseront de s’interroger<br />

sérieusement à propos de leur système politique ou des tenants et aboutissants<br />

de la démocratie. En attendant, le problème reste entier.<br />

En dernière analyse, ce que démontre le rejet de l’entente de Charlottetown et,<br />

avant cela, l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech, c’est bien l’épuisement, voire la<br />

faillite, du modèle traditionnel des relations fédérales-provinciales pour<br />

solutionner les problèmes inhérents à la dynamique de la société civile. Il y a<br />

peut-être là un mal pour un bien. <strong>La</strong> défaite référendaire vient en quelque sorte<br />

confirmer ce qu’Alan Cairns a si finement identifié comme la nonconcordance,<br />

provoquée par la constitutionnalisation de la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne<br />

des droits et libertés, entre deux logiques contradictoires : celle des citoyens<br />

désormais détenteurs de droits et drapés de prétention multiples et<br />

polymorphes à la différence; et celle des gouvernements, gestionnaires<br />

historiques et souverains de l’expression des droits individuels et des<br />

revendications communautaires. Ces deux logiques comm<strong>and</strong>ent des<br />

mécanismes institutionnels opposés et, somme toute, irréconciliables (Cairns,<br />

1992b). Le drame de l’histoire constitutionnelle canadienne récente tient dans<br />

cet entêtement à arrimer l’une et l’autre logique, et même parfois la tentation<br />

d’imposer l’une à l’autre. Le référendum de 1992 enseigne finalement que cet<br />

arrimage est impossible et qu’il faut chercher ailleurs.<br />

<strong>La</strong> question demeure ouverte : où chercher ? <strong>La</strong> forme et la cohérence<br />

institutionnelle de l’État participent toujours plus ou moins des modulations<br />

particulières de la société civile, bien que dans certaines conjonctures<br />

historiques, il arrive que l’État imprime à celle-ci ses propres paramètres. En<br />

instaurant une mouvance politique désormais fondée sur les droits, la réforme<br />

constitutionnelle de 1982 a remis en quelque sorte la société civile à l’avantscène.<br />

<strong>La</strong> dynamique politique s’accomplit de plus en plus dans l’interface<br />

entre des citoyens parés de leurs droits distinctifs, individuels et<br />

collectifs—droits des femmes contre ceux des hommes, droits des<br />

Autochtonnes et des minorités visibles contre ceux de la majorité blanche.<br />

C’est dans ce registre nouveau et inhabituel pour la culture politique<br />

canadienne que s’expriment maintenant les prétentions à la citoyenneté et que<br />

d’aucuns entendent jeter les fondations d’une démocratie élargie, inclusive,<br />

cherchant à équilibrer la reconnaissance des droits individuels universels à la<br />

nécessaire reconnaissance des particularismes.<br />

Tout n’est pas réglé pour autant. Si l’échec référendaire a démontré les limites<br />

de l’hégémonie institutionnelle du fédéralisme canadien et annoncé la<br />

réaffirmation de la société civile, cela ne garantit pas une redéfinition<br />

institutionnelle idéale exempte de conflits. Dans le contexte actuel où les droits<br />

individuels dominent de plus en plus le discours politique, l’unanimité devient<br />

presque impossible, puisque tout est contestable et qu’il n’existe plus de<br />

rationalité unique et universelle.<br />

Pour certains, le processus de personnalisation, évoqué plus haut, constitue un<br />

premier pas vers le renouveau démocratique des sociétés occidentales, la<br />

garantie de l’essentielle remise en question des consensus (Lipovetsky, 1983 :<br />

183 et sq.). Certes, on peut espérer, à la façon de certains philosophes libéraux<br />

181


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

communautariens, que, puisque la production de l’identité subjective résulte<br />

du désir humain de reconnaissance par les autres, et donc d’un nécessaire<br />

dialogue, le respect des identités individuelles et des différences débouche sur<br />

une société inévitablement plus démocratique où chacun est ouvert à l’autre,<br />

où les identités individuelles s’épanouissent par le dialogue collectif et une<br />

conception unanimement partagée de la communauté (Taylor, 1992).<br />

Dans la réalité, la glorification actuelle des droits individuels et l’obsession<br />

juridique qui l’alimente reposent sur une vision atomiste du social — vision<br />

décriée avec conviction par les philosophes communautariens, Taylor en tête<br />

— où chaque être est une île autosuffisante qui ne doit rien à la communauté.<br />

Dans un tel contexte, le dialogue est forcément, et plus souvent qu’autrement,<br />

un dialogue de sourds. Une juriste américaine observait récemment qu’aux<br />

États-Unis, la primauté accordée aux droits individuels dans le discours<br />

politique avait conduit à une situation qui<br />

in its absoluteness, promotes unrealistic expectations, heightens<br />

social conflict, <strong>and</strong> inhibits dialogue that might lead toward<br />

consensus, accommodation, or at least <strong>the</strong> discovery of common<br />

ground. In its silence concerning responsibilities, [rights talk] seems<br />

to condone acceptance of <strong>the</strong> benefits of living in a democratic social<br />

welfare state, without accepting <strong>the</strong> corresponding personal <strong>and</strong> civic<br />

obligations. In its relentless individualism, it fosters a climate that is<br />

inhospitable to society’s losers, <strong>and</strong> that systematically<br />

disadvantages caretakers <strong>and</strong> dependents, young <strong>and</strong> old (...). We<br />

make it difficult for persons <strong>and</strong> groups with conflicting interests <strong>and</strong><br />

views to build a coalition <strong>and</strong> achieve compromise, or even to acquire<br />

that minimal degree of mutual forbearance <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing that<br />

promotes peaceful coexistence <strong>and</strong> keeps <strong>the</strong> door open to fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

communication (Glendon, 1991 : 14-15).<br />

Sans doute que le Canada n’en est pas rendu là. Mais comme le donne à penser<br />

le rejet de l’entente de Charlottetown, l’incapacité à définir les conditions<br />

minimales de coexistence des identités plurielles laisse croire que le processus<br />

est déjà bien amorcé.<br />

Comme nous l’avons indiqué plus haut, seule la reviviscence des liens<br />

fondamentaux de solidarité communautaire et de réciprocité peut stopper ce<br />

glissement. Mais entre pareille exhortation normative et la réalité, un fossé<br />

semble se creuser dont personne ne peut prédire l’ampleur, ni même s’il ira en<br />

s’élargissant. Tout dépendra de la dynamique sociétale que les Canadiens se<br />

forgeront.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Nous tenons à remercier Michel Sarra-Bournet qui nous a assistés dans la phase préliminaire<br />

de la recherche.<br />

Bibliographie<br />

Barrie, Doreen (1988), « Who Spoke for Canada ? » dans Roger Gibbins (dir.), Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong><br />

Canada. Perspectives from <strong>the</strong> West, Edmonton, Academic Printing <strong>and</strong> Publishing,<br />

pp. 143-146.<br />

Behiels, Michael D., (dir.), (1989), <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer. Conflicting Views on <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord, Ottawa, Presses de l’Université d’Ottawa.<br />

182


Démocratie et réforme constitutionnelle :<br />

discours et pratique<br />

Breton, Gilles et Jane Jenson (1991), « After Free Trade <strong>and</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: Quoi de neuf ? »,<br />

Studies in Political Economy, n o 34, Spring, pp. 199-218.<br />

Brock, Kathy L. (1991), « <strong>The</strong> Politics of Process » dans Douglas M. Brown, (dir.), Canada: <strong>The</strong><br />

State of <strong>the</strong> Federation 1991, Kingston, Institut des relations intergouvernementales, pp. 57-<br />

87.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. (1988), « Citizens (Outsiders) <strong>and</strong> Governments (Insiders) in <strong>Constitution</strong>-<br />

Making: <strong>The</strong> Case of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke », Canadian Public Policy, vol. 15, september, pp. S121-<br />

S145.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. (1991), « <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, Interest Groups, Executive <strong>Federalism</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Reform » dans David E. Smith et al., After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke. Lessons for <strong>the</strong> Future, Saskatoon,<br />

Fifth House, pp. 13-31.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. (1992a), <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al World We Have Lost, communication présentée au<br />

congrès annuel de l’Association canadienne de science politique, Charlottetown, University<br />

of Prince Edward Isl<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. (1992b), <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Versus <strong>Federalism</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Dilemmas of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform,<br />

Montréal et Kingston, Mc-Gill-Queen’s University Press.<br />

Canada (1987), Procès-verbaux et témoignages du Comité mixte spécial du Sénat et de la<br />

Chambre des communes de L’entente constitutionnelle de 1987, Ottawa, 17 fascicules.<br />

Canada (1991a), Procès-verbaux et témoignages du Comité mixte spécial du Sénat et de la<br />

Chambre des communes sur le Processus de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada,<br />

Ottawa, 34 fascicules.<br />

Canada (1991b), Le processus de modification de la <strong>Constitution</strong>, Rapport du comité mixte spécial<br />

du Sénat et de la Chambre des communes, Ottawa.<br />

Canada (1992), Procès-verbaux et témoignages du Comité mixte spécial sur Le renouvellement du<br />

Canada, Ottawa, 65 fascicules.<br />

Dobell, Peter et Byron Berry (1992), « <strong>La</strong> colère à l’égard du régime : mécontentement politique<br />

au Canada », Le gouvernement parlementaire, n o 39, janvier, pp. 3-22.<br />

Doyal, Len et Ian Gough (1991), A <strong>The</strong>ory of Human Need, New York, <strong>The</strong> Guilford Press.<br />

Fortin, Sarah (1992), Le discours démocratique et l’enjeu constitutionnel, Montréal, inédit.<br />

Glendon, Mary Ann (1991), Rights Talk. <strong>The</strong> Impoverishment of Political Discourse, New York,<br />

Free Press.<br />

Guttman, Amy, dir., (1988), Democracy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Welfare State, Princeton, Princeton University<br />

Press.<br />

Maillé, Chantal (1992), <strong>La</strong> réforme constitutionnelle pensée dans une perspective féministe :<br />

quelques remarques préliminaires à un débat à venir, communication présentée à<br />

l’Association canadienne droit et société, Congrès des sociétés savantes, Charlottetown.<br />

McLellan, A. Anne (1992), « Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Process of <strong>Constitution</strong>-Making » dans D.<br />

Schneiderman (dir.), Conversations. Among Friends « » Entre Amies, Proceedings of an<br />

Interdisciplinary Conference on Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform, Edmonton, Centre for<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies, Alberta <strong>La</strong>w Fondation, pp. 9-13.<br />

Gould, Carol C. (1988), Rethinking Democracy. Freedom <strong>and</strong> Social Cooperation in Politics,<br />

Economy, <strong>and</strong> Society, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.<br />

Hueglin, Thomas (1992), « Have We Studied <strong>the</strong> Wrong Authors? On <strong>the</strong> Relevance of Johannes<br />

Althusius », Studies in Political Thought, vol. 1, n o 1, Winter, pp. 75-93.<br />

Jenson, Jane (1992), Citizenship Claims: Routes to Representation in a Federal System, paper<br />

presented for <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nation State Conference, Centre for International Studies,<br />

University of Toronto, June.<br />

<strong>La</strong>bica, Georges (1992), « Pour une nouvelle rationalité politique » dans Boismenu et al.(dir.), Les<br />

formes modernes de la démocratie, Montréal et Paris, Presses de l’Université de Montréal et<br />

L’Harmattan, pp. 53-65.<br />

Lipietz, Alain (1992), « Bases pour une alternative démocratique », dans Boismenu et al., (dir.),<br />

Les formes modernes de la démocratie, Montréal et Paris, Presses de l’Université de<br />

Montréal et L’Harmattan, pp. 275-296.<br />

Lipovetsky, Gilles (1983), L’ère du vide. Essais sur l’individualisme contemporain, Paris,<br />

Gallimard.<br />

Lyon, Vaughan (1992), « Stalemated Democracy—<strong>the</strong> Canadian Case », Revue d’études<br />

canadiennes, vol. 26, n o 3, pp. 120-139.<br />

Mouffe, Chantal (1992a), « Penser la démocratie moderne avec, et contre, Carl Schmitt », Revue<br />

française de science politique, vol. 42, n o 1 février, pp. 83-96.<br />

Mouffe, Chantal (1992b), Dimensions of Radical Democracy. Pluralism, Citizenship,<br />

Community, Londres, Verso.<br />

Panitch, Leo (1991), « Démocratie et <strong>Constitution</strong> », Le gouvernement parlementaire, vol. 10,<br />

n o 1, pp. 19-20.<br />

Rocher, François et Daniel Salée (1991), « <strong>Charte</strong> et société : vers un nouvel ordre politique<br />

canadien ? », Revue québécoise de science politique, n o 20, automne, pp. 35-64.<br />

Silipo, Tony (1991), « S’ouvrir aux nouvelles réalités », Le gouvernement parlementaire, vol. 10,<br />

n o 1, pp. 11-13.<br />

183


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Smith, Jennifer (1991), « Representation <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform in Canada » dans David E.<br />

Smith et al., After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke. Lessons for <strong>the</strong> Future, Saskatoon, Fifth House, pp. 69-82.<br />

Taylor, Charles (1992), Multiculturalism <strong>and</strong> “<strong>The</strong> Politics of Recognition”, Princeton, N.J.,<br />

Princeton University Press.<br />

Whitaker, Reg (1992), A Sovereign Idea. Essays on Canada as a Democratic Community,<br />

Montréal et Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press.<br />

Young, Iris Marion (1990), « Polity <strong>and</strong> Group Difference: A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Ideal of Universal<br />

Citizenship » dans Cass R. Sunstein, (dir.), Feminism & Political <strong>The</strong>ory, Chicago,<br />

University of Chicago Press, pp. 117-141.<br />

184


Stephen McBride<br />

Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of<br />

Competitiveness: Liberal Political Economy <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> *<br />

Abstract<br />

This article examines attempts by Canada’s Conservative government to<br />

introduce proposals based on <strong>the</strong> principles of liberal political economy into a<br />

constitutional renewal process driven by o<strong>the</strong>r issues. From <strong>the</strong> viewpoint of<br />

liberal political economy, a suitably renewed <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> federal system<br />

could serve as an instrument of economic success <strong>and</strong> competitiveness. <strong>The</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>the</strong> government’s 1991 constitutional proposals, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord are analyzed. <strong>The</strong> article concludes that although<br />

Canada’s ongoing constitutional crisis provided an opportunity for <strong>the</strong><br />

introduction of this type of constitutional proposal, o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of Canada’s<br />

political system—political culture <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal system itself—have<br />

obstructed <strong>the</strong> government’s agenda. <strong>The</strong> rejection of Charlottetown was, in<br />

this respect, less decisive than <strong>the</strong> dilution of <strong>the</strong> government’s proposals that<br />

had occurred earlier in <strong>the</strong> process.<br />

Résumé<br />

Cet article porte sur les tentatives du gouvernement conservateur canadien de<br />

profiter du processus de révision de la <strong>Constitution</strong> pour faire adopter des<br />

propositions fondées sur les principes de l’économie politique libérale. Dans<br />

l’optique de cette dernière, un renouvellement efficace de la <strong>Constitution</strong> et du<br />

régime fédéral pouvait favoriser l’essor et le compétitivité du pays. Après<br />

avoir passé en revue l’Accord du lac Meech, les propositions<br />

constitutionnelles de 1991 ainsi que l’Accord de Charlottetown, l’auteur en<br />

arrive à la conclusion que le débat constitutionnel en cours offrait<br />

manifestement une bonne occasion de soumettre un tel projet, mais d’autres<br />

aspects de la situation politique canadienne — la culture politique et le régime<br />

fédéral lui-même — ont fait avorter le programme gouvernemental. Le rejet de<br />

l’Accord de Charlottetown a été moins déterminant que les modifications qu’il<br />

a subies au cours des négociations antérieures.<br />

Liberal Political Economy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> Keynesian era has stimulated a renewed interest in <strong>the</strong><br />

connection between economic doctrines <strong>and</strong> political programs. <strong>The</strong><br />

conservative, or neo-conservative, political parties that have benefited from<br />

Keynesianism’s failure to deal with <strong>the</strong> problems created by an increasingly<br />

internationalized economy have become much more doctrinaire organizations<br />

than <strong>the</strong>ir pragmatic predecessors of <strong>the</strong> 1950s <strong>and</strong> 1960s. Despite <strong>the</strong> neo-<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

conservative label, however, <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>the</strong>y espouse consists of a<br />

refurbished version of classical liberal political economy.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a large literature on <strong>the</strong> policy agenda of various neo-conservative<br />

governments. Much has been written on <strong>the</strong> policy impact of <strong>the</strong> economic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory which inspires <strong>the</strong>se parties. Thatcher’s Britain <strong>and</strong> Reagan’s America<br />

are seen as laboratories in which liberal political economy has been applied.<br />

Perhaps because of <strong>the</strong> emphasis on <strong>the</strong>se two countries, much less has been<br />

written about <strong>the</strong> constitutional impact of liberal political economy; nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Mrs. Thatcher nor Mr. Reagan were great constitutional innovators. Nor were<br />

<strong>the</strong>y leaders of countries in which constitutional politics plays a great role.<br />

Yet liberal political economy has much to say about <strong>the</strong> “good constitution”<br />

<strong>and</strong> its potential role in facilitating such economic ends as competitiveness. In<br />

Canada, which has been in <strong>the</strong> throes of constitutional crisis <strong>and</strong> debate for<br />

quite some time, a greater opportunity existed to take action on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>. Canada’s own neo-conservatives may have had to play second<br />

fiddle to <strong>the</strong>ir more renowned foreign cousins in many areas, but in attempting<br />

to constitutionalize <strong>the</strong> principles of liberal political economy <strong>the</strong>y have been<br />

in <strong>the</strong> vanguard. This article explores <strong>the</strong>ir efforts.<br />

Liberal political economy’s response to economic globalization <strong>and</strong><br />

intensifying competitive pressures is to downsize <strong>the</strong> state <strong>and</strong> liberate market<br />

forces from its regulatory constraints. Restraint <strong>and</strong> retrenchment of state<br />

activity can, of course, be accomplished without constitutional change. <strong>The</strong><br />

role of <strong>the</strong> state may simply be reduced by normal political processes.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>re is a corresponding danger that such processes will, in a later<br />

period, lead to an expansion of <strong>the</strong> state’s role—thus reversing <strong>the</strong> neoconservative<br />

revolution. Hence, <strong>the</strong> possibility of rendering <strong>the</strong> neoconservative<br />

assault on <strong>the</strong> state’s role permanent, through constitutional<br />

change, has its attractions.<br />

A number of analysts have noted <strong>the</strong> challenge posed for all nation-states by<br />

<strong>the</strong> growing power of transnational corporations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> markets in which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

operate (eg. Simeon 1991:47-9). And, in light of Canada’s free trade solution<br />

to <strong>the</strong>se pressures, it is worth noting <strong>the</strong> widespread perception that North<br />

American integration <strong>and</strong> Canadian disintegration are directly correlated (eg.<br />

Simeon 1991:51; <strong>and</strong> Watkins quoted in Norman, 1991:27). <strong>The</strong> impact of<br />

globalization on Canada’s political system has increased <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

strains generated by Canada’s internal <strong>and</strong> idiosyncratic cleavages based on<br />

language <strong>and</strong> region.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> institutional arrangements of <strong>the</strong> country are unsettled<br />

has provided an opportunity for Canadian neo-conservatives that has been<br />

denied <strong>the</strong>ir colleagues in o<strong>the</strong>r countries. Even though <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

constitutional change itself has been driven by a different agenda, expressed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> discourse of Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s, provincial powers, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dissatisfaction<br />

of regions, it has been possible for neo-conservatives to initiate constitutional<br />

reforms that reflect <strong>the</strong>ir political <strong>and</strong> economic agenda.<br />

Indeed, according to Jenson (1989, 1990), <strong>the</strong> connection between <strong>the</strong> two<br />

constitutional agendas may be more intimate than suggested by this<br />

discussion. This is because “<strong>the</strong> paradigm which helped to stabilize <strong>the</strong> fordist<br />

mode of regulation in Canada after World War II was organized around<br />

national identities... <strong>The</strong> social compromises <strong>and</strong> institutionalized<br />

relationships of <strong>the</strong> welfare state were rationalized in terms of <strong>the</strong> needs of <strong>the</strong><br />

188


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

whole nation <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong> federal system. <strong>The</strong>refore, when <strong>the</strong> fordist paradigm<br />

began to dissolve, it would do so around <strong>the</strong> issues of national existence <strong>and</strong><br />

proper state forms” (Jenson 1989:84). This is not <strong>the</strong> place to explore this<br />

insight in great depth, but <strong>the</strong>re is certainly a conjunction between <strong>the</strong><br />

development of a crisis in Canada’s institutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> opportunity to use <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> to bind <strong>the</strong> state to a role consistent with neo-conservative ends.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se ends include reducing <strong>the</strong> role of government generally, <strong>and</strong> in<br />

particular <strong>the</strong> welfare state (Marchak 1991: Chapter 5; Shields 1990; Whitaker<br />

1987), although students of actually existing neo-conservative governments<br />

have noted a tendency to condemn <strong>the</strong> state in <strong>the</strong>ory while simultaneously<br />

relying on a strong state in certain spheres of state activity. Given <strong>the</strong>se<br />

ambiguities, is it possible to identify a body of neo-conservative constitutional<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory which might serve as a benchmark in evaluating <strong>the</strong> Mulroney<br />

government’s constitutional initiatives?<br />

Three <strong>the</strong>mes may be emphasized. First, <strong>the</strong>re is a genuine desire to confine <strong>the</strong><br />

state to a much more restricted sphere of intervention in <strong>the</strong> economy <strong>and</strong><br />

social policy. While this might be accomplished by normal political activity, it<br />

is also possible to restrict <strong>the</strong> state’s role by constitutional provisions. By<br />

prohibiting <strong>the</strong> state from certain activities it can also be insulated from<br />

democratic pressures—a goal some have attributed to liberal political<br />

economy (Shields 1990:162). Second, however, <strong>the</strong> state must be sufficiently<br />

strong to confront <strong>and</strong> defeat <strong>the</strong> special interests that can be expected to<br />

defend <strong>the</strong> welfare state, to police <strong>and</strong> protect <strong>the</strong> market order, <strong>and</strong> to uphold<br />

authority in society. Finally, in federal political systems we may not find a<br />

permanent <strong>the</strong>oretical position in favour of assigning powers to a particular<br />

level of government, but in practice decentralization will be viewed in most<br />

cases as more likely to lead to “less government in general <strong>and</strong> less<br />

redistributive activity in particular” (Boadway 1992:3).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se guidelines provide a profile of <strong>the</strong> constitutional preferences of liberal<br />

political economy. How are <strong>the</strong>se preferences connected to <strong>the</strong> basic economic<br />

strategy favoured by Canadian neo-conservatives? What kinds of specific<br />

constitutional proposals emerge from <strong>the</strong> conjunction of economic <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional preferences?<br />

<strong>The</strong> interplay of economic strategies <strong>and</strong> constitutional preferences has been<br />

most comprehensively analyzed by Peter Leslie (1987: especially Chapter 9)<br />

who outlines <strong>the</strong> constitutional <strong>and</strong> political implications of three potential<br />

economic strategies. In one of <strong>the</strong>se, which he terms <strong>the</strong> liberal-continentalist<br />

option, minimal government intervention occurs <strong>and</strong> continental free trade<br />

obtains. It is <strong>the</strong> strategy recommended by <strong>the</strong> Macdonald Commission <strong>and</strong>, in<br />

broad terms, adopted by <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government. What are <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional correlates of this option?<br />

Although liberal political economy generally favours a reduced role for <strong>the</strong><br />

state in <strong>the</strong> economy <strong>and</strong> in social policy, it is often necessary to assign matters<br />

to one or o<strong>the</strong>r level of government given <strong>the</strong> constitutional principle of <strong>the</strong><br />

supremacy of Parliament. In general this will lead to a preference for a<br />

decentralization of powers to <strong>the</strong> provinces. An alternative approach would be<br />

to exp<strong>and</strong> those elements in <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> which prohibit ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

order of government from undertaking certain activities. One might <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

look for some combination of limits on federal powers <strong>and</strong> transfer of<br />

jurisdictions to <strong>the</strong> provinces. Through decentralization <strong>and</strong> deference to <strong>the</strong><br />

market, <strong>the</strong> ideal of a limited <strong>and</strong> constrained state might be approximated.<br />

189


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

However, Leslie (1987:167-70) notes that even <strong>the</strong> liberal-continentalist<br />

option requires a strong state: “<strong>the</strong> market-enhancing policies advocated by<br />

<strong>the</strong> [Macdonald] commission are anything but anodyne in <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional<br />

effects. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>y dem<strong>and</strong> more extensive limitations on provincial powers<br />

than anything proposed by <strong>the</strong> federal government during <strong>the</strong> [earlier<br />

constitutional] negotiations” (Leslie 1987:24). For example, <strong>the</strong> divided<br />

jurisdiction over fiscal policy that is involved in any federal system of<br />

government opens <strong>the</strong> possibility that one level of government may use its<br />

fiscal powers to offset initiatives taken by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. If a low tax <strong>and</strong> low<br />

spending policy is to prevail, some form of coordination would seem<br />

necessary. Similarly, for a truly free market to exist in Canada, a more<br />

complete economic union than that guaranteed by Section 121 of <strong>the</strong> British<br />

North America Act is necessary. Section 121 has not prevented <strong>the</strong> creation of<br />

barriers to interprovincial trade by both levels of government. Striking down<br />

such obstacles seems to require streng<strong>the</strong>ned national institutions. Finally, <strong>the</strong><br />

Macdonald Commission anticipated that <strong>the</strong> federal government’s lack of a<br />

treaty implementation power, where treaties touched areas of provincial<br />

jurisdiction, might make problematic <strong>the</strong> implementation of continental free<br />

trade with <strong>the</strong> United States (see Leslie 1987:108-9).<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> constitutional program of liberal political economy might include a<br />

general predeliction to weaken <strong>the</strong> powers of <strong>the</strong> central government,<br />

especially as far as economic <strong>and</strong> social intervention are concerned, toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

with a selective streng<strong>the</strong>ning of <strong>the</strong> federal government’s ability to overcome<br />

interventionism by <strong>the</strong> provinces. One might expect also some reliance upon<br />

<strong>the</strong> American connection, as manifested in <strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement, to<br />

provide strong state support for a free market economy should domestic<br />

politics in Canada deny it. Among <strong>the</strong> chief supporters of such an agenda have<br />

been <strong>the</strong> business community, especially as represented by <strong>the</strong> Business<br />

Council on National Issues, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> mainstream of <strong>the</strong> economics profession,<br />

many of whose ideas found expression in <strong>the</strong> report of <strong>the</strong> Macdonald Royal<br />

Commission (Simeon 1987; Carmichael, Dobson, Lipsey 1986). O<strong>the</strong>r vocal<br />

supporters of <strong>the</strong> agenda include a range of think-tanks <strong>and</strong> research institutes<br />

associated with <strong>the</strong> business community (see, for example, Ernst 1992).<br />

Canadian Business <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>: Macdonald, Meech <strong>and</strong> Post-<br />

Meech<br />

<strong>The</strong> Macdonald Commission devoted most of <strong>the</strong> third volume of its report to<br />

political institutions <strong>and</strong> reforms to <strong>the</strong> political system. Many of its<br />

recommendations found <strong>the</strong>ir way, in one form or ano<strong>the</strong>r, into ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord or <strong>the</strong> federal government’s 1991 constitutional<br />

proposals, Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>The</strong> Macdonald Report (v.3,<br />

385-408) recommended Senate reform to enhance regional representation,<br />

recognition of <strong>the</strong> distinctive character of Quebec, a form of constitutional<br />

veto for Quebec, <strong>and</strong> opt-out rights with compensation to all provinces. <strong>The</strong><br />

existence of barriers within <strong>the</strong> Canadian economic union occupied <strong>the</strong><br />

attention of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> report called for an amendment to<br />

extend <strong>the</strong> provisions of Section 121 to include services, <strong>and</strong> for a Code of<br />

Economic Conduct to help eliminate non-tariff barriers to trade in goods <strong>and</strong><br />

services. An intergovernmental agency to police <strong>the</strong> economic union was<br />

proposed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commission foresaw that if a Code of Economic Conduct<br />

were eventually made legally enforceable it would become “a regulatory<br />

agency ... that regulates governments” (v.3:393). <strong>The</strong> Commission also<br />

190


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

recommended a constitutional amendment to make international treaties<br />

enforceable, even when <strong>the</strong>ir substance lay in areas of provincial jurisdiction,<br />

subject to <strong>the</strong> proviso that <strong>the</strong> relevant sections of <strong>the</strong> treaties be approved by<br />

<strong>the</strong> legislatures of seven provinces containing 50 percent of <strong>the</strong> population.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commission stopped short of recommending formal limitations on <strong>the</strong><br />

federal spending power, but felt its future use ought to be subject to conditions<br />

<strong>and</strong> guidelines.<br />

Some of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s thinking found its way into <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord. Both were supported by <strong>the</strong> Business Council (BCNI 1990). <strong>The</strong><br />

Accord’s demise, though regrettable to business among o<strong>the</strong>rs, did provide an<br />

opportunity to initiate a new constitutional round. It was widely conceded that<br />

<strong>the</strong> agenda in this—<strong>the</strong> Canada Round—would need to be broader than that of<br />

Meech. As a result one finds a more consistent expression of liberal political<br />

economy than had been possible in <strong>the</strong> Quebec round represented in Meech.<br />

<strong>The</strong> BCNI became more specific about <strong>the</strong> linkages between <strong>the</strong> economy <strong>and</strong><br />

political system, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ways in which <strong>the</strong> latter might be restructured to more<br />

adequately serve <strong>the</strong> former. “In <strong>the</strong> quest for competitiveness, <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

political system must be an ally <strong>and</strong> not an impediment. First <strong>and</strong> foremost, <strong>the</strong><br />

reforms to our federal system must ensure that <strong>the</strong> Canadian common market is<br />

established in fact <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> Canadian economic union is streng<strong>the</strong>ned. <strong>The</strong><br />

free movement of labour, capital, goods <strong>and</strong> services must be guaranteed under<br />

any new constitutional arrangement, <strong>and</strong> in this area, we see <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government having a streng<strong>the</strong>ned role” (Business Council on National Issues<br />

1991:8). This goal outweighed all o<strong>the</strong>rs in business’s mind. So while <strong>the</strong><br />

BCNI was prepared to countenance “meaningful decentralization or a reduced<br />

federal government role in fields assigned to <strong>the</strong> provinces under <strong>the</strong> current<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> or a revised <strong>Constitution</strong>,” this was subject to <strong>the</strong> proviso that<br />

“any decentralization must be accompanied by concrete arrangements to<br />

assure greater coordination or co-operation—o<strong>the</strong>rwise, <strong>the</strong> existing Canadian<br />

economic union, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> benefits it confers, will be threatened” (Business<br />

Council on National Issues 1992:24). Essentially <strong>the</strong> Business Council’s<br />

constitutional program consisted of contriving a new balance such that <strong>the</strong><br />

threat of Quebec separatism would be removed <strong>and</strong> a reformed federation,<br />

characterized by political stability, could function effectively <strong>and</strong> contribute to<br />

economic competitiveness <strong>and</strong> prosperity. A re-ordered division <strong>and</strong> sharing<br />

of powers was viewed as necessary to this end—but this by no means implied a<br />

wholesale decentralization of powers; in some areas, at least, enhanced federal<br />

power would result. To render this palatable to regional opinion, reform of<br />

federal institutions, including <strong>the</strong> Senate, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

development of new consultative procedures for federal-provincial<br />

communication, was necessary (Business Council on National Issues 1991).<br />

Clearly <strong>the</strong>se measures amount to a form of intra-state federalism.<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord was driven by <strong>the</strong> refusal of <strong>the</strong> Quebec government<br />

to endorse <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong>Constitution</strong>. A number of propitious circumstances in <strong>the</strong><br />

mid 1980s—<strong>the</strong> departure of Trudeau <strong>and</strong> Levesque, <strong>the</strong> election of a federal<br />

Conservative government pledged to national reconciliation <strong>and</strong> wishing to<br />

consolidate its new found electoral support in Quebec, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> election of a<br />

Liberal government in Quebec whose chief priority was to normalize <strong>the</strong><br />

position of <strong>the</strong> province (McRoberts 1988: Ch.11) explain why <strong>the</strong> attempt<br />

was made when it was.<br />

191


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

My own concern here, of course, is not with <strong>the</strong> Quebec issue or Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

per se, but with <strong>the</strong> opportunity which Canada’s unfinished constitutional<br />

agenda afforded for <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative view of <strong>the</strong> good <strong>Constitution</strong> to be<br />

implemented. <strong>The</strong> federal government sensed that success in “bringing<br />

Quebec back in,” a considerable political prize in its own right, would be<br />

enhanced to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong> agenda was limited (see Monahan 1991:50-4).<br />

This meant that it should be restricted, as far as possible, to <strong>the</strong> specific points<br />

raised by <strong>the</strong> Quebec government. For this reason it is unrealistic to search for<br />

<strong>the</strong> intrusion, into an already difficult set of negotiations, of an explicit<br />

commitment to <strong>the</strong> constitutional principles of liberal political economy. <strong>The</strong><br />

most that one can expect to find is a correspondence or consistency between<br />

<strong>the</strong> federal government’s position in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> its general<br />

ideology.<br />

Much of <strong>the</strong> fabric of Canada’s post-war welfare state was developed at federal<br />

initiative but in areas of provincial jurisdiction. <strong>The</strong> federal government’s<br />

spending power was used as an instrument to create shared-cost social<br />

programs. While <strong>the</strong> precise arrangements varied by program, a common<br />

feature was provincial delivery of <strong>the</strong> service, but with significant financial<br />

contribution from <strong>the</strong> federal government which, also, imposed conditions<br />

designed to produce national coherence in <strong>the</strong> programs.<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>the</strong> Government of Canada undertook to<br />

provide “reasonable compensation to <strong>the</strong> government of a province that<br />

chooses not to participate in a [new] national shared-cost program... in an area<br />

of exclusive provincial jurisdiction, if <strong>the</strong> province carries on a program or<br />

initiative that is compatible with national objectives.” <strong>The</strong> opposition to<br />

federal spending power had originated with Quebec <strong>and</strong> thus forms part of <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional constitutional agenda, based on language <strong>and</strong> territory. However,<br />

significant support existed among <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provinces for Quebec’s proposal<br />

to limit <strong>the</strong> spending power. Some of <strong>the</strong>m had argued for years that Ottawa’s<br />

social policy initiatives distorted provincial priorities <strong>and</strong> that, in an era of<br />

fiscal restraint, <strong>the</strong> federal government had become an unreliable financial<br />

partner. Once established, social programs were politically difficult to<br />

terminate. As <strong>the</strong> federal government pared back its financial support, <strong>the</strong><br />

provinces were left to sustain some very expensive programs. Quebec,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore, could rely on considerable support, from o<strong>the</strong>r provinces on this<br />

issue. Some of this support came from provinces in which neo-conservative<br />

thinking was influential, such as Alberta <strong>and</strong> British Columbia, <strong>and</strong> which had<br />

been in <strong>the</strong> forefront of dem<strong>and</strong>s for constitutional change. 1 What was new in<br />

<strong>the</strong> mid-1980s was <strong>the</strong> hostility of <strong>the</strong> federal government to <strong>the</strong> nationbuilding<br />

<strong>and</strong> social reform agenda that <strong>the</strong> spending power had promoted. This<br />

meant that <strong>the</strong> provinces’ dem<strong>and</strong>s met little resistance. <strong>The</strong>re was thus a<br />

conjunction of interest between those whose <strong>the</strong>ory of federalism was based on<br />

<strong>the</strong> claims of language <strong>and</strong> territory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative desire, on <strong>the</strong><br />

part of both federal <strong>and</strong> some provincial governments, to reduce <strong>the</strong> state’s role<br />

in economic <strong>and</strong> social policy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> linkage between <strong>the</strong> Accord’s provisions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> preferences of liberal<br />

political economy was drawn most clearly by those opposed to Meech. Coyne<br />

(1989:246-8) argued that <strong>the</strong> ability to opt-out of future national programs,<br />

without financial disincentive, would erode Ottawa’s ability to build a national<br />

identity based on relatively st<strong>and</strong>ardized access to social provision. When<br />

combined with o<strong>the</strong>r provisions in <strong>the</strong> Accord, she considered that <strong>the</strong> effect<br />

“involves a substantial devolution of power to <strong>the</strong> provinces <strong>and</strong> significant<br />

192


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

shift of political dynamism on matters of national importance away from <strong>the</strong><br />

federal Parliament, as well as undermining <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Freedoms” (247).<br />

Probably <strong>the</strong> most controversial item in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord was <strong>the</strong><br />

inclusion in <strong>the</strong> constitutional draft of an interpretive clause recognizing<br />

Quebec as a distinct society. Since this article concerns <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative<br />

agenda that is driven largely by <strong>the</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> social values expressed in<br />

liberal political economy, while <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause addresses <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional linguistic cleavage in Canadian federalism, <strong>the</strong> debate need not<br />

detain us unduly.<br />

<strong>The</strong> neo-conservatives conditional preference for a decentralized federation<br />

may have played a minor role in rendering asymetrical arrangements palatable<br />

to <strong>the</strong>m, in a way that <strong>the</strong>y never were for <strong>the</strong> nationally-focused Trudeau<br />

Liberals. However, <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government’s prime motivation was probably<br />

to be found in <strong>the</strong> political <strong>and</strong> partisan imperatives of building a coalition<br />

between Western provincialists <strong>and</strong> Quebec nationalists. O<strong>the</strong>r elements of <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech package appear to demonstrate <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>and</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> “all<br />

provinces are equal” doctrine. In making <strong>the</strong>se concessions to provincial<br />

pressure, neo-conservative tolerance for a decentralized federation is probably<br />

of greater significance; quite simply, <strong>the</strong>re were few purposes for which neoconservatives<br />

required a strong national government (though <strong>the</strong>re were<br />

some), <strong>and</strong> many uses to which a strong national government could be put that<br />

were inimical to <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative project.<br />

This interpretation of Meech is reinforced when it is considered in t<strong>and</strong>em with<br />

<strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement. <strong>The</strong> connection between <strong>the</strong> two has been<br />

forcefully expressed by Simeon (1989:4-6): “<strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement is far<br />

more significant a restraint on governments in general than Meech <strong>La</strong>ke is, <strong>and</strong><br />

more of a restraint on <strong>the</strong> federal government than it is on <strong>the</strong> provinces ... each<br />

does have this one element underlying it: a sense of <strong>the</strong> need to limit <strong>and</strong><br />

constrain <strong>the</strong> state in <strong>the</strong> modern era...one can at least make <strong>the</strong> argument that<br />

both in <strong>the</strong> long-run are likely to increase domestic fragmentation <strong>and</strong> certainly<br />

to inhibit a strong nation-building policy led by <strong>the</strong> federal government...for<br />

<strong>the</strong> many who argue for both, <strong>the</strong> two are tied toge<strong>the</strong>r by hostility towards an<br />

activist, interventionist, national state, both in its nation-building role <strong>and</strong> in its<br />

economic development role...decentralization <strong>and</strong> a degree of noninterventionism<br />

go toge<strong>the</strong>r.”<br />

To what extent, <strong>the</strong>n, can <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord be viewed as an expression<br />

of a neo-conservative constitutional agenda? Banting (1988: 588-9) views <strong>the</strong><br />

debate over Meech <strong>La</strong>ke as one between those committed to a nation-building,<br />

centralist view of federalism in which a strong central government is <strong>the</strong> key<br />

instrument of national integration, <strong>and</strong> between those who view Canadian<br />

politics as being about <strong>the</strong> reconciliation of regional, territorial <strong>and</strong> linguistic<br />

differences. <strong>The</strong> latter view favours a decentralized federation since <strong>the</strong><br />

cleavages to which it is sensitive require locally differentiated policies <strong>and</strong><br />

programs. Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, <strong>the</strong>refore, involved asserting <strong>the</strong> primacy of linguistic<br />

<strong>and</strong> territorial cleavages over those class-based cleavages which led to an<br />

agenda of social reform <strong>and</strong> national integration. Neo-conservatives would<br />

clearly prefer <strong>the</strong> former to <strong>the</strong> latter since it involved weakening <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

level: “<strong>the</strong> new stress on interdependence is purchased almost entirely at <strong>the</strong><br />

cost of reducing <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>and</strong> discretion of <strong>the</strong> federal government, <strong>and</strong> of<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ning <strong>the</strong> role of provincial governments in virtually every area<br />

193


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

touched by <strong>the</strong> Accord” (Cairns 1991:158). In this sense at least <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

was decentralizing <strong>and</strong> could be viewed with favour by neo-conservatives,<br />

even if <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>ning of provincial governments was somewhat<br />

problematic. And, although <strong>the</strong>re are various explanations for federal<br />

compliance, one of <strong>the</strong>se is that provincial governments were less likely to<br />

impede realization of a neo-conservative economic <strong>and</strong> social agenda. This<br />

perception is based upon <strong>the</strong> historical roles played by <strong>the</strong> two levels of<br />

government: “<strong>The</strong> creation of a political culture conducive to <strong>the</strong> creation of a<br />

social service state was slow to emerge. Governments, particularly those at <strong>the</strong><br />

provincial level, preferred to spend <strong>the</strong>ir tax revenues on private <strong>and</strong> public<br />

projects that contributed directly to capital accumulation. Provincial<br />

governments saw little or no political advantage to involving revenues in<br />

projects of legitimization, such as health <strong>and</strong> social welfare programs”<br />

(Behiels 1989:236). When this situation began to change it was primarily as a<br />

result of federal government initiatives. On <strong>the</strong> basis of historical experience,<br />

transferring powers to <strong>the</strong> provinces might reasonably be expected to lead to<br />

policy outcomes consistent with liberal political economy.<br />

Certainly, <strong>the</strong>se calculations could help to account for a striking feature of <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government’s negotiating posture: an apparent indifference to <strong>the</strong><br />

maintenance of federal authority. One provincial premier has been reported as<br />

saying that Mulroney “kept asking if we had a deal... It was as if he didn’t have<br />

any idea what <strong>the</strong> deal was or he didn’t care that much as long as he got one”<br />

(cited in Cairns 1991:252). Yet a journalist’s account, also cited by Cairns<br />

(153), points to <strong>the</strong> underlying content or substance of an o<strong>the</strong>rwise<br />

incomprehensible attitude. According to this account, <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister gave<br />

Lowell Murray “carte blanche to negotiate away whatever federal powers<br />

were necessary to get Quebec into <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.” Obviously, <strong>the</strong>re was no<br />

shortage of willing takers. Moreover, as Trudeau pointed out (1989:90),<br />

Mulroney had already made major concessions of powers to <strong>the</strong> provinces<br />

before <strong>the</strong> constitutional talks began (abolition of <strong>the</strong> National Energy<br />

Program, grant of offshore resources to Newfoundl<strong>and</strong>, etc.).<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are some interesting parallels between <strong>the</strong> government’s negotiating<br />

strategy at Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> that adopted in <strong>the</strong> Free Trade negotiations with<br />

<strong>the</strong> Americans. In Clarkson’s view (1991:116), Mulroney:<br />

...put Canada in <strong>the</strong> weakest possible bargaining situation ... As<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>eur in <strong>the</strong> negotiations, Canada laid its cards on <strong>the</strong> table....<br />

<strong>The</strong> United States made no concessions but sat back <strong>and</strong> waited.<br />

When <strong>the</strong> bargaining crunch came, <strong>the</strong> Canadian negotiators were<br />

under instructions to do anything to get a deal.<br />

<strong>The</strong> ultimate document represented an astonishing gain for American<br />

trade diplomacy while surrendering virtually no American<br />

sovereignty. ... Canada had made enormous concessions that limited <strong>the</strong><br />

federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments’ capacity to make industrial<br />

policies to promote <strong>the</strong>ir exports, to husb<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir energy reserves, or<br />

to foster <strong>the</strong>ir cultural industries.<br />

How can we explain <strong>the</strong> negotiating stance of <strong>the</strong> federal government? Was it<br />

monumental incompetence? Or, as <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> agreements suggests,<br />

was it <strong>the</strong> practical extension of <strong>the</strong> logic of liberal political economy? In my<br />

view <strong>the</strong> latter is <strong>the</strong> more realistic position. Both Meech <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Free Trade<br />

194


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

Agreement constrained governments: <strong>the</strong> federal (<strong>and</strong> most interventionist)<br />

government most severely. And, although <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned provincial governments, <strong>the</strong> exercise of some of <strong>the</strong> new powers<br />

would be constrained by <strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement. Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> two<br />

agreements may not represent <strong>the</strong> perfect situation from <strong>the</strong> viewpoint of<br />

liberal political economy; but <strong>the</strong>y do represent a preferable situation to that<br />

inherited by <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government.<br />

Awkwardly, from <strong>the</strong> point of view of this happy scenario, <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord was not ratified. In 1991-92 <strong>the</strong> constitutional question had to be<br />

addressed once more.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “Canada Round,” 1991-92<br />

<strong>The</strong> demise of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of crisis it occasioned led<br />

inevitably to ano<strong>the</strong>r round of constitutional proposals. <strong>The</strong> agenda was<br />

broadened partly by Quebec’s shift to a “maximalist” set of dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

expressed in <strong>the</strong> Allaire <strong>and</strong> Bélanger-Campeau reports (in contrast to <strong>the</strong><br />

modest proposals of 1986) . <strong>The</strong>se were reinforced by legislation to hold a<br />

referendum by <strong>the</strong> fall of 1992.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>re was intense <strong>and</strong> widespread activity elsewhere on <strong>the</strong> fate of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> which featured initiatives by both governments <strong>and</strong> private<br />

individuals <strong>and</strong> organizations. <strong>The</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for citizen input in <strong>the</strong> new round<br />

of constitutional renewal sprang from <strong>the</strong> widespread perception that <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech Accord had been hatched in <strong>the</strong> back rooms or, more formally, that it<br />

was <strong>the</strong> result of executive federalism ra<strong>the</strong>r than popular participation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> federal government unveiled its own constitutional proposals in<br />

September 1991 (Canada 1991a). Quantitatively, in terms of <strong>the</strong> proportion of<br />

proposals dealing with “prosperity,” <strong>the</strong> government seems to have accorded<br />

greatest priority to transforming <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> into <strong>the</strong> help-mate of<br />

economic success. <strong>The</strong> federal proposals in this part of <strong>the</strong> package, toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

with property rights which was included elsewhere, represent <strong>the</strong> core of <strong>the</strong><br />

neo-conservative constitutional agenda.<br />

Competitiveness as a Rationale for Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong><br />

In <strong>the</strong> past, <strong>the</strong> government argued, <strong>the</strong> mutually supportive combination of a<br />

federal political system <strong>and</strong> an economic union, had enabled Canada to<br />

become one of <strong>the</strong> world’s most prosperous countries. For <strong>the</strong>se benefits to be<br />

maintained in <strong>the</strong> face of <strong>the</strong> impact of globalization on national sovereignty,<br />

<strong>the</strong> basic combination must continue—“economic <strong>and</strong> political integration go<br />

h<strong>and</strong>-in-h<strong>and</strong>” (Canada 1991b:9). But a variety of challenges, internal <strong>and</strong><br />

external, meant that continuity was insufficient—“to prosper we must change”<br />

(Canada 1991a:29).<br />

More specifically, <strong>the</strong> external challenge of globalization <strong>and</strong> technological<br />

change required “Greater adaptability <strong>and</strong> more effective approaches to how<br />

federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments interact with each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong><br />

private sector” (Canada 1991b:1). Internally, <strong>the</strong> existence of barriers to <strong>the</strong><br />

free flow of goods <strong>and</strong> services, combined with <strong>the</strong> phenomena of federal <strong>and</strong><br />

provincial policies working at cross purposes to each o<strong>the</strong>r, pointed in <strong>the</strong><br />

same direction. In <strong>the</strong> government’s view, one of <strong>the</strong> key ingredients of future<br />

competitiveness lay in streng<strong>the</strong>ning <strong>the</strong> free market basis of <strong>the</strong> economic<br />

union: “At <strong>the</strong> heart of effective economic integration must be <strong>the</strong> absence of<br />

195


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

restrictions to <strong>the</strong> free flow of people, goods, services <strong>and</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

existence of a common currency, which encourages this free flow by removing<br />

exchange rate uncertainty <strong>and</strong> transaction costs that can impede trade.”<br />

Streng<strong>the</strong>ning <strong>the</strong> Economic Union<br />

<strong>The</strong> impact of various government policies was recognized as on-going <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> need as one of harmonization <strong>and</strong> predictability. However, <strong>the</strong> core of <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal is <strong>the</strong> laissez-faire notion that, as far as possible, governments should<br />

be constrained from interference with <strong>the</strong> operation of markets. This<br />

viewpoint, dear to <strong>the</strong> hearts of liberal political economists, found expression<br />

in <strong>the</strong> text of <strong>the</strong> proposal to amend Section 121, <strong>the</strong> common market clause of<br />

<strong>the</strong> existing <strong>Constitution</strong>: “(1) Canada is an economic union within which<br />

persons, goods, services <strong>and</strong> capital may move freely without barriers or<br />

restrictions based on provincial or territorial boundaries. (2) Nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

Parliament or Government of Canada nor <strong>the</strong> legislatures or governments of<br />

<strong>the</strong> provinces shall by law or practice contravene <strong>the</strong> principle expressed in<br />

subsection (1).” Although some exceptions follow, <strong>the</strong> core of <strong>the</strong> proposed<br />

article is clear: <strong>the</strong> principle that no government can legitimately interfere<br />

with market relations would be constitutionally entrenched. It is a clear case of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian government seeking to constitutionalize its particular economic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory or ideology. 2<br />

General exceptions could be made by <strong>the</strong> federal government, with <strong>the</strong> consent<br />

of seven provinces with at least 50 percent of <strong>the</strong> population: (a) to exempt any<br />

barrier from judicial review, by declaring it in <strong>the</strong> national interest; (b) to<br />

legislate on anything related to <strong>the</strong> efficiency of <strong>the</strong> economic union.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> proposed amendment was both decentralizing, in<br />

than it prohibited any level of government from interfering with <strong>the</strong> free flow<br />

of economic activity, <strong>and</strong> centralizing, in its impact on federal-provincial<br />

relations. If provinces wish exemptions <strong>the</strong>y must obtain federal permission<br />

(plus that of sufficient o<strong>the</strong>r provinces). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government “has almost unlimited capacity to interfere with democratic<br />

outcomes within a particular province, as long as enough o<strong>the</strong>r provinces<br />

agree” (Howse 1991:15). Traditionally, centralization in <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

political economy has been a formula for an active government <strong>and</strong> for nationbuilding<br />

projects. But as <strong>the</strong> earlier discussion of business’ constitutional<br />

program indicated, a degree of central political authority is necessary for o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

policy regimes as well. Under <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government, centralization seems<br />

to be envisaged as an instrument to enforce a minimalist conception of<br />

government. If we bear in mind <strong>the</strong> “free economy, strong state” depiction of<br />

neo- conservative political economy, any paradox is only apparent.<br />

Liberal political economy posits that large, barrier-free markets permit<br />

economies of scale, more efficient use of resources, <strong>and</strong> thus maximize <strong>the</strong><br />

general welfare. <strong>The</strong>re is no shortage of documentation that existing provincial<br />

<strong>and</strong> federal practices deviate from <strong>the</strong> neo-classical ideal. Many of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

policies have, of course, been <strong>the</strong> stock-in-trade of <strong>the</strong> nation-building (<strong>and</strong><br />

province-building) efforts of activist Canadian governments. <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

prohibition, <strong>and</strong> its entrenchment in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, would represent a strong<br />

defence for <strong>the</strong> market order against democratically-elected governments<br />

seeking to satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir electorates by moderating market outcomes. Of course,<br />

<strong>the</strong> assumption that free trade, whe<strong>the</strong>r internally or internationally, will<br />

produce a net increment in welfare depends upon assumptions, such as full-<br />

196


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

employment, which demonstrably are not present in Canada (Jackson<br />

1992:73-5; Furlong <strong>and</strong> Moggach 1990). 3<br />

Such a development entrenches one value—efficiency—as <strong>the</strong> prime goal of<br />

social activity in <strong>the</strong> country. Entrenchment constrains potential democratic<br />

majorities who may favour a different value, say equity, from achieving <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

ends. <strong>The</strong> effect is to insulate from democratic control something which ought<br />

to be subject to it. In <strong>the</strong> context of a federal system, a watertight economic<br />

union may be incompatible with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of federalism: “<strong>The</strong> very purpose<br />

of fiscal federalism ... inevitably leads to differences in <strong>the</strong> levels of taxation<br />

<strong>and</strong> public services ... (which) ... may interfere with <strong>the</strong> most efficient<br />

allocation of resources <strong>and</strong> location of industry for <strong>the</strong> region (nation) as a<br />

whole; such is <strong>the</strong> cost of political subdivision” (Musgrave, cited in Courchene<br />

1986:204). <strong>The</strong> federal proposals, <strong>the</strong>refore, had far reaching implications.<br />

Harmonization Measures<br />

A related proposal was designed to achieve better coordination of federal <strong>and</strong><br />

provincial fiscal policies, to improve <strong>the</strong> harmonization of <strong>the</strong>se with Canada’s<br />

monetary policy, <strong>and</strong> to apply moral suasion to a province pursuing<br />

disharmonious policies. <strong>The</strong> government proposed new procedures such as a<br />

relatively fixed annual budget cycle; a fixed annual schedule of <strong>the</strong> Finance<br />

Minister’s meetings; <strong>the</strong> publication by all governments of pre-budget<br />

economic/fiscal outlooks; <strong>and</strong> common accounting conventions (Canada<br />

1991a:32). Beyond that, however, “guidelines” to better coordinate policies<br />

were foreseen. If approved by <strong>the</strong> federal government <strong>and</strong> seven provinces<br />

with at least fifty percent of <strong>the</strong> population, meeting in a new Council of<br />

Federation, <strong>the</strong> guidelines would be set in federal legislation under <strong>the</strong> new<br />

economic union power. Although up to three provinces could opt-out, with a<br />

60 percent vote in <strong>the</strong>ir legislative assemblies, <strong>the</strong> opt-out was only for three<br />

years <strong>and</strong> it was unclear, in <strong>the</strong> federal proposals, whe<strong>the</strong>r such measures were<br />

renewable. <strong>The</strong> federal government also favoured establishing an independent<br />

agency “to monitor <strong>and</strong> evaluate” <strong>the</strong> macroeconomic policies of <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

<strong>and</strong> provincial governments.<br />

<strong>The</strong> effect was clearly centralizing (albeit requiring substantial provincial<br />

consent). Certainly a common reaction in Quebec was that <strong>the</strong> proposals<br />

represented a federal “power grab.” More generally, it is reasonable to infer<br />

that <strong>the</strong> ability of any province, or small number of provinces, to deviate from a<br />

national majority viewpoint would be circumscribed under <strong>the</strong>se proposals. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> context of Canadian electoral history this might be expected to be more of a<br />

problem for provinces with a left-leaning government than for those with more<br />

conservative administrations.<br />

Reforming <strong>the</strong> Bank of Canada’s M<strong>and</strong>ate<br />

<strong>The</strong> government included in its constitutional proposals a number of ideas for<br />

changing <strong>the</strong> Bank of Canada’s m<strong>and</strong>ate, <strong>and</strong> for changing <strong>the</strong> appointments<br />

system to <strong>the</strong> Board <strong>and</strong> Governorship of <strong>the</strong> Bank. Since <strong>the</strong> Bank is under <strong>the</strong><br />

exclusive jurisdiction of <strong>the</strong> federal authorities this could be accomplished<br />

without provincial involvement <strong>and</strong> without amending <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in any<br />

way.<br />

<strong>The</strong> changes in appointment procedures must be seen as largely symbolic.<br />

This is because <strong>the</strong> Bank’s m<strong>and</strong>ate, under <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong> federal proposal,<br />

would be focused on a single goal—<strong>the</strong> preservation of price stability. At<br />

197


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

present <strong>the</strong> Bank’s m<strong>and</strong>ate is much broader: “to regulate credit <strong>and</strong> currency<br />

in <strong>the</strong> best interest of <strong>the</strong> economic life of <strong>the</strong> nation, to control <strong>and</strong> protect <strong>the</strong><br />

external value of <strong>the</strong> national monetary unit <strong>and</strong> to mitigate by its influence<br />

fluctuations in <strong>the</strong> general level of production, trade prices, <strong>and</strong> employment,<br />

so far as may be possible within <strong>the</strong> scope of monetary action, <strong>and</strong> generally to<br />

promote <strong>the</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> financial welfare of Canada” (Canada 1991b:38).<br />

Nothing in <strong>the</strong> package demonstrates more clearly <strong>the</strong> influence of liberal<br />

political economy upon <strong>the</strong> government’s constitutional agenda than <strong>the</strong><br />

argumentation surrounding this proposal: “<strong>The</strong> only contribution <strong>the</strong> Bank of<br />

Canada can make to <strong>the</strong> well-being of all Canadians in <strong>the</strong> long run is to pursue<br />

policies which maintain <strong>the</strong> purchasing power of <strong>the</strong> nation’s money.... <strong>The</strong><br />

references to mitigating fluctuations in production, trade <strong>and</strong> employment <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r objectives should be eliminated as <strong>the</strong>y represent objectives ei<strong>the</strong>r that<br />

history has taught us a central bank cannot achieve or that can only be achieved<br />

through price stability” (Canada 1991b:38-9). This is, of course, a somewhat<br />

selective <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretically blinkered reading of what history has to offer.<br />

Pierre Fortin (1991:3) comments that <strong>the</strong> new m<strong>and</strong>ate, zero inflation would<br />

“force our central bank to support a priori a scientific position that is highly<br />

controversial at best <strong>and</strong>, at worst, completely in error.”<br />

Re-distribution of Powers<br />

<strong>The</strong> decentralization of federal powers previously noted in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord was replicated <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ed in <strong>the</strong> 1991 proposals. A number of areas<br />

were to be recognized as being within exclusive provincial jurisdiction:<br />

training, tourism, forestry, mining, recreation, housing, <strong>and</strong> municipal <strong>and</strong><br />

urban affairs. A number of o<strong>the</strong>r areas were identified for review to see which<br />

level of government could best provide <strong>the</strong>m. With respect to immigration <strong>and</strong><br />

culture, <strong>the</strong> federal government was prepared to negotiate <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutionalize agreements with individual provinces. In addition, <strong>the</strong><br />

government proposed a constitutional amendment to permit <strong>the</strong> delegation of<br />

legislative authority between <strong>the</strong> two levels of government. It was also willing<br />

to remove <strong>the</strong> federal declaratory power from <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> to<br />

recognize provincial possession of <strong>the</strong> residual power on “non-national<br />

matters not specifically assigned to <strong>the</strong> federal government under <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> or by virtue of court decisions.” Finally, <strong>the</strong> Meech objective of<br />

limiting <strong>the</strong> federal spending power found a place in <strong>the</strong> 1991 proposals. <strong>The</strong><br />

result would be major decentralization of Canadian federalism (Johnson<br />

1992). Most of <strong>the</strong> decentralizing measures are consistent with neoconservative<br />

principles, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal government’s desire to rid itself of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se responsibilities is unsurprising. However, <strong>the</strong> impulse to<br />

decentralization should be placed in <strong>the</strong> context of o<strong>the</strong>r proposals which, in<br />

certain areas, would have had <strong>the</strong> effect of enhancing federal authority.<br />

Property Rights<br />

<strong>The</strong> government failed to advance any rationale for its proposal to include in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms a guarantee for property rights. Bakan<br />

(1992:118) offers three possible reasons: a desire to undercut Reform Party<br />

support, to give <strong>the</strong>mselves a bargaining chip in <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

negotiations, or a desire “to elevate <strong>the</strong>ir market ideology to constitutional<br />

status. David Milne argued that property rights provisions are a “favourite<br />

vehicle for conservative interests resisting social legislation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> welfare<br />

state” (cited in Mittelstaedt 1991). Such comments demonstrate <strong>the</strong><br />

198


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

consistency of <strong>the</strong> property-rights proposal with <strong>the</strong> general neo-conservative<br />

constitutional agenda. <strong>The</strong> government’s precise motivation in making <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal at this time, however, remains unclear.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Process 1991-92<br />

<strong>The</strong> government’s economic constitutional proposals were not well- received<br />

by <strong>the</strong> Renewal of Canada conferences called to discuss <strong>the</strong>m. <strong>The</strong> principle of<br />

a strong economic union seems not to have been problematic. However, <strong>the</strong><br />

proposed mechanisms for achieving it were. In particular, <strong>the</strong> proposed<br />

Section 91A granting Parliament (subject to provincial approval on <strong>the</strong> 7/50<br />

formula) <strong>the</strong> right to make laws it declared to be for <strong>the</strong> efficient functioning of<br />

<strong>the</strong> economic union, was rejected almost unanimously on <strong>the</strong> grounds that it<br />

was unnecessary, illegitimate <strong>and</strong> inappropriate (Canada 1992a:10-13; 19-<br />

22). <strong>The</strong> proposals for greater harmonization of fiscal policies, <strong>and</strong> of fiscal<br />

policy with monetary policy, received <strong>the</strong> same response. Delegates to <strong>the</strong><br />

conference were quite suspicious of rigid <strong>and</strong> constitutionally entrenched<br />

mechanisms for dealing with problems <strong>the</strong>y felt ought to be addressed flexibly<br />

(Canada 1992a:14-16). Delegates unequivocally felt that <strong>the</strong> Bank of Canada<br />

reforms ought not to be part of <strong>the</strong> constitutional process <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> Bank’s<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ate should not be narrowed to focus only on price stability (Canada<br />

1992a:17-18; Canada 1992b:11). <strong>The</strong> Conference on Identity, Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Values overwhelmingly rejected <strong>the</strong> inclusion of property rights (Canada<br />

1992c:15-16). Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> proposal to include a Social <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, clearly nei<strong>the</strong>r part of <strong>the</strong> federal government’s proposals nor a<br />

neo-conservative preference, surfaced in a number of <strong>the</strong> conferences <strong>and</strong> it<br />

was apparent that <strong>the</strong> idea enjoyed substantial support. Finally, although <strong>the</strong><br />

results of <strong>the</strong> Conference on <strong>the</strong> Division of Powers could not be construed as a<br />

repudiation of <strong>the</strong> federal proposals, <strong>the</strong>re was clearly strong support for a<br />

strong central government, national st<strong>and</strong>ards, <strong>and</strong> a willingness to deal with<br />

Quebec’s aspirations through asymmetry ra<strong>the</strong>r than through generalized<br />

devolution (Canada 1992d:21).<br />

Given its composition, one could expect <strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee to<br />

be generally supportive of <strong>the</strong> federal proposals. While this expectation was<br />

met, even <strong>the</strong> Conservatives who belonged to it were affected by <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

public discussion. In a number of areas <strong>the</strong> Report suggested alterations to <strong>the</strong><br />

federal package; <strong>the</strong> Committee felt fur<strong>the</strong>r consultations with <strong>the</strong> artistic <strong>and</strong><br />

cultural communities should take place before proceeding with <strong>the</strong> proposal to<br />

transfer jurisdiction over culture to <strong>the</strong> provinces (Beaudoin- Dobbie<br />

1992:77); it favoured a non-judicial dispute settlement mechanism for<br />

policing <strong>the</strong> economic union (87); <strong>the</strong> inclusion in it of undertakings to pursue<br />

<strong>the</strong> goals of full-employment <strong>and</strong> ensuring that all Canadians have a<br />

reasonable st<strong>and</strong>ard of living (88-9); <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> inclusion of a “social covenant”<br />

(87). In addition, <strong>the</strong> report recommended that <strong>the</strong> issue of <strong>the</strong> Bank of<br />

Canada’s m<strong>and</strong>ate not be part of <strong>the</strong> constitutional discussions.<br />

Enter <strong>the</strong> Provinces<br />

However widespread <strong>the</strong> public consultations, <strong>the</strong> amendment of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> remains an intergovernmental process. A number of provinces<br />

had well defined constitutional dem<strong>and</strong>s to pursue once <strong>the</strong> negotiations<br />

began in <strong>the</strong> spring of 1992. <strong>The</strong>se included Alberta’s advocacy of a Triple E<br />

Senate, Manitoba’s concern to see a “Canada clause” in <strong>the</strong> new package that<br />

would express <strong>the</strong> underlying values of Canadians <strong>and</strong> thus help unify <strong>the</strong><br />

199


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

country, <strong>and</strong> Ontario’s dem<strong>and</strong> for a social charter to guarantee social<br />

programs <strong>and</strong> national st<strong>and</strong>ards. A number of provinces had differing<br />

concerns about aboriginal issues <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposed recognition of an inherent<br />

right to self-government. <strong>The</strong> most detailed, longest, <strong>and</strong> most public list of<br />

constitutional requirements was that of Quebec, which declined to participate<br />

in <strong>the</strong> negotiations until <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada came up with an acceptable<br />

“offer”—a position Premier Bourassa had adopted after Meech unravelled.<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> complexities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> clash of agendas <strong>the</strong> nine provinces <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government arrived at an agreement covering a wide range of topics on<br />

July 7, 1992. On this basis Quebec rejoined <strong>the</strong> constitutional negotiations <strong>and</strong><br />

on August 28, in Charlottetown, an agreement was reached between <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government, all provinces, <strong>and</strong> native <strong>and</strong> territorial leaders. Here we<br />

shall be concerned only with those provisions previously identified as part of a<br />

neo-conservative constitutional agenda. All references will be to <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown agreement unless o<strong>the</strong>rwise stated.<br />

A number of <strong>the</strong> federal government’s original proposals, including measures<br />

to harmonize fiscal policy, change <strong>the</strong> Bank of Canada’s m<strong>and</strong>ate, <strong>and</strong><br />

entrench property rights, were absent. A number of <strong>the</strong> items that were<br />

included were ei<strong>the</strong>r undesirable from <strong>the</strong> viewpoint of liberal political<br />

economy or, at best, a mixed blessing. A non justiciable provision described<br />

<strong>the</strong> commitment of <strong>the</strong> governments <strong>and</strong> legislatures to preserve <strong>and</strong> develop<br />

Canada’s social <strong>and</strong> economic union, <strong>and</strong> called for a monitoring mechanism<br />

to be established by a future First Ministers’ Conference. Presumably such a<br />

mechanism could apply moral suasion against any goverment deviating from<br />

<strong>the</strong> policy objectives of <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic union. <strong>The</strong> policy objectives<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves, however, provide little joy to <strong>the</strong> liberal political economist. In<br />

addition to a commitment to streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> economic union <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> free<br />

movement of persons, goods, services, <strong>and</strong> capital, which was obviously<br />

acceptable, <strong>the</strong> clause included items that were not.<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> social union, governments <strong>and</strong> legislatures would be committed to<br />

maintain a health care system which met <strong>the</strong> criteria established by <strong>the</strong> current<br />

Canada Health Act, provision of adequate social services, <strong>and</strong> high quality <strong>and</strong><br />

accessible education, toge<strong>the</strong>r with protection of workers’ rights to organize<br />

<strong>and</strong> bargain collectively. Under <strong>the</strong> economic union, <strong>the</strong> goals of fullemployment<br />

<strong>and</strong> ensuring that all Canadians have a reasonable st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

living were prominent. Ano<strong>the</strong>r provision, which was to be justiciable,<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned <strong>the</strong> federal government’s commitment to regional equalization<br />

under Section 36 of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act. Henceforth <strong>the</strong> federal government<br />

would be charged with ensuring that “provincial governments have sufficient<br />

revenues to provide reasonably comparable levels of public services at<br />

reasonably comparable levels of taxation” <strong>and</strong> to provide “reasonably<br />

comparable economic infrastructures of a national nature in each province <strong>and</strong><br />

territory.” Although <strong>the</strong> precise impact of such language was difficult to<br />

predict, its fiscal consequences were potentially contrary to <strong>the</strong> goals espoused<br />

by liberal political economy. Certainly <strong>the</strong> wish list of policy objectives in <strong>the</strong><br />

non-justiciable clause could have served to legitimate Keynesian policies as or<br />

more easily than neo-conservative ones.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> July 7 accord, Section 121, <strong>the</strong> common market clause, was to be<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned by preventing any interprovincial trade barrier “by law or<br />

practice that arbitrarily discriminates on <strong>the</strong> basis of province or territory of<br />

residence, origin or destination <strong>and</strong> unduly impedes <strong>the</strong> efficient functioning<br />

200


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Canadian economic union.” <strong>The</strong> provision was to have been policed by<br />

an independent tribunal which, to strike down a barrier, would have to find that<br />

it (a) was arbitrary <strong>and</strong> (b) unduly impeded <strong>the</strong> economic union. Liberal<br />

political economists were quick to denounce this language as weak <strong>and</strong> limited<br />

(e.g. Corcoran 1992). In addition <strong>the</strong>re was a lengthy list of areas in which<br />

interprovincial trade barriers could continue to function. This included<br />

subsidies or tax incentives aimed at encouraging investment, “reasonable”<br />

public sector investment programs, agricultural marketing <strong>and</strong> supply<br />

management programs, consumer <strong>and</strong> environmental protection, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

establishment <strong>and</strong> maintenance of government-owned monopolies. Clearly<br />

<strong>the</strong>se were much weaker measures than originally proposed by <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government.<br />

During <strong>the</strong> summer’s negotiations, a number of changes were made to <strong>the</strong><br />

provisions affecting <strong>the</strong> common market. Under <strong>the</strong> August 28 agreement,<br />

Section 121 would remain unchanged <strong>and</strong> a future First Ministers’ Conference<br />

would discuss how best to implement a number of “principles <strong>and</strong><br />

commitments related to <strong>the</strong> Canadian Common Market” that were included in<br />

<strong>the</strong> accord. <strong>The</strong>se principles included a prohibition against governments<br />

erecting interprovincial trade barriers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> criteria that a possible future<br />

enforcement agency would apply were streng<strong>the</strong>ned slightly. Instead of<br />

having to find that an arbitrarily discriminatory measure unduly impeded <strong>the</strong><br />

efficient functioning of <strong>the</strong> Canadian economic union, it would suffice to find<br />

that such a measure did impede its efficient functioning. However, a lengthy<br />

list of exemptions continued to be appended to this section.<br />

Only in <strong>the</strong> area of transferring powers to <strong>the</strong> provinces did <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

package reflect <strong>the</strong> federal agenda. Although decentralization is consistent with<br />

<strong>the</strong> preferences of liberal political economy, it is a second best solution unless<br />

combined with measures to prohibit market intervention by all levels of<br />

government. This clearly was <strong>the</strong> purpose of <strong>the</strong> strong economic union<br />

proposals. Without those proposals, decentralization represents only a partial<br />

victory for liberal political economy since <strong>the</strong> interventionism it abhors at <strong>the</strong><br />

federal level could continue at <strong>the</strong> provincial level. Also, <strong>the</strong> non-justiciable<br />

but highly symbolic language on <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic union could be used<br />

to legitimate provincial or popular pressures for federal interventionism.<br />

Conclusions<br />

<strong>The</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown proposals brought <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

constitutional reform to a no doubt temporary conclusion. No definitive<br />

explanations have yet emerged for <strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Accord; clearly <strong>the</strong>re were<br />

many factors at work <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir interaction was complex. What can be stated<br />

with some certainty is that <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 constitutional process served to<br />

highlight some of <strong>the</strong> obstacles to implementing a constitutional agenda based<br />

on neo- conservative political economy.<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> introduction of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, it is apparent that a great many<br />

Canadians, especially in English Canada, have become attached to <strong>the</strong><br />

(primarily liberal) individual rights it contains—<strong>the</strong>y have, as Cairns has put it,<br />

become “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Canadians.” But <strong>the</strong>re is little evidence of attachment to<br />

liberal political rights extending to <strong>the</strong> liberal economic values expressed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> federal government’s constitutional agenda. If <strong>the</strong> views of <strong>the</strong> Renewal of<br />

Canada conferences can be taken as in any way representative of informed<br />

Canadian opinion, it would seem that Canadian political culture still inclines<br />

201


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

toward collective social provision <strong>and</strong> tolerates reasonable levels of<br />

government intervention in <strong>the</strong> economy to moderate <strong>the</strong> effects of market<br />

forces. Members of <strong>the</strong> current Canadian government may have become “true<br />

believers” in liberal political economy but, in this respect, <strong>the</strong>ir position is<br />

incongruent with <strong>the</strong> broader political culture.<br />

A second obstacle, of course, is <strong>the</strong> federal system itself. Although many<br />

provinces are prepared to accept some decentralization of <strong>the</strong> federal system,<br />

this is normally accompanied by a desire to maximize <strong>the</strong> powers of <strong>the</strong><br />

provincial government ra<strong>the</strong>r than to repudiate <strong>the</strong> powers of government in<br />

general. Certainly many of <strong>the</strong>m found <strong>the</strong> attachment to pure market<br />

economics represented in <strong>the</strong> economic union proposal to be unacceptable in<br />

practice. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, a number of provinces continue to support <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> a<br />

strong federal role in some areas. In taking this position <strong>the</strong>y seem to be<br />

congruent with <strong>the</strong> preferences of Canadians—at least those outside<br />

Quebec—where opinion poll data regularly demonstrates a preference for a<br />

strong federal government.<br />

Canada’s ongoing constitutional crisis provided an opportunity for Canada’s neoconservatives<br />

to attempt to shape <strong>the</strong> outcome along <strong>the</strong> lines of <strong>the</strong>ir ideology. To<br />

date, however, it appears that Canada’s traditionally statist political culture,<br />

combined with its federal institutions, have been strong enough to dilute that effort<br />

to a very significant degree. Indeed, given <strong>the</strong> context, neo-conservative<br />

constitutional proposals were widely viewed as an unhelpful intrusion into an<br />

already complicated situation. As a result, any renewed federalism that<br />

eventually emerges may not provide a better instrument to achieve<br />

competitiveness, as defined by liberal political economy, than <strong>the</strong> present<br />

arrangements. Yet <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative effort continues. Having failed to<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> Canadian economic union by constitutional means, <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government, spurred on by business pressure (Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, 5 December<br />

1992:B3), is trying to achieve it through a new approach to intergovernmental<br />

negotiations. If agreed to by <strong>the</strong> provinces, <strong>the</strong> comprehensive negotiating<br />

process, modelled on <strong>the</strong> free trade negotiations with <strong>the</strong> United States, would<br />

force <strong>the</strong> governments to come up with an all-or-nothing agreement by June<br />

30, 1994, <strong>and</strong> to pass enforcing legislation by mid-1995. <strong>The</strong>re are o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

parallels with free trade: many of <strong>the</strong> goals pursued in <strong>the</strong> constitutional talks<br />

may be achievable through <strong>the</strong> provisions of <strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement (<strong>and</strong> its<br />

NAFTA successor, if ratified). Informed commentators on <strong>the</strong> latter refer to it<br />

as an “economic <strong>Constitution</strong> for North America.” It remains to be seen<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r this approach will be more successful from <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative<br />

viewpoint than <strong>the</strong> constitutional renewal process ended for <strong>the</strong> moment by <strong>the</strong><br />

October 26 Referendum.<br />

Notes<br />

* An earlier version of this article was prepared for presentation at <strong>the</strong> annual conference of <strong>the</strong><br />

Atlantic Provinces Political Studies Association, Halifax, October 16-18, 1992. I am<br />

grateful for comments received from participants at <strong>the</strong> conference, <strong>and</strong> thanks are also due<br />

to my colleagues Gary Munro <strong>and</strong> Douglas West, <strong>and</strong> an anonymous reviewer, for o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

comments <strong>and</strong> suggestions.<br />

1. <strong>The</strong>se provinces, toge<strong>the</strong>r with Quebec, were also, of course, among <strong>the</strong> most enthusiastic<br />

about <strong>the</strong> centrepiece of <strong>the</strong> neo-conservative policy agenda—free trade with <strong>the</strong> U.S. I am<br />

grateful to an anonymous reviewer for emphasizing this linkage.<br />

2. It might be argued that <strong>the</strong> priority accorded a stronger economic union pre-dated <strong>the</strong><br />

Mulroney government <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> identification of that government with an agenda based<br />

on liberal political economy is <strong>the</strong>refore overdrawn. Certainly <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government<br />

202


Renewed <strong>Federalism</strong> as an Instrument of Competitiveness<br />

advocated a stronger economic union. Two differences between <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government’s<br />

proposals <strong>and</strong> those of <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government should be noted. First, <strong>the</strong> Trudeau<br />

government was “far less accommodating to <strong>the</strong> devolutionary dem<strong>and</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> provinces”<br />

[Russell 1992: 110]. This was a government about to launch an interventionalist “third<br />

national policy.” It was more concerned to assert federal power over <strong>the</strong> economy than to<br />

deny such power to any level of government. Second, <strong>and</strong> consistent with <strong>the</strong> first point, in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Trudeau proposals <strong>the</strong> power of <strong>the</strong> federal government to escape <strong>the</strong> limitations imposed<br />

by stronger language on <strong>the</strong> economic union, on <strong>the</strong> grounds of “overriding national<br />

interest,” were unconstrained by <strong>the</strong> need for provincial approval. In <strong>the</strong> Mulroney proposals<br />

this would only be possible with provincial approval on <strong>the</strong> 7/50 formula. This made federal<br />

intervention less likely <strong>and</strong> was <strong>the</strong>refore more consistent with <strong>the</strong> principles of liberal<br />

political economy.<br />

3. In addition to its utility in constraining domestic government intervention, <strong>the</strong> Business<br />

Council on National Issues pointed to <strong>the</strong> advantages it believed a streng<strong>the</strong>ned economic<br />

union would confer in international trade negotiations: “Canadian negotiators are able to<br />

offer our trading partners improved access to <strong>the</strong> broad, diversified Canadian market. ... Two<br />

concessions made by Canada to win better access to <strong>the</strong> U.S. market during <strong>the</strong> free trade<br />

negotiations illustrate <strong>the</strong> advantage of having a national economic union. Under <strong>the</strong> FTA,<br />

Canada agreed: i) to provide <strong>the</strong> U.S. with certain guarantees with respect to access to<br />

Canadian energy, <strong>and</strong> ii) to modify duty remission schemes <strong>and</strong> certain o<strong>the</strong>r policies related<br />

to <strong>the</strong> Auto Pact. Only a single central government authority, able to negotiate on behalf of<br />

all regions of <strong>the</strong> country, could deliver on <strong>the</strong>se issues. A fragmented Canada would not<br />

have been in a position to offer <strong>the</strong>se concessions“ (Business Council on National Issues<br />

1992, 17).<br />

Bibliography<br />

Bakan, Joel (1992), “Against <strong>Constitution</strong>al Property Rights” in Cameron <strong>and</strong> Smith, eds. (1992),<br />

117-26.<br />

Banting, K. G. (1988), “<strong>Federalism</strong>, Social Reform <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Spending Power,” Canadian Public<br />

Policy, XIV Supplement, 581-92.<br />

Beaudoin, Gérald A. <strong>and</strong> Dorothy Dobbie (1992), Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a<br />

Renewed Canada (Ottawa).<br />

Behiels, Michael D., ed. (1989), <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer: Conflicting Views on <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord (Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press).<br />

Boadway, Robin (1992), <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Division of Powers: An Economic Perspective<br />

(Ottawa: Economic Council of Canada).<br />

Business Council on National Issues (1990a), <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Renewal (Ottawa: BCNI).<br />

Business Council on National Issues (1990b), Canada’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Options (Ottawa: BCNI).<br />

Business Council on National Issues (1991), Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 21st Century: Towards a More<br />

Effective <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> a Stronger Economy (Ottawa: BCNI).<br />

Business Council on National Issues (1992), Canada’s Economic Union (Ottawa: BCNI).<br />

Cairns, Alan C. [edited by Douglas E. Williams] (1991), Disruptions: <strong>Constitution</strong>al Struggles,<br />

from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke (Toronto: McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Stewart).<br />

Cameron, Duncan <strong>and</strong> Miriam Smith, eds. (1992), <strong>Constitution</strong>al Politics: <strong>The</strong> Canadian Forum<br />

Book on <strong>the</strong> Federal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Proposals (Toronto: James Lorimer).<br />

Canada (1991a), Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Proposals (Ottawa: Supply <strong>and</strong> Services).<br />

Canada (1991b), Canadian <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> Economic Union: Partnership for Prosperity<br />

(Ottawa: Supply <strong>and</strong> Services).<br />

Canada (1992), Renewal of Canada Conferences: Compendium of Reports (Ottawa): (a)<br />

Economic Union Conference; (b) Institutional Reform Conference; (c) Identity, Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Values Conference; (d) Division of Powers Conference.<br />

Carmichael, E.A., W. Dobson <strong>and</strong> R.G. Lipsey (1986), “<strong>The</strong> Macdonald Report: Signpost on<br />

Shopping Basket,” Canadian Public Policy 12, Supplement, 23-39.<br />

Clarkson, Stephen (1991), “Disjunctions: Free Trade <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Paradox of Canadian Development”<br />

in Drache <strong>and</strong> Gertler, eds. (1991), 103-26.<br />

Corcoran, Terence (1992), “How <strong>The</strong>y Eviscerated <strong>the</strong> Common Market” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, 10<br />

July, B2.<br />

Courchene, Thomas J. (1986), Economic Management <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Division of Powers (Toronto:<br />

University of Toronto Press, v.67 Studies of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on <strong>the</strong> Economic Union<br />

<strong>and</strong> Development Prospects for Canada).<br />

203


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Coyne, Deborah (1987), “<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Spending Power Proposals:<br />

Fundamentally Flawed,” in Behiels, ed., (1987), 245-71.<br />

Ernst, Alan (1992), “From Liberal Continentalism to Neoconservatism: North American Free<br />

Trade <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Politics of <strong>the</strong> C.D. Howe Institute,” Studies in Political Economy 39, 109-<br />

140.<br />

Fortin, Pierre (1991), “Exclusive focus on zero inflation: A dangerous proposal,” <strong>The</strong> Network<br />

(November-December), 2-5.<br />

Furlong, Kieran <strong>and</strong> Douglas Moggach (1990), “Efficiency, Competition <strong>and</strong> Full Employment in<br />

Canadian Free Trade Literature,” Studies in Political Economy 33 (Autumn).<br />

Howse, Robert (1991), “Economic Integration or Political Fragmentation?” <strong>The</strong> Network<br />

(October) 14-15.<br />

Jackson, Andrew (1992), “<strong>The</strong> Economic Union” in Cameron <strong>and</strong> Smith, eds. (1992), 70-8.<br />

Jenson, Jane (1989), “Different but not Exceptional,” Canadian Review of Sociology <strong>and</strong><br />

Anthropology.<br />

Jenson, Jane (1990), “Representations in Crisis: <strong>The</strong> Roots of Canada’s Permeable Fordism,”<br />

Canadian Journal of Political Science XXIII, 653-83.<br />

Johnson, A.W. (1992), “A National Government in a Federal State” in Cameron <strong>and</strong> Smith eds.<br />

(1992) 79-91.<br />

Leslie, Peter (1987), Federal State, National Economy (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).<br />

Marchak, M. Patricia (1991), <strong>The</strong> Integrated Circus: <strong>The</strong> New Right <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Restructuring of<br />

Global Markets (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press).<br />

McRoberts, Kenneth (1988), Quebec: Social Change <strong>and</strong> Political Crisis (Toronto: McClell<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Stewart,Third Edition)<br />

Milib<strong>and</strong>, Ralph, Leo Panitch <strong>and</strong> John Saville, eds. (1987), Socialist Register 1987 (London:<br />

Merlin Press).<br />

Mittelstaedt, Martin (1991), “Property-rights plan under fire,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, 2 October.<br />

Monahan, Patrick J. (1991), Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: <strong>The</strong> Inside Story (Toronto: University of Toronto<br />

Press).<br />

Norman, Wayne, rapporteur (1991), “Network Seminar on Economics,” in Network Seminar on<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Taking Stock (Ottawa 1991).<br />

Russell, Peter (1992), <strong>Constitution</strong>al Odyssey: Can Canadians Be A Sovereign People? (Toronto:<br />

University of Toronto Press).<br />

Shields, John (1990), “Democracy Versus Leviathan: <strong>The</strong> State, Democracy <strong>and</strong> Neoconservatism,”<br />

Journal of History <strong>and</strong> Politics 8, 153-74.<br />

Simeon, Richard (1987), “Inside <strong>the</strong> Macdonald Commission,” Studies in Political Economy 22,<br />

167-79.<br />

Simeon, Richard (1989), “Parallelism in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement,”<br />

in Whyte <strong>and</strong> Peach eds. (1989), 3-8.<br />

Simeon, Richard (1991), “Globalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian Nation State,” in Doern <strong>and</strong> Purchase<br />

(1991), 46-58.<br />

Trudeau, Pierre Elliot (1989), “Who Speaks for Canada: Defining <strong>and</strong> Sustaining a National<br />

Vision,” in Behiels ed. (1989), 60-99.<br />

Whitaker, Reg (1987), “Neo-Conservatism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State” in Milib<strong>and</strong>, Panitch <strong>and</strong> Saville, eds.<br />

(1987), 1-31.<br />

Whyte, John D. <strong>and</strong> Ian Peach eds. (1989), Re-Forming Canada? <strong>The</strong> Meaning of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Free Trade Agreement for <strong>the</strong> Canadian State (Kingston: Queen’s<br />

University Institute of Intergovernmental Relations).<br />

204


Lilianne E. Krosenbrink-Gelissen<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong><br />

Aboriginal Women’s Rights:<br />

Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Abstract<br />

This article examines Indian women’s conflicts <strong>and</strong> dilemmas with <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of 1982 as a result of <strong>the</strong>ir culture <strong>and</strong> gender.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir dual identity has made it difficult for <strong>the</strong>m to settle on an acceptable<br />

balance between <strong>the</strong>ir aboriginal <strong>and</strong> sexual equality rights. By examing <strong>the</strong><br />

views of <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada, a national, aboriginal<br />

women’s group, <strong>the</strong> author describes Indian women’s aspirations <strong>and</strong><br />

strategies for reformulating an Indian female identity within <strong>the</strong> aboriginal<br />

constitutional reform process.<br />

Résumé<br />

L’article examine les tiraillements que provoquent la <strong>Constitution</strong> de 1982 et<br />

la <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne des droits et libertés chez les amérindiennes en raison de<br />

leurs antécédents culturels et de leur sexe. Leur double identité rend difficile la<br />

réalisation d’un équilibre entre les aspirations à l’autonomie de leurs peuples<br />

et leurs droits à l’égalité sexuelle. À partir des vues adoptées par la Native<br />

Women’s Association of Canada, un organisme national de femmes<br />

autochtones, l’auteure expose les aspirations et les stratégies des<br />

amérindiennes eu égard à la redéfinition de leur identité en tant que femme à<br />

l’occasion de la réforme constitutionnelle.<br />

Having been classified as a Métis, as a non-status person, <strong>and</strong> now as<br />

a status Indian, having lived in a city all my life, <strong>and</strong> having to deal<br />

with discrimination whe<strong>the</strong>r I was or was not a status Indian, I believe<br />

that all native people, including women, have aboriginal rights in<br />

this country no matter where <strong>the</strong>y live, no matter what distinctive<br />

category has been assigned to <strong>the</strong>m. (Aggamaway Pierre, former<br />

president of NWAC 1983:68; emphasis added)<br />

<strong>The</strong> time has come to break down <strong>the</strong> mentality forced upon us as<br />

Aboriginal people by <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. <strong>The</strong> time has come to rebuild<br />

our nations with all of our people — not just those who meet criteria<br />

established not by us but by <strong>the</strong> government. (NWAC, cited in: Govt.<br />

of Canada 1992:32)<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> repatriation of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> establishment of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms in 1982, <strong>the</strong> profile of aboriginal issues in <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian political culture has grown considerably. Three aboriginal issues<br />

have become especially prominent: aboriginal peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> criminal justice<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

system; aboriginal l<strong>and</strong> title; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> legal rights of aboriginal groups <strong>and</strong><br />

individuals within <strong>the</strong> Canadian state (cf. Hall 1992:42). Aboriginal selfgovernment,<br />

which integrates <strong>the</strong>se three areas, has emerged as a preeminent<br />

issue on <strong>the</strong> aboriginal constitutional reform agenda.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> have vitally affected aboriginal<br />

women as a group. However, aboriginal women’s experiences as well as <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

political concerns have been largely neglected in academic <strong>and</strong> political<br />

discourse on both aboriginal rights <strong>and</strong> women’s rights. Aboriginal rights<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s largely reflect <strong>the</strong> interests of aboriginal men, while women’s rights<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s, until very recently, have largely reflected <strong>the</strong> interests of white,<br />

middle-class women. In both cases, aboriginal women’s distinct perceptions<br />

are ignored. This article focuses on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> women’s<br />

rights specifically as <strong>the</strong>y pertain to First Nations’ women. I will explore <strong>the</strong><br />

nature <strong>and</strong> degree of <strong>the</strong> problems that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> raise<br />

for Indian women, 1 based on <strong>the</strong> views of <strong>the</strong>ir national political body, <strong>the</strong><br />

Native Women’s Association of Canada (NWAC). Because <strong>the</strong>y face a double<br />

discrimination, in contrast to <strong>the</strong>ir male counterparts, Indian women encounter<br />

special conflicts <strong>and</strong> dilemmas in trying to reconcile, as aboriginal persons <strong>and</strong><br />

as women, <strong>the</strong>ir self-government aspirations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir sexual equality<br />

aspirations.<br />

First, I will describe NWAC’s political aspirations <strong>and</strong> arguments with respect<br />

to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of 1982. Secondly, I will review sexual<br />

equality as it relates to aboriginal rights within <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act of 1982,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> problems NWAC perceives in this Act. Thirdly, I will briefly review<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional process on aboriginal matters (1982-1987) <strong>and</strong> NWAC’s<br />

strategy to re-define <strong>the</strong> aboriginal female identity in order to balance Indian<br />

women’s self-government aspirations with <strong>the</strong>ir feminist aspirations. I will<br />

also discuss Indian women’s problems after <strong>the</strong> 1984 constitutional<br />

amendment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> new Indian Act of 1985. <strong>The</strong>se problems remain intact <strong>and</strong><br />

have a bearing on NWAC’s strong rejection of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal rights provisions<br />

set out in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord which went down to defeat on October 26,<br />

1992. Although <strong>the</strong> material for this article primarily covers <strong>the</strong> period from<br />

1982 to 1987, it is also relevant to <strong>the</strong> period from 1987 to 1992. Indian<br />

women’s problems concerning <strong>the</strong> legal protection of <strong>the</strong>ir rights as First<br />

Nations citizens <strong>and</strong> as women remains, <strong>and</strong> NWAC continues to pursue its<br />

political aspirations <strong>and</strong> arguments. 2<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada<br />

<strong>The</strong> development of a distinct, aboriginal women’s movement in <strong>the</strong> early<br />

1970s is rooted in two global movements; <strong>the</strong> human rights movement <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

women’s movement. <strong>The</strong> first movement redirected <strong>the</strong> public’s <strong>and</strong><br />

politicians’ attention to <strong>the</strong> fundamental group rights of minorities within<br />

nation-states. As a consequence, since 1970 (<strong>and</strong> after <strong>the</strong> withdrawal of <strong>the</strong><br />

1969 “White Paper” plans to terminate Indian people’s separate legal status<br />

<strong>and</strong> special rights), <strong>the</strong> Canadian federal government began to promote selfcontrol<br />

mechanisms on Indian reserves <strong>and</strong> to foster <strong>the</strong> establishment of<br />

national aboriginal organizations that could effectively negotiate with <strong>the</strong><br />

government aboriginal peoples’ future status within <strong>the</strong> Canadian cultural <strong>and</strong><br />

political constellation. <strong>The</strong> second movement brought about a growing<br />

awareness of women’s subordinate status, made women’s issues more<br />

relevant to <strong>the</strong> public discourse, <strong>and</strong> fostered <strong>the</strong> political will to change <strong>the</strong><br />

position of women in society. <strong>The</strong> creation of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on <strong>the</strong><br />

208


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Status of Women (later <strong>the</strong> Advisory Council on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women) by <strong>the</strong><br />

government in 1967 reflects <strong>the</strong>se new developments.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada (NWAC) was established in<br />

1974 to politically represent aboriginal women’s views. NWAC’s m<strong>and</strong>ate<br />

consisted of promoting <strong>the</strong> interests of aboriginal women, <strong>and</strong> changing <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

image among Canadian society at large <strong>and</strong> among aboriginal men. Aboriginal<br />

women felt that existing national aboriginal organizations, particularly <strong>the</strong><br />

National Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood (later <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations), were maledominated<br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir leadership, <strong>the</strong>ir decision-making processes, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

political m<strong>and</strong>ates. As a result, aboriginal women’s particular concerns were<br />

not addressed (cf. Jamieson 1979; Krosenbrink 1991:67-90). Although<br />

NWAC was an Indian (status <strong>and</strong> non-status), Inuit <strong>and</strong> Métis women’s<br />

organization, it predominantly reflected Indian women’s grievances <strong>and</strong><br />

aspirations since <strong>the</strong>y comprised <strong>the</strong> overall majority. To date, Indian men <strong>and</strong><br />

women in particular have serious political differences. <strong>The</strong>se can largely be<br />

accounted for by colonial Indian policies that were sex-discriminatory <strong>and</strong><br />

detrimental to Indian women’s legal <strong>and</strong> socio-political status both in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

own communities <strong>and</strong> in Canadian society as a whole.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Indian Act of 1876 is synonymous with federal Indian policy. To this day,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Indian Act regulates who may legally claim to be Indian <strong>and</strong> controls<br />

Indian people’s lives to a significant degree. Traditional Indian political<br />

institutions were largely replaced <strong>and</strong> Indian male chieftainship was instituted<br />

to back-up <strong>the</strong> colonial system. Women were barred from political decisionmaking<br />

processes. From 1869 until 1951, <strong>the</strong>y could not hold electoral office<br />

nor vote for male representatives in <strong>the</strong>ir own communities. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong><br />

imposed Eurocanadian nuclear family structure, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> roles <strong>and</strong> rights of<br />

women <strong>the</strong>rein, constructed Indian women as a subordinate gender. Women<br />

were assumed to be dependent subjects who could only derive rights from <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

fa<strong>the</strong>rs or husb<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Most importantly, Indian ethnic belongingness could only be legally<br />

established through <strong>the</strong> male line of descendance. As a result, Indian women<br />

suffered from discrimination on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong>ir sex <strong>and</strong> marital status. Indian<br />

women, in contrast to men, could lose <strong>the</strong>ir legal status as Indians upon<br />

marriage to a non Indian man, including <strong>the</strong>ir offspring. Status Indians, who<br />

were automatically b<strong>and</strong> members, enjoyed certain exclusive rights such as <strong>the</strong><br />

right to live on a reserve, to participate in b<strong>and</strong> politics, <strong>and</strong> to receive free<br />

education <strong>and</strong> health care assistance. More importantly, status Indians had<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir cultural identity officially recognized, including <strong>the</strong>ir link to a homel<strong>and</strong><br />

(reserve). Several o<strong>the</strong>r Sections of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act discriminate against Indian<br />

women (cf. Sections 4, 10-6, 74, 76, 109, <strong>and</strong> 110 of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act 1970).<br />

However, I will limit my comments to Section 12(1)b of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act since it<br />

came to symbolize sexual discrimination against women. Jamieson (1978:1)<br />

summarizes <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act on Indian women who lost <strong>the</strong>ir legal<br />

status as follows:<br />

<strong>The</strong> woman, on marriage, must leave her parents’ home <strong>and</strong> her<br />

reserve. She may not own property on <strong>the</strong> reserve <strong>and</strong> must dispose of<br />

any property she does hold. She may be prevented from inheriting<br />

property left to her by her parents. She cannot take any fur<strong>the</strong>r part in<br />

b<strong>and</strong> business. Her children are not recognized as Indian <strong>and</strong> are<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore denied access to cultural <strong>and</strong> social amenities of <strong>the</strong> Indian<br />

community. And most punitive of all, she may be prevented from<br />

209


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

returning to live with her family on <strong>the</strong> reserve, even if she is in dire<br />

need, very ill, a widow, divorced or separated. Finally, her body may<br />

not be buried on <strong>the</strong> reserve with those of her forebears.<br />

Until <strong>the</strong> Indian Act was amended in 1985, <strong>the</strong> “old” Indian Act implicitly held<br />

19th century European assumptions on women. Legal Indian status<br />

regulations did not respect <strong>the</strong> cultural variety of Indian people’s social <strong>and</strong><br />

political organizations. <strong>The</strong>y imposed a uniform, Eurocanadian system<br />

reflecting racial images of Indians <strong>and</strong> male dominance in gender relations.<br />

Gradual internalization of <strong>the</strong> western notions of femaleness distorted <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian consciousness. Over <strong>the</strong> years, sexually discriminatory regulations had<br />

dramatic consequences not only for women, who lost <strong>the</strong>ir legal status as<br />

Indians by being deprived of <strong>the</strong>ir birth right, but also in terms of gender<br />

relations within Indian communities. <strong>The</strong> <strong>La</strong>vell <strong>and</strong> Bedard cases of 1973 as<br />

well as <strong>the</strong> Lovelace case of 1977, involving non-status Indian women who<br />

fought to regain <strong>the</strong>ir Indian rights, proved that Indian women could hope for<br />

little support from Indian men. Male Indian political leaders merely used<br />

women’s grievances with <strong>the</strong> Indian Act to force <strong>the</strong> federal government into<br />

negotiating a revised Indian Act (or better, a repeal) to allow for Indian selfgovernment<br />

(cf. note 3; Fiske 1992:12-4; Krosenbrink 1991: 84-102; Silman<br />

1987).<br />

<strong>The</strong> 1970s can be characterized as a period when Indian men <strong>and</strong> women,<br />

through <strong>the</strong>ir political organizations, engaged in often bitter debates over <strong>the</strong><br />

nature of “Indian rights” <strong>and</strong> “women’s rights.” It appeared that <strong>the</strong> National<br />

Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood more or less interpreted “Indian rights” to mean rights to<br />

which only status Indian men were entitled. <strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association<br />

argued that Indian women did not fight for sexual equality as such; <strong>the</strong>y fought<br />

for “Indian rights for Indian women” which were withheld through both <strong>the</strong><br />

legal instruments of <strong>the</strong> federal government <strong>and</strong> male chauvinist attitudes<br />

within b<strong>and</strong> councils on <strong>the</strong> reserves. Thus, Indian women felt that <strong>the</strong>re was a<br />

serious denial through sex discrimination of equal Indian rights for Indian<br />

women (ibid).<br />

Considering <strong>the</strong> different experiences of Indian men <strong>and</strong> women, it is no<br />

wonder that NWAC formulated different goals within <strong>the</strong> framework of<br />

constitutional aboriginal reform. All national, aboriginal organizations,<br />

including NWAC, focused on defining <strong>the</strong> nature of self-government within<br />

<strong>the</strong> constitutional aboriginal rights provision. However, NWAC claimed that<br />

<strong>the</strong> principle of sexual equality between aboriginal men <strong>and</strong> women must<br />

clearly <strong>and</strong> constitutionally st<strong>and</strong> above <strong>and</strong> permeate all aspects of aboriginal<br />

rights, including self-government (NWAC 1980, 1981). Indian women, <strong>and</strong><br />

also Métis <strong>and</strong> Inuit women, wanted clear, unambiguous <strong>and</strong> adequately<br />

secured constitutional protection for aboriginal women. Thus, <strong>the</strong> main issue<br />

for NWAC was that aboriginal self-government, irrespective of its diversity,<br />

should always legally guarantee <strong>and</strong> practically reflect gender equality.<br />

NWAC’s sexual equality aspirations grounded its arguments for rejecting <strong>the</strong><br />

aboriginal self-government wording of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. NWAC<br />

primarily concerns itself with constitutional protection of aboriginal women’s<br />

rights. <strong>The</strong> Association considers law a valid instrument in seeking changes in<br />

women’s status <strong>and</strong> ensuring <strong>the</strong>ir full participation within <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

aboriginal communities. So, when speaking in terms of legal rights, what is it<br />

that <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada explicitly wants?<br />

210


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Aboriginal Women’s Rights<br />

Part I of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act (Sections 1-34) is referred to as <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> sets out basic guarantees of<br />

rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms that apply to all Canadians, including aboriginal persons.<br />

According to Section 15(1):<br />

Every individual is equal before <strong>and</strong> under <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> has <strong>the</strong> right to<br />

<strong>the</strong> equal protection <strong>and</strong> equal benefit of <strong>the</strong> law without<br />

discrimination <strong>and</strong>, in particular, without discrimination based on<br />

race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age or mental or<br />

physical disability (Govt. of Canada 1981:6).<br />

Gibson (1985:45) argues that before <strong>the</strong> establishment of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>the</strong>re was<br />

no constitutional protection for aboriginal persons against discrimination<br />

based on <strong>the</strong>ir aboriginal ancestry. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, Section 91(24) of <strong>the</strong><br />

British North America Act provided <strong>the</strong> Canadian state with <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

right to discriminate particularly against Indian persons. However, <strong>the</strong> Indian<br />

Act is now subject to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

Section 15 was not to come into effect until three years after patriation of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> (April 17, 1985) to enable <strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments<br />

to make <strong>the</strong> necessary adjustments to <strong>the</strong>ir laws. One of <strong>the</strong> many reasons for<br />

<strong>the</strong> three year delay was to allow time to revise <strong>the</strong> Indian Act (cf. Govt. of<br />

Canada 1982:13-4).<br />

Section 15 makes it difficult for <strong>the</strong> courts to restrict sexual equality. <strong>The</strong> listed<br />

grounds, such as race or sex, serve to alert <strong>the</strong> courts that any form of<br />

discrimination should be combatted in a more rigorous fashion than was<br />

previously <strong>the</strong> case. For instance, that marital status is not spelled out in <strong>the</strong><br />

equality rights provision does not mean that discrimination is allowed. Should<br />

an Indian woman ever decide to litigate on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong> sexdiscriminatory<br />

provisions of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act violate Section 15 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

(after April 17, 1985), it is most likely that <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court would be<br />

compelled to declare <strong>the</strong> offending Sections of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act invalid. Thus, a<br />

decision such as in <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>vell case could not be repeated (cf. Mahoney 1992;<br />

NWAC Newsletter 1, 5, 1982:7). 3<br />

<strong>The</strong> sexual equality rights in Section 15 refer to individual human rights which<br />

are never<strong>the</strong>less quasi-collective human rights as well. Indian women, as a<br />

group, have suffered as a result of <strong>the</strong> sex-discriminatory provisions of <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian Act (cf. Richstone 1983:42-43). Affirmative action, as set out in<br />

Section 15(2) of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act 1982, will enable aboriginal women in<br />

general, <strong>and</strong> Indian women in particular, to fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir needs <strong>and</strong> goals as a<br />

collectivity (ibid:52).<br />

Section 15, albeit crucially important to aboriginal women, is not of primary<br />

concern to <strong>the</strong>m. Whereas <strong>the</strong> women’s movement in Canada focuses on<br />

Section 15, <strong>the</strong> aboriginal women’s movement focuses on Section 25 of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. 4 <strong>The</strong> reason for this difference may be that equality rights, as<br />

formulated in Section 15, are perceived as non-aboriginal, liberal democratic<br />

concepts that may contravene <strong>the</strong> cultural traditions of aboriginal peoples. For<br />

instance, <strong>the</strong> traditionally exclusive right of Iroquois women to choose a<br />

(male) chief violates <strong>the</strong> rights of Iroquois men as stipulated in Section 15 of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (cf. Tooker 1984, in Spittal 1990). Never<strong>the</strong>less, we should not<br />

underestimate <strong>the</strong> power of Section 15. It dictated foremost a repeal of all<br />

211


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Sections in <strong>the</strong> “old” Indian Act which discriminate against Indian women on<br />

<strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong>ir sex <strong>and</strong> marital status. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, according to Section 28:<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing anything in this <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms<br />

referred to in it are guaranteed equally to male <strong>and</strong> female persons<br />

(Govt. of Canada 1981:10).<br />

This section is meant to ensure that “person” includes females as well as males.<br />

It should restrict loopholes for <strong>the</strong> provinces to legislate outside total<br />

agreement with <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights. Thus, Section 28 does assert <strong>the</strong> primacy of<br />

sexual equality rights over all o<strong>the</strong>r <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights, <strong>and</strong> in this respect it is<br />

important to aboriginal women as well (Gibson 1985:48-49; Mahoney<br />

1992:242; NWAC Newsletter, 1,5, 1982:8-9). <strong>The</strong> term “notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing”<br />

could eventually create problems. Although it may be presumed that <strong>the</strong> courts<br />

will subject <strong>the</strong> collective rights of aboriginal peoples to individual equality<br />

rights, <strong>the</strong>re is no absolute guarantee. No matter how important to aboriginal<br />

women’s rights, Section 28 could be used to debilitate <strong>the</strong> collective rights of<br />

aboriginal peoples which are referred to in Section 25:<br />

<strong>The</strong> guarantee in this <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of certain rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms shall not<br />

be construed so as to abrogate or derogate from any aboriginal, treaty<br />

or o<strong>the</strong>r rights or freedoms that pertain to <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples of<br />

Canada including (a) any rights or freedoms that have been<br />

recognized by <strong>the</strong> Royal Proclamation of October 7, 1763; <strong>and</strong> (b)<br />

any rights or freedoms that may be acquired by <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples<br />

of Canada by way of l<strong>and</strong> claims settlement (Govt. of Canada<br />

1981:9).<br />

This Section creates an exemption for aboriginal rights from being subjected to<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights. It ensures that Section 15 will not be used to strike down any<br />

collective rights of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples. 5 In contrast to Section 15, Section<br />

25 does nothing to advance <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples (Gibson<br />

1985:46). Aboriginal rights also refer to <strong>the</strong> collective right of aboriginal<br />

peoples to decide group membership for <strong>the</strong>mselves. <strong>The</strong> Indian Act,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore, violates Section 25 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, for it prevents Indian people from<br />

determining Indian status <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong> membership as long as <strong>the</strong> Indian Act<br />

remains intact. Within this framework, a repeal of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act is necessary<br />

as well. 6 However, <strong>the</strong> important question is whe<strong>the</strong>r Section 25 is subject to<br />

<strong>the</strong> equality rights of individuals. If not, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> rights of aboriginal women in<br />

aboriginal constitutions could be easily ignored. Indian self-governing b<strong>and</strong>s<br />

may design constitutions that provide for <strong>the</strong> equality rights of Indian men <strong>and</strong><br />

women, but <strong>the</strong>y could be easily modified to do away with <strong>the</strong> rights of women<br />

by majority consent of <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong>. Given <strong>the</strong> internalization of patriarchal<br />

notions as a result of <strong>the</strong> sex-discriminatory provisions of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act,<br />

Section 25 could represent a potential risk to Indian women that <strong>the</strong>ir equality<br />

rights may be denied by <strong>the</strong>ir own communities. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it could mean<br />

that Indian self-government does not provide uniform equality rights for<br />

Indian men <strong>and</strong> women (Richstone 1983:55). <strong>The</strong> uneasiness experienced by<br />

Indian women in trying to reconcile <strong>the</strong>ir culture (Section 25) <strong>and</strong> gender<br />

(Section 15) was clearly expressed by <strong>the</strong> president of <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association during 1992 debates on <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. She argued<br />

that when First Nations exercise powers under self-government, individuals<br />

deserve a guarantee of <strong>the</strong>ir basic human rights as set out in Section 15. If a<br />

First Nation should develop its own aboriginal <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

212


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Freedoms, it must include equality. This should be entrenched in <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> be enforceable in courts. Only <strong>the</strong>n would she agree to<br />

replacing <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (cf. note 4; Govt. of Canada 1992:32).<br />

Indian women’s serious concerns are closely related to <strong>the</strong>ir experience. When<br />

local Indian control was established in <strong>the</strong> early 1970s—meaning that Indian<br />

agents as government representatives left <strong>the</strong> reserves, <strong>the</strong>reby assigning <strong>the</strong><br />

execution of Indian Act regulations to b<strong>and</strong> councils— differences among<br />

b<strong>and</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> treatment of women became evident. Whereas one b<strong>and</strong> might<br />

have decided not to evict Indian women upon loss of <strong>the</strong>ir legal status, a<br />

neighbouring b<strong>and</strong> might have done just <strong>the</strong> opposite. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, in 1981,<br />

b<strong>and</strong>s were given <strong>the</strong> opportunity to request suspension of Section 12(1)b of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Indian Act although less than twenty percent of all b<strong>and</strong>s appears to have<br />

done so (Holmes 1987:6n6; NWAC Newsletter 1, 3, 1982:18).<br />

<strong>The</strong> relationship between Sections 15 <strong>and</strong> 28—in providing for (individual)<br />

sexual equality rights—<strong>and</strong> Section 25—in providing for (collective)<br />

aboriginal rights—is seriously strained. Given <strong>the</strong> experiences that Indian<br />

women, in particular, have faced as a result of <strong>the</strong>ir dual discrimination, <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> presented <strong>the</strong>m with a dilemma. What rights should come first, those<br />

relating to <strong>the</strong>ir gender or those relating to <strong>the</strong>ir aboriginal ancestry?<br />

Feminist groups have continually argued that sexual equality under all<br />

circumstances should prevail over aboriginal self-government. <strong>The</strong> National<br />

Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood (later <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations) has always taken <strong>the</strong><br />

position that no constitutional provision may supercede <strong>the</strong> aboriginal<br />

peoples’ right to self-government, including sexual equality rights. To<br />

aboriginal women, <strong>and</strong> most particularly Indian women, <strong>the</strong> situation was not<br />

that clear at all. <strong>The</strong>y could not escape conflicts in reconciling <strong>the</strong>ir gender <strong>and</strong><br />

cultures. <strong>The</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong> sex-dicriminatory status regulations of <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian Act play a crucial role in <strong>the</strong>ir experiences of conflict <strong>and</strong> dilemma (cf.<br />

Duclos 1990:369).<br />

<strong>The</strong> aboriginal rights provision considered <strong>the</strong> most important victory by<br />

aboriginal peoples is Section 35:<br />

(1). <strong>The</strong> existing aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples<br />

of Canada are hereby recognized <strong>and</strong> affirmed. (2). In this Act,<br />

“aboriginal peoples of Canada” includes <strong>the</strong> Indian, Inuit <strong>and</strong> Metis<br />

peoples of Canada’ (Govt. of Canada 1981:11).<br />

Although Section 35 is not part of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong>re is no doubt that <strong>the</strong> rights<br />

described in it are as effectively enforceable by <strong>the</strong> courts as <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights<br />

(Gibson 1985: 46-47). Its entrenchment was vigorously fought for by<br />

aboriginal peoples, especially during <strong>the</strong> November 1981 <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

repatriation upheavals. Because of its entrenchment, aboriginal peoples<br />

regained new pride in <strong>the</strong>ir distinct cultures <strong>and</strong> identities. For instance, <strong>the</strong><br />

inclusion of <strong>the</strong> Métis as an aboriginal people gave a considerable boost to <strong>the</strong><br />

Métis’ self-image.<br />

<strong>The</strong> term “existing” aboriginal rights in Section 35 creates ambiguity. With<br />

reference to aboriginal women, “existing” aboriginal rights could be<br />

interpreted as <strong>the</strong> perpetuation of existing discrimination, against Indian<br />

women in particular, as stipulated in <strong>the</strong> Indian Act (NWAC Newsletter, 1, 5,<br />

1982:10). For this reason, NWAC insisted that not only sexual discrimination<br />

213


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

be repealed but also that women <strong>and</strong> children who had previously lost <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

Indian rights as a result of sex discrimination should have <strong>the</strong>ir rights restored.<br />

<strong>The</strong> meaning of aboriginal rights is not clear. For <strong>the</strong> purpose of defining <strong>the</strong>se<br />

rights, Section 37 of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> provided for a negotiation process<br />

between state authorities <strong>and</strong> national aboriginal organizations. Aboriginal<br />

peoples in general refer to aboriginal rights as a multitude of socio-economic,<br />

political, legal <strong>and</strong> cultural rights. More specifically, <strong>the</strong>se rights are integrated<br />

in <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples’ concept of aboriginal self-government which has<br />

become <strong>the</strong> single most important issue on <strong>the</strong> agenda for Section 35<br />

discussions. Nei<strong>the</strong>r First Nations nor <strong>the</strong> federal government are precise<br />

about what self-government means. Most generally, it refers to a collective<br />

right of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples—in accordance with <strong>the</strong>ir own traditions—to<br />

control <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>the</strong>ir resources, <strong>the</strong>ir own destiny <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own political<br />

future.<br />

Whereas <strong>the</strong> collective rights of aboriginal peoples are referred to in Sections<br />

25 <strong>and</strong> 35, Sections 15 <strong>and</strong> 28 pertain to <strong>the</strong> equality rights of individuals.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is an obvious tension between individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights of<br />

aboriginal peoples that creates a serious dilemma for Indian women: if <strong>the</strong>y<br />

give priority to women’s rights, <strong>the</strong>y might endanger <strong>the</strong> collective (selfgoverning)<br />

rights of Indians; <strong>and</strong> should <strong>the</strong>y give priority to <strong>the</strong> collective<br />

rights of Indians, <strong>the</strong>y risk sexual discrimination by <strong>the</strong>ir own people. As a<br />

result of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act system, <strong>the</strong> collective rights of Indians as a group<br />

collide with individual Indian women’s rights. Thus, Inuit <strong>and</strong> Métis women’s<br />

issues are more integrated into community issues <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y do not experience<br />

conflicts <strong>and</strong> dilemmas in <strong>the</strong>ir political aspirations to <strong>the</strong> extent that Indian<br />

women do. As yet, <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association has argued that women do<br />

not see <strong>the</strong>ir rights as First Nations citizens <strong>and</strong> as women explicitly protected<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Process: <strong>The</strong> Indian Traditional Mo<strong>the</strong>rhood<br />

Concept in Defence of Aboriginal Women’s Rights<br />

For <strong>the</strong> purpose of defining “aboriginal rights” in Section 35 of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> Act <strong>the</strong> federal government invited <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations<br />

(AFN), <strong>the</strong> Native Council of Canada, <strong>the</strong> Métis National Council, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Inuit Tapirisat of Canada to participate in <strong>the</strong> First Ministers’ Conferences on<br />

Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters that took place in 1983, 1984, 1985 <strong>and</strong><br />

1987. Both <strong>the</strong> federal government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association’s<br />

male counterpart, <strong>the</strong> AFN, objected to its participation. <strong>The</strong> government<br />

denied Indian women a formal seat on <strong>the</strong> grounds that NWAC was not<br />

democratic since it only represented women. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> government felt<br />

that aboriginal women were already represented in <strong>the</strong> negotiation process by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir respective national (male-dominated) organizations. <strong>The</strong> Assembly of<br />

First Nations objected because it feared that Indian women would steer <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional discussions away from self-government by focussing on <strong>the</strong><br />

sexual equality issue. Hence, <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association was only<br />

accorded observer status. Even after 1987, <strong>and</strong> to this day, NWAC has never<br />

won a seat at <strong>the</strong> constitutional table. 7<br />

In contrast to <strong>the</strong> AFN, <strong>the</strong> federal government never<strong>the</strong>less recognized <strong>the</strong><br />

need to address aboriginal women’s rights within <strong>the</strong> constitutional context.<br />

Except for NWAC, each one of <strong>the</strong> four national aboriginal organizations<br />

received extra funds to study sexual equality rights (Krosenbrink 1986;<br />

214


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Secretary of State 1985:21). However, it took until May 1984 before <strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations was willing to discuss with <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association <strong>the</strong> issue of sexual equality among Indian men <strong>and</strong> women. AFN<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less insisted that sexual equality was a matter that could only be dealt<br />

with by individual b<strong>and</strong>s once self-government was constitutionally<br />

entrenched as an aboriginal right <strong>and</strong> became operational. Hence, <strong>the</strong> AFN did<br />

not consider non-status Indian women wrongly deprived of <strong>the</strong>ir birth rights or<br />

entitled to participate in b<strong>and</strong> decisions on developing self-government<br />

(Krosenbrink 1991:160-4).<br />

NWAC’s fundamental condition that <strong>the</strong> principle of sexual equality should<br />

constitutionally st<strong>and</strong> above aboriginal self-government aimed to clearly<br />

guarantee that status as well as (in future reinstated) non-status Indian women<br />

have an equal right to participate in First Nations community life <strong>and</strong> would<br />

not encounter discrimination by b<strong>and</strong> councils under self-government (cf.<br />

NWAC Newsletter, 1, 8, 1983:3; Silman 1987:219). <strong>The</strong> following quote from<br />

NWAC (1984:15) is most illustrative:<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is an obvious contradiction in attempting to negotiate<br />

[aboriginal] rights that predate <strong>the</strong> very existence of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

government if <strong>the</strong> only base for recognition is a registration system<br />

[Indian Act] created by that government. It is <strong>the</strong>refore essential that<br />

all aboriginal people, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y possess a government<br />

number, realize <strong>the</strong> potential consequences of endorsing <strong>the</strong> status<br />

quo.<br />

Indian women did not want to wait until Indian self-government was<br />

established on reserves for fear that <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong>s would not treat <strong>the</strong>m fairly <strong>and</strong><br />

would not be willing to restore <strong>the</strong>ir rights. Whe<strong>the</strong>r sexual inequality is<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntically Indian or an historical offshoot of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act is not important.<br />

Nowadays, Indian women, as well as Metis <strong>and</strong> Inuit women, do not wish to be<br />

sexually discriminated against ei<strong>the</strong>r by law or in practice:<br />

In any case <strong>the</strong> appeal to tradition is irrelevant. If it had been part of<br />

our tradition to castrate first born males, this would not make it right<br />

or just to practise now. <strong>The</strong>re is always room for improvement (IRIW<br />

1980:5).<br />

As long as <strong>the</strong> constitutional right of aboriginal self-government was not<br />

entrenched, <strong>the</strong> Indian Act remained a regulating force. NWAC realized that<br />

one cannot do away with <strong>the</strong> Indian Act overnight, because several generations<br />

of Indians had based <strong>the</strong>ir identity <strong>and</strong> existence on it. <strong>The</strong>refore, a lot of Indian<br />

b<strong>and</strong>s would most likely establish <strong>the</strong>ir self-government, including b<strong>and</strong><br />

membership, along <strong>the</strong> lines of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act regulations. <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

equality guarantees were perceived as a prerequisite to aboriginal selfgovernment<br />

or a review of <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. NWAC eventually aimed to legally<br />

upgrade <strong>the</strong> socio-political status of Indian women in particular. Whoever or<br />

whatever would decide membership in <strong>the</strong> future, Indian women were not<br />

prepared to tolerate sexual discrimination anymore. As one of my female<br />

Indian informants summarized: “Sexual equality in law will help women to<br />

resume <strong>the</strong>ir traditional roles <strong>and</strong> to exercise <strong>the</strong> power that comes with <strong>the</strong>m<br />

naturally” (cited in: Krosenbrink 1991:139).<br />

215


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

To NWAC <strong>and</strong> its constituency, sexual equality comprised a whole range of<br />

issues, such as employment, political decision-making, recognition of<br />

women’s roles in communities, political respect by b<strong>and</strong> councils <strong>and</strong>, most<br />

importantly, <strong>the</strong> equal right to transmit status <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong> membership to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

families. <strong>The</strong> main problems for NWAC were: how to resolve differences of<br />

opinion with <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations; how to get involved in <strong>and</strong> have an<br />

impact on decision-making in <strong>the</strong> constitutional process despite Indian<br />

women’s marginalization; <strong>and</strong>, how to legitimatize <strong>the</strong> notion that aboriginal<br />

self-governing powers should not extend beyond <strong>the</strong> sexual equality<br />

provisions of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (meaning that NWAC’s political claims contravened<br />

<strong>the</strong> principle of aboriginal self-government).<br />

Within <strong>the</strong> aboriginal constitutional process from 1982 to 1987, NWAC began<br />

to re-define “female Indian identity” <strong>and</strong> to re-formulate its political goals to<br />

make <strong>the</strong>m valid <strong>and</strong> relevant within <strong>the</strong> self-government negotiations. <strong>The</strong><br />

Native Women’s Association knew that <strong>the</strong> federal government was in no<br />

position to oppose its objectives. Through equality provisions in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,<br />

as well as through international legal obligations, <strong>the</strong> government was<br />

compelled to resolve sexual discrimination against Indian women before April<br />

17, 1985. <strong>The</strong> federal government in particular appeared prepared to repeal <strong>the</strong><br />

sex-discriminatory status regulations in <strong>the</strong> Indian Act while at <strong>the</strong> same time<br />

providing for an equality guarantee within <strong>the</strong> aboriginal rights Section of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> Act.<br />

In order to make its claims relevant, particularly to its male counterpart, <strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations, NWAC began to operationalize <strong>the</strong> Indian people’s<br />

traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood notion. Traditional Indian mo<strong>the</strong>rhood reflects Indian<br />

men’s <strong>and</strong> women’s contemporary views of women’s past, de-symbolizes<br />

male authority, <strong>and</strong> expresses women’s distinct double identity as women <strong>and</strong><br />

as Indians. During fieldwork in Ottawa (1985, 1986, <strong>and</strong> 1987) among<br />

national aboriginal organizations, all male <strong>and</strong> female informants claimed that<br />

aboriginal women from all different cultures traditionally played central roles.<br />

Just as in o<strong>the</strong>r societies, <strong>and</strong> in o<strong>the</strong>r times, Indian women were<br />

predominantly defined by <strong>the</strong>ir reproductive role. However, this role was<br />

esteemed much differently. Indian women were traditionally responsible for<br />

<strong>the</strong> biological <strong>and</strong> cultural continuity of <strong>the</strong>ir communities. In <strong>the</strong> “old days,”<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were much respected for <strong>the</strong>ir ability to give birth <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong>ir family <strong>and</strong><br />

community roles. This was so strongly felt that metaphors of mo<strong>the</strong>rhood<br />

came to st<strong>and</strong> for female Indian identity. Mottos such as: “Indian women are<br />

<strong>the</strong> centre <strong>and</strong> wheel of life”; “Women are <strong>the</strong> core of Indian cultures”; “Indian<br />

women are <strong>the</strong> ultimate leaders”; “Women are <strong>the</strong> keepers of Indian cultures”;<br />

<strong>and</strong> “Without Indian women <strong>the</strong>re would be no Indian nations” directly refer to<br />

<strong>the</strong> symbolism of traditional Indian mo<strong>the</strong>rhood. <strong>The</strong>re is no question that<br />

Indian people recognize cultural diversity among <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> differences<br />

in sociopolitical organization. <strong>The</strong>y are well aware that women in traditionally<br />

matrilineal cultures have more fundamental rights than women in patrilineal<br />

cultures. In spite of this, Indian men <strong>and</strong> women confirm that <strong>the</strong>re was still<br />

more equality among <strong>the</strong> sexes in all traditional Indian cultures than non-<br />

Indians would ever recognize. For example, <strong>La</strong>vell, an important<br />

spokesperson for <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association during <strong>the</strong> early 1970s,<br />

argued:<br />

216<br />

[Indian] women had much respect <strong>and</strong> had decision-making powers<br />

within <strong>the</strong>ir own community. Perhaps it was not as evident to <strong>the</strong>


anthropologist, but within our system it was <strong>the</strong>re (cited in: House of<br />

Commons:15).<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it was claimed:<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

<strong>The</strong> fundamental role of <strong>the</strong> Indian mo<strong>the</strong>r as a basic link in <strong>the</strong><br />

cultural <strong>and</strong> linguistic continuity must not be underestimated if <strong>the</strong><br />

preservation <strong>and</strong> growth of <strong>the</strong> Indian way of life in Canada is indeed<br />

a priority (IRIW 1979:14).<br />

Irrespective of <strong>the</strong> many cultural differences, Indian men <strong>and</strong> women do<br />

believe that <strong>the</strong>ir traditional societies were egalitarian; that <strong>the</strong> sexes had<br />

different but equal socio-political positions (Krosenbrink 1991:44-8, 123-8). 8<br />

By contextualizing <strong>and</strong> exploring <strong>the</strong> functional mechanisms of <strong>the</strong><br />

ideological concept of traditional Indian mo<strong>the</strong>rhood, its importance for a<br />

political strategy becomes comprehensible.<br />

Unity, Boundary Establishment, <strong>and</strong> Mobilization<br />

Firstly, NWAC supported <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations’ notion of selfgovernment:<br />

As women we speak for ourselves, our children <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> generations<br />

yet unborn, <strong>and</strong> join with <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples of this l<strong>and</strong> in unity to<br />

declare that our rights, our nations <strong>and</strong> our sovereignty are ours to<br />

proclaim <strong>and</strong> ours to exercise (NWAC 1980).<br />

Secondly, by using <strong>the</strong> ideological concept of traditional Indian mo<strong>the</strong>rhood,<br />

NWAC facilitated group cohesiveness since Indian, Inuit <strong>and</strong> Métis women<br />

<strong>and</strong> men agreed upon it. <strong>La</strong>stly, <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>rhood concept was instrumental to<br />

<strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples’ political opposition to Canadian society at large. <strong>The</strong><br />

Federal government’s colonial policies were blamed for <strong>the</strong> current gender<br />

inequality within Indian communities which is considered inherently un-<br />

Indian. Paula Gunn Allen (a famous Pueblo Indian woman, feminist, scholar<br />

<strong>and</strong> poet) claims that gender equality inhered in all traditional First Nations’<br />

cultures of <strong>the</strong> North American hemisphere: “Among <strong>the</strong> major conceptual<br />

gifts First Nation people shared with <strong>the</strong> world is <strong>the</strong> concept of <strong>the</strong> central<br />

value of women in every sphere of community life; that <strong>the</strong> proper place of<br />

women, especially of elder women, is at <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong> spiritual, social,<br />

political, <strong>and</strong> economic life of <strong>the</strong> nation” (1992:3). Hence, NWAC did not<br />

have to publicly blame <strong>the</strong> AFN for its reluctance to perceive women’s issues<br />

as relevant. AFN’s statement (1984:10-1) on Indian women’s sexual equality<br />

during <strong>the</strong> 1984 constitutional conference is most illustrative:<br />

<strong>The</strong> discrimination <strong>the</strong>y [women] suffered was forced upon us by<br />

white colonial government through <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. It was not <strong>the</strong><br />

result of our traditional laws, <strong>and</strong> in fact it would not have occurred<br />

under our traditional laws. We must make it perfectly clear why we<br />

feel so strongly that we must control our own citizenship (...).<br />

<strong>The</strong> AFN maintains that “equality” does already exist within <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional “citizenship code” of all First Nations people.<br />

217


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

As <strong>the</strong> president of NWAC argued earlier: “B<strong>and</strong> governments must not mimic<br />

<strong>the</strong> discriminatory practices of <strong>the</strong> dominant governments” (NWAC<br />

Newsletter, 1, 8, 1983, p. 3). And, in accordance with <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association’s Declaration of Principles <strong>and</strong> Beliefs (1980):<br />

We believe that it is <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal people to determine<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own citizenship, <strong>and</strong> that it is <strong>the</strong> right of all people of aboriginal<br />

descent who so wish to be recognized as such ... We believe that it is<br />

<strong>the</strong> fundamental right of Native women to have access <strong>and</strong><br />

participation in any decision-making process, <strong>and</strong> full protection of<br />

<strong>the</strong> law without discrimination based on sex or marital status ... We<br />

believe that our future lies as sovereign nations with our rights as<br />

women protected. We desire to live under a government of our own<br />

making.<br />

<strong>The</strong> traditional Indian mo<strong>the</strong>rhood concept is an integral part of <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

culture argument used in <strong>the</strong> Indian people’s struggle for self-government.<br />

Indian self-government is only attainable when cultural traditions<br />

reestablished. Hence, <strong>the</strong>re cannot be true Indian self-government without<br />

sexual equality. NWAC’s arguments <strong>the</strong>refore compelled <strong>the</strong> AFN to discuss<br />

sexual equality within <strong>the</strong> aboriginal constitutional context.<br />

Legitimization of NWAC’s Separate Existence <strong>and</strong> Exclusive M<strong>and</strong>ate<br />

<strong>The</strong> traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood concept is inextricably tied to notions of care as<br />

<strong>the</strong>y apply to women. Indian women are traditionally held responsible for<br />

caring about <strong>the</strong> cultural <strong>and</strong> biological continuity of <strong>the</strong>ir families <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

communities. Firstly, NWAC exp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>se notions of care to legitimize<br />

Indian women’s political separateness, respecting both <strong>the</strong>ir organization <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir aspirations:<br />

In fact, all subject areas have a direct affect on us, as <strong>the</strong>y do on all<br />

segments of aboriginal society. However, <strong>the</strong>re are some issues<br />

which are of more particular interest to us because of our special role<br />

in aboriginal society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> direct influence those issues have on<br />

native women (NWAC Newsletter, 1, 8, 1983:2).<br />

Secondly, in fulfilling <strong>the</strong>ir caring roles, Indian women integrate <strong>the</strong>ir care for<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves with care for <strong>the</strong>ir families <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir communities, <strong>and</strong> this<br />

automatically motivates women to political participation <strong>and</strong> action. For<br />

example, women’s political struggle to acquire clear water <strong>and</strong> sewer systems<br />

on today’s reserves is motivated by <strong>the</strong>ir responsibility to care. This entails that<br />

women’s roles <strong>and</strong> responsibilities cannot be met unless women have<br />

decision-making rights (cf. Fiske 1990-1, 1992). NWAC claimed that, on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of women’s caring responsibilities, <strong>the</strong>y had to politically take care also.<br />

This way, <strong>the</strong> Association was able to legitimize itself among its own<br />

constituency, o<strong>the</strong>r (male-dominated) national aboriginal organizations, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian government. This was necessary for NWAC to become involved<br />

<strong>and</strong> to play a role in <strong>the</strong> constitutional process on aboriginal matters in spite of<br />

lacking a formal participant position.<br />

Mainstreaming Indian Women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Challenge for Change<br />

Particularly with respect to NWAC’s lack of a formal position it was necessary<br />

to formulate political aspirations within <strong>the</strong> frame of reference of both <strong>the</strong><br />

218


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> AFN (cf. Adamson et al. 1988:180-190). NWAC had to<br />

reckon with non-aboriginal perceptions of aboriginal peoples, as well as <strong>the</strong><br />

views of women held by society at large <strong>and</strong> those held by aboriginal men.<br />

Hence, because of Indian women’s double identity—gender <strong>and</strong><br />

culture—<strong>the</strong>y were in triple jeopardy. 9 If NWAC had disengaged from <strong>the</strong><br />

aboriginal movement it would have seriously risked compromising its goals<br />

within <strong>the</strong> aboriginal constitutional context. 10 It is not a matter of “buying-off”<br />

but ra<strong>the</strong>r an Indian women’s challenge to re-define femaleness <strong>and</strong> to<br />

engender aboriginal identity. In view of <strong>the</strong> above, <strong>the</strong> only avenue open for<br />

NWAC was to formulate its aspirations within <strong>the</strong> context of aboriginal selfgovernment.<br />

Dissociation from <strong>the</strong> Women’s Movement<br />

<strong>The</strong>re can be no doubt that aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir way of politically<br />

organizing has been considerably influenced by <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s<br />

movement since <strong>the</strong> late 1960s <strong>and</strong> early 1970s. But Indian women in<br />

particular faced <strong>the</strong> challenge of balancing loyalty to <strong>the</strong> aboriginal peoples’<br />

self-government aspirations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir feminist aspirations. In order for NWAC<br />

to integrate women’s rights into aboriginal rights, it had to choose a strategy of<br />

dissociation from <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement, which was largely<br />

portrayed as white, middle-class dominated. Discussions on Indian women’s<br />

issues—through <strong>the</strong> underlying traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood notion—were<br />

replaced from <strong>the</strong> context of human, individual <strong>and</strong> white feminist rights to<br />

that of aboriginal, collective rights. <strong>The</strong> connection between sexual equality<br />

<strong>and</strong> aboriginal rights was necessary to establish better terms with <strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations <strong>and</strong> to gain support (Krosenbrink 1991:128-41; cf.<br />

NWAC 1980). However, it appears that after 1990 <strong>the</strong> old controversy<br />

between NWAC <strong>and</strong> AFN revived, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association<br />

(particularly <strong>the</strong> national office) re-established relations with <strong>the</strong> National<br />

Action Committee of Women, an umbrella organization of Canadian women’s<br />

groups (<strong>The</strong> Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, October 9/92).<br />

<strong>The</strong> strategic use of <strong>the</strong> ideological concept of Indian traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r with Indian women’s actions <strong>and</strong> lobbying was not without positive<br />

results. NWAC was able to play a role in <strong>the</strong> negotiations on aboriginal<br />

constitutional rights. NWAC presented position papers to <strong>the</strong> heads of <strong>the</strong><br />

federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments as well as to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r national aboriginal<br />

organizations. It vigorously lobbied through its National Committee on<br />

Aboriginal Rights. After all, it took part in <strong>the</strong> First Ministers’ Conferences on<br />

Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters as delegates from several provincial<br />

governments (e.g. Ontario, Manitoba, Quebec, <strong>and</strong> Saskatchewan), as<br />

delegates of <strong>the</strong> Native Council of Canada (1983 <strong>and</strong> 1984), <strong>and</strong> later of <strong>the</strong><br />

AFN (1985 <strong>and</strong> 1987). <strong>The</strong> Association also participated in parliamentary<br />

commissions on Indian self-government <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> Indian Act (Krosenbrink<br />

1991:146-79).<br />

When <strong>the</strong> constitutional process on aboriginal matters officially ended in<br />

March, 1987, NWAC could count its gains. Sexual equality was put on <strong>the</strong><br />

aboriginal constitutional agenda by <strong>the</strong> government. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Accord on Aboriginal Rights of 1983, which became <strong>the</strong> 1984 <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

Amendment Proclamation, entailed a sexual equality guarantee in <strong>the</strong><br />

aboriginal rights provision of Section 35. However, since <strong>the</strong> matter of<br />

aboriginal rights (self-government) was not resolved during <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

process—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord that included recognition of <strong>the</strong> right<br />

219


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

to aboriginal self-government was defeated by referendum in 1992—<strong>the</strong><br />

provision has only symbolic value. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, AFN <strong>and</strong> NWAC joined in<br />

May 1984 to uphold an Indian Act amendment whose details <strong>the</strong>y objected to<br />

(cf. AFN/NWAC Press Statement on Bill C-47, 22-6-84). <strong>La</strong>stly, in 1985 <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian Act was amended by Bill C-31. <strong>The</strong> sex-discriminatory regulations in<br />

<strong>the</strong> old Act were repealed <strong>and</strong> reinstatement was provided to persons who had<br />

lost or who had never had <strong>the</strong>se rights as a result. <strong>The</strong> new Indian Act also<br />

provided for Indian b<strong>and</strong> control of membership, meaning that legal status <strong>and</strong><br />

b<strong>and</strong> membership in future are disconnected <strong>and</strong> that b<strong>and</strong>s may decide to<br />

include certain non-status Indians in, <strong>and</strong> to exclude certain status Indians,<br />

from <strong>the</strong>ir membership (cf. Indian Act 1985; Krosenbrink 1991:170-94).<br />

Since self-government has not been constitutionally defined <strong>and</strong> entrenched as<br />

yet, <strong>the</strong> Indian Act, with its legal status stipulations, is still <strong>the</strong> most important<br />

regulator of Indian people’s lives. <strong>The</strong> new Indian Act, Bill C-31, is far too<br />

complex to discuss in this article.<br />

Where Do Indian Women Go From Here?<br />

Given NWAC’s marginal position, <strong>and</strong> in view of Indian women’s conflicts<br />

<strong>and</strong> dilemmas in balancing aboriginal <strong>and</strong> feminist aspirations, we can<br />

conclude that NWAC was relatively successful in reaching its goals with<br />

respect to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> by 1987. NWAC’s strategic use of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Indian traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood concept largely attributed to its success.<br />

However, as Mancini Billson argues:<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> 1982 Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms<br />

entrenches equality for women <strong>and</strong> minorities, <strong>the</strong> eradication of<br />

racism, ethnocentrism <strong>and</strong> sexism will be harder to guarantee<br />

(1991:64).<br />

A comprehensive assessment of <strong>the</strong> impact of Bill C-31, which was released<br />

by Indian Affairs in 1990 (in conjunction with particularly NWAC <strong>and</strong> AFN),<br />

clearly illustrates that Indian women still suffer from sexual discrimination<br />

(INAC 1990). <strong>The</strong> Indian Act may have done away with some aspects of<br />

sexual discrimination but has given room to o<strong>the</strong>rs. Not all persons who had<br />

lost or never gained Indian status are eligible for reinstatement. Children of<br />

reinstated Indian women do not have <strong>the</strong> same right to transmit status <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong><br />

membership as children of <strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r’s bro<strong>the</strong>r. Not only do <strong>the</strong> new rules<br />

appear to perpetuate (residual) sexual discrimination, but Indian b<strong>and</strong>s<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves appear to put up barriers to prevent directly or indirectly reinstated<br />

women from exercising <strong>the</strong>ir (automatic) b<strong>and</strong> membership rights. Indian<br />

women who have <strong>the</strong>ir birth rights restored are excluded from <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

communities’ political processes <strong>and</strong> are hampered from residing on <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

homel<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> from voting in b<strong>and</strong> elections. Thus, Indian women still face<br />

legal <strong>and</strong> practical problems in reconciling <strong>the</strong>ir culture <strong>and</strong> gender (cf.<br />

Holmes 1987; Duclos 1990).<br />

To some b<strong>and</strong>s, practical <strong>and</strong> economical reasons for denying reinstated<br />

women <strong>the</strong> exercise of <strong>the</strong>ir Indian rights, such as access to <strong>the</strong>ir reserves, may<br />

have a greater weight than any argument leading in <strong>the</strong> direction of sexual<br />

discrimination. However, Indian women who have never lost <strong>the</strong>ir status <strong>and</strong><br />

who have lived on a reserve all <strong>the</strong>ir lives appear to suffer from sexual<br />

discrimination also (cf. Silman 1987). Many b<strong>and</strong>s oppose <strong>the</strong> old as well as<br />

<strong>the</strong> new Indian Act as <strong>the</strong> government’s tool for setting <strong>the</strong> parameters of<br />

220


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Indian self-government. To <strong>the</strong>se b<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>the</strong> issue of sexual discrimination or<br />

sexual equality is not relevant (cf. Duclos 1990). However, to Indian women,<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir struggle for sexual equality remains inextricably tied to Indian selfgovernment.<br />

So, where do Indian women go from here? Firstly, I argue that it is necessary<br />

that both <strong>the</strong> government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations recognize <strong>the</strong><br />

Native Women’s Association as a separate organization with a legitimate<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y include it in all national political discussions on an equal<br />

footing. This is particularly important in view of future self-government<br />

negotiations during <strong>the</strong> “Charlottetown aftermath.” Secondly, <strong>the</strong><br />

government, which was responsible for Indian women’s problems in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

place, has to provide very explicit <strong>and</strong> unambiguous guarantees of Indian<br />

women’s equality rights. This means also that residual sexual discrimination<br />

in <strong>the</strong> new Indian Act should be eliminated. Thirdly, Indian women in <strong>the</strong><br />

communities have to take action to alter sex-discriminatory attitudes. <strong>La</strong>stly,<br />

<strong>the</strong> matter of Indian self-government should be constitutionally resolved in<br />

due course. Only when men’s <strong>and</strong> women’s special legal status <strong>and</strong> rights are<br />

explicitly <strong>and</strong> constitutionally recognized <strong>and</strong> affirmed may <strong>the</strong> Indian Act’s<br />

status regulations become redundant <strong>and</strong> Indian men <strong>and</strong> women better able to<br />

work toge<strong>the</strong>r towards a future as truly self-governing First Nations.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada can be viewed as manifestation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Indian women’s movement. It is unique in its claim that<br />

equality between <strong>the</strong> sexes can only be established through <strong>the</strong> restoration of<br />

cultural traditions, among which gender equality. By strategically using <strong>the</strong><br />

ideological concept of traditional mo<strong>the</strong>rhood <strong>the</strong> Association was able to<br />

resolve conflicts <strong>and</strong> dilemmas in connecting aboriginal <strong>and</strong> equality rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> author argues that explicit sexual equality guarantees within <strong>the</strong> frame of<br />

constitutionally entrenched Indian self-government are a prerequisite in order<br />

for women to have <strong>the</strong>ir rights as First Nations’ citizens protected.<br />

Notes<br />

1. I am grateful for <strong>the</strong> financial support of <strong>The</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s Organization for Scientific<br />

Research (NWO) during <strong>the</strong> preparation of this article.<br />

2. Informants’ data for <strong>the</strong> article were ga<strong>the</strong>red during fieldwork in Canada in 1983, 1985,<br />

1986, 1987 <strong>and</strong> 1990. For a more extensive study on Canadian Indian women, see<br />

Krosenbrink (1991).<br />

3. <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court decided in a five to four vote against <strong>La</strong>vell. <strong>The</strong> Canadian Bill of Rights<br />

(1960) was not considered effective to overrule <strong>the</strong> Indian Act, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that Indian<br />

women were treated differently was not considered relevant to <strong>the</strong> case as brought forward<br />

(Eberts 1985:61; Jamieson 1978:85-86; Kerr 1975:23).<br />

4. This argument holds specifically for <strong>the</strong> period 1982-1987. During <strong>the</strong> debates on <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown agreement in <strong>the</strong> summer of 1992, it appeared that NWAC shifted its focus to<br />

Section 15. <strong>The</strong> Association’s President argued that basic human rights as recognized in<br />

international law <strong>and</strong> enforceable under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> must be guaranteed to every individual<br />

including First Nations persons (Govt. of Canada 1992:32).<br />

5. Ethnic (immigrant) groups in Canada cannot claim collective rights, o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> quasicollective<br />

rights spelled out in section 15 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> aboriginal peoples’ rejection of<br />

being classified as ethnic group st<strong>and</strong>s in close relationship to section 25 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

6. <strong>The</strong> U.N. decision in 1981 on <strong>the</strong> Lovelace case particularly referred to <strong>the</strong> self- determining<br />

rights of minority groups in relation to membership (cf. article 27 of <strong>the</strong> International<br />

Covenant on Civil <strong>and</strong> Political Rights, 1976).<br />

221


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

7. In August 1992, NWAC tried through <strong>the</strong> Federal Court of Appeal to obtain <strong>the</strong> right to a<br />

formal seat at <strong>the</strong> constitutional bargaining table. Although <strong>the</strong> Association won, <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government continued negotiations with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r four national aboriginal organizations <strong>and</strong><br />

refused direct participation to <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association. On October 13, 1992,<br />

NWAC tried to block <strong>the</strong> national referendum in Federal Court because <strong>the</strong> aboriginal selfgovernment<br />

provision of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord was not explicitly subordinated to <strong>the</strong><br />

equality provision in <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (<strong>The</strong> Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, Oct. 13/92:A8).<br />

8. Primary <strong>and</strong> secondary source material on <strong>the</strong> (re)evaluation of Indian women’s traditional<br />

roles <strong>and</strong> positions have grown since <strong>the</strong> second women’s movement of <strong>the</strong> late 1960s <strong>and</strong><br />

early 1970s (cf. e.g. Brant 1988; Green 1983; Gunn Allen 1989; Jamieson 1982;<br />

Krosenbrink 1984:5-27, 1991:39-48).<br />

9. According to Hall: “Compelling arguments can be made in support of <strong>the</strong> assertion that <strong>the</strong><br />

oppression of women in Aboriginal communities represents a distilled variety of <strong>the</strong> basis<br />

present more generally throughout Canadian society” (1992:42).<br />

10. <strong>The</strong> National Committee on Indian Rights for Indian Women (IRIW) favoured a strategy of<br />

disengagement in <strong>the</strong> 1970s. <strong>The</strong> consequence was that <strong>the</strong>y continued <strong>the</strong>ir existence as<br />

merely an Alberta (non-status) Indian women’s group after 1981 (Krosenbrink 1991:99).<br />

Bibliography<br />

Adamson, N. et al. 1988. Feminist Organizing for Change: <strong>The</strong> Contemporary Women’s<br />

Movement in Canada. Toronto: Oxford Univ. Press.<br />

AFN. 1984. “AFN Statement on Equality during FMC.” In: Unity 1(1):10-1.<br />

AFN/NWAC Press Statement. 1984. Statement on Bill C-47, June 22, 1984.<br />

Aggamaway Pierre, M. 1983. “Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State.” In: Turner, J. & L. Emery, eds.<br />

Perspectives on Women in <strong>the</strong> 1980s, pp. 66-73. Winnipeg: <strong>The</strong> Univ. of Manitoba Press.<br />

Brant, B., ed. 1988. A Ga<strong>the</strong>ring of Spirit: A Collection by North American Indian Women.<br />

Ithaca/New York: Firebr<strong>and</strong> Books.<br />

Duclos, N. 1990. “Lessons of Difference: Feminist <strong>The</strong>ory on Cultural Diversity.” In: Buffalo <strong>La</strong>w<br />

Review 38(2):325-81.<br />

Eberts, M. 1985. “<strong>The</strong> Use of Litigation under <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms as a<br />

Strategy for Achieving Change.” In: Nevitte, N. & A. Kornberg, eds. Minorities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian State, pp. 53-70. Oakville: Mosaic Press.<br />

Fiske, J. 1990-1. “Native Women in Reserve Politics: Strategies <strong>and</strong> Struggles.” In: Journal of<br />

Legal Pluralism <strong>and</strong> Unofficial <strong>La</strong>w 30(1):121-37.<br />

–––––1992. Child of <strong>the</strong> State Mo<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> Nation: Aboriginal Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ideology of<br />

Mo<strong>the</strong>rhood. Paper presented to <strong>the</strong> Joint Meetings of <strong>the</strong> Atlantic Canada Studies <strong>and</strong> B.C.<br />

Studies Associations, May 21-4, 1992.<br />

Gibson, D. 1985. “Protection of Minority Rights under <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Freedoms: Can Politicians <strong>and</strong> Judges Sing Harmony?” In: Nevitte, N. & A. Kornberg, eds.<br />

Minorities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian State, pp. 31-52. Oakville: Mosaic Press.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail. 1992. Support for Deal Growing Among Native Women, October 9, 1992.<br />

–––––1992. Native Women Aim to Block National Referendum in Court: Women’s Association<br />

Says Federal Government Violated Rights by Failing to Give <strong>The</strong>m Voice at <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Talks, October 13, 1992:A8.<br />

Government of Canada. 1981. <strong>The</strong> Canadian <strong>Constitution</strong>, 1981: A Resolution Adopted by <strong>the</strong><br />

Parliament of Canada, December, 1981. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada.<br />

–––––1982. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> You. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada.<br />

–––––1992. First Peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>: Conference Report, Ottawa, March 13-5, 1992.<br />

Ottawa: Privy Council Office.<br />

Green, R. 1983. Native American Women: A Contextual Bibliography. Bloomington: Indiana<br />

Univ. Press.<br />

Gunn Allen, P., ed. 1989. Spider Woman’s Gr<strong>and</strong>daughters: Traditional Tales <strong>and</strong> Contemporary<br />

Writing by Native American Women. Boston: Beacon Press.<br />

–––––1992. <strong>The</strong> Voice of <strong>the</strong> Turtle: A Century of American Indian Fiction. Paper presented at <strong>the</strong><br />

7th Bertrant Russell Lecture of <strong>the</strong> Working Group Indigenous Peoples in <strong>The</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s,<br />

Amsterdam, October 11, 1992.<br />

Hall, T. 1992. “<strong>The</strong>oretical Discourse in Native Studies.” In: ACS Newsletter 14(1):40-3.<br />

Holmes, J. 1987. Bill C-31, Equality or Disparity? <strong>The</strong> Effects of <strong>the</strong> New Indian Act on Native<br />

Women. Ottawa: CACSW.<br />

House of Commons St<strong>and</strong>ing Committee on Indian Affairs <strong>and</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Development. 1976.<br />

Minutes of Proceedings <strong>and</strong> Evidence, issue # 53. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer for Canada.<br />

INAC (Indian <strong>and</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Affairs Canada). 1990. Impacts of <strong>the</strong> 1985 Amendments to <strong>the</strong> Indian<br />

Act (Bill C-31): Summary Report. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada.<br />

222


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Women’s<br />

Rights: Conflicts <strong>and</strong> Dilemmas<br />

Indian Act: An Act Respecting Indians, Chapter I-6. 1970. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer for Canada.<br />

–––––1985. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada.<br />

IRIW (Indian Rights for Indian Women). 1979. A Study on <strong>the</strong> Emotional Impact of Arbitrary<br />

Enfranchisement on Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir Families in Canada. Edmonton: IRIW.<br />

–––––1980. Position Review. Edmonton: IRIW (not published).<br />

Jamieson, K. 1978. Indian Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>La</strong>w in Canada: A Citizens Minus. Ottawa: Minister of<br />

Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada.<br />

–––––1979 “Multiple Jeopardy: <strong>The</strong> Evolution of a Native Women’s Movement.” In: Atlantis<br />

4(2):157-78.<br />

–––––1982. Native Women in Canada: A Selected Bibliography. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong><br />

Services Canada.<br />

Kerr, S. 1975. Women’s Rights <strong>and</strong> Two National Native Organizations: <strong>The</strong> Native Council of<br />

Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> National Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood. Ottawa: Carleton University (not published).<br />

Krosenbrink-Gelissen, L. 1984. No Indian Women No Indian Nation: Canadian Native Women in<br />

Search of <strong>The</strong>ir Identity. Nijmegen Univ. (not published).<br />

–––––1986.“Indiaanse-, Inuit en Metis organisaties in Canada en hun constitutionele fondsen.” In:<br />

De Kiva 23(1):15-6; 23(2):22-3.<br />

–––––1991. Sexual Equality as an Aboriginal Right: <strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association of Canada<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Process on Aboriginal Matters, 1982-1987. Saarbrucken/Fort<br />

<strong>La</strong>uderdale: Verlag Breitenbach Publishers.<br />

Mahoney, K. 1992. “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al <strong>La</strong>w of Equality in Canada.” In: Maine <strong>La</strong>w Review<br />

44(2):229-59.<br />

Mancini Billson, J. 1991. “Interlocking Identities: Gender Ethnicity <strong>and</strong> Power in <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

Context.” In: International Journal of Canadian Studies 3:49-67<br />

NWAC (Native Women’s Association of Canada). 1980. Declaration of Principles <strong>and</strong> Beliefs.<br />

Ottawa: NWAC.<br />

–––––1981. “Statement by NWAC on Native Women’s Rights.” In: Doerr, A. & M. Carrier, eds.<br />

Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in Canada, pp. 64-73. Ottawa: CACSW.<br />

–––––1982. “Millbrook ends Discrimination.” In: NWAC Newsletter 1(3):18.<br />

–––––1982. “Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.” In: NWAC Newsletter 1(5):7-11.<br />

–––––1983. “Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Issues.” In: NWAC Newsletter 1(8):2.<br />

–––––1983. “Equality Clause Not Enough Says NWAC President.” In: NWAC Newsletter 1(8):3.<br />

–––––1984. Contemporary Issues: Information Kit. Ottawa: NWAC.<br />

Richstone, J. 1983. Native Women, <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Equality Rights in Canada.<br />

Discussion paper prepared for NWAC. Ottawa: NWAC (not published).<br />

Secretary of State. 1985. Guide to Native Citizens’ Programs. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong><br />

Services Canada.<br />

Silman, J. 1987. Enough is Enough: Aboriginal Women Speak Out. Toronto: <strong>The</strong> Women’s Press.<br />

Tooker, E. 1990 (1984). “Women in Iroquois Society.” In: Spittal, W., ed. Iroquois Women: An<br />

Anthology (Iroquois Reprints), pp. 199-216. Oshweken: Iroqrafts.<br />

223


Radha Jhappan<br />

Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Discourse from 1982 to <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord *<br />

Abstract<br />

<strong>The</strong> 1992 Charlottetown Accord proposed to enshrine Canadian Aboriginal<br />

peoples’ inherent right to self-government. Had it been approved in <strong>the</strong><br />

national referendum of October 1992, <strong>the</strong> Accord would have created a third<br />

order of government within <strong>the</strong> federation. Aboriginal governments would<br />

have enjoyed great latitude in exercising a variety of powers currently<br />

available only to <strong>the</strong> provincial <strong>and</strong> federal governments. As governments <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> majority of citizens have previously resisted Aboriginal claims for a<br />

constitutional right to self-government, <strong>the</strong> Accord’s provisions indicated a<br />

profound shift in <strong>the</strong> Canadian mind-set regarding Aboriginal entitlements.<br />

Through analysis of position papers of <strong>the</strong> national Aboriginal organizations<br />

<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parties to <strong>the</strong> reform process, this paper surveys <strong>the</strong> central dialogue<br />

surrounding <strong>the</strong> main constitutional developments in Aboriginal affairs over<br />

<strong>the</strong> past decade. <strong>The</strong>re is evidence of considerable convergence on selfgovernment<br />

<strong>and</strong> its meaning, especially as politicians <strong>and</strong> citizens appear to<br />

have substantially accepted several of <strong>the</strong> core elements of Aboriginal<br />

discourse; inherency, <strong>the</strong> three nations concept <strong>and</strong> collective rights.<br />

However, questions regarding <strong>the</strong> application of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> gender<br />

equality rights show a continuing dissonance between individual <strong>and</strong><br />

collective rights as applied to Aboriginal governments.<br />

Résumé<br />

L’Accord de Charlottetown de 1992 proposait la constitutionnalisation du<br />

droit inhérent des peuples autochtones à l’autonomie. Si le référendum<br />

d’octobre de la même année avait entériné l’Accord, on aurait alors assisté à<br />

la création d’un troisième ordre de gouvernement au sein de la fédération. Les<br />

gouvernements autochtones auraient pu exercer un large éventail de pouvoirs<br />

qui n’appartiennent aujourd’hui qu’aux autorités fédérales et provinciales.<br />

Comme, jusqu’alors, les gouvernements et la majorité de la population<br />

s’étaient opposés à la reconnaissance officielle du droit à l’autonomie des<br />

peuples autochtones, les dispositions à cet égard de l’Accord de<br />

Charlottetown indiquaient un changement radical des mentalités chez les<br />

Canadiens. En procédant à l’analyse des exposés de vues présentés par les<br />

organismes autochtones et d’autres participants au processus de réforme, le<br />

présent article scrute le dialogue principal qui, depuis une décennie, a mené<br />

aux développements constitutionnels majeurs dans le dossier autochtone. Une<br />

nette convergence des opinions sur l’autonomie des peuples autochtones s’est<br />

réalisée au fur et à mesure que les hommes politiques et les citoyens ont<br />

accepté les éléments clés du discours autochtone : les droits inhérents; le<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

concept des trois nations; et les droits collectifs. Des désaccords persistent<br />

toutefois au sujet des droits collectifs et des droits individuels quant au respect<br />

par les gouvernments autochtones de la disposition de la <strong>Charte</strong> en matière<br />

d’égalité des sexes.<br />

In October 1992, <strong>the</strong> five hundredth anniversary of <strong>the</strong> arrival of Columbus in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Americas, <strong>the</strong> citizens of Canada voted on a constitutional reform package<br />

which could have begun <strong>the</strong> restoration of that which <strong>the</strong> European invasion<br />

was to suppress: <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> indigenous peoples to govern <strong>the</strong>mselves. If<br />

passed, <strong>the</strong> self-government provisions would have put Canada’s Aboriginal<br />

peoples in <strong>the</strong> forefront of <strong>the</strong> international movement of indigenous peoples<br />

dedicated to reclaiming <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> socio-economic, cultural <strong>and</strong><br />

political rights usurped over five centuries of European settlement. In <strong>the</strong> end,<br />

however, Canadian voters rejected <strong>the</strong> package, which included a wide range<br />

of proposals apart from Aboriginal self-government. Indeed, although all but<br />

one of <strong>the</strong> Inuit communities of <strong>the</strong> North voted overwhelmingly in favour of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord, 62% of <strong>the</strong> on-reserve status Indian population rejected it. 1 Yet<br />

despite <strong>the</strong> Accord’s ultimate defeat, what is exceptional is that constitutional<br />

entrenchment of such a far-reaching bundle of rights was contemplated at all.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re has undoubtedly been a major contextual shift in Aboriginal politics in<br />

recent years. Just two decades ago, <strong>the</strong> federal government’s proposal to<br />

abolish <strong>the</strong> Indian Act met with <strong>the</strong> concerted <strong>and</strong> ultimately successful<br />

resistance of First Nations 2 across <strong>the</strong> country, who feared that <strong>the</strong>y would be<br />

cut adrift from <strong>the</strong> federal government’s fiduciary responsibilities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

admittedly limited benefits of <strong>the</strong> Act. 3 Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, although Aboriginal<br />

peoples made an historic break-through in winning <strong>the</strong> entrenchment of<br />

Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights in <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong>Constitution</strong> Act (discussed below),<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were unable to secure an amendment on <strong>the</strong> right to self-government in<br />

<strong>the</strong> four First Ministers Conferences on Aboriginal Matters held between 1983<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1987. This failure was principally due to <strong>the</strong> provinces’ refusal to entrench<br />

a right, <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>and</strong> nature of which <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal organizations involved<br />

were reluctant to limit via definition. As Gibbins has argued, in <strong>the</strong> political<br />

arena, politicians could be persuaded to deal with “domain-specific” issues<br />

which were both demonstrable <strong>and</strong> amenable to remedy (issues such as<br />

unemployment, housing shortages, inadequate education <strong>and</strong> infant mortality,<br />

for example). However, while <strong>the</strong>y were willing to contemplate Aboriginal<br />

autonomy in some areas of jurisdiction on an incremental basis, when issues of<br />

constitutional principle <strong>and</strong> national symbolism arose, “constitutional<br />

recognition of Indian sovereignty was a pill upon which <strong>the</strong> political system<br />

gagged.” 4<br />

In view of <strong>the</strong>se problems, <strong>the</strong> recent constitutional negotiations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

proposed constitutional amendments (outlined below) have revealed a seachange<br />

in <strong>the</strong> discourse surrounding Aboriginal peoples’ constitutional<br />

entitlements. <strong>The</strong> metamorphosis of this discourse is perceptible, not primarily<br />

among Aboriginal peoples, who have steadfastly held a core set of concepts<br />

<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, this change is evident among political decision-makers<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> public, where support for Aboriginal peoples’ political aspirations is at<br />

an all-time high. 5<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Agreement was reached after a long process of public<br />

discussions <strong>and</strong> hearings, sparked by <strong>the</strong> government of Canada’s<br />

constitutional reform proposals of September, 1991, entitled Shaping<br />

226


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r. 6 <strong>The</strong> proposals were followed by a series of crosscountry<br />

hearings by a Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> House of Commons <strong>and</strong><br />

Senate (<strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee), which issued its recommendations<br />

in February 1992. 7 In addition, <strong>the</strong> federal government sponsored a series of<br />

six constitutional conferences which included a sprinkling of “ordinary<br />

citizens” along with representatives of various interest groups, academics,<br />

politicians <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r “experts.” Finally, <strong>the</strong> federal government provided<br />

funding for four of <strong>the</strong> major national Aboriginal organizations—<strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations (AFN), <strong>the</strong> Native Council of Canada (NCC), <strong>the</strong><br />

Inuit Tapirisat of Canada (ITC), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metis National Council (MNC)—to<br />

hold “parallel processes,” <strong>the</strong> better to ascertain <strong>the</strong> views of Aboriginal<br />

peoples on <strong>the</strong> issue of constitutional reform.<br />

Through an analysis of position papers <strong>and</strong> reports of <strong>the</strong> national Aboriginal<br />

organizations’ “parallel constitutional process” of 1991-92, this paper<br />

examines <strong>the</strong> permutations <strong>and</strong> continuities of Aboriginal constitutional<br />

discourse over <strong>the</strong> past decade, with a view to identifying its major <strong>the</strong>mes <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir expression. <strong>The</strong> nucleus of national Aboriginal organizations’<br />

constitutional goals has been self-government. However, while some of <strong>the</strong><br />

orbital concepts (such as <strong>the</strong> claims of an inherent right to self-government <strong>and</strong><br />

to distinct society status) have persisted over <strong>the</strong> period, <strong>the</strong>y have been<br />

articulated in different forms as <strong>the</strong> constellation of political forces at work in<br />

constitutional reform has shifted. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> early 1990s have witnessed<br />

<strong>the</strong> re-emergence of issues such as Aboriginal women’s rights, <strong>the</strong> “two<br />

founding nations” concept <strong>and</strong> equity of access. <strong>The</strong>se issues are ei<strong>the</strong>r relative<br />

newcomers to <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal constitutional agenda, or <strong>the</strong>y have assumed<br />

enhanced significance due to <strong>the</strong> florescence of previously marginalized<br />

voices within both Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> non-Aboriginal society.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first part of <strong>the</strong> paper outlines Aboriginal peoples’ constitutional position<br />

under <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir potential constitutional rights under<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposed provisions of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. <strong>The</strong> second part<br />

examines some of <strong>the</strong> factors which have induced change in Aboriginal<br />

constitutional discourse, both among Aboriginal peoples <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong><br />

among politicians <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> public. <strong>The</strong> third part of <strong>the</strong> paper tracks <strong>the</strong><br />

development of three sets of essential, interrelated <strong>the</strong>mes in <strong>the</strong> contemporary<br />

discourse. <strong>The</strong> first set of <strong>the</strong>mes links assertions of Aboriginal nationalism<br />

<strong>and</strong> sovereignty to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for constitutional recognition of an inherent<br />

right to self-government. <strong>The</strong> second set of <strong>the</strong>mes relates to <strong>the</strong> intersection of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Aboriginal constitutional agenda with Quebec’s claims to distinct society<br />

status based on <strong>the</strong> “two founding nations” concept. <strong>The</strong> analysis shows that<br />

Aboriginal peoples have launched a successful assault on <strong>the</strong> latter conception<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Canadian compact. Finally, <strong>the</strong> third set of <strong>the</strong>mes is associated with <strong>the</strong><br />

attempt to reconcile individual with collective rights. <strong>The</strong> discussion focuses<br />

on <strong>the</strong> application of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association of Canada’s quest for protection of gender equality rights under<br />

Aboriginal governments. <strong>The</strong> tension between individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights<br />

is an especially important element of constitutional discourse; it involves<br />

unresolved issues both between Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> non-Aboriginal communities,<br />

<strong>and</strong> within Aboriginal communities <strong>the</strong>mselves.<br />

Spatial limitations inevitably require a focus on some <strong>the</strong>mes to <strong>the</strong> exclusion<br />

of o<strong>the</strong>rs. Aboriginal constitutional discourse is complex, <strong>and</strong> features many<br />

interrelated elements. Quite apart from spatial constraints, however, I have<br />

chosen not to analyze (o<strong>the</strong>r than tangentially) issues such as <strong>the</strong> treaties,<br />

227


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

equity of access, <strong>the</strong> Indian Act, <strong>the</strong> creation of new provinces <strong>and</strong> ethnic<br />

versus public government, on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong>y are of special interest to<br />

specific sections of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal population, but not to everyone. Instead, I<br />

have selected what are, in my view, <strong>the</strong> major conceptual elements of<br />

Aboriginal peoples’ discourse in view of <strong>the</strong> new political relationship <strong>the</strong>y<br />

wish to craft with Canada, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir preferred status in <strong>the</strong> constitutional order.<br />

<strong>The</strong> analysis shows that Aboriginal peoples have made some major conceptual<br />

breakthroughs in terms of constitutional talk in Canada, breakthroughs which<br />

appeared in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown proposals. Finally, although <strong>the</strong> Accord failed<br />

(due to a range of factors mostly unrelated to <strong>the</strong> self-government provisions),<br />

it is possible that amendments on self-government may proceed separately.<br />

<strong>The</strong> paper thus concludes with an analysis of <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> discourse to<br />

date, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> prospects for future reforms in <strong>the</strong> area.<br />

Comparison of <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong>Constitution</strong> Act <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accord<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982, Aboriginal organizations had secured for<br />

<strong>the</strong> first time in Canadian history constitutional entrenchment of Aboriginal<br />

<strong>and</strong> treaty rights, though <strong>the</strong>ir precise meaning has not to date been fully<br />

fleshed out by <strong>the</strong> courts. As amended in 1983, <strong>the</strong> Act provided that:<br />

25. <strong>The</strong> guarantee in this <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of certain rights <strong>and</strong> freedoms shall not be<br />

construed so as to abrogate or derogate from any Aboriginal, treaty or o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

rights or freedoms that pertain to <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples of Canada<br />

including<br />

(a) any rights or freedoms that have been recognized by <strong>the</strong> Royal<br />

Proclamation of October 7, 1763; <strong>and</strong><br />

(b) any rights or freedoms that now exist by way of l<strong>and</strong> claims<br />

agreements or may be so acquired.<br />

35. (1) <strong>The</strong> existing Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples of<br />

Canada are hereby recognized <strong>and</strong> affirmed.<br />

(2) In this Act, “Aboriginal peoples of Canada” includes <strong>the</strong> Indian,<br />

Inuit <strong>and</strong> Metis peoples of Canada.<br />

(3) For greater certainty, in subsection (1) “treaty rights” includes<br />

rights that now exist by way of l<strong>and</strong> claims agreements or may be<br />

so acquired.<br />

(4) Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing any o<strong>the</strong>r provision of this Act, <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal<br />

<strong>and</strong> treaty rights referred to in subsection (1) are guaranteed<br />

equally to male <strong>and</strong> female persons.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord of August 28, 1992, would have added<br />

substantially to <strong>the</strong>se provisions. Briefly, <strong>the</strong> Accord proposed to entrench<br />

Aboriginal peoples’ “inherent right of self-government within Canada,” 8<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby creating a new institutional framework under <strong>the</strong> rubric of federalism.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canada Clause, an interpretive clause governing <strong>the</strong> entire constitution,<br />

provided that “<strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples of Canada, being <strong>the</strong> first peoples to<br />

govern this l<strong>and</strong>, have <strong>the</strong> right to promote <strong>the</strong>ir languages, cultures <strong>and</strong><br />

traditions <strong>and</strong> to ensure <strong>the</strong> integrity of <strong>the</strong>ir societies, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir governments<br />

constitute one of three orders of government in Canada.” 9 A contextual<br />

statement in s.35(3) of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982, would have specified that<br />

duly constituted legislative bodies of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples had <strong>the</strong> right “(a)<br />

228


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

to safeguard <strong>and</strong> develop <strong>the</strong>ir languages, cultures, economies, identities,<br />

institutions <strong>and</strong> traditions, <strong>and</strong> (b) to develop, maintain <strong>and</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

relationship with <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>and</strong>s, waters <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> environment, so as to determine<br />

<strong>and</strong> control <strong>the</strong>ir development as peoples according to <strong>the</strong>ir own values <strong>and</strong><br />

priorities <strong>and</strong> to ensure <strong>the</strong> integrity of <strong>the</strong>ir societies.” 10<br />

<strong>The</strong>re were to be certain limitations on <strong>the</strong> inherent right. First, <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms was to apply to Aboriginal governments.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> extent of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s application was rendered ambiguous by<br />

three provisions. Aboriginal governments were to have access to s. 33 (<strong>the</strong><br />

override clause) so that <strong>the</strong>y could exempt <strong>the</strong>ir laws from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>’s<br />

fundamental freedoms, legal <strong>and</strong> equality rights. In addition, <strong>the</strong> existing s. 25<br />

exemption of Aboriginal, treaty or o<strong>the</strong>r rights from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was to be<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned by adding “(c) any rights or freedoms relating to <strong>the</strong> exercise or<br />

protection of <strong>the</strong>ir languages, cultures or traditions.” Finally, <strong>the</strong> democratic<br />

rights in s. 3 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> were only to be applied to <strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial<br />

legislatures, not to Aboriginal governments. Hence, it is not clear whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> would have applied to Aboriginal governments in any significant way,<br />

though this is discussed in more detail below.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, a second limitation in s. 35.4(1) stated that federal <strong>and</strong><br />

provincial laws of general application would continue to apply until <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

displaced by laws passed by Aboriginal governments pursuant to negotiated<br />

authorities. Section 35(2) represented a third limit, providing that “no<br />

Aboriginal law or any o<strong>the</strong>r exercise of <strong>the</strong> inherent right of selfgovernment...may<br />

be inconsistent with federal or provincial laws that are<br />

essential to <strong>the</strong> preservation of peace, order <strong>and</strong> good government in Canada.”<br />

Fourth, no new l<strong>and</strong> rights were to be created, though nothing in <strong>the</strong> provisions<br />

were to derogate from existing l<strong>and</strong> rights. Fifth, s. 35.7 provided that <strong>the</strong><br />

rights of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples of Canada were to be guaranteed equally to<br />

male <strong>and</strong> female persons. Finally, <strong>the</strong>re was to be a five-year delay on<br />

justiciability.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se limitations notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>the</strong> Accord would have committed<br />

governments to negotiate in good faith <strong>the</strong> implementation of selfgovernment,<br />

including issues of jurisdiction, l<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> resources <strong>and</strong><br />

economic <strong>and</strong> fiscal arrangements. In addition, treaty rights were to be<br />

interpreted in “a just, broad <strong>and</strong> liberal manner taking into account <strong>the</strong>ir spirit<br />

<strong>and</strong> intent,” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government of Canada was to establish treaty processes to<br />

clarify, implement, or rectify <strong>the</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> treaties. In fact, <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal<br />

components of <strong>the</strong> Accord were quite extensive. <strong>The</strong>y included: guaranteed<br />

Aboriginal representation in <strong>the</strong> Senate; an Aboriginal veto over constitutional<br />

amendments directly affecting Aboriginal peoples; <strong>and</strong> at least four biennial<br />

constitutional conferences on Aboriginal issues starting no later than 1996.<br />

Aboriginal representatives were to have items of <strong>the</strong>ir choice included on <strong>the</strong><br />

agendas. 11<br />

Compared with <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r sparse 1982 provisions, <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord<br />

would have signalled a massive change <strong>and</strong> considerable improvement in <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional position of Aboriginal peoples. It would have given Aboriginal<br />

governments unassailable constitutional status, while at <strong>the</strong> same time<br />

recognizing that <strong>the</strong> right to self-government preceded <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

constitution. At a philosophical level, several of its key provisions are<br />

indicative of <strong>the</strong> transformation of Aboriginal constitutional discourse in<br />

recent years <strong>and</strong> its acceptance by political elites. In particular, <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

229


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

an inherent right to self-government enshrines collective rights <strong>and</strong> is an<br />

implicit recognition of Aboriginal nationhood <strong>and</strong> sovereignty. Meanwhile,<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of a third order of government in <strong>the</strong> Canadian federal<br />

system displaces <strong>the</strong> traditional “two nations” conception of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

federal compact. <strong>The</strong>se elements of Aboriginal constitutional discourse are<br />

discussed below.<br />

Explaining <strong>the</strong> Discursive Shift<br />

As noted above, Aboriginal organizations were unable to secure constitutional<br />

recognition of <strong>the</strong> right to self-government during <strong>the</strong> 1980s. During that<br />

decade, public interest in <strong>and</strong> support for Aboriginal political aspirations was<br />

moderate, <strong>and</strong> had even declined somewhat since <strong>the</strong> 1970s. 12 Hence, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

was no particular public pressure for governments to act on <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong>s. In<br />

fact, in 1983 <strong>the</strong> Special Committee on Indian Self-Government (<strong>the</strong> Penner<br />

Committee) had released its report which recommended that Indian selfgovernment<br />

be constitutionally entrenched as an Aboriginal right, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

First Nation governments should form “a distinct order of government in<br />

Canada.” 13 Although hailed as a breakthrough by <strong>the</strong> AFN, <strong>the</strong> Report’s<br />

recommendations were never implemented. Moreover, less than a month after<br />

<strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> 1987 F.M.C. on Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters, <strong>the</strong><br />

Governments of Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ten provinces signed <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord,<br />

a reform package which dealt wholly with Quebec’s agenda, <strong>and</strong> which made<br />

no attempt to address Aboriginal concerns.<br />

In view of <strong>the</strong>se events, <strong>the</strong> political process of 1991-92 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> final package<br />

proposed by <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord almost suggested that we had been<br />

flipped into an alternate universe. What seemed impossible in <strong>the</strong> 1980s had<br />

suddenly become not only possible, but unavoidable. In <strong>the</strong> early 1990s,<br />

Aboriginal organizations were able to force <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong>s onto a<br />

constitutional agenda which was intended by <strong>the</strong> Mulroney government to<br />

address Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s for recognition as a distinct society (among o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

things). Now it seems unlikely that any attempt at constitutional reform which<br />

fails to address Aboriginal dem<strong>and</strong>s for self-government could succeed in <strong>the</strong><br />

foreseeable future. What has caused this curious turn of events?<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> principal explanations for <strong>the</strong> inclusion of Aboriginal dem<strong>and</strong>s for<br />

self-government involves <strong>the</strong> role of Aboriginal peoples in <strong>the</strong> death of <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. When Elijah Harper, an Aboriginal member of <strong>the</strong><br />

Manitoba Legislature, used a procedural loophole to postpone debate in <strong>the</strong><br />

Legislature until it became impossible to ratify <strong>the</strong> Accord before <strong>the</strong> deadline,<br />

he was supported by Aboriginal organizations (<strong>and</strong> many citizens) across <strong>the</strong><br />

country. Indeed, Frances Abele has noted “<strong>the</strong> way in which Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

First Nations have stumbled over each o<strong>the</strong>r’s progress” in <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

constitutional reform:<br />

230<br />

In 1982, Aboriginal peoples registered a limited victory, in securing<br />

constitutional entrenchment of “existing Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty<br />

rights” while Quebec, absent, was excluded; <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> urgency of<br />

resolving Quebec’s exclusion led to <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, which<br />

in turn contributed to <strong>the</strong> failure of <strong>the</strong> First Ministers’ Conferences<br />

on Aboriginal Matters; <strong>the</strong> apparent victory of reconciliation at<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke was turned into a debacle by Aboriginal resistance to<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir exclusion from <strong>the</strong> process. 14


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

Shortly after <strong>the</strong> failure of Meech, a centuries-old dispute between <strong>the</strong><br />

Mohawks of Oka, Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> imperial <strong>and</strong> Canadian Crowns flared up<br />

afresh as <strong>the</strong> town of Oka proposed to exp<strong>and</strong> a golf course on <strong>the</strong>ir traditional<br />

burial grounds. After a peaceful blockade over several months had failed to<br />

dissuade <strong>the</strong> developers, Mohawk Warriors responded by engaging in an<br />

armed confrontation with <strong>the</strong> Quebec Provincial Police (<strong>and</strong> later <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian Armed Forces) at Oka <strong>and</strong> several reserves in Quebec in <strong>the</strong> late<br />

summer of 1990. <strong>The</strong> ninety-day st<strong>and</strong>-off sparked a spate of sympa<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

protests by Aboriginal communities <strong>and</strong> non-Aboriginal groups <strong>and</strong><br />

individuals across <strong>the</strong> country. Although many citizens reacted negatively to<br />

<strong>the</strong> tactic of armed protest, Oka demonstrated <strong>the</strong> profound frustration felt by<br />

many Aboriginal people. <strong>The</strong> siege provoked anxiety that more serious <strong>and</strong><br />

possibly more bloody confrontations might ensue if Aboriginal peoples’<br />

socio-economic conditions <strong>and</strong> political position were not remedied. This<br />

unusual demonstration of militancy drove <strong>the</strong> message home to politicians <strong>and</strong><br />

to <strong>the</strong> viewing public that Aboriginal people were serious, impatient with <strong>the</strong><br />

normal political process, <strong>and</strong> determined to resist encroachments on <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> political rights. Indeed, Meech <strong>and</strong> Oka are widely credited by Aboriginal<br />

leaders as <strong>the</strong> chief explanations of <strong>the</strong> discursive shift:<br />

However hideous <strong>the</strong> Oka confrontation was, it could hardly have<br />

done a better job of changing Canadian opinion, as white Canadians<br />

watched <strong>the</strong> QPP charge Mohawk barricades in order to preserve <strong>the</strong><br />

Mayor of Oka’s self-assumed right to exp<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> municipal golf<br />

course. <strong>The</strong> ugliness at <strong>the</strong> Mercier Bridge brought racism out into<br />

<strong>the</strong> open, to be confronted. <strong>The</strong> Donald Marshall case, <strong>the</strong><br />

investigation into <strong>the</strong> cover-up of Helen Betty Osborne’s murder,<br />

task forces on Aboriginal justice in various provinces—all of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

have opened white Canadians’ eyes as never before, to Native issues<br />

<strong>and</strong> concerns...And <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re was Meech <strong>La</strong>ke. In <strong>the</strong> brangling <strong>and</strong><br />

hysteria of <strong>the</strong> last weeks of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke fiasco, Elijah Harper’s<br />

quiet dignity...deeply impressed many white Canadians. 15<br />

Whereas <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal role in <strong>the</strong> demise of <strong>the</strong> “Quebec Round” of<br />

constitutional reform <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> militancy of Oka signalled <strong>the</strong> growing political<br />

potency of Aboriginal peoples, renewed conceptions of collective rights<br />

following <strong>the</strong> 1982 <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights were empowered by a series of Supreme<br />

Court decisions in <strong>the</strong> 1980s. <strong>The</strong> Guerin, Sioui, Simon <strong>and</strong> Sparrow decisions<br />

acknowledged <strong>the</strong> survival of Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights, <strong>and</strong> brea<strong>the</strong>d new<br />

life into Aboriginal claims that <strong>the</strong>ir “natural rights” never<strong>the</strong>less had <strong>the</strong> force<br />

of law in <strong>the</strong> Eurocanadian legal system. In particular, in <strong>the</strong> Sparrow decision,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Supreme Court found that regulation of a right (in this case a fishing right)<br />

could nei<strong>the</strong>r extinguish nor determine “<strong>the</strong> scope <strong>and</strong> content of an existing<br />

Aboriginal right.” 16 Moreover, in its first interpretation of s. 35 of <strong>the</strong> 1982<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> Act, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court found that <strong>the</strong> section implies a fiduciary<br />

responsibility on <strong>the</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> federal government, suggesting “some<br />

restraint on <strong>the</strong> exercise of sovereign power.” 17 Section 35, <strong>the</strong> Court held, was<br />

to be given “a generous <strong>and</strong> liberal interpretation,” applied as it is to a sui<br />

generis category of rights. 18<br />

Certainly, <strong>the</strong>se far-reaching legal victories impressed upon politicians <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that Aboriginal peoples’ claims to l<strong>and</strong>, treaty <strong>and</strong> unextinguished Aboriginal<br />

rights were much stronger in legal <strong>and</strong> constitutional terms than many had<br />

believed. Hence, taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> enhanced legal recognition of Aboriginal<br />

231


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

rights, Aboriginal peoples’ role in <strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> new wave of militancy <strong>and</strong> direct action inspired by <strong>the</strong> cataclysm of Oka<br />

account at least in part for <strong>the</strong> transfiguration of Aboriginal constitutional<br />

discourse <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> willingness of political elites to embrace it.<br />

Aboriginal Nationhood, Sovereignty <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Inherent Right to Self-<br />

Government<br />

Aboriginal nationalism has been developing in Canada since at least <strong>the</strong> 1970s,<br />

when <strong>the</strong> Red Power movement began to craft an ideology of opposition which<br />

rejected <strong>the</strong> dominant political ethos <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> place of Aboriginal people within<br />

it. As Chartr<strong>and</strong> observes, <strong>the</strong> recently mobilizing movement of Aboriginal<br />

peoples “is characterized by an emerging sense of nationalism which presents<br />

a number of challenges to traditional notions about <strong>the</strong> nation-state in<br />

Canada...[including]...<strong>the</strong> legitimacy of a constitutional order based upon a<br />

division of powers between <strong>the</strong> federal Parliament <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> provincial<br />

Legislatures.” 19<br />

Two of <strong>the</strong> core elements of Aboriginal political <strong>and</strong> constitutional discourse<br />

in recent years have been claims to nationhood <strong>and</strong> sovereignty, which have<br />

culminated in a dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> recognition of an inherent right to selfgovernment.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concepts of nationhood <strong>and</strong> sovereignty are not understood<br />

by Aboriginal peoples in quite <strong>the</strong> same way as <strong>the</strong>y are comprehended by non-<br />

Aboriginal people. “Nationhood” is not normally understood by Aboriginal<br />

people in Canada in <strong>the</strong> sense of “nation-state.” <strong>The</strong> latter would imply an<br />

international status whereby <strong>the</strong> nation would exercise complete sovereignty<br />

over a discrete territory, while enjoying <strong>the</strong> right to make foreign policy <strong>and</strong> to<br />

enter into treaties with o<strong>the</strong>r nations. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, Aboriginal nationhood is<br />

generally understood as describing a socio-cultural (usually tribal) group,<br />

sharing a common language, history, territory <strong>and</strong> identity.<br />

Yet Aboriginal nationalism is more than cultural nationalism: it has political<br />

implications, even if <strong>the</strong>se do not extend as far as a claim to full-fledged nationstatehood.<br />

As Boldt has suggested, nationalism can refer to a range of<br />

autonomous political conditions, <strong>and</strong> if full independence is one extreme on a<br />

continuum, Canada’s Aboriginal peoples are best characterized as<br />

“autonomists.” 20 Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most renowned assertion of nationhood <strong>and</strong><br />

sovereignty was <strong>the</strong> Dene Declaration of 1975, which read in part:<br />

We <strong>the</strong> Dene of <strong>the</strong> [Northwest Territories] insist on <strong>the</strong> right to be<br />

regarded by ourselves <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> world as a nation. Our struggle is for<br />

<strong>the</strong> recognition of <strong>the</strong> Dene Nation by <strong>the</strong> Government <strong>and</strong> people of<br />

Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> peoples <strong>and</strong> governments of <strong>the</strong> world....<strong>The</strong> Dene<br />

find <strong>the</strong>mselves as part of a country. That country is Canada. But <strong>the</strong><br />

Government of Canada is not <strong>the</strong> government of <strong>the</strong> Dene. <strong>The</strong><br />

Government of <strong>the</strong> N.W.T. is not <strong>the</strong> government of <strong>the</strong> Dene. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

governments were not <strong>the</strong> choice of <strong>the</strong> Dene, <strong>the</strong>y were imposed on<br />

<strong>the</strong> Dene. Our plea to <strong>the</strong> world is to help us in our struggle to find a<br />

place in <strong>the</strong> world community where we can exercise our right to selfdetermination<br />

as a distinct people <strong>and</strong> as a nation. What we seek <strong>the</strong>n<br />

is independence <strong>and</strong> self-determination within <strong>the</strong> country of<br />

Canada. 21 (emphasis added)<br />

In <strong>the</strong> 1970s, various Aboriginal writers <strong>and</strong> organizations pointed out that<br />

before colonization, Aboriginal societies were sovereign. <strong>The</strong> British Crown,<br />

232


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

<strong>the</strong>y argued, recognized <strong>the</strong> pre-existing sovereignty of Indian nations in<br />

particular through <strong>the</strong> Royal Proclamation of 1763, 22 <strong>and</strong> through <strong>the</strong> treaties<br />

it authorized, which were conducted on a nation-to-nation basis. <strong>The</strong>y argued<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y never gave up <strong>the</strong>ir right to govern <strong>the</strong>mselves. <strong>The</strong> treaties may have<br />

limited sovereignty, but <strong>the</strong>y did not erase it:<br />

Prior to colonial settlement in North America, <strong>the</strong> Indian... people<br />

had uncontested dominion over <strong>the</strong>ir tribal territories <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong><br />

people <strong>the</strong>rein. <strong>The</strong>y could govern, make laws, wage war, <strong>and</strong> had<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own political, social, cultural, educational, economic, <strong>and</strong><br />

property systems. Each tribe had absolute control over <strong>the</strong> resources<br />

<strong>and</strong> products of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> tribes had political<br />

sovereignty. To Indian people, <strong>the</strong>ir title to tribal l<strong>and</strong>s was explicit in<br />

this political sovereignty. <strong>The</strong> actions of <strong>the</strong> colonial powers in<br />

entering into treaties with Indian peoples were an acknowledgement<br />

of sovereignty <strong>and</strong> a recognition of Indian rights to <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>. 23<br />

In contemporary discourse, however, Aboriginal nationalism <strong>and</strong> assertions of<br />

sovereignty do not require a return to <strong>the</strong> absolute autonomy of <strong>the</strong> pre-contact<br />

period. Chartr<strong>and</strong> notes that in general, “Aboriginal peoples...have not been<br />

anxious to assert that <strong>the</strong>ir right of self-determination requires that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

separate politically <strong>and</strong> economically from Canada.” 24 John Moss notes that in<br />

<strong>the</strong> early 1980s, <strong>the</strong> NIB (National Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood, forerunner to <strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations), NCC <strong>and</strong> ITC each stated that <strong>the</strong>ir members<br />

represented separate <strong>and</strong> distinct nations, <strong>the</strong> NIB even declaring that<br />

“sovereignty continues to reside in each [Indian] nation.” For <strong>the</strong> NIB <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

NCC, <strong>the</strong>ir status as nations gave <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> right to choose whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y wished<br />

to be part of Confederation or not. 25<br />

<strong>The</strong> prescription, however, was not secession from Canada, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

“internal sovereignty” via new political arrangements <strong>and</strong> institutions by<br />

which Aboriginal peoples might govern <strong>the</strong>ir own internal affairs. For <strong>the</strong> NIB<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> NCC, <strong>the</strong> answer lay in <strong>the</strong> formation of a “third order of government”<br />

where Aboriginal governments would exercise a wide range of powers<br />

(combining municipal, provincial <strong>and</strong> some federal powers). Such<br />

governments would exist within current provincial boundaries, but would not<br />

be municipalities or “arms of <strong>the</strong> provincial governments.” 26 <strong>The</strong> ITC, on <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, envisioned <strong>the</strong> creation of a new province in <strong>the</strong> Northwest<br />

Territories in which Inuit would form <strong>the</strong> majority, though <strong>the</strong> ITC was not<br />

proposing “ethnically-exclusive government institutions [or] anything outside<br />

this country’s fundamental political principles.” 27<br />

In <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 round of constitutional reform, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>mes of nationhood <strong>and</strong><br />

sovereignty were expressed anew. <strong>The</strong> AFN’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Commissioners<br />

for example, reiterated <strong>the</strong> historical basis of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal-Eurocanadian<br />

relationship:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian government may try to sidestep <strong>the</strong> question of<br />

nationhood for <strong>the</strong> First Peoples, but in <strong>the</strong> 17th <strong>and</strong> 18th centuries, its<br />

predecessors had no such doubts. Treaties weren’t made between<br />

victor <strong>and</strong> defeated or between superior <strong>and</strong> inferior; <strong>the</strong>y were made<br />

between equals, on <strong>the</strong> basis of mutual respect...[Presenters] said that<br />

treaty after treaty...recognized <strong>the</strong> First Nations as independent<br />

equals....[However], unilaterally, <strong>the</strong> Federal government assumed<br />

233


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

responsibility for “Indians” <strong>and</strong> passed <strong>the</strong> Indian Act through a<br />

Parliament for which “status Indians” were not even eligible to<br />

vote....But <strong>the</strong> people who came to join <strong>the</strong> circle were quite clear. At<br />

no point had <strong>the</strong>y or <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors ever consented to be governed by<br />

<strong>the</strong> incomers. We govern ourselves; we have never given up that<br />

right, <strong>the</strong>y told us. Self-government exists. It has always existed; it<br />

will always exist. Recognition of this fundamental fact would be<br />

simple justice, but whatever happens, we are our own people, our<br />

own Nations, with our own culture <strong>and</strong> traditions to treasure. 28<br />

As in <strong>the</strong> 1970s, <strong>the</strong> national Aboriginal organizations used <strong>the</strong> language of<br />

sovereignty, but did not see <strong>the</strong> notion as requiring secession from Canada.<br />

<strong>The</strong> ITC, for example, noted that Inuit have not advocated sovereignty or a<br />

desire to separate from Canada. Instead, “our position signifies <strong>the</strong> opposite<br />

approach, a desire to seek unity with o<strong>the</strong>r Canadians <strong>and</strong> become equal<br />

partners in <strong>the</strong> federation.” 29<br />

While <strong>the</strong> national organizations concurred in this view, it is not necessarily<br />

<strong>the</strong> view espoused by all First Nations, however. Indeed, some Aboriginal<br />

groups have a long history of asserting complete sovereignty <strong>and</strong><br />

independence from Canada. For example, since <strong>the</strong> late 1950s, <strong>the</strong> Iroquois of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Six Nations Confederacy have resisted Canada’s claims to sovereignty<br />

over <strong>the</strong>ir peoples <strong>and</strong> territories, 30 <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> 1984 FMC on Aboriginal<br />

Matters, Chief Billy Two Rivers of <strong>the</strong> Kahnawake Mohawk Council declared<br />

that:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Haudenosaunee Six Nations Confederacy have no desire to<br />

separate from Canada, since <strong>the</strong> Confederacy have never been part of<br />

Canada....[<strong>The</strong>] new constitution will have no jurisdictional authority<br />

within our territories or over our people. Our people are citizens of<br />

our nation <strong>and</strong> do not seek citizenship within <strong>the</strong> nation of Canada. 31<br />

In view of this position, it is not surprising that <strong>the</strong> Mohawks boycotted <strong>the</strong><br />

October referendum. Nor are <strong>the</strong> Mohawks <strong>the</strong> only Aboriginal group to<br />

challenge <strong>the</strong> authority <strong>and</strong> jurisdiction of <strong>the</strong> Canadian state. In 1989, <strong>the</strong><br />

Haidas of <strong>the</strong> Queen Charlotte Isl<strong>and</strong>s off <strong>the</strong> coast of British Columbia<br />

declared <strong>the</strong>mselves an independent nation, <strong>and</strong> even issued passports to<br />

underscore <strong>the</strong> point. While such dramatic declarations have been <strong>the</strong><br />

exception ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> rule in Aboriginal politics, <strong>the</strong>re is some evidence<br />

that <strong>the</strong> idea of absolute sovereignty has begun to take hold among more<br />

Aboriginal groups, <strong>and</strong> Chartr<strong>and</strong> notes that “Aboriginal leaders are now<br />

concerned with asserting <strong>the</strong> illegitimacy of <strong>the</strong> Canadian state <strong>and</strong> its<br />

constitution on <strong>the</strong> basis that it was imposed upon Aboriginal peoples.” 32 Not<br />

surprisingly, <strong>the</strong> issue of sovereignty was to surface in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 round of<br />

constitutional reform.<br />

<strong>The</strong> logic of <strong>the</strong> claim to nationhood <strong>and</strong> continuing sovereignty ultimately<br />

produces a claim to an inherent right to self-government in <strong>the</strong> present. When<br />

<strong>the</strong> federal government’s September 1991 document, Shaping Canada’s<br />

Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r, proposed to enshrine in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> a general right to<br />

self-government (subject to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights, federal <strong>and</strong> provincial laws<br />

of general application <strong>and</strong> a ten-year delay on justiciability), Aboriginal<br />

leaders across <strong>the</strong> country reacted with considerable skepticism. Ovide<br />

Mercredi <strong>and</strong> Saul Terry of <strong>the</strong> Union of British Columbia Indian Chiefs<br />

234


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

(among o<strong>the</strong>rs) took <strong>the</strong> position that nothing less than <strong>the</strong> recognition of selfgovernment<br />

as an inherent right would be acceptable. Within a month,<br />

Mercredi was threatening to boycott <strong>the</strong> Parliamentary “unity” process unless<br />

<strong>the</strong> inherent right to self-government was recognized. At <strong>the</strong> opening of <strong>the</strong><br />

AFN’s “parallel process,” Mercredi even went as far as to say that if inherent<br />

rights were not acknowledged, Aboriginal people could form <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

national government <strong>and</strong> declare sovereignty <strong>and</strong> independence from<br />

Canada. 33 Although <strong>the</strong>y did not necessarily support <strong>the</strong> latter claim, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

national Aboriginal organizations lined up behind <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> inherent<br />

right.<br />

<strong>The</strong> language of inherency has much more than merely symbolic importance. It<br />

recognizes <strong>the</strong> fact that Aboriginal peoples were historically self-governing, that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y never gave up <strong>the</strong> right to govern <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> right is not<br />

granted by any o<strong>the</strong>r government or legislative or constitutional enactment.<br />

Ultimately, it signifies a pre-existing, natural <strong>and</strong> continuing right which cannot<br />

be abrogated or revoked by any o<strong>the</strong>r government, especially without <strong>the</strong><br />

consent of Aboriginal peoples.<br />

Throughout <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal parallel process of 1991-92, speakers emphasized<br />

<strong>the</strong> inherent nature of Aboriginal rights, although its consequences were<br />

expressed in different ways. <strong>The</strong> AFN’s Commissioners noted that:<br />

<strong>The</strong> word “inherent” has caused considerable confusion. In fact, it’s<br />

very simple. <strong>The</strong> people say that First Nations self-government<br />

exists; <strong>the</strong> question is one of recognition only. <strong>The</strong> federal<br />

government cannot grant self-government to <strong>the</strong> First Nations any<br />

more than <strong>the</strong> Mayor of Sudbury can declare war on Japan. A man<br />

cannot divorce a woman who never married him....<strong>The</strong> people claim<br />

that this right stems from First Nations’ occupation of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> from<br />

time immemorial, from Aboriginal title <strong>and</strong> rights recognized under<br />

international conventions, from elementary principles of democracy.<br />

We heard that <strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments cannot give <strong>the</strong><br />

First Nations <strong>the</strong> right to self-government, because that right has been<br />

given <strong>the</strong>m by an even more powerful governor [<strong>the</strong> Great Creator].<br />

All governments can do is to recognize <strong>the</strong> fact. 34<br />

Each of <strong>the</strong> national organizations insisted that <strong>the</strong> inherent right should be<br />

enshrined without limitations. <strong>The</strong> ITC took <strong>the</strong> view that “by virtue of being<br />

inherent <strong>and</strong> a fundamental right of indigenous peoples, <strong>the</strong> right of selfgovernment<br />

is of a permanent nature <strong>and</strong> cannot be restricted or limited to<br />

delegated powers. 35 Meanwhile, <strong>the</strong> NCC’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Review<br />

Commission recommended: that <strong>the</strong> inherent right be immediately entrenched<br />

without a delay on enforcement; that it include title <strong>and</strong> ownership of l<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong><br />

resources; that <strong>the</strong> Indian Act system not be <strong>the</strong> basis for self-government; that<br />

<strong>the</strong> right should be “freely exercisable by all Aboriginal people regardless of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir status under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act, or of where <strong>the</strong>y live”; <strong>and</strong> that it could not<br />

limit or detract from “existing rights <strong>and</strong> our original jurisdictions.” 36<br />

<strong>The</strong> appearanœ of <strong>the</strong> conœpt of inherency in 1991-92 seemed to surprise <strong>the</strong><br />

viewing public, as well as many politicians, who seemed never to have heard<br />

of it before. Yet <strong>the</strong> four national Aboriginal organizations had been using it<br />

for some years. In fact, <strong>the</strong>y had tabled a “Joint Aboriginal Proposal for Self-<br />

Government” during <strong>the</strong> 1987 FMC, which proposed to recognize <strong>and</strong> affirm<br />

<strong>the</strong> inherent right. Negotiations were to proceed on such issues as l<strong>and</strong>s,<br />

235


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

resourœs, economic <strong>and</strong> fiscal arrangements, education, preservation <strong>and</strong><br />

enhanœment of Aboriginal languages <strong>and</strong> cultures, <strong>and</strong> equity of access. 37 It<br />

must be noted, however, that at that time Aboriginal issues did not enjoy a<br />

particularly high profile in Canadian politics, nor were Aboriginal<br />

organizations able to flex <strong>the</strong> political muscle developed latterly by virtue of<br />

<strong>the</strong> collapse of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>the</strong> militancy at Oka <strong>and</strong> a variety of<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r factors.<br />

For several months after <strong>the</strong> release of Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government vigorously resisted <strong>the</strong> idea of inherency. Tom Siddon, <strong>the</strong><br />

Minister of Indian Affairs, said that Ottawa was willing to make jurisdictional<br />

spaœ for native self-government, “but not if it means yielding <strong>the</strong> ultimate<br />

sovereignty of <strong>the</strong> Crown <strong>and</strong> of Canada.” 38 <strong>The</strong> major concern was that <strong>the</strong><br />

idea of inherency might import a right to sovereign independence from<br />

Canada, that it might produce a “Swiss cheese map riddled with tiny pockets of<br />

independent native nations.” 39 Joe Clark, <strong>the</strong> Minister Responsible for<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Affairs, did not rule out inherency, but told <strong>the</strong> NCC at a<br />

meeting in Hull, Quebec on November 7, 1991, that:<br />

We believe that <strong>the</strong> word—undefined or unmodifed—could be used<br />

as <strong>the</strong> basis for a claim to international sovereignty or as <strong>the</strong><br />

justification of a unilateral approach to deciding what laws did or did<br />

not apply to Aboriginal peoples....If Aboriginal Canadians can help<br />

define what inherency would mean in practical terms—in terms of<br />

authorities <strong>and</strong> jurisdictions <strong>and</strong> powers—in such a way that <strong>the</strong><br />

integrity of this federation is not put in question, we would welcome<br />

that. We are not opposed to inherency.”<br />

<strong>The</strong>se concerns were certainly not alleviated by <strong>the</strong> threats of secession made<br />

by Mercredi <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> particularly by Aboriginal leaders in Quebec, who<br />

feared for <strong>the</strong>ir collective fate should Quebec itself secede from Canada. Nor<br />

were <strong>the</strong> government’s fears tranquilized by assurances that Aboriginal groups<br />

were really after inclusion in <strong>the</strong> federation, particularly as Aboriginal<br />

lobbying on <strong>the</strong> international front in recent years has been devoted to gaining<br />

recognition of indigenous peoples’ right to self-determination, whe<strong>the</strong>r within<br />

or outside existing nation-states. 40<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, governments’ concerns notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing, by early 1992 <strong>the</strong><br />

concept of inherency appeared to have penetrated <strong>the</strong> Canadian political<br />

psyche. Amid government charges that Aboriginal (<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r “special<br />

interest”) groups were “hijacking” <strong>the</strong> five constitutional conferences, <strong>the</strong><br />

final wrap-up conference in Vancouver concluded that “<strong>the</strong> inherent right of<br />

self-government, exercised within Canada, should be recognized in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, including jurisdictions over l<strong>and</strong>s, resources, culture, <strong>and</strong><br />

language.” 41 Similarly, <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples<br />

intervened in <strong>the</strong> process in mid-February. <strong>The</strong> Commission recommended<br />

that “...any new constitutional provision dealing with <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal right of<br />

self-government...should indicate that <strong>the</strong> right is inherent in nature,<br />

circumscribed in extent, <strong>and</strong> sovereign in its sphere.” 42 Although some<br />

Aboriginal leaders (such as Yvon Dumont of <strong>the</strong> Metis National Council)<br />

objected to <strong>the</strong> limitations <strong>the</strong> Commission would place on <strong>the</strong> right even<br />

before negotiations had begun, 43 <strong>the</strong> intervention never<strong>the</strong>less lent added<br />

credibility to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for an inherent right.<br />

236


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

In a similar vein, <strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee, which reported in late<br />

February after conducting nation-wide hearings, recommended “<strong>the</strong><br />

entrenchment in section 35 of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982 of <strong>the</strong> inherent right<br />

of Aboriginal peoples to self-government within Canada.” 44 With two of <strong>the</strong><br />

government’s own committees on-side, <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for entrenchment of <strong>the</strong><br />

inherent right to self-government seemed unassailable. It survived <strong>the</strong><br />

subsequent rounds of bargaining among <strong>the</strong> First Ministers, <strong>the</strong> territorial<br />

governments <strong>and</strong> representatives of <strong>the</strong> four national Aboriginal organizations<br />

held from May to August, 1992, <strong>and</strong> appeared in <strong>the</strong> Draft Legal Text of <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord of October 9, 1992.<br />

Hence, with regard to <strong>the</strong> inherent right to self-government, <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accord was an exceptional coup for <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal organizations <strong>and</strong> leaders<br />

(particularly Ovide Mercredi) who risked exclusion of <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong>s from <strong>the</strong><br />

process of reform altoge<strong>the</strong>r by holding out for an unassailable inherent right.<br />

This achievement is <strong>the</strong> more notable, since, as Chartr<strong>and</strong> notes, “traditionally,<br />

<strong>the</strong> judicial dialogue of ‘rights’ has considered rights as legal boundaries<br />

beyond which <strong>the</strong> individuaT is shielded from <strong>the</strong> legislative intrusion of <strong>the</strong><br />

State [whereas] governmental ‘rights’ to legislate have been expressed in<br />

terms of ‘powers’, not of ‘rights.”’ 45 What is significant <strong>the</strong>n, is <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

whereas <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two levels of government cannot claim “rights” vis-à-vis one<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r (<strong>the</strong>y can at most claim <strong>the</strong> improper exercise of power beyond <strong>the</strong><br />

jurisdictional powers set out in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act), Aboriginal governments<br />

would have been able to claim a right to govern, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y would claim it vis-àvis<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r governments. Moreover, Aboriginal governments were to enter <strong>the</strong><br />

domain of law-making under <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> (albeit subject to some<br />

constraints), an historic reversal of over a century of colonial law.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Intersection of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> Quebec <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Agendas: “Two Founding Nations” <strong>and</strong> Distinct Society Status<br />

Since before Confederation, <strong>the</strong> relationship between English <strong>and</strong> French<br />

Canada has been characterized as a compact between “two founding nations.”<br />

Indeed, federalism itself has been regarded as an arrangement designed to join<br />

<strong>the</strong> two ethnic/linguistic groups in a system which would allow each to flourish<br />

while reaping <strong>the</strong> benefits of broader union. Since Quebec’s “Quiet<br />

Revolution” of <strong>the</strong> 1960s, <strong>the</strong> agenda of constitutional reform has revolved<br />

largely around Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s for a renegotiation of <strong>the</strong> division of powers<br />

to facilitate its nation-building strategies. <strong>The</strong> conception of Canada as a<br />

compact between English- <strong>and</strong> French- speaking peoples has been reinforced<br />

by federal policies such as official bilingualism. Moreover, various initiatives,<br />

from <strong>the</strong> Victoria <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of 1971 to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, to <strong>the</strong> post-Meech round of<br />

1991-92, have attempted to solve <strong>the</strong> problem of Quebec’s dem<strong>and</strong>s for more<br />

provincial powers as well as a veto over subsequent constitutional change.<br />

Although challenged by <strong>the</strong> principle of <strong>the</strong> equality of <strong>the</strong> provinces <strong>and</strong> by<br />

multiculturalism, <strong>the</strong> two nations conception has survived as a dominant<br />

element of Canadian political discourse.<br />

Canada’s Aboriginal peoples, however, have long rejected <strong>the</strong> “two founding<br />

nations” conception of Canada. In fact, it is almost always characterized as a<br />

“myth.” For example, as early as 1979, <strong>the</strong> National Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood (NIB,<br />

later retitled <strong>the</strong> Assembly of First Nations) told <strong>the</strong>Task Force on Canadian<br />

Unity that “<strong>the</strong> myth suggesting that <strong>the</strong> French <strong>and</strong> English are founding<br />

peoples of Canada... is historically inaccurate <strong>and</strong> an insult to <strong>the</strong> Indian people<br />

of Canada.” 46<br />

237


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal challenge to <strong>the</strong> dominant conception of <strong>the</strong> national<br />

compact did not gain currency until <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 “Canada Round.” Throughout<br />

<strong>the</strong> four Aboriginal parallel processes (<strong>and</strong> elsewhere), opinion was uniform<br />

that this conception was in need of revision as it excluded <strong>the</strong> original<br />

inhabitants of <strong>the</strong> continent. For example, an ITC position paper pointed out<br />

that “<strong>the</strong> myth of English <strong>and</strong> French speahng Canadians as <strong>the</strong> two founding<br />

peoples of Canada ignores <strong>the</strong> contribution <strong>and</strong> needs of Aboriginal peoples as<br />

Canada’s first citizens.” 47 Similarly, a number of submissions to <strong>the</strong> AFN’s<br />

First Nations Circle asserted <strong>the</strong> prior presence <strong>and</strong> unique rights of Aboriginal<br />

peoples:<br />

<strong>The</strong> principle of two founding nations is one of <strong>the</strong> biggest fallacies in<br />

this century. Time did not start ticking on this continent when <strong>the</strong><br />

European people arrived. <strong>The</strong> constitution must recognize <strong>and</strong> give<br />

due regard to <strong>the</strong> special status <strong>the</strong> First Nations have in Canada. 48<br />

On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, perhaps because a significant proportion of its constituency<br />

is Metis, <strong>the</strong> NCC has taken a less pointed <strong>and</strong> perhaps more conciliatory view<br />

of <strong>the</strong> “two founding nations” discourse. <strong>The</strong> NCC’s Executive Task Force on<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in fact called for “a recognition of French Canada as a<br />

founding or distinct society,” on <strong>the</strong> basis that <strong>the</strong> Quebec <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal<br />

positions should be “mutually supportable.” 49<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, during <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 process, <strong>the</strong> two nations concept was under<br />

siege, displaced by an alternate concept: three founding peoples. <strong>The</strong> AFN<br />

First Nations Circle Commissioners, for example, concluded that “<strong>the</strong>re is<br />

widespread <strong>and</strong> growing support for <strong>the</strong> position that First Nations are one of<br />

Canada’s three founding peoples.” 50 In fact, <strong>the</strong> idea had surfaced during <strong>the</strong><br />

five constitutional conferences held in various cities in early 1992. <strong>The</strong><br />

Toronto conference in particular (which focussed on <strong>the</strong> “distinct society”<br />

clause) endorsed NCC President Ron George’s insistence that Aboriginal<br />

peoples be accepted as <strong>the</strong> first of three “founding national communities.” 51<br />

Indeed, so powerful was <strong>the</strong> displacement of <strong>the</strong> two nations concept that even<br />

central Canadian academics, who had long accepted it, began to make space in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir constitutional discourse for Aboriginal peoples.<br />

Of course, <strong>the</strong> three founding peoples concept is an unsatisfactory rival to <strong>the</strong><br />

two nations concept, since Aboriginal peoples have been adamant in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

insistence that <strong>the</strong>y are not an undifferentiated mass, but are distinctive nations<br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir own right. However, <strong>the</strong> idea was to displace <strong>the</strong> previous exclusionary<br />

discourse. More than anything, <strong>the</strong> “three founding peoples” concept<br />

challenges <strong>the</strong> core of <strong>the</strong> Canadian federal community’s self-definition; it<br />

requires a radical reconceptualization of <strong>the</strong> political compact. As Chartr<strong>and</strong><br />

observes:<br />

238<br />

<strong>The</strong> nationalistic movement among Aboriginal peoples presents a<br />

challenge to <strong>the</strong> notion of two founding nations in establishing <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian state. Since <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples had virtually no say in<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of Canada, <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of Canada, not only as a<br />

constitutional entity, but as a country with a legitimate vision of its<br />

own society is being challenged. It so happens, however, that <strong>the</strong><br />

Aboriginal nationalism is occuring at a time when <strong>the</strong> nationalism of<br />

one of <strong>the</strong> “offficial founding nations” is itself causing a fundamental<br />

re-examination of <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of <strong>the</strong> existing order. 52


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with <strong>the</strong> alternative conception, however, concerned its<br />

implications for <strong>the</strong> manner in which Aboriginal peoples would be recognized<br />

in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>. Since <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, in which Quebec was to be<br />

recognized as a “distinct society,” <strong>the</strong> term had become widely associated with<br />

Quebec’s status claims. However, Aboriginal groups had been using it since at<br />

least <strong>the</strong> 1970s. 53 In May 1987, <strong>the</strong> leaders of <strong>the</strong> four national Aboriginal<br />

organizations had written a letter to <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister asking for recognition<br />

of Aboriginal peoples as a distinct society in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. 54 Hence,<br />

by <strong>the</strong> 1990s, Aboriginal leaders resented <strong>the</strong> implication that Quebec had<br />

somehow gained a copyright on <strong>the</strong> concept. Thus began <strong>the</strong> discursive<br />

competition between Aboriginal versus Quebec claims. It was not simply a<br />

question of “whatever Quebec gets, we want too.” Instead, it was a question of<br />

prior claims, as well as of <strong>the</strong> effect of distinct society status for Quebec on <strong>the</strong><br />

Aboriginal populations of that province. As <strong>the</strong> Commissioners of <strong>the</strong> AFN’<br />

First Nations Circle noted:<br />

<strong>The</strong> people who spoke to us said this: of course Quebec is distinct<br />

from English Canada...<strong>The</strong> cultures are not <strong>the</strong> same...We<br />

sympathize with Quebec’s desire to preserve <strong>and</strong> transmit what is<br />

uniquely Quebecois. All we ask is that <strong>the</strong>y give us <strong>the</strong> same right that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y claim for <strong>the</strong>mselves...Aboriginal peoples are not merely<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r ethnic group like <strong>the</strong> Ukrainians or <strong>the</strong> Dutch. We too are a<br />

distinct society. We are <strong>the</strong> original society....how does one define<br />

“distinctness”? Linguistic differences? As one white contributor<br />

pointed out, French <strong>and</strong> English belong to <strong>the</strong> same family of<br />

languages....Our languages belong to an entirely different group.<br />

Legal systems? <strong>The</strong> Common <strong>La</strong>w of English Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Napoleonic Code may differ, but <strong>the</strong>y share <strong>the</strong> same approach to<br />

crime <strong>and</strong> punishment, an approach totally unlike Aboriginal justice.<br />

Cultural differences? Consider Aboriginal attitudes towards l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

ownership, which are radically different from whites’. [One]<br />

presenter noted that Aboriginal peoples are so distinct that even <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

biochemistry, <strong>the</strong>ir blood types <strong>and</strong> metabolism, are not quite <strong>the</strong><br />

same as Eurocanadians’...If <strong>the</strong>re is to be competition for Most<br />

Distinct Society in Canada, <strong>the</strong> French would not be winners. <strong>The</strong><br />

competition matters only because Quebec, in dem<strong>and</strong>ing its rights,<br />

risks trampling on ours. Fear for <strong>the</strong> future of First Nations in Quebec<br />

was voiced...all across <strong>the</strong> country. It is not in Quebec’s interests to<br />

respect First Nations’ rights. 55<br />

In a similar vein, Ovide Mercredi, National Chief of <strong>the</strong> AFN, addressed <strong>the</strong><br />

Commons-Senate Committee on a Renewed Canada (<strong>the</strong> Beaudoin -Dobbie<br />

Committee), outlining not only <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal claim to distinct society status,<br />

but also <strong>the</strong> potential dangers to Aboriginal interests if Quebec were so<br />

recognized:<br />

We want to preserve a distinct way of life that has suffered<br />

dramatically under policies of assimilation. So we look at <strong>the</strong><br />

constitution as a vehicle for accomplishing that objective...<strong>The</strong><br />

recognition of Quebec as a distinct society can be very detrimental to<br />

First Nations within Quebec. It does not take much to conjure<br />

numerous possibilities of how this recognition can be used to <strong>the</strong><br />

detriment of First Nations, from l<strong>and</strong> claims to hydroelectric<br />

239


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

developments to language programs to education <strong>and</strong> even military<br />

defence. 56<br />

<strong>The</strong>se concerns were echoed by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r national Aboriginal organizations.<br />

<strong>The</strong> ITC, for example, took <strong>the</strong> position that:<br />

Inuit strongly believe that it is necessary to identify Aboriginal<br />

peoples as distinct societies...[T]he constitutional recognition of<br />

Quebec as a distinct society wlthout also recognizing Aboriginal<br />

peoples places us in a disadvantageous position. For example, it<br />

could result in Inuit language rights in certain regions of Canada<br />

being accorded secondary status. 57<br />

Again, <strong>the</strong> NCC’s position was less pointed, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> organization’s<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Review Commission took <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong>re was no need to<br />

apply <strong>the</strong> words “distinct societies” to Aboriginal nations, provided that<br />

terminology with an “equivalent significance <strong>and</strong> authority within <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>” was used. 58 <strong>The</strong> NCC was concerned, never<strong>the</strong>less, about<br />

Quebec’s reluctance to recognize distinct society status for Aboriginal<br />

peoples, particularly as off-reserve Indian <strong>and</strong> Metis people in Quebec would<br />

be threatened by <strong>the</strong> imposition of <strong>the</strong> province’s cultural <strong>and</strong> language laws. 59<br />

It was at <strong>the</strong> Toronto conference, however, that <strong>the</strong> competition between<br />

Aboriginal peoples <strong>and</strong> Quebec over distinct society status reached new<br />

heights. Though Aboriginal organizations had not been formally invited to<br />

participate in <strong>the</strong> conference, Mercredi went anyway. He was successful in<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> right to speak <strong>and</strong> complained about <strong>the</strong> exclusion of<br />

Aboriginal groups at <strong>the</strong> conference. <strong>The</strong> opening plenary ended with Zebedee<br />

Nungak of <strong>the</strong> ITC displaying a map of Quebec in which approximately one<br />

half of <strong>the</strong> territory (coloured red) was carved out as <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal territories<br />

which could secede from Quebec if Quebec seceded from Canada. 60 A few<br />

days later, Mercredi addressed <strong>the</strong> Quebec National Assembly committee<br />

examining sovereignty, <strong>and</strong> disputed Quebec’s right to self-determination:<br />

Self-determination is not a right of a “province.” It is <strong>the</strong> right of all<br />

peoples. Are <strong>the</strong> “people of Quebec” a “people” in <strong>the</strong> international<br />

legal sense? <strong>The</strong> population of Quebec is made up of a wide range of<br />

racial <strong>and</strong> ethnic groups. It cannot be considered to be a single<br />

“people” with <strong>the</strong> right of self-determination. O<strong>the</strong>rwise, <strong>the</strong> “people<br />

of Canada” would also be a “people” for <strong>the</strong> purpose of international<br />

law. Through such interpretations, <strong>the</strong> essential purposes of selfdetermination<br />

would be defeated....It is not clear to whom <strong>the</strong> term<br />

“Québécois” refers. Does it imply that people of all racial, national<br />

<strong>and</strong> ethnic origins living within Quebec are a single people...with one<br />

right to self-determination? Are French Quebeckers <strong>and</strong> First<br />

Nations within Quebec part of a single people? If this is your view,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it is contrary to our right to self-determination <strong>and</strong> selfidentification.<br />

6l<br />

<strong>The</strong> map incident, toge<strong>the</strong>r with Mercredi’s comments, provoked angry<br />

reactions in Quebec It also sparked dissent among Aboriginal organizations.<br />

Ron George of <strong>the</strong> NCC, for example, told <strong>the</strong> Beaudoin-Dobbie Committee<br />

that “we are not going to get dragged into a phony war with French Canada or<br />

240


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

Quebec,” <strong>and</strong> maintained that Aboriginal peoples did not need distinct society<br />

status as well as recognition of <strong>the</strong> inherent right to self-government. 62<br />

Perhaps because Mercredi realized that Quebec’s consent would be required<br />

for any constitutional amendment package (<strong>and</strong> perhaps in part because<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Affairs Minister, Joe Clark, warned that such “inflammatory”<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s could result in <strong>the</strong> exclusion of Aboriginal issues from <strong>the</strong><br />

package63), Mercredi’s position softened considerably over <strong>the</strong> ensuing<br />

months. In <strong>the</strong> final rounds of negotiation over <strong>the</strong> summer of 1992, <strong>the</strong><br />

dem<strong>and</strong> for recognition of Aboriginal peoples as distinct societies was<br />

dropped. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord, however, though avoiding that<br />

terminology, included what amounted to a distinct society clause for<br />

Aboriginal peoples in s.2(b) of <strong>the</strong> Canada clause (quoted above).<br />

Hence, while Aboriginal leaders did not succeed in <strong>the</strong>ir quest to obtain<br />

distinct society status for Aboriginal peoples, <strong>the</strong> language of <strong>the</strong> Canada<br />

clause, toge<strong>the</strong>r with recognition of <strong>the</strong> inherent right to self-government,<br />

were arguably stronger guarantees than that imported by <strong>the</strong> distinct society<br />

terminology. <strong>The</strong> discursive breakthrough was significant, moreover, since<br />

<strong>the</strong> bubble of “two nations” had been pricked, <strong>and</strong> as it was widely realized that<br />

Aboriginal peoples had a legitimate claim to special status which could not be<br />

neglected in constitutional reform.<br />

Individual versus Collective Rights: Gender Equality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Application of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> cornerstones of Aboriginal constitutional discourse in recent years<br />

has been <strong>the</strong> primacy of collective over individual rights. Aboriginal rights<br />

claims are claims to collective rights, wherein rights inure to individuals by<br />

virtue of <strong>the</strong>ir group membership. Whereas an Aboriginal right (such as <strong>the</strong><br />

right to hunt or fish) may be exercised by individuals, access to <strong>the</strong> right is predetermined<br />

by <strong>the</strong>ir membership in Aboriginal communities. However, l<strong>and</strong><br />

rights under Aboriginal title, for example, cannot be claimed by individuals, as<br />

<strong>the</strong> notion of Aboriginal title is founded upon <strong>the</strong> idea that l<strong>and</strong>s are held by<br />

communities, not by individuals.<br />

<strong>The</strong> discourse of rights is a ra<strong>the</strong>r recent phenomenon among Aboriginal<br />

peoples, who did not traditionally structure <strong>the</strong>ir communities around rights<br />

concepts. Aboriginal leaders <strong>and</strong> scholars in recent years have critiqued <strong>the</strong><br />

entire basis of <strong>the</strong> rights approach to mediating <strong>the</strong> competing claims of<br />

individuals <strong>and</strong> groups. Mary Ellen Turpel, for example, points out that “rights<br />

discourse has been widely appropriated by Aboriginal peoples in struggles<br />

against <strong>the</strong> effects of colonialism.” 64 However, rights discourse is based on<br />

liberal, individualist ideology with its celebration of <strong>the</strong> right to private<br />

property. This discourse, she argues, is not congruent with Aboriginal<br />

philosophies, since rights are seen as erecting fences around <strong>the</strong> individual <strong>the</strong><br />

better to protect her against harm from o<strong>the</strong>rs:<br />

Although <strong>the</strong>re is no culture or system of beliefs shared by all<br />

Aboriginal peoples, <strong>the</strong> paradigm of rights based conceptually on <strong>the</strong><br />

prototype of right of individual ownership of property is anti<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

to <strong>the</strong> widely shared underst<strong>and</strong>ing of creation <strong>and</strong> stewardship<br />

responsibilities of First Nations peoples for <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, for Mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Earth. Moreover, to my knowledge <strong>the</strong>re are no narratives among<br />

Aboriginal peoples of living toge<strong>the</strong>r for <strong>the</strong> purposes of protecting<br />

241


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

an individual interest in property....<strong>The</strong> collective or communal basis<br />

of Aboriginal life does not really...have a parallel to individual rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> conceptions of law are simply incommensurable....Aboriginal<br />

rights claims are, in my view, requests for <strong>the</strong> recognition by <strong>the</strong><br />

dominant (European) culture of <strong>the</strong> existence of ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> for<br />

toleration of, <strong>and</strong> respect for, <strong>the</strong> practical obstacles that <strong>the</strong> request<br />

brings with it. While this may be cloaked in rights talk, <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

something at stake that is larger than rights, <strong>and</strong> that is conceivably<br />

outside of <strong>the</strong> texts of particular documents intended to guarantee<br />

human rights...What is at stake is a more basic, less “legalized”<br />

condition of survival: <strong>the</strong> dignity of existing as Peoples. 65<br />

<strong>The</strong> clash of individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights was most clearly demonstrated in<br />

1969 when <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government’s proposal that “<strong>the</strong> Indian people’s role<br />

of dependence be replaced by a role of equal status, opportunity <strong>and</strong><br />

responsibility” 66 was resoundingly rejected by status Indians. Those who<br />

would have been stripped of <strong>the</strong>ir special status <strong>and</strong> rights under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act<br />

were manifestly uninterested in <strong>the</strong> sacred cows of liberal individualist<br />

ideology—equality of opportunity <strong>and</strong> freedom from discrimination based on<br />

race, ethnicity, religion, gender <strong>and</strong> so on. That is not to suggest that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

favoured inequality <strong>and</strong> discrimination. Instead, <strong>the</strong>y objected that such<br />

individual rights <strong>and</strong> liberties were being offered at <strong>the</strong> expense of special<br />

status <strong>and</strong> group rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problems of individual versus collective rights are pertinent to Aboriginal<br />

constitutional discourse in two major respects. In <strong>the</strong> first instance, Aboriginal<br />

rights (such as self-government, hunting, fishing <strong>and</strong> treaty rights) are<br />

collective claims in <strong>the</strong> positive sense of extending power to Abonginal<br />

nations to take certain actions (to make laws, for example). <strong>The</strong>y are also<br />

negative in <strong>the</strong> sense of requiring freedom from interference by o<strong>the</strong>rs in <strong>the</strong><br />

exercise of rights. Essentially, <strong>the</strong>se are rights claimed against o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

governments; <strong>the</strong>y concern relations of power between Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> non-<br />

Aboriginal peoples. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> intersection of individual <strong>and</strong><br />

collective rights within Aboriginal communities is a different order of<br />

problem.<br />

With regard to <strong>the</strong> relations of power between Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> non Aboriginal<br />

peoples, many have pointed out that while <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights may be <strong>the</strong><br />

coronation of liberal individualism, it has never<strong>the</strong>less recognized certain<br />

group entitlements, such as language rights. Cenainly, <strong>the</strong> mainstream<br />

discourse of rights has exp<strong>and</strong>ed sufficiently to include collective rights, <strong>and</strong><br />

in a series of cases, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court has recognized that equality may mean<br />

treating groups (not just individuals) differently to ameliorate conditions of<br />

disadvantage. 67 As <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord proposed to add to <strong>the</strong> collective<br />

rights of Aboriginal peoples which had been enshrined in l982, Canadian<br />

political elites at least have shown <strong>the</strong>mselves willing to accommodate certain<br />

group rights.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> question of rights within Aboriginal communities, <strong>and</strong><br />

particularly under self-government regimes, is an especially delicate one. It<br />

involves <strong>the</strong> ability of individuals to claim individual rights against a group<br />

exercising collective rights. This issue surfaced in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 constitutional<br />

talks, revolving around <strong>the</strong> application of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights to Aboriginal<br />

governments. Aboriginal leaders have long rejected <strong>the</strong> idea that Aboriginal<br />

governments should be subject to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> on <strong>the</strong> grounds that some <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

242


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

rights could be inconsistent with <strong>the</strong> exercise of self-government, particularly<br />

in <strong>the</strong> case of communities wishing to follow <strong>the</strong>ir traditional modes of<br />

governance. For example, in 1982 <strong>the</strong> National Chief of <strong>the</strong> AFN told <strong>the</strong><br />

Commons St<strong>and</strong>ing Committee on Aboriginal Affairs that:<br />

...as Indian people we cannot afford to have individual rights override<br />

collective rights. Our societies have never been structured that way,<br />

unlike yours, <strong>and</strong> that is where <strong>the</strong> clash comes...If you isolate <strong>the</strong><br />

individual rights from <strong>the</strong> collective rights, <strong>the</strong>n you are heading<br />

down ano<strong>the</strong>r path that is even more discriminatory...<strong>The</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights is in conflict with our philosophy <strong>and</strong> culture. 68<br />

Mary Ellen Turpel (coincidentally <strong>the</strong> AFN’s chief constitutional adviser) has<br />

offered a number of arguments against <strong>the</strong> application of <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> or individual<br />

rights to Aboriginal governments. She points out that “it is difficult for a<br />

culturally distinct people to define <strong>the</strong> trajectory of its own development if<br />

individuals from within or outside <strong>the</strong> culture can challenge collective<br />

decisions on <strong>the</strong> basis that <strong>the</strong>y infringe <strong>the</strong>ir individual rights under <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Canadian legal system that does not underst<strong>and</strong>, or give priority<br />

to, collective goals.” 69 Turpel warns of <strong>the</strong> threat to <strong>the</strong> cultural identity of<br />

communities pursuing <strong>the</strong>ir idiosyncratic political <strong>and</strong> spiritual traditions if<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are subject to ei<strong>the</strong>r internal challenges by <strong>the</strong>ir own members, or external<br />

challenges by non-Aboriginal individuals arguing that Aboriginal laws do not<br />

conform to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>:<br />

In <strong>the</strong> case of an external challenge, for example, on <strong>the</strong> basis of<br />

voting or c<strong>and</strong>idacy rights where a non-Aboriginal complainant<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong>y could not vote or st<strong>and</strong> for elections in an Aboriginal<br />

community, a Canadian court would be given <strong>the</strong> authority to decide<br />

an important part of <strong>the</strong> future for an Aboriginal people. It would have<br />

to [weigh] <strong>the</strong> protections afforded Aboriginal rights by section 25 of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> [against] <strong>the</strong> individual right to vote recognized in section<br />

3. Should Canadian courts (<strong>and</strong> non-Aboriginal judges) have<br />

authority in such cases? <strong>The</strong> critical question is, do <strong>the</strong>y have cultural<br />

authority?...<br />

<strong>The</strong>...internal challenge is conceivable where a member of an<br />

Aboriginal community who feels dissatisfied with a particular course<br />

of action <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal government has taken, or envisages taking,<br />

turns to <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> for <strong>the</strong> recognition of a right. This is an equally, if<br />

not more, worrisome prospect. This kind of challenge would be a<br />

dangerous opening for a ruling by a Canadian court on individual<br />

versus collective rights within an Aboriginal community. It<br />

would...break down community methods of dispute resolution <strong>and</strong><br />

restoration....It would also have <strong>the</strong> effect of encouraging people to<br />

go outside <strong>the</strong> community <strong>and</strong> its customs, to settle disputes in formal<br />

courts, instead of dealing with problems within <strong>the</strong> community. This<br />

is particularly threatening, perhaps even ethnocidal, to Aboriginal<br />

peoples who are on <strong>the</strong> brink of cultural destruction because of <strong>the</strong><br />

legacy of colonialism <strong>and</strong> paternalism under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. 70<br />

<strong>The</strong>se sorts of concerns explain why Aboriginal organizations insisted that s. 3<br />

should not be applied to Aboriginal governments. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, in addition to<br />

democratic rights, it is possible that <strong>the</strong> legal rights in Sections 7 to 14 of <strong>the</strong><br />

243


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> may pose similar problems for Aboriginal governments seeking to<br />

follow Aboriginal justice traditions. Mobility <strong>and</strong> equality rights could<br />

likewise make Aboriginal governments vulnerable to both internal <strong>and</strong><br />

external challenges. <strong>The</strong> solution in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord was to offer<br />

Aboriginal governments access to Section 33, <strong>the</strong> override clause, so that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

could exempt certain of <strong>the</strong>ir laws from fundamental freedoms, legal <strong>and</strong><br />

equality rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> antagonism between individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights was not to be so<br />

easily resolved, however. One of <strong>the</strong> keenest ironies of <strong>the</strong> recent process was<br />

that, at <strong>the</strong> very moment when non-Aboriginal governments (<strong>and</strong> a large<br />

proportion of <strong>the</strong> citizenry) were accepting for <strong>the</strong> first time <strong>the</strong> idea of<br />

entrenching Aboriginal peoples’ collective rights to self-government, those<br />

rights were being assailed by <strong>the</strong> individual rights claims of <strong>the</strong> Native<br />

Women’s Association of Canada (NWAC). Essentially, NWAC’s challenge<br />

was based on <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> male-dominated Aboriginal organizations <strong>and</strong><br />

B<strong>and</strong> Councils were not representing <strong>and</strong> would not in <strong>the</strong> future guarantee<br />

gender equality for Aboriginal women under self-government regimes. Hence<br />

<strong>the</strong>y dem<strong>and</strong>ed: first, independent funding for <strong>and</strong> representation at any <strong>and</strong> all<br />

constitutional negotiations regarding Aboriginal self-government; <strong>and</strong><br />

second, that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> be applied to Aboriginal governments so that<br />

Aboriginal women would be shielded from <strong>the</strong> potentially discriminatory<br />

effects of traditional forms of government. <strong>The</strong> latter concerns are examined<br />

after a discussion of <strong>the</strong> question of representation <strong>and</strong> funding.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association’s dem<strong>and</strong> for independent representation<br />

<strong>and</strong> funding was to be <strong>the</strong> subject of two court cases. It must be noted, however,<br />

that NWAC had been allowed to participate in its own right at <strong>the</strong> 1983 <strong>and</strong><br />

1985 First Ministers’ Conferences on Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters. But<br />

in <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 round of talks, it was not. However, members of NWAC<br />

participated in <strong>the</strong> parallel processes of <strong>the</strong> national organizations. In fact,<br />

Sharon McIvor, a member of NWAC’s national executive, was one of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners of <strong>the</strong> AFN’s First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>. In<br />

addition, each of <strong>the</strong> national organizations included women’s workshops in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir parallel processes. 71 <strong>The</strong> AFN <strong>and</strong> NCC had each allocated $130,000 of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir grants from <strong>the</strong> Secretary of State to NWAC, money which had been<br />

earmarked in <strong>the</strong> Contribution Agreements with <strong>the</strong> federal government. A<br />

supplementary grant from Secretary of State brought NWAC’s funding to<br />

about 5% of what <strong>the</strong> Agreements had provided to each of <strong>the</strong> four national<br />

organizations, a total of some $10 million. 72 Moreover, <strong>the</strong> NCC had<br />

responded to NWAC’s lobbying by assigning some of its seats to NWAC<br />

representatives in <strong>the</strong> constitutional conferences, particularly <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal<br />

Conference of March 13-15, 1992.<br />

NWAC’s main concerns about independent funding <strong>and</strong> representation were<br />

not, however, satisfied by <strong>the</strong>se arrangements. In <strong>the</strong> spring of 1992, NWAC<br />

went to court to block federal grants to <strong>the</strong> four organizations. <strong>The</strong> Federal<br />

Court of Appeal substantially upheld NWAC’s claims in a judgement issued<br />

just a week before <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Consensus Report was signed. NWAC<br />

asked <strong>the</strong> court for an order prohibiting funding to <strong>the</strong> AFN, NCC, MNC <strong>and</strong><br />

ITC until <strong>the</strong> federal government provided equal funding to NWAC <strong>and</strong> an<br />

equal right of participation in <strong>the</strong> constitutional review process. <strong>The</strong> NCC,<br />

ITC, <strong>and</strong> MNC intervened in <strong>the</strong> case, challenging NWAC’s claim that it<br />

represented Aboriginal women. <strong>The</strong> NCC denied that it was a male or maledominated<br />

organization, noting that <strong>the</strong> Presidents of its Alberta, Yukon <strong>and</strong><br />

244


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

<strong>La</strong>brador constituents were women, <strong>and</strong> that it had been active in opposing<br />

gender discrimination under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. <strong>The</strong> MNC <strong>and</strong> ITC each denied<br />

that NWAC represented Métis <strong>and</strong> Inuit women, <strong>the</strong> latter noting that Inuit<br />

women are represented by Pauktuutit, a national organization whose President<br />

is a member of <strong>the</strong> Board of Directors of ITC. In a unanimous decision,<br />

however, three judges found that:<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is ample evidence that <strong>the</strong>y individually [<strong>the</strong> Appellants, Gail<br />

Stacey-Moore <strong>and</strong> Sharon McIvor] <strong>and</strong> native women as a class<br />

remain doubly disadvantaged in Canadian society by reason of both<br />

race <strong>and</strong> sex <strong>and</strong> disadvantaged in at least some Aboriginal societies<br />

by reason of sex. <strong>The</strong> uncontradicted evidence is that <strong>the</strong>y are also<br />

seriously disadvantaged by reason of sex within <strong>the</strong> segment of<br />

Aboriginal society residing on or claiming <strong>the</strong> right to reside on<br />

Indian reservations....<strong>The</strong> evidence establishes that [NWAC] is a<br />

grassroots organization founded <strong>and</strong> led by Aboriginal women, at<br />

least Métis <strong>and</strong> non-status Indian women.... NWAC is a bona fide,<br />

established <strong>and</strong> recognized national voice of <strong>and</strong> for Aboriginal<br />

women. 73<br />

Significantly, <strong>the</strong> Court held that none of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r national organizations<br />

adequately represented Aboriginal women’s interests. Moreover, although <strong>the</strong><br />

AFN did not intervene in <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong> Court found that First Nations women’s<br />

interests were “likely to be injured if AFN’s position prevails”:<br />

...AFN, <strong>and</strong> its forerunner <strong>the</strong> National Indian Bro<strong>the</strong>rhood, has<br />

vigorously <strong>and</strong> consistently resisted <strong>the</strong> struggle of native women to<br />

rid <strong>the</strong>mselves of <strong>the</strong> gender inequality historically entrenched in <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian Act <strong>and</strong> has intervened in Parliamentary <strong>and</strong> legal proceedings<br />

to oppose those efforts. It opposed repeal of s.12(1)(b) of <strong>the</strong> Indian<br />

Act... <strong>and</strong> it opposed proclamation of <strong>the</strong> amendment to <strong>the</strong><br />

,<strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1982 which added s. 35(4) [guaranteeing<br />

Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights equally to male <strong>and</strong> female persons].” 74<br />

<strong>The</strong> court concluded that by inviting <strong>and</strong> funding <strong>the</strong> participation of <strong>the</strong> four<br />

national organizations, but excluding NWAC, “<strong>the</strong> Canadian government has<br />

accorded <strong>the</strong> advocates of male dominated Aboriginal self-governments a<br />

preferred position in <strong>the</strong> exercise of an expressive activity, <strong>the</strong> freedom of<br />

which is guaranteed to everyone by s. 2(b), <strong>and</strong> which is, by s. 28, guaranteed<br />

equally to men <strong>and</strong> women.” 75<br />

<strong>The</strong> court did not prohibit <strong>the</strong> government from funding <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

organizations, holding that it could not compel <strong>the</strong> government ei<strong>the</strong>r to fund<br />

NWAC equally or to invite its representatives to <strong>the</strong> bargaining table.<br />

None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> finding that NWAC’s freedom of expression rights had been<br />

infringed should have been enough to prompt an invitation to <strong>the</strong> last round of<br />

negotiations in Charlottetown. However, no such invitation was forthcoming.<br />

NWAC subsequently petitioned <strong>the</strong> Federal Court Trial Division for an<br />

injunction prohibiting discussions between <strong>the</strong> governments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> four<br />

national organizations on subjects dealt with in <strong>the</strong> Consensus Report until<br />

NWAC was accorded <strong>the</strong> right to participate in <strong>the</strong> talks. NWAC also asked for<br />

an injunction prohibiting <strong>the</strong> Referendum scheduled for October 26, 1992, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> grounds that it was “based on a nullity” given <strong>the</strong> Appeal Court’s finding of<br />

a violation of NWAC’s freedom of expression right in <strong>the</strong> earlier case. 76 After<br />

245


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

<strong>the</strong> AFN intervened, <strong>the</strong> Federal Court delayed hearing <strong>the</strong> case in order to give<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r groups time to prepare <strong>the</strong>ir arguments. 77 Though <strong>the</strong> decision was<br />

negative, in <strong>the</strong> end, events were to render <strong>the</strong> case moot as <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accord succumbed to defeat at <strong>the</strong> polls.<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> play of events, however, <strong>the</strong> importance of such legal<br />

interventions cannot be underestimated. <strong>The</strong> court challenges exemplify<br />

precisely <strong>the</strong> sorts of concerns raised by Turpel <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs that <strong>the</strong> overall<br />

collective rights of Aboriginal peoples would be prostrated before non-<br />

Aboriginal courts deferring to <strong>the</strong> individual rights discourse in which <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rejoices. <strong>The</strong>y represented a challenge to <strong>the</strong> representivity of <strong>the</strong> four<br />

national organizations which in <strong>the</strong>ir various incarnations have been accepted<br />

<strong>and</strong> funded by <strong>the</strong> federal government for more than twenty years. As such,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y question <strong>the</strong> federal government’s right to decide which groups are<br />

representative of all of <strong>the</strong> various interests of Aboriginal peoples, as well as its<br />

right to select those whose interests are to be given voice.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question of voice is especially significant in light of <strong>the</strong> aftermath of <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord, when a number of First Nations (such as <strong>the</strong> Mohawks)<br />

claimed that <strong>the</strong> AFN did not represent <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> agreement reached by<br />

<strong>the</strong> national organizations did not meet <strong>the</strong> aspirations of all Aboriginal<br />

peoples. It is also significant in view of <strong>the</strong> controversy over <strong>the</strong> government’s<br />

ability to decide who is <strong>and</strong> who is not an Indian for <strong>the</strong> purposes of <strong>the</strong> Indian<br />

Act, a power which has historically robbed thous<strong>and</strong>s of Aboriginal people<br />

(mostly women) of <strong>the</strong>ir Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights. This is a recurring <strong>the</strong>me<br />

in Aboriginal political discourse, since artificial legal classifications have<br />

determined access to rights <strong>and</strong> benefits. <strong>The</strong>y have also created political<br />

divisions between different categories of Aboriginal peoples who have as a<br />

consequence different material <strong>and</strong> political interests. Hence, one of <strong>the</strong> major<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> constitutional discourse has been that membership be<br />

determined by Aboriginal communities <strong>the</strong>mselves, ra<strong>the</strong>r than by <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government with its vested interest in limiting <strong>the</strong> number of people who can<br />

claim status <strong>and</strong> entitlements under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. <strong>The</strong> question of equity of<br />

access to Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights for Métis <strong>and</strong> non-status Indians has<br />

been a major concern for <strong>the</strong> MNC <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> NCC. 78 Hence, <strong>the</strong>ir inclusion in<br />

<strong>the</strong> self-government provisions of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord represented a<br />

major coup for those organizations. Unhappily, however, <strong>the</strong> issue of equal<br />

access to Aboriginal self-government rights has been cited by some<br />

Aboriginal leaders as one of <strong>the</strong> main explanations for <strong>the</strong> overwhelming<br />

treaty <strong>and</strong> status Indian rejection of <strong>the</strong> Accord. 79<br />

As noted above, throughout <strong>the</strong> 1991-92 process, NWAC dem<strong>and</strong>ed that <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> be applied fully to Aboriginal governments. <strong>The</strong> concern was that<br />

Aboriginal women’s rights could be breached under self-governing regimes if<br />

<strong>the</strong>y did not have access to a set of fundamental rights enforceable by an<br />

external authority. <strong>The</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> was based on <strong>the</strong> history of discrimination<br />

against Aboriginal women by <strong>the</strong> Indian Act, as well as by <strong>the</strong> B<strong>and</strong> Councils it<br />

spawned. NWAC cited Section 12(1)(b) of <strong>the</strong> Act which, until its repeal in<br />

1985, had stripped Indian women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir children of <strong>the</strong>ir status <strong>and</strong> rights<br />

upon marriage to non-Indian men; <strong>the</strong> provision that made women members of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir husb<strong>and</strong>s’ b<strong>and</strong>s if <strong>the</strong>y differed from <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> which imposed<br />

‘enfranchisement’ on <strong>the</strong>m if <strong>the</strong>ir husb<strong>and</strong>s became enfranchised; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

1869 legislation which imposed <strong>the</strong> B<strong>and</strong> system with a European-style<br />

electoral system which permitted only males to vote. 80 <strong>The</strong>se provisions<br />

amounted to “<strong>the</strong> statutory banishment” 81 of thous<strong>and</strong>s of Aboriginal women<br />

246


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir children from <strong>the</strong>ir cultures. Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> provisions meant<br />

forced assimilation in <strong>the</strong> dominant society.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, NWAC noted that when Jeanette <strong>La</strong>vell challenged s. 12(1)(b) of <strong>the</strong><br />

Indian Act in 1971, thirteen Aboriginal organizations (including <strong>the</strong> NIB <strong>and</strong><br />

various provincial <strong>and</strong> territorial organizations) funded by <strong>the</strong> Departments of<br />

Justice <strong>and</strong> Indian Affairs intervened to uphold <strong>the</strong> sexually discriminatory<br />

section. Finally, when s. 15 of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> made <strong>the</strong> section untenable, <strong>the</strong><br />

male-dominated Aboriginal organizations had opposed <strong>the</strong> introduction of<br />

Bill C-31, which abolished s. 12(1)(b). <strong>The</strong> Aboriginal organizations claimed<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir opposition was not motivated by sexism, but ra<strong>the</strong>r by <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were not provided with extra resources to meet <strong>the</strong> housing <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

material needs of those who would be reinstated. In addition, <strong>the</strong>y feared an<br />

influx of non-Aboriginal men married to Aboriginal women, who might<br />

attempt to gain control of <strong>the</strong>ir communities through <strong>the</strong> B<strong>and</strong> Councils. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

arguments notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing, by 1990, some 14,000 women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir 40,000<br />

children had regained <strong>the</strong>ir status, but only two percent of <strong>the</strong>m have been<br />

allowed to return to <strong>the</strong>ir reserves. 82 In view of this history, NWAC was not<br />

prepared to trust that male-dominated organizations would safeguard gender<br />

equality, especially if constitutional provisions exempted Aboriginal<br />

governments from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. Indeed, although NWAC supported <strong>the</strong> idea of<br />

self-government, it was pointed out that:<br />

Some Aboriginal women have said no to self-government. Some of<br />

our women do not want more power, money <strong>and</strong> control in <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s<br />

of men in our communities. It is asking a great deal to ask us as<br />

women to have confidence in <strong>the</strong> men in power in our communities.<br />

We do not want you to create Aboriginal governments with white<br />

powers <strong>and</strong> white philosophies in our communities. We do not want<br />

<strong>the</strong> western hierarchical power structure which you have given us.<br />

We do not want Chieftain overlords created by <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. 83<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association directly challenged <strong>the</strong> collective rights<br />

canonized by <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal organizations on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong> individual<br />

rights protected by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> are recognized as fundamental human rights in<br />

<strong>the</strong> U.N.’s Universal Declaration. NWAC recognized that <strong>the</strong>re was a clash<br />

between <strong>the</strong> collective rights of sovereign Aboriginal governments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

individual rights of women. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> had to be applied to<br />

<strong>the</strong>m because patriarchal laws of colonial origin had stripped women of <strong>the</strong><br />

equality <strong>the</strong>y had enjoyed in traditional societies, establishing “male privilege<br />

as <strong>the</strong> norm on reserve l<strong>and</strong>s.” 84<br />

<strong>The</strong> Native Women’s Association’s basic objections to <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

package were four-fold. First, NWAC objected to <strong>the</strong> Accord’s provision that<br />

Aboriginal governments were empowered to “safeguard <strong>and</strong> develop <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

languages, cultures, economies, identities, institutions, <strong>and</strong> traditions,” on <strong>the</strong><br />

grounds that it was not clear who would determine <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

elements. <strong>The</strong> gender equality provision in s. 35(4) had not been streng<strong>the</strong>ned<br />

to ensure that it applied explicitly to s. 35(1), so <strong>the</strong>re was potentially no<br />

protection against “discriminatory cultural practices emanating from <strong>the</strong><br />

current patriarchal Indian Act governments.” 85 Secondly, <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

proposed to change <strong>the</strong> wording of democratic rights in Sections 3-5 of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to exempt Aboriginal governments. Although this provision was<br />

ostensibly included in order to prevent non-Aboriginal people from claiming<br />

247


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

<strong>the</strong> right to vote in Aboriginal elections, <strong>the</strong>re was no provision that such<br />

governments would have to hold elections at all. Hence, NWAC argued that<br />

“Aboriginal citizens will have no democratic rights within Aboriginal<br />

communities under self-government.” 86 This might have meant, for example,<br />

that Aboriginal governments could restrict <strong>the</strong> franchise <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights to run<br />

for <strong>and</strong> hold public office to males only.<br />

Thirdly, NWAC opposed <strong>the</strong> extension of s. 33, <strong>the</strong> override clause, to<br />

Aboriginal governments. This would have meant that those governments<br />

could suspend fundamental freedoms (such as freedom of assembly, belief,<br />

expression, <strong>the</strong> press, religion <strong>and</strong> association), legal rights (such as “life,<br />

liberty, <strong>and</strong> security of <strong>the</strong> person,” <strong>and</strong> protection against “unreasonable<br />

search <strong>and</strong> seizure” <strong>and</strong> arbitrary detention <strong>and</strong> imprisonment), as well as s. 15<br />

equality rights. Aboriginal governments’ ability to restrict mobility rights was<br />

especially worrying in view of <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong> Bill C-31 reinstatees, <strong>the</strong><br />

majority of whom have not been allowed to return to <strong>the</strong>ir reserves. In<br />

NWAC’s view, <strong>the</strong>se provisions would have put “awesome power...in <strong>the</strong><br />

h<strong>and</strong>s of Aboriginal patriarchs.” 87 Fourthly, NWAC was concerned that<br />

Aboriginal women would be forbidden to use <strong>the</strong> courts in <strong>the</strong> event of sex<br />

discrimination by Aboriginal governments. Hence, NWAC dem<strong>and</strong>ed not<br />

only that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> apply (<strong>and</strong> that s. 33 not be extended to Aboriginal<br />

governments), but that an unequivocal gender equality clause be included<br />

which was not vulnerable to suspension or subordination to any conflicting<br />

collective rights.<br />

By <strong>and</strong> large, <strong>the</strong> national organizations took <strong>the</strong> position that gender equality<br />

rights would be guaranteed by Sections 15, 28, <strong>and</strong> 35(4) of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. This<br />

position seemed to ignore <strong>the</strong> fact that s. 15 is subject to <strong>the</strong> override. In<br />

addition, <strong>the</strong>re is much uncertainty as to whe<strong>the</strong>r s. 35(4) of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

Act, 1982 only guarantees general Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> treaty rights equally to male<br />

<strong>and</strong> female persons, or whe<strong>the</strong>r it would actually apply to <strong>the</strong> actions taken by<br />

Aboriginal governments once instituted under negotiated agreements.<br />

Basically, <strong>the</strong> NCC took <strong>the</strong> position that “governments o<strong>the</strong>r than our own<br />

can never be trusted to end discrimination,” <strong>and</strong> that:<br />

...<strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> must not be used to suppress our collective titles <strong>and</strong><br />

jurisdictions by imposing non-Aboriginal concepts of property <strong>and</strong><br />

civil rights on us that could extinguish our status as founding peoples<br />

<strong>and</strong> nations...On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, we must protect <strong>and</strong> promote <strong>the</strong><br />

suppressed rights of women...<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs who have suffered so much<br />

under colonial rule <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, we must<br />

never allow European ideas about culture...to suppress <strong>the</strong> reemergence<br />

of our traditional laws <strong>and</strong> governing systems. 88<br />

<strong>The</strong> NCC recommended that, instead of applying <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong> national<br />

Aboriginal organizations “should examine <strong>the</strong> idea of a manifesto of<br />

Aboriginal rights which would address <strong>the</strong> problem of how people would<br />

participate in <strong>the</strong>ir nation.” 89 This proposal brought little comfort to those<br />

concerned about potential incursions on <strong>the</strong> individual civil rights of<br />

Aboriginal people under First Nations governments dominated by men. In<br />

fact, only <strong>the</strong> ITC was willing to have <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> apply, <strong>and</strong> recommended<br />

including in <strong>the</strong> package an explicit “restriction on all governments—federal,<br />

provincial, <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal—preventing <strong>the</strong>m from passing laws or creating or<br />

248


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

recognizing rights in such a way that discriminates between men <strong>and</strong><br />

women.” 90<br />

It was AFN’s position, however, which caused <strong>the</strong> most concern to NWAC.<br />

<strong>The</strong> AFN had included a Women’s Assembly in its parallel process, <strong>and</strong> had<br />

received many submissions from women. However, in <strong>the</strong>ir report, <strong>the</strong> AFN<br />

Commissioners departed from <strong>the</strong>ir practice of recording submissions without<br />

evaluating <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> commented on <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong>y noted <strong>the</strong><br />

women’s argument that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> had been instrumental in forcing <strong>the</strong> repeal<br />

of s. 12(1)(b) <strong>and</strong> was thus required under self-government so that women who<br />

are discriminated against would have legal recourse against <strong>the</strong>ir oppressors.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y <strong>the</strong>n argued against this position, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir comments are worth quoting<br />

at length:<br />

If we may step outside <strong>the</strong> circle for a moment <strong>and</strong> present our own<br />

opinions, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is a well-intentioned document. And <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

absolutely no doubt that women have suffered from appalling<br />

treatment, in <strong>the</strong> past at <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> federal government, in <strong>the</strong><br />

present as victims of rapes, domestic violence <strong>and</strong> discrimination.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is no answer to women’s problems, for three reasons.<br />

First, [it is true that] a woman can go to court to force her council to<br />

award her membership, a house on reserve, <strong>and</strong> similar rights. But <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cannot protect a woman from violence; it cannot force her<br />

leaders to listen to her problems or help her; it cannot get her a job.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problems that <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is designed to overcome are not, on <strong>the</strong><br />

whole, <strong>the</strong> day-to-day problems that Aboriginal women confront. Job<br />

discrimination <strong>and</strong> pay inequity are low priority when <strong>the</strong>re are no<br />

jobs at all.<br />

Second, traditional Aboriginal society has no need of feminism, for<br />

<strong>the</strong> simple reason that women held <strong>the</strong> real power in<br />

it....Gr<strong>and</strong>mo<strong>the</strong>r makes <strong>the</strong> rules; Gr<strong>and</strong>fa<strong>the</strong>r enforces <strong>the</strong>m. If<br />

traditional values are re-established, Aboriginal women will have<br />

more power, more status, more respect than <strong>the</strong>ir feminist white<br />

sisters—who, since <strong>the</strong> passage of Bill C-31, have shown little<br />

interest in Aboriginal women’s problems. But <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> could<br />

easily st<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> way of, or even prevent, <strong>the</strong> re-establishment of<br />

traditional values. Fundamentally, Eurocanadian culture values<br />

individualism; Aboriginal culture values <strong>the</strong> collective. Certainly<br />

individual rights must be protected, <strong>and</strong> past injustice must be ended.<br />

But if <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> individual conflicts with <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> group,<br />

our tradition is clear. <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is not an Aboriginal document.<br />

Third, applying <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> means, in effect, that women would be<br />

asking <strong>the</strong> Canadian government to look after <strong>the</strong>ir interests,<br />

probably through litigation....Not only is litigation a non-Aboriginal<br />

way of solving disputes, but Canadian courts may or may not give<br />

<strong>the</strong>se women what <strong>the</strong>y want. In any event, real membership in <strong>the</strong><br />

community cannot be litigated; it can only be earned, <strong>and</strong> insisting on<br />

“my rights” is nei<strong>the</strong>r an Aboriginal custom nor a good way of<br />

winning a welcome from <strong>the</strong> community. 91<br />

249


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

In view of this statement, it is not difficult to see why NWAC took little<br />

comfort from <strong>the</strong> AFN’s position. Certainly, <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> is not designed to<br />

deal with <strong>the</strong> problems of inadequate resources <strong>and</strong> inter-personal violence to<br />

which <strong>the</strong> Commissioners refer. However, it is designed to deal with equity of<br />

access <strong>and</strong> non-discrimination on <strong>the</strong> basis of gender in <strong>the</strong> provision of<br />

services. Secondly, it is not at all clear that Aboriginal women would have<br />

more power, status <strong>and</strong> respect than “<strong>the</strong>ir feminist white sisters” under<br />

traditional governments. <strong>The</strong> problem here is what is to be defined as<br />

“traditional”? Are “traditional values” those prevalent in Aboriginal societies<br />

prior to contact with Europeans? If so, it must be noted that not all pre-contact<br />

Aboriginal societies were matriarchal or matrilineal. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, equality in<br />

most of those societies meant “equal but different.” 92 In o<strong>the</strong>r words, women<br />

<strong>and</strong> men had different socially constructed roles <strong>and</strong> responsibilities, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

did not cover <strong>the</strong> range of possibilities in modern life. This could mean that<br />

Aboriginal women’s right to engage in certain occupations would be<br />

prescribed by “traditional” roles. Moreover, several hundred years of<br />

European occupation has resulted in cultural cross-fertilization, so that <strong>the</strong><br />

patriarchy imported into Aboriginal communities by church <strong>and</strong> state over <strong>the</strong><br />

centuries since contact may now be considered “traditional” <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

impregnable to gender equality claims.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commissioners’ unequivocal statement that, in <strong>the</strong> event of a conflict<br />

between individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights, <strong>the</strong> latter are to prevail means that, in<br />

effect, Aboriginal women are to have fewer rights of Canadian citizenship than<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir non-Aboriginal counterparts. Instead, Aboriginal women’s rights are to<br />

be defined by <strong>the</strong>ir membership in enclave ethnic governments. Here,<br />

litigation is not to be an available option. <strong>The</strong>refore, once a collective decision<br />

is taken, <strong>the</strong> individual is to have no recourse to external authorities even if <strong>the</strong><br />

decision violates civil rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commissioners’ answer to <strong>the</strong> problem of balancing individual <strong>and</strong><br />

collective rights was “to return to our tradition of respect for women, to heal<br />

<strong>the</strong> sources of <strong>the</strong> violence, <strong>and</strong> to educate <strong>the</strong> men who have adopted white<br />

attitudes towards women.” 93 However, this will be nei<strong>the</strong>r an easy nor a swift<br />

process, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> meantime, gender equality (<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r civil <strong>and</strong> political)<br />

rights are subject to suspension under Aboriginal governments.<br />

As a result of NWAC’s publicity campaign, <strong>the</strong> court challenges, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

support of groups such as <strong>the</strong> National Action Committee on <strong>the</strong> Status of<br />

Women, <strong>the</strong> final legal text of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord was amended to<br />

include <strong>the</strong> kind of guarantee that NWAC had been dem<strong>and</strong>ing. Section 35.7<br />

(replacing <strong>the</strong> old s. 35[4]) provided that “Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

provision of this Act, <strong>the</strong> rights of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal peoples of Canada referred to<br />

in this part are guaranteed equally to male <strong>and</strong> female persons.” Although it<br />

still did not specify that gender equality would apply to <strong>the</strong> legislative actions<br />

of Aboriginal governments, many of <strong>the</strong> provincial native women’s<br />

organizations began to formally endorse <strong>the</strong> Accord after <strong>the</strong> legal text was<br />

released. Thus, s. 35.7 represented a partial victory for NWAC, without whose<br />

efforts it would not have been included.<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord is now an historical artifact, it is possible<br />

that constitutional amendments to recognize <strong>the</strong> inherent right to selfgovernment<br />

will proceed separately. In this event, <strong>the</strong> problems of individual<br />

versus collective rights, <strong>and</strong> particularly gender equality, will resurface.<br />

Meanwhile, <strong>the</strong> tension between collective rights to self-government<br />

250


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

according to Aboriginal customs <strong>and</strong> values <strong>and</strong> individual rights to equal<br />

treatment in modern society has yet to be resolved in Aboriginal political<br />

discourse.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> foregoing discussion has demonstrated that Aboriginal constitutional<br />

discourse has made substantial strides over <strong>the</strong> past decade. Although all <strong>the</strong><br />

elements of <strong>the</strong> discourse examined in this paper were present in <strong>the</strong> early<br />

1980s, <strong>the</strong>y only came to fruition in <strong>the</strong> constitutional reform process which<br />

culminated in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. This was produced by <strong>the</strong> combined<br />

factors of Aboriginal peoples’ increased political influence following <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

pivotal role in derailing <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord in 1990 <strong>and</strong> escalating<br />

militancy in <strong>the</strong> slip-stream of <strong>the</strong> Oka crisis. It was also a result of broader<br />

forces in Canadian society (<strong>and</strong> internationally) which toge<strong>the</strong>r have induced<br />

an expansion of rights conceptions to legitimize notions of collective rights.<br />

<strong>The</strong> renewed Aboriginal constitutional discourse has had a number of farreaching<br />

effects. First, even though <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord floundered,<br />

Aboriginal organizations’ participation in all facets of <strong>the</strong> negotiations has<br />

changed Canadian constitutional discourse irreversibly. Political elites <strong>and</strong> a<br />

large proportion of <strong>the</strong> citizenry have been willing to acknowledge an inherent<br />

right to self-government. This is tantamount to an acceptance of Aboriginal<br />

sovereignty claims (albeit within <strong>the</strong> federation). Secondly, <strong>the</strong> “two nations”<br />

doctrine has been dealt a mortal wound. We can no longer conceive of Canada<br />

as consisting of two founding nations <strong>and</strong> cultures. This is bad news for<br />

Quebec, which has banked on <strong>the</strong> two nations idea as <strong>the</strong> basis of its claims for<br />

distinct society status. Nor can Aboriginal interests be excluded from future<br />

attempts at constitutional reform. Aboriginal organizations are almost<br />

guaranteed representation at future talks. <strong>The</strong>y cannot now be ignored with<br />

impunity.<br />

Thirdly, Aboriginal peoples have succeeded in legitimating <strong>the</strong>ir claims to<br />

collective rights as between <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r governments, though <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have not yet resolved <strong>the</strong> problem of balancing <strong>the</strong>m against individual rights<br />

within Aboriginal communities. <strong>The</strong> challenge posed by <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association exposed a serious weakness in <strong>the</strong> discourse. Although it is<br />

impossible to estimate how many of <strong>the</strong> 56% of Canadians who voted against<br />

<strong>the</strong> package were swayed by NWAC’s <strong>and</strong> NAC’s arguments on gender<br />

equality, <strong>the</strong>y doubtless had some impact. By flagging <strong>the</strong>se issues in public,<br />

NWAC may well have contributed to <strong>the</strong> Accord’s downfall. Hence,<br />

considerable refinement of <strong>the</strong> discourse is required if <strong>the</strong> issues of gender<br />

equality <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights are not to derail future constitutional deals.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> ante has been upped so that <strong>the</strong> inherent collective right <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provisions of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord will become <strong>the</strong> minimal<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s made in <strong>the</strong> next round of bargaining.<br />

It must be noted that <strong>the</strong>re was dissent among Aboriginal peoples over <strong>the</strong><br />

terms of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord, particularly within <strong>the</strong> AFN’s ranks.<br />

Treaty groups were concerned about <strong>the</strong> potential effects on treaty rights,<br />

while non-treaty groups were anxious about <strong>the</strong> “no new l<strong>and</strong>” provision. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> end, on <strong>the</strong> advice of <strong>the</strong> Mohawks, Elijah Harper, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs who felt that<br />

Aboriginal people had not been given enough time to study <strong>the</strong> proposals,<br />

many Aboriginal people boycotted <strong>the</strong> referendum. But <strong>the</strong> most serious<br />

source of dissent were sovereigntist groups such as <strong>the</strong> Mohawks, who argued<br />

251


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y did not need <strong>the</strong>ir rights recognized in <strong>the</strong> constitution of ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

country. 94 We can expect to see this sort of position adopted by many o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

groups in <strong>the</strong> coming years if increased militancy is <strong>the</strong> by-product of<br />

Charlottetown’s ruin.<br />

Now that <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord is dead, Aboriginal leaders such as Ron<br />

George <strong>and</strong> Ovide Mercredi have warned of <strong>the</strong> possibility of more Okas, more<br />

direct action, <strong>and</strong> more activity at <strong>the</strong> international level. <strong>The</strong> point will be to<br />

gain recognition by <strong>the</strong> international community of rights Aboriginal people<br />

have not been able to convert into constitutional trumps at home. Hence we can<br />

probably expect more assertions of sovereignty in <strong>the</strong> international sense by<br />

Canadian Aboriginal groups.<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> referendum, <strong>and</strong> in response to Aboriginal leaders’ profound<br />

disappointment, various non-Aboriginal leaders have suggested that <strong>the</strong> selfgovernment<br />

agenda can proceed separately. However, this is unlikely to<br />

happen in <strong>the</strong> immediate future for three reasons: first, many Aboriginal<br />

people have taken <strong>the</strong> fall of <strong>the</strong> Accord as yet ano<strong>the</strong>r rejection of Aboriginal<br />

people’s legitimate aspirations; second, only a constitutional amendment on<br />

<strong>the</strong> inherent right will do, but it is doubtful whe<strong>the</strong>r Quebec will agree to<br />

constitutional reform for Aboriginal peoples when its own agenda has also<br />

been rejected again; <strong>and</strong> third, even if all <strong>the</strong> provinces were willing to agree to<br />

substantially <strong>the</strong> same package, it is not clear that any major constitutional<br />

reform can now be legitimated without <strong>the</strong> stamp of public approval. If a<br />

referendum solely on Aboriginal rights had to be held, <strong>the</strong> risk would be that<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian public would say “no.” In that event, <strong>the</strong>re could be no doubt that<br />

voters were rejecting <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal package, unbuckled as it would be from<br />

<strong>the</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>r issues in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord which could have<br />

explained its undoing.<br />

In conclusion, <strong>the</strong>refore, although it seems that Aboriginal constitutional<br />

discourse has established a new floor of minimal requirements for<br />

constitutional reform, <strong>the</strong> possibilities of constitutional change will depend on<br />

many factors. <strong>The</strong>se include <strong>the</strong> outcome of <strong>the</strong> next federal election <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

swerve of events in Quebec. Given <strong>the</strong> shifting s<strong>and</strong>s of constitutional<br />

discourse in <strong>the</strong> aftermath of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord, <strong>the</strong> prospects for <strong>the</strong><br />

near future look less than promising. However, it is to be hoped that <strong>the</strong><br />

Aboriginal peoples of <strong>the</strong> nor<strong>the</strong>rn part of North America at least will be<br />

governing <strong>the</strong>mselves well before <strong>the</strong> six hundredth anniversary of Columbus’<br />

arrival. Mercifully, even in Canada, <strong>the</strong> pace of change is not that slow.<br />

Notes<br />

* I would like to thank Daiva Stasiulis <strong>and</strong> Sharon Su<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong>ir thoughtful<br />

commentaries on an earlier draft of this paper. Thanks are also due to <strong>the</strong> anonymous<br />

reviewers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Editorial Board of this journal.<br />

1. Unfortunately, no figures are available for <strong>the</strong> Métis <strong>and</strong> non-status population, since<br />

Elections Canada was only able to collect specific data from reserve-based polling units.<br />

2. In this paper, <strong>the</strong> term “Aboriginal peoples” refers to <strong>the</strong> Indian, Inuit <strong>and</strong> Métis peoples of<br />

Canada. In current usage, <strong>the</strong> term “First Nations” denotes <strong>the</strong> 633 Aboriginal societies<br />

whose members are defined as “Indians” under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. Some 311,000 status Indians<br />

reside on reserves <strong>and</strong> are politically represented at <strong>the</strong> national level by <strong>the</strong> Assembly of<br />

First Nations. Some 36,000 Inuit are represented by <strong>the</strong> Inuit Tapirisat of Canada, while <strong>the</strong><br />

Native Council of Canada claims to represent <strong>the</strong> interests of approximately 750,000 nonstatus<br />

Indians <strong>and</strong> Métis (those who are not registered under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act <strong>and</strong> do not qualify<br />

252


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

for its benefits). <strong>The</strong> Métis National Council represents <strong>the</strong> Métis of <strong>the</strong> Prairie provinces,<br />

who number around 5,000.<br />

3. For an Aboriginal response to <strong>the</strong> “termination” policy, see H. Cardinal, <strong>The</strong> Unjust Society:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Tragedy of Canada’s Indians (M.G. Hurtig, Edmonton, 1969). For an analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

policy <strong>and</strong> its rationales, see S. Weaver, Making Canadian Indian Policy: <strong>the</strong> Hidden<br />

Agenda, 1968-70 (University of Toronto Press, Toronto, 1981).<br />

4. R. Gibbins, “Canadian Indian Policy: <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Trap,” Canadian Journal of Native<br />

Studies, Vol. IV, No. 1, 1984, p. 4.<br />

5. For example, a national Angus Reid poll of 1670 Canadian adults conducted between May<br />

26 <strong>and</strong> June 3, 1992, found “an evident reservoir of public goodwill...towards Aboriginal<br />

peoples.” See Canadians <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Peoples 1992: A Syndicated National Public<br />

Opinion Research Study (Angus Reid Group, 1992) p .9. Sixty percent of Canadians polled<br />

adhered to <strong>the</strong> view, ei<strong>the</strong>r that “Aboriginal peoples in Canada have a ‘historic, existing,<br />

inherent right to self-government,’ or that ‘<strong>the</strong> federal <strong>and</strong> provincial governments should<br />

allow Aboriginal peoples to govern <strong>the</strong>mselves’ (p. 15). Moreover, <strong>the</strong> study concluded that<br />

“residents of Canada are fully twice as likely to support than oppose <strong>the</strong> entrenchment of<br />

Aboriginal self-government in <strong>the</strong> Canadian constitution [65% to 31%]” (p. 16).<br />

6. Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Proposals, (Ottawa, Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada,<br />

1991).<br />

7. Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a Renewed Canada, (Queen’s Printer for Canada,<br />

Ottawa, February 28, 1992).<br />

8. “<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord”, Draft Legal Text, October 9, 1992, p. 37.<br />

9. Ibid., p. 1.<br />

10. Ibid., pp. 37-38.<br />

11. For an analysis of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal self-government provisions of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord,<br />

see R. Jhappan, “Aboriginal Self-Government,” in Canadian Forum, Vol. LXXI, No. 813,<br />

October 1992, pp. 15-16.<br />

12. See J.R. Ponting, “Public Opinion on Aboriginal Peoples’ Issues in Canada,” Canadian<br />

Social Trends, No.11, Winter 1988, p. 9. Ponting’s data suggested that a core of 30% of adult<br />

non-native Canadians was supportive of special constitutional rights for Aboriginal peoples,<br />

though Canadians in general did not know or care much about natives <strong>and</strong> native issues.<br />

13. Canada, Indian Self-Government in Canada: Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Committee on Indian<br />

Self-Government, (<strong>the</strong> Penner Report), (Queen’s Printer, Ottawa, 1983), p. 44.<br />

14. Frances Abele, “Oddly Incongruent Cases: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Prospects of First Nations<br />

<strong>and</strong> Quebec,” (paper presented to <strong>the</strong> Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Political Science Association,<br />

Charlottetown, May 31, 1992), p. 7.<br />

15. To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Commissioners’ Report, (Assembly<br />

of First Nations, Ottawa, 1992), p. 74.<br />

16. Sparrow v. <strong>the</strong> Queen, SCC 20311, May 31st, 1990, at p. 3.<br />

17. Ibid., at p. 4.<br />

18. Ibid.<br />

19. Paul Chartr<strong>and</strong>, “<strong>The</strong> Claims of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal Peoples in Canada: A Challenge to <strong>the</strong> Idea of<br />

Two Founding Nations,” (paper presented to a Conference on <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nation<br />

State, Centre for International Studies, University of Toronto, June 5, 1992), p. 2.<br />

20. Menno Boldt, “Indian Leaders in Canada: Attitudes Towards Equality, Identity, <strong>and</strong><br />

Political Status,” (Ph.D <strong>the</strong>sis, Yale University, New Haven, 1973), p. 10.<br />

21. Dene Declaration, reprinted in full in Mel Watkins, <strong>The</strong> Dene Nation: <strong>the</strong> Colony Within,<br />

(University of Toronto Press, Toronto, 1977), pp. 3-4.<br />

22. <strong>The</strong> Royal Proclamation of 1763 was Canada’s first constitutional document. It was<br />

primarily designed to lay down a policy for treating with Indians, <strong>and</strong> declared that Indian<br />

l<strong>and</strong>s could only be alienated to <strong>the</strong> Crown under specified conditions. It also reserved<br />

unceded territories to <strong>the</strong> exclusive use of <strong>the</strong> Indians.<br />

23. Fred Plain of <strong>the</strong> Nishnawbe-Aski Nation outlined <strong>the</strong> claim to nationhood in international<br />

terms: “<strong>The</strong> criteria for recognition as a nation are as follows: that <strong>the</strong> people have a<br />

permanent population...a defined territory...a government...[<strong>and</strong>] <strong>the</strong> ability to enter into<br />

relations with o<strong>the</strong>r states. We can assure Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> international community that...we<br />

can define ourselves as a nation....<strong>The</strong> Royal Proclamation of 1763 refers to our sovereignty;<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government of Canada approached us as a nation to enter into treaty with <strong>the</strong>m.” See<br />

253


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Fred Plain, “A Treatise on <strong>the</strong> Rights of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal Peoples of <strong>the</strong> Continent of North<br />

America,” in M. Boldt <strong>and</strong> J.A. Long, <strong>The</strong> Quest for Justice, (University of Toronto Press,<br />

Toronto, 1985), p. 31.<br />

24. Chartr<strong>and</strong>, op. cit., p. 21.<br />

25. John E. Moss, “Native Proposals for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform”, Journal of Canadian Studies,<br />

Vol. 15, No. 4, Winter 1980-81, pp. 86-87.<br />

26. Ibid., pp. 87-88.<br />

27. Ibid., p. 87.<br />

28. To <strong>the</strong> Source: <strong>The</strong> First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Commissioners Report, op. cit.,<br />

pp. 13-15.<br />

29. <strong>Constitution</strong>al Position Paper—Inuit in Canada: Striving for Equality, (Inuit Tapirisat of<br />

Canada, Ottawa, February 6, 1992), p. 6.<br />

30. In 1959, <strong>the</strong> Six Nations reserve near Brantford, Ontario, “ceded” from Canada <strong>and</strong> sent a<br />

Declaration of Independence to <strong>the</strong> Queen, <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister, <strong>the</strong> President of <strong>the</strong> United<br />

States <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United Nations. In 1969, <strong>the</strong> Six Nations responded to <strong>the</strong> White Paper, which<br />

proposed to terminate <strong>the</strong> Indian Act <strong>and</strong> special status for Indians, by declaring <strong>the</strong> reserve a<br />

sovereign state.<br />

31. First Ministers Conference on Aboriginal Matters, March 8-9, 1984, unofficial verbatim<br />

transcript, pp. 256-257.<br />

32. Chartr<strong>and</strong>, op. cit., pp. 36-37.<br />

33. Andre Picard, “Mercredi warns of native independence,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, October 22, 1991,<br />

p. A2.<br />

34. To <strong>the</strong> Source: <strong>The</strong> First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Commissioners Report, op. cit.,<br />

pp. 15-16.<br />

35. <strong>Constitution</strong>al Position Paper—Inuit in Canada: Striving for Equality, op. cit., p. 3.<br />

36. <strong>The</strong> First Peoples <strong>Constitution</strong>al Congress: Parallel Process on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Report,<br />

0(Native Council of Canada, Ottawa, June 1992), p. 33.<br />

37. Assembly of First Nations, Native Council of Canada, Metis National Council, Inuit<br />

Committee on National Issues, “Joint Aboriginal Proposal for Self-Government,” First<br />

Ministers’ Conferences on Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters, Ottawa, March 27, 1987,<br />

CICS Document 800-23/030.<br />

38. Quoted in Rudy Platiel, “Inherent sovereignty, unity process linked”, Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail,<br />

October 22, 1991, p. A7.<br />

39. Ibid.<br />

40. Aboriginal peoples’ international lobbying efforts at <strong>the</strong> United Nations, <strong>the</strong> European<br />

Community, <strong>the</strong> Organization of American States <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r bodies are analyzed in R.<br />

Jhappan, “A Global Community?: Supranational Strategies of Canada’s Aboriginal<br />

Peoples,” Journal of Indigenous Studies, Spring 1993, forthcoming.<br />

41. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Chronicles: First Peoples <strong>Constitution</strong>al Congress, March 27-30, 1992,<br />

(Native Council of Canada, Ottawa, 1992), p. 4.<br />

42. Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, <strong>The</strong> Right of Aboriginal Self-Government <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>: A Commentary, (February 13, 1992), p. 23.<br />

43. See Rudy Platiel, “Native rights inherent, panel says,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, February 14, 1992, p.<br />

A5.<br />

44. Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a Renewed Canada, (Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada,<br />

Ottawa, February 28, 1992), p. 29.<br />

45. Chartr<strong>and</strong>, op. cit., p. 33.<br />

46. Statement by <strong>the</strong> NIB, quoted in <strong>The</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity, A Time to Speak: <strong>the</strong><br />

Views of <strong>the</strong> Public, (Ottawa, Supply <strong>and</strong> Services, 1979), p. 30.<br />

47. Inuit in Canada: Striving for Equality, (<strong>Constitution</strong>al Position Paper, Inuit Tapirisat of<br />

Canada, Ottawa, February 6, 1992), p. 3.<br />

48. Russell Roundpoint of Akwesasne, quoted in To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>, Commissioners’ Report, (Assembly of First Nations, Ottawa, 1992), p. 27.<br />

49. Backgrounder: Executive Task Force on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> of Canada, (Native Council of<br />

Canada, January 28, 1992), p. 5.<br />

50. To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, op. cit., p. 74.<br />

51. Ibid., p.4.<br />

254


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

52. Paul Chartr<strong>and</strong>, “<strong>The</strong> Claims of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal Peoples in Canada: A Challenge to <strong>the</strong> Idea of<br />

Two Founding Nations,” (paper presented to a Conference on “<strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nation<br />

State,” Centre for International Studies, University of Toronto, June 5, 1992), p. 24.<br />

53. For example, Moss cites ITC <strong>and</strong> NCC claims that <strong>the</strong>y are not just elements of Canada’s<br />

ethnic minorities, but ra<strong>the</strong>r are “distinct national groups.” See John E. Moss, “Native<br />

Proposals for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform,” Journal of Canadian Studies, Vol. 15, No. 4, Winter<br />

1980-81, p. 86.<br />

54. Jack Aubry, “Mercredi shows consistency in distinct society campaign,” Ottawa Citizen,<br />

February 13, 1992, p. A3.<br />

55. To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, op. cit., pp. 37-38.<br />

56. Quoted in Susan Delacourt, “Natives want own distinct society,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, February<br />

11, 1992, p. A6.<br />

57. Inuit in Canada: Striving for Equality, op. cit., pp. 6-7.<br />

58. <strong>The</strong> First Peoples <strong>Constitution</strong>al Congress: Parallel Process on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Report,<br />

(Native Council of Canada, Ottawa, June 1992), p. 18.<br />

59. Backgrounder: Executive Task Force on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> of Canada, op. cit., p. 5.<br />

60. See Roy MacGregor, “Natives dem<strong>and</strong> meeting: First Nations Chief takes off gloves at<br />

Toronto conference,” Ottawa Citizen, February 10, 1992, pp. A1-A2.<br />

61. Quoted in Rheal Seguin, “Quebec right to self-rule disputed by Mercredi”, <strong>The</strong> Globe <strong>and</strong><br />

Mail, February 12, 1992, p. A4.<br />

62. Ibid.<br />

63. See Joan Bryden, “Quebec urged back to table”, <strong>The</strong> Ottawa Citizen, March 16, 1992, p.A 1.<br />

64. Mary Ellen Turpel, “Aboriginal Peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Interpretive Monopolies,<br />

Cultural Differences,” in R. Devlin, Ed., Canadian Perspectives on Legal <strong>The</strong>ory, (Emond<br />

Montgomery Publications, Toronto, 1991), p. 507<br />

65. Ibid., pp. 517-520, passim.<br />

66. Canada, Department of Indian Affairs <strong>and</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Development, Statement of <strong>the</strong><br />

Government of Canada on Indian Policy, 1969, (Queen’s Printer, Ottawa, 1969), p. 5.<br />

67. See, for example, Andrews v. <strong>La</strong>w Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 SCR 143.<br />

68. Quoted in Turpel, op. cit., p. 524.<br />

69. Ibid.<br />

70. Ibid., pp. 524-525.<br />

71. <strong>The</strong>re is some dispute about this. Gail Stacey-Moore of NWAC claimed that <strong>the</strong> AFN had<br />

decided to set aside $228,000 for a women’s conference as part of <strong>the</strong> parallel process, but<br />

that <strong>the</strong> money was never received <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> conference never held. See NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen,<br />

op. cit., Exhibit F, Affidavit of Gail Stacey-Moore, September 16, 1992, at p. 22.<br />

72. NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen , Federal Court of Appeal, Reasons for Judgement, August 20, 1992, at<br />

p. 4.<br />

73. Ibid., at p. 2.<br />

74. Ibid., at p. 9.<br />

75. Ibid., at p. 15.<br />

76. IN RE <strong>the</strong> Referendum Act: NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen, <strong>the</strong> Right Honourable Brian Mulroney <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Right Honourable Joe Clark, Statement of Claim, Federal Court of Canada, September<br />

15, 1992, at pp. 9-10.<br />

77. “Judge delays attempt by native women to halt referendum,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, September 23,<br />

1992, p. A8.<br />

78. For discussions of <strong>the</strong> consequences of what Chartr<strong>and</strong> has called “outside-naming,” see To<br />

<strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, op. cit., pp. 21, 35, 36, <strong>and</strong> 52; <strong>and</strong><br />

various NCC documents, including Parallel Process on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Report, (NCC,<br />

Ottawa, June 1992), pp. 25-28; Backgrounder: Executive Task Force on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> of<br />

Canada, op. cit., pp. 17-18; Ron George, Becoming Visible: Urban Self-Government in <strong>the</strong><br />

1990’s, (NCC, Ottawa, July 1992); <strong>and</strong> Jill Wherrett <strong>and</strong> Douglas Brown, Self-Government<br />

for Aboriginal Peoples Living in Urban Areas: A Discussion Paper Prepared for <strong>the</strong> Native<br />

Council of Canada, (Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, Queen’s University,<br />

Kingston, April 1992).<br />

79. Ron George, interviewed in Ottawa, February 10, 1993. Treaty Indians <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong> council<br />

leaders were apparently concerned about a fur<strong>the</strong>r influx of non-status Indians to <strong>the</strong> reserves<br />

if <strong>the</strong> latter were granted equal access.<br />

255


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

80. NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen, op. cit., Exhibit F, Affidavit of Gail Stacey-Moore, September 16,<br />

1992, at p. 6. Kathleen Jamieson traces <strong>the</strong> development of gender-biased legislation <strong>and</strong><br />

Aboriginal women’s struggle against it in “Sex Discrimination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Indian Act,” in J.R.<br />

Ponting, Ed., Arduous Journey: Canadian Indians <strong>and</strong> Decolonization, (McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Stewart, Toronto, 1986), pp.112-136.<br />

81. This term was used by Justice <strong>La</strong>skin in a dissenting opinion in <strong>La</strong>vell v. A.G. Canada,<br />

[1974] S.C.R. 1349, at p. 1386.<br />

82. “Memor<strong>and</strong>um to Premiers, Government Leaders of NWT <strong>and</strong> Yukon Re Gender Equality,”<br />

(NWAC, Ottawa, September 14, 1992), p. 2.<br />

83. “Statement on <strong>the</strong> Canada Package,” (NWAC, Ottawa, 1991), pp. 7-8.<br />

84. Ibid., pp. 10-11.<br />

85. Teressa Nahanee, “Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Package: Plain <strong>La</strong>nguage<br />

Version,” (prepared for <strong>the</strong> NWAC Board Meeting, Ottawa, Sept. 12-13, 1992), p. 2.<br />

86. Ibid., p. 4.<br />

87. “Statement on <strong>the</strong> Canada Package,” op. cit., p. 12.<br />

88. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Chronicles, op. cit. p. 5.<br />

89. Parallel Process on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Report, op. cit., p. 41.<br />

90. Discussion Paper on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Draft # 2, (ITC, Ottawa, May 6, 1992), p. 5.<br />

91. To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, op. cit., pp. 62-63.<br />

92. Ibid., p. 59.<br />

93. Ibid., p. 64.<br />

94. Rheal Seguin, “Quebec chiefs suspicious of accord,” Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail, September 26, 1992,<br />

p. A5.<br />

Bibliography<br />

Abele, Frances. “Oddly Incongruent Cases: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Prospects of First Nations <strong>and</strong><br />

Quebec.” Paper presented to <strong>the</strong> Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Political Science Association,<br />

Charlottetown, May 31, 1992.<br />

Angus Reid Group. Canadians <strong>and</strong> Aboriginal Peoples 1992: A Syndicated National Public<br />

Opinion Research Study. Vancouver: 1992.<br />

Assembly of First Nations. To <strong>the</strong> Source: First Nations Circle on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>,<br />

Commissioners’ Report. Ottawa: 1992.<br />

_____Native Council of Canada, Metis National Council, Inuit Committee on National Issues.<br />

“Joint Aboriginal Proposal for Self-Government.” Ottawa: First Ministers’ Conferences on<br />

Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Matters, March 27, 1987, CICS Document 800-23/030.<br />

Boldt, Menno. “Indian Leaders in Canada: Attitudes Towards Equality, Identity, <strong>and</strong> Political<br />

Status.” Ph.D <strong>the</strong>sis. New Haven: Yale University, 1973.<br />

Canada. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord: Draft Legal Text. Ottawa: October 9, 1992.<br />

_____Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Proposals. Ottawa: Supply <strong>and</strong> Services Canada,<br />

1991.<br />

_____Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a Renewed Canada. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer,<br />

February 28, 1992.<br />

_____First Ministers Conference on Aboriginal Matters: unofficial verbatim transcript. Ottawa:<br />

Queen’s Printer, March 8-9, 1984.<br />

_____Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, <strong>The</strong> Right of Aboriginal Self-Government <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>: A Commentary. Ottawa: February 13, 1992.<br />

_____Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee on a Renewed Canada. Ottawa: Supply <strong>and</strong> Services<br />

Canada, February 28, 1992.<br />

_____Indian Self-Government in Canada: Report of <strong>the</strong> Special Committee on Indian Self-<br />

Government, (<strong>the</strong> Penner Report). Ottawa: Queen’s Printer, 1983.<br />

_____<strong>The</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity, A Time to Speak: <strong>the</strong> Views of <strong>the</strong> Public. Ottawa:<br />

Supply <strong>and</strong> Services, 1979.<br />

_____Statement of <strong>the</strong> Government of Canada on Indian Policy, 1969. Ottawa: Queen’s<br />

Printer,1969.<br />

Cardinal, Harold. <strong>The</strong> Unjust Society: <strong>the</strong> Tragedy of Canada’s Indians. Edmonton: M.G.<br />

Hurtig,1969.<br />

Chartr<strong>and</strong>, Paul. “<strong>The</strong> Claims of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal Peoples in Canada: A Challenge to <strong>the</strong> Idea of Two<br />

Founding Nations.” Paper presented to a Conference on <strong>Federalism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nation State,<br />

Centre for International Studies, University of Toronto, June 5, 1992.<br />

Gibbins, Roger. “Canadian Indian Policy: <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Trap.” Canadian Journal of Native<br />

Studies IV, 1, 1984:1-9.<br />

256


Inherency, Three Nations <strong>and</strong> Collective Rights:<br />

<strong>the</strong> Evolution of Aboriginal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Discourse<br />

Inuit Tapirisat of Canada. <strong>Constitution</strong>al Position Paper—Inuit in Canada:<br />

Striving for Equality. Ottawa: February 6, 1992.<br />

Discussion Paper on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, Draft # 2. Ottawa: May 6, 1992.<br />

Jamieson, Kathleen. “Sex Discrimination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Indian Act.” In Arduous Journey: Canadian<br />

Indians <strong>and</strong> Decolonization, pp. 112-136. Edited by J.R. Ponting. Toronto: McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Stewart, 1986.<br />

Jhappan, R. “A Global Community?: Supranational Strategies of Canada’s Aboriginal Peoples.”<br />

Journal of Indigenous Studies. April 1993, forthcoming.<br />

“Aboriginal Self-Government.” Canadian Forum, LXXI, 813, October 1992, pp. 15-16.<br />

Moss, John E. “Native Proposals for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform.” Journal ofCanadian Studies. 15, 4,<br />

Winter 1980-81: 85-92.<br />

Native Council of Canada. Backgrounder: Executive Task Force on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> of Canada.<br />

Ottawa: January 28, 1992.<br />

_____Becoming Visible: Urban Self-Government in <strong>the</strong> 1990’s. By Ron George. Ottawa: July<br />

1992.<br />

_____<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Chronicles: First Peoples <strong>Constitution</strong>al Congress, March 27-30, 1992.<br />

Ottawa: 1992.<br />

_____<strong>The</strong> First Peoples <strong>Constitution</strong>al Congress: Parallel Process on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Report.<br />

Ottawa: June 1992.<br />

Native Women’s Association of Canada. “Memor<strong>and</strong>um to Premiers, Government Leaders of<br />

NWT <strong>and</strong> Yukon Re Gender Equality.” Ottawa: September 14, 1992.<br />

_____“Native Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Package: Plain <strong>La</strong>nguage Version.” Prepared by<br />

Teressa Nahanee for <strong>the</strong> NWAC Board Meeting, Ottawa, Sept. 12-13, 1992.<br />

_____“Statement on <strong>the</strong> Canada Package”. Ottawa: 1991.<br />

Plain, Fred. “A Treatise on <strong>the</strong> Rights of <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal Peoples of <strong>the</strong> Continent of North<br />

America.” In <strong>The</strong> Quest for Justice, pp. 31-40. Edited by M. Boldt <strong>and</strong> J.A. Long. Toronto:<br />

University of Toronto Press, 1985.<br />

Ponting, J.R. “Public Opinion on Aboriginal Peoples’ Issues in Canada.” Canadian Social Trends.<br />

11, Winter 1988: 9-17.<br />

Turpel, Mary Ellen. “Aboriginal Peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>: Interpretive Monopolies,<br />

Cultural Differences.” In Canadian Perspectives on Legal <strong>The</strong>ory, pp. 503-538. Edited by<br />

R. Devlin. Toronto: Emond Montgomery Publications, 1991.<br />

Watkins, Mel. <strong>The</strong> Dene Nation: <strong>the</strong> Colony Within. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977.<br />

Weaver, Sally. Making Canadian Indian Policy: <strong>the</strong> Hidden Agenda, 1968-70. Toronto:<br />

University of Toronto Press,1981.<br />

Wherrett, Jill, <strong>and</strong> Brown, Douglas. “Self-Government for Aboriginal Peoples Living in Urban<br />

Areas: A Discussion Paper Prepared for <strong>the</strong> Native Council of Canada.” Kingston: Institute<br />

of Intergovernmental Relations, Queen’s University, April 1992.<br />

Legal Cases Cited<br />

Andrews v. <strong>La</strong>w Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 SCR 143.<br />

IN RE <strong>the</strong> Referendum Act: NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen, <strong>the</strong> Right Honourable Brian Mulroney <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Right Honourable Joe Clark, Statement of Claim, Federal Court of Canada, September 15,<br />

1992.<br />

<strong>La</strong>vell v. A.G. Canada , [1974] S.C.R. 1349<br />

NWAC v. <strong>the</strong> Queen , Federal Court of Appeal, Reasons for Judgement, August 20, 1992.<br />

Sparrow v. <strong>the</strong> Queen, SCC 20311, May 31st, 1990.<br />

257


Jill Vickers<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement And a<br />

Changing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Order 1<br />

Abstract<br />

In this paper, I examine a decade of women’s constitutional activism focusing<br />

on debates about <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, <strong>the</strong> Boyer Committee on Equality Rights, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown Accords. I provide a typology of a<br />

women’s movement composed of two majoritarian elements (English-<br />

Canadian <strong>and</strong> Quebec francophone) <strong>and</strong> a number of minority elements,<br />

including francophone women outside of Quebec, First Nations women, racial<br />

minority women <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, such as lesbians <strong>and</strong> women with disabilities, who<br />

sought to present distinct constitutional views. <strong>The</strong> paper explores <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional concerns Canadian women had in common <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> different<br />

<strong>and</strong> sometimes conflicting concerns <strong>the</strong>y had because of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

majority/minority cultural locations. In general, I offer tools of gender<br />

analysis to help observers underst<strong>and</strong> women’s new <strong>and</strong> often disruptive <strong>and</strong><br />

surprising entrance into Canadian constitutional politics as women.<br />

Résumé<br />

Axé sur les délibérations concernant la <strong>Charte</strong>, le Comité Boyer sur l’égalité,<br />

l’Accord du lac Meech et l’Accord de Charlottetown, cet article examine les<br />

dix dernières années de militantisme effectué par les femmes eu égard à la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne. Il fournit également une typologie du mouvement<br />

des femmes : deux éléments majoritaires (les Canadiennes anglaises et les<br />

Québécoises francophones) et quelques éléments minoritaires (les<br />

Francophones hors Québec, les femmes des Premières nations, les femmes<br />

provenant des minorités ethniques, les lesbiennes et les h<strong>and</strong>icapées).Les<br />

membres de ces éléments ont essayé de présenter une vision de la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

qui leur étaient propres. L’auteure explore les questions constitutionnelles<br />

qu’ont en commun les Canadiennes ainsi que les questions divergentes voire<br />

contradictoires dues à leur emplacement culturel de majoritaires/<br />

minoritaires.Cet article servira d’outil à une analyse féministe et aidera le<br />

lecteur ou la lectrice à comprendre l’entrée nouvelle, surprenante et, parfois,<br />

perturbatrice des femmes en tant que femmes dans la politique<br />

constitutionnelle canadienne.<br />

In 1993, <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement marks a century of continuous<br />

organization. Yet it is only in <strong>the</strong> past decade that Canadian women, acting<br />

through more than 3,000 groups organized to advance women’s status <strong>and</strong><br />

condition, have engaged in constitutional politics. Initially, many women,<br />

especially in English Canada, approached constitutional politics with<br />

reluctance. That reluctance overcome, women have created a collective<br />

presence in <strong>the</strong> constitutional arena, acknowledged by <strong>the</strong> (mostly male)<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

politicians, academics <strong>and</strong> media gurus who consider constitutional change<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir purview. Progressive women have insisted on <strong>the</strong>ir right to be heard as<br />

women who need autonomous voices in <strong>the</strong> process because women may be<br />

differently affected than men by constitutional change. And yet, women have<br />

not always agreed on <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> constitutional arrangements desired<br />

despite frequent agreement on <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> changes needed to improve<br />

women’s status <strong>and</strong> condition. It is this puzzle I will address in this paper.<br />

This process of women relating to <strong>the</strong> constitutional order as women; as<br />

citizens differentiated from men by <strong>the</strong>ir sex/gender characteristics, is little<br />

understood. In liberal <strong>the</strong>ory, it is assumed that <strong>the</strong> constitutional citizen is an<br />

undifferentiated abstraction. 2 In Canadian practice, <strong>the</strong> constitutional citizen<br />

is characterized by language, religion <strong>and</strong> place of residence. Only with <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms was <strong>the</strong> process begun of recognizing o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

identities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> interests organized around <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

My study of a decade of women’s constitutional activism shows that women<br />

were drawn into constitutional politics because <strong>the</strong>ir “unique reproductive<br />

roles created a significantly different relationship between women <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> state than...between men <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state,” (Vickers, 1992b: 19; Young,<br />

1989, 1990; Pateman; 1988). This led women to create a widely shared agenda<br />

for change. Also widely shared, was a belief in <strong>the</strong> appropriateness of state<br />

action in achieving this agenda (Vickers, 1992a; Vickers, Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle,<br />

1993). Thus, women’s increased involvement in constitutional politics came<br />

partly from an evolving awareness that changes in <strong>the</strong> constitutional order,<br />

including in <strong>the</strong> division of powers, mattered to <strong>the</strong>m as women. Despite <strong>the</strong><br />

shared agenda, however, <strong>and</strong> a common pro-statism, <strong>the</strong> various elements of<br />

<strong>the</strong> women’s movement often have differed sharply on strategic issues such as<br />

which level of government should be charged with achieving particular<br />

changes for women.<br />

In this text, I will not explore in any detail my underlying assumption that<br />

constitutional politics matters to women because <strong>the</strong>y are differently related to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian state than <strong>the</strong>ir menfolk. In this assertion, I follow analyses<br />

offered by Carol Pateman (1986; 1988), Susan Okin (1978; 1986), Linda<br />

<strong>La</strong>nge (1979) <strong>and</strong> Iris Marion Young (1990). As Young notes, however, <strong>the</strong><br />

ideal of impartiality, whe<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> constitutional relationship of citizens to<br />

states or in our <strong>the</strong>ories of justice, denies <strong>the</strong> political significance of difference<br />

(ch. 4). It is not my view, however, that difference always has political or<br />

constitutional implications in some eternal, essential sense, although this is an<br />

issue on which feminists often disagree. <strong>The</strong> historically situated organization<br />

of sex/gender, however, underlies <strong>the</strong> conflict among <strong>the</strong> different parts of <strong>the</strong><br />

women’s movement as <strong>the</strong>y engage in constitutional politics (Vickers, 1993).<br />

While <strong>the</strong> women’s movement is not monolithic, <strong>the</strong>re actually have been few<br />

major differences in <strong>the</strong> agendas for change of its two majoritarian str<strong>and</strong>s, 3<br />

<strong>the</strong> English-Canadian <strong>and</strong> Quebec francophone str<strong>and</strong>s. Issues related to<br />

reproduction, sexuality, health care, childcare, economic well-being <strong>and</strong><br />

participation in decision making have dominated both agendas (Dumont,<br />

1991; 1992; Vickers, Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle, 1993). Minority elements within<br />

<strong>the</strong> movement, including ethnic <strong>and</strong> racial minorities, aboriginal women,<br />

women with disabilities, lesbians <strong>and</strong> immigrant women, however, have<br />

challenged some aspects of <strong>the</strong>se majoritarian agendas. Although <strong>the</strong>se<br />

differences are important (indeed, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> very stuff of “politics as if<br />

262


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

women mattered”), in this text I will focus on <strong>the</strong> differences of strategy <strong>and</strong><br />

philosophy which underlie women’s positions in constitutional politics.<br />

Elements of <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement have differed fundamentally<br />

on <strong>the</strong> relative importance of individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> value<br />

of a centralized or decentralized federal system for <strong>the</strong> achievement of feminist<br />

goals. (Indeed, some Quebec <strong>and</strong> First Nations women reject federalism<br />

completely.) <strong>The</strong>y have also differed about <strong>the</strong> value of a strategy of legal <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional protection. In exploring <strong>the</strong>se positions, I will outline how<br />

women, who are differently situated as part of a majority or minority culture,<br />

for example, could be affected differently by <strong>and</strong>, hence, have different views<br />

on constitutional change than women with whom <strong>the</strong>y shared identical views<br />

on <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> feminist agenda.<br />

In summary, <strong>the</strong>n, my framework involves three basic assumptions:<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> constitutional citizen must be viewed as a sexed <strong>and</strong><br />

gendered citizen, <strong>and</strong> women understood as differently related to<br />

<strong>the</strong> state(s) <strong>the</strong> constitution regulates;<br />

2. Women may differ on <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> changes desired<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y are differently situated, especially as members of<br />

majority or minority cultures;<br />

3. Women who hold identical views on <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong><br />

movement’s agenda for change may none<strong>the</strong>less hold different<br />

philosophical <strong>and</strong> strategic views concerning how <strong>the</strong> agenda<br />

can best be realized. It is this third proposition on which I will<br />

focus in this paper.<br />

In preparing this text, I have based my analysis primarily on <strong>the</strong> feminist<br />

literature about constitutional politics. 4 This literature consists of three parts:<br />

<strong>the</strong> popular feminist press, briefs submitted by women’s groups to committees<br />

<strong>and</strong> commissions <strong>and</strong> writings by feminist lawyers <strong>and</strong> academics. I have also<br />

relied on my own experiences as an observing participant in <strong>the</strong> process. 5 <strong>The</strong><br />

text which follows is divided into three sections: first, I outline <strong>the</strong> two<br />

majoritarian elements of <strong>the</strong> movement <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> racial, ethnic <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

minority elements which operate in relation to <strong>the</strong>m. In <strong>the</strong> second section, I<br />

outline <strong>the</strong> issues which have motivated Canadian women’s constitutional<br />

politics. In <strong>the</strong> third section, I explore <strong>the</strong>se issues as <strong>the</strong>y evolved over <strong>the</strong><br />

decade from <strong>the</strong> patriation crisis to <strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord.<br />

Finally, I offer some conclusions <strong>and</strong> my prognosis for women’s involvement<br />

in constitutional politics in <strong>the</strong> future.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Women’s Movement in Canada — A Brief Overview<br />

<strong>The</strong> typology I will use to characterize <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement does<br />

not rely on <strong>the</strong> usual ideological differences within feminism. Instead, I begin<br />

with <strong>the</strong> proposition that <strong>the</strong>re are two dominant elements—<strong>the</strong> English-<br />

Canadian movement, which relates primarily to <strong>the</strong> federal state, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

largely Francophone movement, which relates primarily to <strong>the</strong> Quebec state.<br />

Each is a majority position in relation to “its” state <strong>and</strong> has more power than <strong>the</strong><br />

minority elements with which it interacts. Majoritarian elements represent<br />

women of cultures which are dominant within <strong>the</strong>ir state, although Quebec<br />

Francophones are in a minority relationship vis-à-vis <strong>the</strong> Anglo-Canadian<br />

element, <strong>and</strong> English- Canadian feminists feel dominated by <strong>the</strong> U.S.<br />

movement, while Francophone feminists in Quebec are more comfortable<br />

with U.S. influences (Vickers, 1991b; Dumont, 1992).<br />

263


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>The</strong> majoritarian movements have similar agendas, although <strong>the</strong>y differ in<br />

organization <strong>and</strong> constitutional strategies. Diane <strong>La</strong>moureux (1990) <strong>and</strong><br />

Sylvia Bashevkin (1985), in strikingly similar analyses, identify in each<br />

movement a fundamental tension between a desire for integration, evidenced<br />

by work within <strong>the</strong> existing system, <strong>and</strong> a desire for autonomy expressed by <strong>the</strong><br />

use of non-traditional tactics in independent movement organizations.<br />

<strong>La</strong>moureux (1990) believes that this tension explains <strong>the</strong> oscillation of Quebec<br />

feminism between modernity (women’s rights) <strong>and</strong> post-modernity (women’s<br />

liberation). Vickers, Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle (1993) similarly identify a number of<br />

forces within English-Canadian movement organizations, such as <strong>the</strong> National<br />

Action Committee on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women (NAC). Micheline de Sève argues<br />

that “<strong>the</strong> history of <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong>and</strong> Quebec women’s movements is<br />

interwoven with complex relationships between equally feminist tendencies,<br />

reflecting <strong>the</strong> diverse <strong>and</strong> composite identities of <strong>the</strong> women’s groups at<br />

various times” (1992: 137).<br />

<strong>The</strong> similarities in <strong>the</strong>se two majoritarian elements continue in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

relationships with <strong>the</strong> minorities with whom <strong>the</strong>y interact. Both, in <strong>the</strong> past,<br />

have “included” some aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir projects but, more recently,<br />

<strong>the</strong> relationships have become more complex as aboriginal women create <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

own movements centred primarily on <strong>the</strong> issues raised by aboriginal selfgovernment.<br />

Immigrant, ethnic <strong>and</strong> racial minority women perceive<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves to have been marginalized by <strong>the</strong> two majoritarian elements, <strong>and</strong><br />

both English-Canadian <strong>and</strong> Quebec feminists have had to respond to <strong>the</strong>se<br />

perceptions (Basseletti <strong>and</strong> Méhu, 1991; Day, 1991). Similarly, lesbian<br />

women <strong>and</strong> women with disabilities, while not part of minority cultures in <strong>the</strong><br />

same sense, have none<strong>the</strong>less experienced marginalization <strong>and</strong> have<br />

expressed constitutional positions <strong>the</strong>y feared would o<strong>the</strong>rwise be<br />

unrepresented.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> purposes of this paper, <strong>the</strong>n, I will characterize <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s<br />

movement as composed of four major elements. <strong>The</strong> first three “elements”—<br />

<strong>the</strong> Anglo-Canadian, <strong>the</strong> Quebec Francophone <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> aboriginal—have<br />

internal dynamics of <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> each could be analyzed as a movement in its<br />

own right. Each also interacts with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, however, especially in <strong>the</strong><br />

context of constitutional politics. <strong>The</strong> fourth “element” is more artificial,<br />

including francophones outside of Quebec, immigrant <strong>and</strong> racial minority<br />

women, lesbians <strong>and</strong> women with disabilities, all characterized by <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

marginalization from <strong>the</strong> dynamics of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r three. Each of <strong>the</strong>se four<br />

“elements” <strong>and</strong> each of <strong>the</strong> groups within <strong>the</strong> fourth element has developed a<br />

conscious identity in relation to <strong>the</strong> constitutional order.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se fragments are reflected in something as simple as when Canadian<br />

women got <strong>the</strong> right to vote. <strong>The</strong> “official” answer is 1918, when white women<br />

got <strong>the</strong> federal franchise. Quebec women might answer 1940, when <strong>the</strong>y won<br />

<strong>the</strong> Quebec franchise after a long struggle. Some racial minority (Asian)<br />

women suffered exclusion along with <strong>the</strong>ir menfolk, <strong>and</strong> aboriginal women<br />

who retained <strong>the</strong>ir government-assigned “status” under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act were<br />

denied <strong>the</strong> vote until 1960, first exercising it in 1961. Hence, Mohawk poet<br />

Lee Maracle declared recently: “So women got <strong>the</strong> vote in 1961 <strong>and</strong> not a<br />

second before. I want every single person to put it that way <strong>and</strong> never again (to)<br />

erase any woman in this country” (1991: 67). This fragmentation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

limited (elite) interaction among <strong>the</strong> different fragments in <strong>the</strong> past led women<br />

to assume <strong>the</strong>ir experiences were common to all. With a decade of involvement<br />

in constitutional politics, however, knowledge of o<strong>the</strong>r women’s experiences<br />

264


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

has grown <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is now greater awareness that <strong>the</strong> relative power of <strong>the</strong><br />

different elements is not <strong>the</strong> same. My accounts of <strong>the</strong>se identities will be<br />

sketchy but should illuminate both <strong>the</strong> movement’s complexity <strong>and</strong> its success<br />

in developing stable movement institutions within which dialogue can occur.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Aboriginal Element<br />

Aboriginal women have experienced <strong>the</strong> most profound oppression both<br />

because of gender <strong>and</strong> because of <strong>the</strong> expropriation, cultural disruption,<br />

racism, poverty <strong>and</strong> marginalization which resulted from conquest <strong>and</strong><br />

colonization. In 1928, shortly after white women received <strong>the</strong> federal franchise,<br />

<strong>the</strong> aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> men called “Indian” by <strong>the</strong> Europeans were denied<br />

<strong>the</strong> right to organize politically (Maracle, 1991: 67).<br />

Aboriginal women’s responses to damage <strong>the</strong>y suffered from colonial <strong>and</strong><br />

post-colonial racism <strong>and</strong> oppression has differed. Patricia Monture-Okanne,<br />

for example, argues:<br />

Aboriginal persons cannot be healed until <strong>the</strong> truth is told about <strong>the</strong><br />

history of this country. Until this is possible, I cannot do <strong>the</strong> womanspecific<br />

healing that is also necessary to my well-being. This is so<br />

because my woman’s identity flows from my racial <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

identity. (1991: 30)<br />

Monture-Okanne’s view is that “rights” 6 for individual women can only result<br />

from securing <strong>the</strong>ir nation’s collective right to self-government (indeed, for<br />

Monture-Okanne, its sovereignty). Only an autonomous nation could develop<br />

an appropriate underst<strong>and</strong>ing of “rights.” O<strong>the</strong>r women seek a balance<br />

between individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights <strong>and</strong> between traditional <strong>and</strong> modern<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ings of “rights.” A third position has been advanced primarily by<br />

women who were denied “Indian rights” under <strong>the</strong> Indian Act. Having<br />

successfully employed <strong>the</strong> power of a constitutional regime protecting<br />

individual “rights” to regain <strong>the</strong>ir Indian “status,” <strong>the</strong>y fear <strong>the</strong> possible effects<br />

of any exemption of First Nations from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Native Women’s<br />

Association of Canada (NWAC), for example, while supporting recognition of<br />

aboriginal people’s inherent right to self-government, also argued for<br />

protecting aboriginal women’s “sexual equality rights” which, it believed,<br />

would not be respected if governments “simply choose to recognize <strong>the</strong><br />

patriarchal forms which now exist in our communities” (Stacey-Moore, 1991:<br />

5). Many aboriginal leaders, however, argue that “to place aboriginal groups<br />

under <strong>the</strong> higher authority of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>...would sabotage <strong>the</strong> fundamental<br />

principle that <strong>the</strong> Aboriginal governments drew <strong>the</strong>ir authority from <strong>the</strong><br />

inherent rights of Aboriginal people” (Hall, 1992: 42).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se positions have not always been easy for <strong>the</strong> majoritarian movements to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>. Anglo-Canadian feminists have been supportive of <strong>the</strong> position<br />

advanced by NWAC with organizations like NAC providing moral <strong>and</strong><br />

tangible support. <strong>The</strong> aboriginal element, however, involves women along a<br />

continuum. While most support some kind of self-government, many also<br />

want some kind of protection for <strong>the</strong>ir rights as women. Francophone women<br />

in Quebec have also been faced with accommodating <strong>the</strong> aboriginal fact. <strong>The</strong><br />

Fédération des femmes du Québec (FFQ)’s 1992 forum “Un Québec féminin<br />

pluriel : pour un projet féministe de société,” included plans for a pluralist,<br />

feminist Quebec which would “respect” First Nations while still asserting <strong>the</strong><br />

rights of <strong>the</strong> Francophone majority in <strong>the</strong> territory of Quebec. <strong>The</strong> FFQ’s<br />

265


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

recognition of aboriginal women as subject to double discrimination, like<br />

NAC’s support for <strong>the</strong> NWAC, however, was not based on an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of<br />

<strong>the</strong> full range of positions among aboriginal women from acceptance of full<br />

integration within a sovereign Quebec to dem<strong>and</strong>s for complete sovereignty.<br />

Aboriginal women, eight of ten of whom are survivors of abusive<br />

relationships, often reject majoritarian feminist “solutions” for <strong>the</strong>se<br />

problems, preferring a community healing approach, which keeps abusers out<br />

of white jails. This difference in philosophy has limited <strong>the</strong> practical<br />

interaction between aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> most majority feminists. In<br />

general, <strong>the</strong> stance of <strong>the</strong> majoritarian movements has been to “integrate”<br />

(incorporate) aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir projects. Many aboriginal women<br />

have resisted this trend, especially in <strong>the</strong> last decade.<br />

As <strong>the</strong> most disadvantaged women in Canada, it is not surprising that <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional views of aboriginal women were rarely unanimous. Aboriginal<br />

women have not enjoyed <strong>the</strong> opportunity or <strong>the</strong> financial support necessary to<br />

build parliamentary umbrella organizations like NAC <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> FFQ within<br />

which a common strategy could have been attempted. Both <strong>the</strong> NWAC <strong>and</strong><br />

Métis women, for example, were denied access as groups of women to <strong>the</strong><br />

federal funding provided to aboriginal associations for preparing <strong>and</strong><br />

presenting constitutional positions <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> constitutional bargaining table.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Federal Court of Appeal ruled on August 20, 1992, that <strong>the</strong> NWAC’s<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> freedom of expression had been violated. <strong>The</strong> court also held that <strong>the</strong><br />

Assembly of First Nations (AFN), <strong>the</strong> Inuit Tapirasat, <strong>the</strong> Métis National<br />

Council <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Native Council of Canada “do not speak for <strong>the</strong> women of <strong>the</strong><br />

First Nations” (Bayevsky, 1992:1). O<strong>the</strong>r aboriginal women, however, did not<br />

agree with this position. <strong>The</strong> President of <strong>the</strong> Metis National Council stated<br />

that Métis women “do not feel that <strong>the</strong> Native Women’s Association (NWAC)<br />

speaks for <strong>the</strong>m,” (Genaille, 1992). Similarly, Rosemarie Kuptana <strong>and</strong> Mary<br />

Simon represented <strong>the</strong> Inuit Tapirasat at <strong>the</strong> bargaining table in <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown “round” of constitutional talks <strong>and</strong> supported <strong>the</strong> Accord,<br />

indicating that <strong>the</strong>re is significant division among aboriginal women both on<br />

how <strong>the</strong>y ought to be represented <strong>and</strong> on matters of constitutional substance.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Quebec Element<br />

In Quebec, <strong>the</strong> largely Francophone movement grew to maturity in symbiosis<br />

with Quebec’s drive to modernization. As Micheline Dumont argues: “<strong>The</strong><br />

truth is that feminism in Quebec was stimulated <strong>and</strong> nurtured by <strong>the</strong> powerful<br />

nationalist movements which swept Quebec between 1963 <strong>and</strong> 1990”<br />

(1992:89). <strong>The</strong> movement’s major institution is <strong>the</strong> FFQ, founded in 1966<br />

(Clio Collective, 1987). <strong>The</strong> FFQ has become more inclusive <strong>and</strong> multi-ethnic<br />

with many more members, although most leftist <strong>and</strong> radical feminist groups<br />

remain outside (Maroney, 1988). In 1987, it included 58 associations <strong>and</strong><br />

45,000 individual members (FFQ, 1987).<br />

Most elements of <strong>the</strong> Quebec movement favour <strong>the</strong> decentralization of <strong>the</strong><br />

federal system; that is, most Quebec feminists, whe<strong>the</strong>r federalists or<br />

separatists, support <strong>the</strong> devolution of more power to Quebec. Ethnic <strong>and</strong> racial<br />

minority women in Quebec along with Anglophone <strong>and</strong> many aboriginal<br />

women, are less accepting of this devolution of power. Most Francophone<br />

feminists are nationalists because <strong>the</strong>y are feminists not in spite of it. <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

feminist “project of <strong>the</strong> state” involves making feminism fully<br />

institutionalized within <strong>the</strong> Quebec state <strong>and</strong> society (Clio Collective, 1987;<br />

266


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

FFQ, 1992). For Dumont, “<strong>the</strong> slogan ‘No women’s liberation without Quebec<br />

liberation. No Quebec liberation without women’s liberation’” is at <strong>the</strong> heart<br />

of Quebec feminism (1992:76). None<strong>the</strong>less, Francophone feminists in<br />

Quebec are divided on how to complete “<strong>the</strong> project of <strong>the</strong> state.” As Ginette<br />

Busque notes, “Canadian women outside of Quebec do not have to choose<br />

between federalism <strong>and</strong> sovereignty, while Quebec women find it difficult to<br />

decide on <strong>the</strong>ir future as women without taking into account <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong><br />

province,” (1991:15). <strong>The</strong> FFQ, however, while remaining neutral in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

sovereignty referendum, now advances a sovereigntist position.<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r federalist or sovereigntist, Francophone feminists trust <strong>the</strong> Quebec<br />

state more than <strong>the</strong> federal state. Writing about women’s groups outside of<br />

Quebec, an FFQ brief in 1987 noted, “<strong>the</strong>se groups are usually much more<br />

distrustful of <strong>the</strong> provincial authorities than we are,” (26). Many in Quebec<br />

believe that “...it is probably easier to initiate changes at <strong>the</strong> provincial level<br />

than at <strong>the</strong> federal level,” (Maillé, 1991:80). Some, like Chantal Maillé,<br />

believe that women are best served by <strong>the</strong> government closest to <strong>the</strong>m having<br />

<strong>the</strong> powers critical to <strong>the</strong>ir lives as women.<br />

Thus, Francophone feminists in Quebec operate as a majoritarian movement<br />

vis-à-vis aboriginal <strong>and</strong> minority women within Quebec society. Claire<br />

Bonenfant argues that continuing as part of Canada would preclude <strong>the</strong><br />

development in Quebec of <strong>the</strong> feminist “projet de société” which could meet<br />

<strong>the</strong> needs of women because of <strong>the</strong> inefficiencies <strong>and</strong> duplication she views as<br />

inherent in Canadian federalism. This rejection of federalism began with<br />

Quebec feminists’ inability get divorce transferred to <strong>the</strong> Quebec jurisdiction<br />

where o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of family law reside (Bonenfant, 1991). This frustration<br />

with <strong>the</strong>ir inability to create a coherent policy on <strong>the</strong> family has marked <strong>the</strong><br />

views of <strong>the</strong> Francophone majority in Quebec from <strong>the</strong> late 1970s to <strong>the</strong><br />

present.<br />

No women in Canada have undergone changes in <strong>the</strong>ir beliefs <strong>and</strong> behaviour<br />

as profound as Francophone women in Quebec since <strong>the</strong> 1960s, making<br />

Quebec society Canada’s most progressive jurisdiction on many issues<br />

(Lipset, 1990). Not all Francophone feminists in Quebec, however, fully share<br />

this view of Quebec as a jurisdiction so advanced as to gain nothing from, for<br />

example, an entrenched federal <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms. In a<br />

September, 1987 brief, apparently written in reaction to accusations made<br />

against “les féministes anglophones” by well-known Québécois feminist<br />

Lysianne Gagnon, <strong>the</strong> Réseau d’Action et d’Information pour les Femmes<br />

(RAIF) argued that Quebec feminists should have joined with <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

Anglophone colleagues seeking to streng<strong>the</strong>n gender equality in <strong>the</strong> context of<br />

a constitutional recognition of Quebec as a “distinct society.” In fact, RAIF<br />

believed that, from 1981 on, Quebec feminists should have joined <strong>the</strong><br />

campaign to gain <strong>the</strong> best possible legal protection from a dual jurisdictional<br />

constitution. <strong>The</strong> RAIF brief identified a number of areas in which RAIF<br />

believed Quebec law was severely lacking in terms of women’s rights,<br />

especially in economic areas. RAIF expressed fear that a clash of loyalties<br />

could weaken or subordinate women’s rights under a distinct society regime<br />

by elevating collective over individual rights (RAIF, 1987).<br />

Anglophone feminists have had mixed views about <strong>the</strong> “projet de société.”<br />

Historically, left-wing feminists in English Canada tended to sympathize with<br />

Quebec’s desire for self-determination. More recently, especially since<br />

Quebec’s embracing of Mulroney conservatism <strong>and</strong> free trade, this support has<br />

267


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

weakened. None<strong>the</strong>less, current support in NAC, for example, for a “three<br />

nations” position reflects a growing awareness of <strong>the</strong> position put by<br />

Micheline de Sève that national identity ra<strong>the</strong>r than always hostile to feminism<br />

is “a potential tool for creating adequate space of all kinds of individual <strong>and</strong><br />

group self-awareness,” (1992:135).<br />

<strong>The</strong> Anglo-Canadian Element<br />

<strong>The</strong> Anglo-Canadian movement has a history of continuous organization since<br />

1892, with <strong>the</strong> many organizations founded during <strong>the</strong> early period of<br />

mobilization being revitalized by <strong>the</strong> cross-country hearing of <strong>the</strong> Royal<br />

Commission on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women (Begin, 1992) so that most came to<br />

support feminist causes. Hence <strong>the</strong> older women’s organizations, which<br />

played a key role in establishing <strong>the</strong> Canadian welfare state (Andrew, 1984),<br />

were not alienated from <strong>the</strong> movement as it was reshaped by <strong>the</strong> women’s<br />

liberation movement <strong>and</strong> by left feminism. Consequently, in English Canada,<br />

ideologically diverse groups, instead of being organized into separate<br />

“wings,” share institutions such as NAC <strong>and</strong> co-operate in alliances to achieve<br />

common goals (Vickers, Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle, 1993).<br />

Anglo-Canadian feminists have been deeply distrustful of <strong>the</strong>ir provincial<br />

governments, looking instead to <strong>the</strong> federal government. Albertan Ann<br />

McLellan argues that many women “have viewed provincial governments as<br />

less tolerant <strong>and</strong> receptive to <strong>the</strong>ir claims for equality than <strong>the</strong> national<br />

government” (1991:10). By contrast to Chantal Maillé’s logic, McLellan<br />

argues for <strong>the</strong> greater practicality <strong>and</strong> efficiency in women’s groups directing<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir lobbying to one (federal) government instead of ten (provincial) ones,<br />

concluding that “once <strong>the</strong> federal government is convinced of <strong>the</strong> need of a<br />

program or initiative, it can ensure its availability on a national basis,”<br />

(1991:10).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se conclusions reflect <strong>the</strong> quite different experiences of <strong>the</strong> two<br />

movements. <strong>The</strong> Quebec movement, made optimistic by two decades of<br />

substantial progress for women under different Quebec governments, has<br />

experienced frustrations with federal governments which <strong>the</strong>y see as less<br />

progressive <strong>and</strong> inclined to intervene in Quebec in ways harmful to women. 7<br />

Anglo-Canadian feminists are part of a movement which has been a client of<br />

<strong>and</strong>, until recently, significantly funded by <strong>the</strong> federal government. Shelagh<br />

Day, currently Chair of <strong>the</strong> NAC constitution committee reveals <strong>the</strong> roots of<br />

this pro-federalism when she argues “...as a woman from B.C., a province<br />

which has suffered government by car dealer for all but four of <strong>the</strong> past forty<br />

years...I fear...powers being devolved to my province,” (1991:98). Moreover,<br />

some recent research suggests that in most of English Canada (Alberta is an<br />

exception) regionalism, that is political loyalty to a province or region, is more<br />

characteristic of men than of women in contemporary Canada at least on issues<br />

such as free trade (O’Neill, 1992; Gidengil, 1992). Indeed, gender would<br />

appear to be a more salient political force among Anglophone women who can<br />

reach a “national” approach on major issues more easily than Anglophone men<br />

for whom regionalism is a more potent force. <strong>The</strong> English-Canadian<br />

movement, <strong>the</strong>n, is composed of women who often see <strong>the</strong>ir views as Canadian<br />

views to be defined in opposition to male-stream views or U.S. views. It is also<br />

clearly a majoritarian element vis-à-vis minority <strong>and</strong> marginalized women.<br />

268


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

<strong>The</strong> Fourth Element: Minorities <strong>and</strong> Marginalized Voices<br />

Until <strong>the</strong> 1980s, <strong>the</strong> Canadian movement was largely bi-national in character<br />

with <strong>the</strong> two majoritarian movements dominating <strong>the</strong> agenda <strong>and</strong> debate (De<br />

Sève, 1992:111). In <strong>the</strong> past decade, this dominance was challenged by waves<br />

of women marginalized because of race, ethnic minority status, disability or<br />

sexual orientation. Because racial <strong>and</strong> immigrant minority communities have<br />

often chosen to operate in English, <strong>the</strong>se pressures have been especially<br />

evident in NAC (Vickers, Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle, 1993). None<strong>the</strong>less, as <strong>the</strong> FFQ<br />

became increasingly multi-ethnic, it also experienced <strong>the</strong>se pressures<br />

(Basseletti <strong>and</strong> Méhu, 1991; FFQ, 1991; 1992).<br />

<strong>The</strong> women who make up what I have called <strong>the</strong> “fourth element” have created<br />

networks of <strong>the</strong>ir organizations through which <strong>the</strong>y advocate for change. <strong>The</strong><br />

struggle for <strong>the</strong> institutions of <strong>the</strong> two majoritarian movements has been to<br />

“become a voice for all women...(so) that we articulate <strong>the</strong> many issues of<br />

women, not only those of white middle-class women” so as to foster “<strong>the</strong><br />

politics of inclusion,” (Day, 1991:96). A genuine acceptance of difference,<br />

however, may challenge what were previously thought of as “bottom-line”<br />

feminist positions, as when women with disabilities challenge <strong>the</strong> view that a<br />

fetus which will result in a child with a disability ought routinely to be aborted.<br />

Canadian feminists have insisted that equality between men <strong>and</strong> women does<br />

not necessarily result from same treatment (Vickers, 1984). Using this<br />

principle, as a way of underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>and</strong> views of minority <strong>and</strong><br />

marginalized women has not always been so easy.<br />

In NAC, women representing groups of minority <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise marginalized<br />

women now constitute almost half of <strong>the</strong> executive <strong>and</strong> hold several major<br />

leadership positions representing a major change over <strong>the</strong> past decade. This<br />

has resulted in NAC policies being more supportive of positions advanced by<br />

minority <strong>and</strong> marginalized women. In particular, women in this category have<br />

tended to feel especially dependent on <strong>the</strong> protection of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government’s provision of programs of support. While minority <strong>and</strong><br />

marginalized women tend to share <strong>the</strong>se constitutional positions, none<strong>the</strong>less,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are important differences among <strong>the</strong>m. In Quebec, some minority<br />

women have integrated <strong>the</strong>ir concerns into <strong>the</strong> “projet de société” <strong>and</strong>, indeed,<br />

Quebec explicitly protects <strong>the</strong> rights of gays <strong>and</strong> lesbians at a much higher<br />

level than <strong>the</strong> federal <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>.<br />

Francophone women outside of Quebec represented by <strong>the</strong> Fédération<br />

nationale des femmes canadiennes-françaises (FNFCF), have had a unique<br />

perspective on <strong>the</strong> issues raised in a decade of constitutional debate <strong>and</strong><br />

bargaining. Founded in 1914, <strong>the</strong> Fédération includes forty women’s groups<br />

<strong>and</strong> is a member of NAC. In a 1990 brief, <strong>the</strong> FNFCF, while not taking a st<strong>and</strong><br />

on <strong>the</strong> possibility of independence for Quebec, stressed its members’ desire to<br />

weave alliances, especially with Quebec women’s groups. In a 1992 brief,<br />

while supporting NAC’s constitutional positions, <strong>the</strong> FNFCF expressed its<br />

own ten principles regarding constitutional renewal. It stressed such things as<br />

linguistic duality in Canada <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Senate, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> protection (with no override)<br />

of <strong>the</strong> rights of minority linguistic communities. In general, it supported a<br />

vision of an asymmetrical federation supporting <strong>the</strong> transfer of many powers to<br />

Quebec but not to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provinces. In this, it influenced NAC’s<br />

development of <strong>the</strong> asymmetrical federalism position.<br />

269


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Issues in Common <strong>and</strong> Issues in Conflict: What Makes <strong>the</strong> Women’s<br />

Movement “Tick” <strong>Constitution</strong>ally?<br />

A common thread in all feminist commentary is a profound sense of exclusion<br />

from <strong>the</strong> process of constitution-making. Until 1992, when Inuit Tapirasat<br />

leaders Rosemarie Kuptana <strong>and</strong> Mary Simon, <strong>and</strong> Northwest Territories<br />

government leader Nellie Cournoyea took <strong>the</strong>ir hard-won places at <strong>the</strong> First<br />

Ministers’ bargaining table, Ginette Busque’s declaration that “our country<br />

has had many ‘fa<strong>the</strong>rs’ but no ‘mo<strong>the</strong>rs,’” (Busque, 1991:13) held true.<br />

Intellectually, most feminists still feel it is true. At least half of Canada’s<br />

population, women have been forced to lobby from outside <strong>the</strong> process,<br />

described as a “special interest” by <strong>the</strong> constitutional gurus <strong>and</strong> media alike.<br />

Distrustful of political parties, many have no great trust in women of <strong>the</strong><br />

political class.<br />

In my survey of feminist writings on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, I identified four basic<br />

sets of issues:<br />

(1) <strong>the</strong> process of constitution making;<br />

(2) federal/provincial powers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue of decentralization/<br />

sovereignty;<br />

(3) women’s representation in political institutions;<br />

(4) <strong>the</strong> entrenchment of legal rights in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

legal approach to equality-seeking it entails.<br />

Women tended to advance common positions on <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional process <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> issue of women’s representation. By<br />

contrast, <strong>the</strong>re were significant differences expressed on <strong>the</strong> issues of<br />

federalism <strong>and</strong> decentralization <strong>and</strong> on a legal approach to equality-seeking. In<br />

this text, I will pay ra<strong>the</strong>r more attention to <strong>the</strong> three substantive issues dealing<br />

only briefly with <strong>the</strong> matter of process. 8<br />

<strong>Federalism</strong>, <strong>the</strong> Division of Powers <strong>and</strong> Decentralization<br />

Women’s original interest in constitutional matters stemmed from questions<br />

concerning <strong>the</strong> division of powers. Quebec women supported <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

government’s request to have divorce transferred to <strong>the</strong> provincial jurisdiction<br />

to permit an integrated approach to family law. 9 English-Canadian women<br />

mobilized in opposition when <strong>the</strong> federal government proposed to transfer <strong>the</strong><br />

regulation of divorce to <strong>the</strong> provinces in 1978.<br />

Throughout <strong>the</strong> decade, this divide is evident with Quebec women supporting<br />

greater decentralization (many of <strong>the</strong>ir groups favour sovereignty) while<br />

English-Canadian <strong>and</strong> most minority women support <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

spending power <strong>and</strong> shared jurisdictions to achieve a greater st<strong>and</strong>ardization<br />

of programs across Canada. Given that <strong>the</strong>re is little difference in terms of <strong>the</strong><br />

substance of <strong>the</strong>ir agendas, why do <strong>the</strong>y disagree about how <strong>the</strong>se goals should<br />

be achieved?<br />

<strong>The</strong> divorce issue illustrates one reason for <strong>the</strong> difference quite clearly, <strong>and</strong><br />

shows <strong>the</strong> kind of analysis we must develop to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. To<br />

women outside of Quebec, transferring responsibility for divorce to <strong>the</strong><br />

provinces would have created a patchwork quilt with different grounds <strong>and</strong><br />

waiting periods from province to province. For Francophone feminists this<br />

does not cause concern if <strong>the</strong>y anticipate living all of <strong>the</strong>ir lives in Quebec.<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r women, however, face <strong>the</strong> possibility of being moved from province to<br />

270


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

province while married <strong>and</strong> of being marooned in a province without a divorce<br />

law or with one which is not helpful to women. 10<br />

This central difference reflects <strong>the</strong> fact that English-Canadian <strong>and</strong> minority<br />

women feel <strong>the</strong>y must be concerned with conditions anywhere in Canada<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y may find <strong>the</strong>mselves living <strong>the</strong>re. Quebec women, who must<br />

accept less physical mobility if <strong>the</strong>y wish to live in French, wish to get <strong>the</strong> best<br />

possible system <strong>the</strong>re (Vickers, 1991a; Dumont, 1991). Ann McLellan has<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong> inclusion of an enforceable social charter would make women<br />

outside of Quebec less fearful of decentralization, provided <strong>the</strong>y could use it to<br />

ensure some comparability of benefits, legal conditions <strong>and</strong> support programs<br />

wherever <strong>the</strong>y might end up living (McLellan, 1991:11). This point of view is<br />

also apparent in <strong>the</strong> FNFCF analysis (1992).<br />

This analysis points to women’s recognition that at this point in our history<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are more likely to be dependent on <strong>the</strong> state than men for programs of<br />

support. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> FNFCF brief argued this explicitly (1992:18-19).<br />

Canadian women, however, also have been concerned with <strong>the</strong> obstacles that<br />

<strong>the</strong> division of powers has put in <strong>the</strong> way of women’s political objectives such<br />

as <strong>the</strong> “federalism foxtrot” in which governments compete in not invading one<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r’s jurisdiction by not doing what women need or want all <strong>the</strong> while<br />

saying “my h<strong>and</strong>s are tied.” English-Canadian <strong>and</strong> most minority women,<br />

while frustrated by <strong>the</strong> “federalism foxtrot,” none<strong>the</strong>less see shared<br />

jurisdictions as providing leverage for federal influence on reluctant provinces<br />

in achieving desired goals. By contrast, Quebec feminists see “une<br />

irresponsabilité partagée” (<strong>La</strong>moureux, 1991:60) as something to be<br />

eliminated (FFQ, 1990; 1992; Bonenfant, 1991).<br />

<strong>The</strong> debate about federalism has not yet developed a philosophical dimension<br />

among feminists. <strong>The</strong> position of Lord Acton (which is associated in Canada<br />

with P.E. Trudeau) that concentrated power permits <strong>the</strong> abuse of power more<br />

easily than a federal system in which power is deliberately divided, is not<br />

advanced or refuted by feminists of any ethnicity or ideology. Philosophically,<br />

Francophone feminists in Quebec appear to favour <strong>the</strong> concentration of all (or<br />

most) powers in Quebec to allow for greater participation by women in<br />

decentralizing decision making, for example, to <strong>the</strong> local state (FFQ, 1992:<br />

Fiche 9, e.g.; Begin, Marine, 1991; Dumont, 1991; <strong>La</strong>joie; 1991; <strong>La</strong>moureux,<br />

1991).<br />

Most Francophone feminists believe <strong>the</strong> success of <strong>the</strong>ir agenda in Quebec has<br />

depended on <strong>the</strong> decentralization of powers in areas where this has been<br />

possible. Chantal Maillé concludes, for example, that “...it has been possible<br />

for <strong>the</strong> women’s health movement to obtain positive results...because <strong>the</strong><br />

claims were negotiated with a provincial government which had already<br />

negotiated a maximum amount of autonomy in <strong>the</strong> definition of policies <strong>and</strong><br />

programs,” (1991:79). While <strong>the</strong> decentralized <strong>and</strong> non-bureaucratic<br />

administration of programs is consistent with women-centred philosophies,<br />

most Anglophone <strong>and</strong> most minority women believe “national st<strong>and</strong>ards” <strong>and</strong><br />

coast-to-coast programs are also important to <strong>the</strong>ir well-being.<br />

Representation in Political Institutions<br />

Within <strong>the</strong> movement, <strong>the</strong>re is wide agreement with <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> more<br />

equitable representation for women in Canada’s political institutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

reform of its electoral system. In 1981, Mary O’Brien argued that <strong>the</strong><br />

movement should dem<strong>and</strong> proportional representation “to erode <strong>the</strong><br />

271


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

monolithic substance of <strong>the</strong> state” (O’Brien, 1981:7). 11 <strong>The</strong> movement seeks<br />

equitable political representation 12 <strong>and</strong> has identified <strong>the</strong> structural barriers<br />

which inhibit this. Quebec women have also recognized <strong>the</strong>ir exclusion as<br />

women. Ginette Busque notes, for example:<br />

...women exerted pressure to be represented as a group on <strong>the</strong><br />

Bélanger-Campeau Commission...which was not granted. <strong>The</strong>y were<br />

told that ‘women’ had already been named...[but] [n]o significance<br />

was attached to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se women had no m<strong>and</strong>ate to represent<br />

<strong>the</strong> interests of women. (1991:13)<br />

She concludes, “this probably denotes a fundamental refusal to believe that<br />

women, as a group, have special interests” (1991:13) or that most men believe<br />

women’s interests can be represented by male leaders or that any woman can<br />

“represent” <strong>the</strong> interests <strong>and</strong> views of all women. 13<br />

Aboriginal women agreed that women should be equitably represented. But<br />

<strong>the</strong>y differed significantly among <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> majoritarian<br />

movements concerning what that meant. In 1992, Wendy Moss, lead<br />

constitutional advisor to <strong>the</strong> Inuit Tapirasat, wrote: “if one of <strong>the</strong> goals of <strong>the</strong><br />

organized struggle of women is to ensure that women participate in<br />

governments <strong>and</strong> have a real voice, why have NAC <strong>and</strong> NWAC so discounted<br />

<strong>the</strong> role <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> voice of <strong>the</strong> aboriginal women who were at <strong>the</strong> table on behalf<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Inuit nation, namely, Mary Simon <strong>and</strong> Rosemarie Kuptana?” (2).<br />

NWAC, denied a seat at <strong>the</strong> constitutional “table” in 1992 on <strong>the</strong> grounds that<br />

<strong>the</strong> male-led organizations could represent <strong>the</strong>m, could not accept assurances<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir concerns were being represented by Kuptana <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs at <strong>the</strong> table.<br />

Sharon McIvor of NWAC argued “We want a seat at <strong>the</strong> table <strong>and</strong> recognition<br />

as a separate group...” (Hill, 1992:3). One court eventually established<br />

NWAC’s right but only after <strong>the</strong> event. NAC’s dem<strong>and</strong> for a constituent<br />

assembly <strong>and</strong> its support for <strong>the</strong> NWAC position reflects <strong>the</strong> view that women<br />

need to articulate <strong>the</strong>ir diverse constitutional views directly <strong>and</strong> not through<br />

<strong>the</strong> voices of men or of women of o<strong>the</strong>r nations. Of course, this also reflects<br />

NAC’s view that it should have been “at <strong>the</strong> table” (presumably along with <strong>the</strong><br />

FFQ) to represent majoritarian women’s specific interests, as women.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Entrenchment of Rights <strong>and</strong> Equality-Seeking as a Legal Enterprise<br />

<strong>The</strong> majoritarian women’s movements in Canada have tended to see equalityseeking<br />

as a sociopolitical <strong>and</strong> economic process (Vickers, 1986). Pursuing<br />

legal equality goals, <strong>the</strong>refore, was controversial. As Chaviva Hosek notes,<br />

“...<strong>the</strong> drive for legal rights did not spring spontaneously from within <strong>the</strong><br />

women’s movement. Ra<strong>the</strong>r it developed in response to <strong>the</strong> determination of<br />

<strong>the</strong> federal government to entrench a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms during<br />

<strong>the</strong> patriation process,” (1983:283). If <strong>the</strong>re was to be a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, most feminists<br />

agreed it must not become an obstacle to <strong>the</strong> broader, substantive equalityseeking<br />

process. <strong>The</strong> legal strategy created a cadre of prominent feminist<br />

lawyers. Over <strong>the</strong> decade, <strong>the</strong>y have played a central role in educating<br />

Canadian women about legal <strong>and</strong> constitutional matters affecting women’s<br />

rights. Through <strong>the</strong> work of organizations like <strong>the</strong> Legal, Education <strong>and</strong> Action<br />

Fund (LEAF), most Anglophone <strong>and</strong> minority feminists came to see some<br />

value in <strong>the</strong> legal option.<br />

Despite this pragmatic acceptance of <strong>the</strong> legal equality project, o<strong>the</strong>rs opposed<br />

<strong>the</strong> enterprise. Most Francophone feminists in Quebec were hostile because of<br />

272


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

<strong>the</strong> overall alienation of Quebec from <strong>the</strong> patriation process. <strong>The</strong>y also<br />

believed that <strong>the</strong> Quebec “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” passed in 1976, while not entrenched,<br />

made <strong>the</strong> protection offered by <strong>the</strong> federal <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> unnecessary. RAIF later<br />

disagreed, arguing that, in <strong>the</strong> case of human rights, too much protection is<br />

better than not enough (1987). Few Anglophone feminists even comprehended<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir Quebec Francophone sisters were absent from <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

debates or why. Francophones from outside Quebec were present <strong>and</strong> most<br />

supported <strong>the</strong> Anglophone position on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. To this day, many<br />

Anglophone feminists believe <strong>the</strong> struggle for women’s <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights is a<br />

great victory in which all feminists share equal pride.<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r philosophical positions are expressed in opposition to <strong>the</strong> legal approach<br />

to equality. As labour lawyer Sheila Greckol has argued: “I do not believe in<br />

<strong>the</strong> legal system <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> law as a vehicle for achieving social justice for<br />

women,” (1991:103). Similar, Donna Greschner argues that “constitutional<br />

politics...historically have submerged <strong>the</strong> concerns <strong>and</strong> experiences of<br />

women,” (1991:55). Sherene Razack, speaking from <strong>the</strong> perspective of<br />

minority women, argues that <strong>the</strong> very nature of <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> legal system<br />

“tended to characterize femaleness in ways that reflect <strong>the</strong> experiences of...<strong>the</strong><br />

kind of women likely to be working in law—a white middle-class woman,”<br />

(1991:39). Megan Ellis concluded that <strong>the</strong> judiciary is not capable of acting to<br />

advance substantive equality for women because of its use of gender-neutral<br />

terms like sexual assault which harm women by hiding <strong>the</strong> fundamentally<br />

gendered nature of sexual violence (1986:17). Finally, many grass-roots<br />

feminists are resentful of <strong>the</strong> extent to which pursuit of <strong>the</strong> legal strategy has<br />

involved <strong>the</strong> dominance of movement strategy by lawyers <strong>and</strong> academics <strong>and</strong><br />

siphoned off money previously available for services. <strong>The</strong> government<br />

strategy of incorporating women’s equality-seeking under <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

threatened <strong>the</strong> stability of coalitions within <strong>and</strong> between movement<br />

organizations. Although <strong>the</strong> movement has largely recovered from those<br />

conflicts, <strong>the</strong> problems raised by <strong>the</strong> legal equality approach continue to<br />

threaten its effectiveness.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Politics<br />

Historically, Canadian constitutional politics have been so dominated by <strong>the</strong><br />

issues of dualism <strong>and</strong> regionalism that, “...<strong>the</strong> concerns of women...[were]<br />

simply not visible against <strong>the</strong> two parameters of Canadian cleavage...” (Ayim,<br />

1980:218). Given this constitutional invisibility <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> reluctance of English-<br />

Canadian feminists to enter into constitutional politics, how did movement<br />

leaders find a point of entry around which <strong>the</strong>y could mobilize support? 14<br />

Once Prime Minister Trudeau proposed to patriate <strong>the</strong> BNA Act along with a<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms, <strong>the</strong> mobilizing event for English-Canadian<br />

women was <strong>the</strong> resignation of Doris Anderson, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> President of <strong>the</strong><br />

government-appointed Canadian Advisory Council on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women<br />

(CACSW), in January 1981, charging that government interference had<br />

resulted in <strong>the</strong> cancellation of a Women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conference. <strong>The</strong><br />

timing was crucial; <strong>the</strong> Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> House<br />

was still deliberating but <strong>the</strong> government had brought a revised <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> into <strong>the</strong><br />

House. A later conference would not do. <strong>The</strong> Council, moreover, like most<br />

autonomous women’s groups, was critical of <strong>the</strong> equality guarantees in <strong>the</strong><br />

proposed <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> (Hosek, 1983:288). Anderson’s resignation meant that:<br />

273


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>The</strong> women’s movement suddenly had a heroine, a villain <strong>and</strong> an<br />

event, all of which symbolized its exclusion from <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

process. <strong>The</strong> media had a field day. <strong>The</strong> complex issues involved<br />

were reduced to a dramatic fight between a woman <strong>and</strong> a man (Lloyd<br />

Axworthy, <strong>the</strong> minister responsible for <strong>the</strong> status of women).<br />

(Hosek, 1983:289)<br />

Not all feminists, however, rallied round. A majority of <strong>the</strong> executive <strong>and</strong><br />

council of <strong>the</strong> CACSW declined to support Anderson <strong>and</strong> endorsed cancelling<br />

<strong>the</strong> conference. NAC was “sidelined” by internal conflict, part of which was<br />

resistance by left-wing members of <strong>the</strong> executive to a legal strategy (Vickers,<br />

Rankin <strong>and</strong> Appelle, 1993). Progressive Conservative feminists resisted<br />

unilateral patriation <strong>and</strong> were also divided on <strong>the</strong> value of an entrenched<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>. As late as <strong>the</strong> fall of 1981, Saskatchewan women’s groups opposed<br />

entrenching <strong>the</strong> sex equality guarantee (Section 28) as did <strong>the</strong> Saskatchewan<br />

NDP government on <strong>the</strong> grounds that, by shifting decisions about equality to<br />

<strong>the</strong> courts, progressive governments would be limited in advancing women’s<br />

equality (Hosek, 1983:289).<br />

<strong>The</strong> briefs presented to <strong>the</strong> Joint Committee, show that women wanted any<br />

constitutional guarantees of equality for women to go beyond equality in <strong>the</strong><br />

administration of justice to equal benefit <strong>and</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> law. <strong>The</strong>y also<br />

wanted sexual orientation, marital status <strong>and</strong> political beliefs added to <strong>the</strong><br />

grounds on which discrimination would be prohibited. <strong>The</strong>y wanted no<br />

possibility that <strong>the</strong> proposed <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> could be interpreted as conferring rights<br />

on a fetus. <strong>The</strong>y wanted affirmative action programs protected against possible<br />

charges of reverse discrimination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposed <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to confer what <strong>the</strong>y<br />

called “Indian rights” on non-status Indian women. <strong>The</strong>y also wanted women<br />

to be fairly represented on <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court which would play an enlarged<br />

role under a <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> regime.<br />

A Women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conference of over a thous<strong>and</strong> women, held on<br />

February 14, exp<strong>and</strong>ed women’s dem<strong>and</strong>s to include guarantees of<br />

reproductive freedom <strong>and</strong> equitable representation throughout <strong>the</strong> political<br />

system. After <strong>the</strong> conference, <strong>the</strong> process was directed by <strong>the</strong> largely Torontobased<br />

Ad Hoc group of “experts” in law <strong>and</strong> lobbying15 which was revived to<br />

play a role in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debates <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> referendum on <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord. <strong>The</strong> Ad Hoc group drew heavily on NAC networks.<br />

<strong>The</strong> lobbying which followed <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conference focused on<br />

getting legally effective texts for <strong>the</strong> equality rights sections (15 <strong>and</strong> 28) <strong>and</strong><br />

ensuring that Section 28 was not subject to governmental override. <strong>The</strong> experts<br />

marshalled thous<strong>and</strong>s of women, now enraged at <strong>the</strong> intransigence of male<br />

politicians who sought to deny <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> legal equality <strong>the</strong>y thought <strong>the</strong>y had<br />

always had in what became widely viewed as an “icon of feminist<br />

effectiveness” (Black, 1992:104).<br />

Few English-Canadian feminists understood <strong>the</strong> resistance to <strong>the</strong> new<br />

constitutional regime by most of Quebec’s Francophone feminists. <strong>The</strong><br />

misconception that in <strong>the</strong>ir resistance Quebec feminists were acting more as<br />

nationalists than as feminists developed. Majoritarian feminists also had<br />

difficulty underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> views of many aboriginal women. Hastings <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>La</strong>wrence, for example, in reporting on <strong>the</strong> Women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Conference, concluded “native women constituted a strong presence, although<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir presentation requesting a supportive resolution could not be considered<br />

because it asked for support of <strong>the</strong>ir plea for independent nationhood ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

274


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

than anything to do with issues of specific concern to native women<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves,” (my emphasis;1981:4). Few white feminists understood why<br />

some aboriginal women could believe that <strong>the</strong> rights of individual women<br />

couldn’t be secured until <strong>the</strong> collective rights of <strong>the</strong>ir nations were secured,<br />

while many non-status aboriginal women sought “status” through an<br />

individual rights regime.<br />

Many racial <strong>and</strong> ethnic minority women were mobilized into movement<br />

organizations like NAC, as were women with disabilities, by <strong>the</strong>se high profile<br />

campaigns for equality rights. O<strong>the</strong>r minority women, however, became<br />

involved in constitutional politics when <strong>the</strong>y were mobilized to fight against<br />

<strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. 16<br />

<strong>The</strong> Road to Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

From 1982 to 1987 was a period of great activity <strong>and</strong> expansion for all parts of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement with <strong>the</strong> rapid mobilization of minority <strong>and</strong><br />

marginalized women in particular. <strong>The</strong>re was also an extension of services in<br />

small towns, rural areas, ethnic <strong>and</strong> some aboriginal communities for women<br />

encountering rape <strong>and</strong> battering. Groups were created to fight <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> cases.<br />

Women’s unionization increased significantly as did <strong>the</strong> presence of women<br />

leaders in unions. Women in traditional occupations, especially nurses, were<br />

radicalized <strong>and</strong> fought a series of long, tough <strong>and</strong> successful strikes which<br />

gained wide support.<br />

In this period, English-Canadian society also became more ideologically<br />

polarized with <strong>the</strong> development of anti-feminist groups which rapidly<br />

mobilized right-wing women. <strong>The</strong> new Progressive Conservative government<br />

issued a Discussion Paper on Equality Issues in Federal <strong>La</strong>w (Sessional Paper<br />

No. 331-416) on January 31, 1985. When <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was enacted, <strong>the</strong> equality<br />

sections were suspended until 1985 to allow governments to conduct statute<br />

audits. Instead, <strong>the</strong> Discussion Paper argued “that if <strong>the</strong>re is something in <strong>the</strong><br />

present law <strong>the</strong>n this indicates that it is acceptable social practice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

should be immune from <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> challenge” (Proceedings 16:115). <strong>The</strong><br />

Committee to which it was referred reflected <strong>the</strong> government’s huge<br />

majority—five Conservatives, one Liberal <strong>and</strong> one New Democrat. <strong>The</strong><br />

Committee Chair, Toronto MP Patrick Boyer, however, was a progressive on<br />

rights issues <strong>and</strong> determined to hold national hearings. NAC established an<br />

Equality Rights project to support its members in attending hearings <strong>and</strong><br />

preparing briefs, which seventy NAC affiliates did (Feminist Action,<br />

December, 1985:11).<br />

NAC’s strategy was to discredit <strong>the</strong> “acceptable social practice” approach to<br />

equality rights <strong>and</strong> to “fill” <strong>the</strong> concept of equality with content about women’s<br />

lives during <strong>the</strong> hearings so that an “equality equals same treatment”<br />

formulation would not be endorsed by Parliament. Anti-feminist groups,<br />

which had not had time to organize during <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> debate, now argued that<br />

<strong>the</strong> very existence of constitutional equality guarantees were a “total attack on<br />

<strong>the</strong> foundation of a good stable country—<strong>the</strong> family,” (Proceedings 17:113).<br />

But <strong>the</strong>y were too late. Traditional women’s groups supported <strong>the</strong> equality<br />

sections advancing an equality of results approach similar to that advanced by<br />

NAC’s affiliates. <strong>The</strong> out-pouring of experiences from gay <strong>and</strong> lesbian groups<br />

seeking <strong>the</strong> explicit protection of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> was perhaps <strong>the</strong> most moving<br />

aspect of <strong>the</strong> Committee’s hearings, leading <strong>the</strong> Committee to endorse explicit<br />

protection.<br />

275


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

To <strong>the</strong> surprise of many, <strong>the</strong> Committee produced a unanimous report in under<br />

a year. Forty-one of its eighty-five recommendations involved changes in<br />

government legislation, policy or practice related to sexual equality<br />

guarantees. It also supported positive action such as contract compliance to<br />

achieve equality of results <strong>and</strong> rejected <strong>the</strong> view that this was “reverse<br />

discrimination.” While <strong>the</strong> government refused to act on many of <strong>the</strong><br />

Committee’s recommendations <strong>and</strong> dragged its feet on o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong> body of<br />

arguments developed was important in creating a discourse which focused on<br />

substantive instead of formal equality. Many grass-roots feminists, however,<br />

were disappointed that <strong>the</strong> Committee made no recommendations concerning<br />

abortion rights or pornography <strong>and</strong> declined to see denial of family status to<br />

same-sex couples as discrimination (Eliot, 1986:5).<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> also provided leverage to achieve changes in <strong>the</strong> Indian Act,<br />

allowing many Indian women to regain <strong>the</strong>ir “status” under <strong>the</strong> Act. Although<br />

majoritarian feminists saw this as <strong>the</strong> righting of an injustice imposed by a<br />

racist <strong>and</strong> patriarchal government, many aboriginal women <strong>and</strong> men, who<br />

were dem<strong>and</strong>ing self-government for <strong>the</strong>ir nations, saw it as ano<strong>the</strong>r attempt<br />

by white society to define citizenship in <strong>the</strong>ir nations, adding population<br />

without adding <strong>the</strong> resources needed to actually re-integrate women into <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

b<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Quebec’s continuing alienation from <strong>the</strong> constitutional order led <strong>the</strong> new<br />

Prime Minister to negotiate <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, which recognized<br />

Quebec’s conditions for accepting <strong>the</strong> new <strong>Constitution</strong>. Many women were<br />

concerned about <strong>the</strong> recognition of Quebec as a distinct society, fearing that<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir hard-won equality rights could somehow be “trumped” by <strong>the</strong> “distinct<br />

society” provision which some feminist lawyers warned would create a<br />

hierarchy of rights. <strong>The</strong> limitation to be placed on <strong>the</strong> federal spending power<br />

also caused concern. <strong>The</strong> national shared-cost programs women had hoped to<br />

gain, such as childcare, now seemed impossible if <strong>the</strong> federal spending power<br />

were to be constrained as <strong>the</strong> Accord proposed. As Ginette Busque notes:<br />

“What Quebec women eventually began to realize...was that, maybe more<br />

than distinct society, it was <strong>the</strong> structuring of shared-cost programs which<br />

caused profound apprehension,” (1991:16).<br />

Ginette Busque notes that “Quebec women would have remained relatively<br />

remote from <strong>the</strong> issue had <strong>the</strong>y not been deeply offended by <strong>the</strong> interpretations<br />

placed by some groups on <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> impact it could<br />

eventually have on women both inside <strong>and</strong> outside Québec,” (1991:15). As<br />

Diane <strong>La</strong>moureux points out, “Ces groupes considèrent que l’expérience<br />

sociale des femmes fait également partie de la société distincte québécoise,”<br />

(1991:60). Quebec women “...repudiated... [a] vision of a small-minded<br />

Quebec where a distinct society could be promoted to <strong>the</strong> detriment of women<br />

<strong>and</strong> minorities.” As Ginette Busque concluded, in any event, “We also felt<br />

perfectly able to defend ourselves on our own ground, if need be,” (1991:15).<br />

Resentment of Quebec’s claims for special treatment, felt especially by some<br />

western, aboriginal <strong>and</strong> minority women, would perhaps have been softened if<br />

<strong>the</strong>y had known <strong>the</strong>se views.<br />

<strong>The</strong> revived Ad Hoc group, with LEAF <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r feminist legal groups,<br />

directed <strong>the</strong> campaign. When <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister called Anglophone feminists<br />

“racists” in <strong>the</strong> House, Christie Jefferson, executive director of LEAF, replied<br />

that “Most women’s organizations have predicated all critiques of<br />

<strong>the</strong>...Accord with a statement saying we favour Quebec’s status as a unique<br />

276


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

society...” (quoted Broadside, November 1987:3). Indeed, most of <strong>the</strong> briefs<br />

from <strong>the</strong> non-Quebec organizations to <strong>the</strong> Joint Committee on <strong>the</strong> 1987<br />

Accord did support distinct or unique society status for Quebec, but few<br />

showed any deep underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how this might create a different<br />

relationship to <strong>the</strong> constitutional order for <strong>the</strong> Quebec movement. On Section<br />

28 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “distinct society” issue, however, NAC <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> FFQ managed to<br />

develop a joint position on <strong>the</strong> protection of women’s equality guarantees<br />

(Roberts, 1988:14,15). This moved NAC closer to <strong>the</strong> “three nations” position<br />

it currently holds in support of asymmetrical federalism.<br />

Aboriginal <strong>and</strong> minority women were especially concerned about <strong>the</strong> Accord,<br />

although for different reasons. Most aboriginal women rejected <strong>the</strong> accord<br />

because of <strong>the</strong> possible impact of recognizing Quebec as a “distinct society” on<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir nations’ claims to l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> self-government. Marginalized women,<br />

especially those with disabilities, wanted to streng<strong>the</strong>n not weaken federal<br />

power. As Shelagh Day has argued:<br />

<strong>The</strong> desire of <strong>the</strong> equality-seeking groups is not to see <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

spending power dismantled through decentralization of<br />

responsibilities to <strong>the</strong> provinces. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong>ir desire is to<br />

ensure that <strong>the</strong> federal responsibility is enhanced by requiring <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government to ensure that every dollar that goes to o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

levels of government is spent in a way that complies with<br />

constitutional guarantees. (1991:98)<br />

In addition to <strong>the</strong>se substantive concerns, many feminists also opposed <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord because of <strong>the</strong> process used by <strong>the</strong> eleven white men<br />

whose constitutional “baby” it was. Grass-roots feminists in English Canada<br />

again had clear enemies <strong>and</strong> viewed <strong>the</strong> process through jaundiced eyes <strong>and</strong>,<br />

although <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord was supported by <strong>the</strong> majority of women’s<br />

groups in Quebec, <strong>the</strong> closed processes of executive federalism caused offense<br />

<strong>the</strong>re as well. Moreover, as NAC <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> FFQ struggled to develop a<br />

compromise position on <strong>the</strong> Accord, some minority <strong>and</strong> marginalized women<br />

objected to <strong>the</strong>ir exclusion from this process of elite accommodation within<br />

organized feminism as well.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se controversies were an important learning opportunity in which <strong>the</strong> two<br />

majoritarian elements, came to underst<strong>and</strong> one ano<strong>the</strong>rs’ positions on<br />

constitutional issues far more clearly as a result. In January 1988, moreover,<br />

<strong>the</strong> efficacy of <strong>the</strong> legal strategy became more apparent as <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court,<br />

relying on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, removed <strong>the</strong> legal impediments to abortion in Canada.<br />

Quebec women, however, were shocked in 1989 when <strong>the</strong> Quebec Superior<br />

Court upheld an injunction granted to an ex-boyfriend preventing Chantal<br />

Daigle from having an abortion. Although <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court overturned <strong>the</strong><br />

injunction <strong>and</strong> made such third-party interventions impossible in <strong>the</strong> future,<br />

most Quebec feminists remained unpersuaded of <strong>the</strong> value of an entrenched<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> or of a federal court system. Indeed, as <strong>the</strong> presentations of prominent<br />

Francophone feminists <strong>and</strong> women’s groups to <strong>the</strong> Bélanger-Campeau<br />

Commission made clear, by <strong>the</strong> 1990s <strong>the</strong> Quebec francophone movement was<br />

largely, if not universally, supportive of a sovereigntist position.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord<br />

<strong>The</strong> threat of ano<strong>the</strong>r referendum on sovereignty in Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> civil<br />

disturbances surrounding aboriginal l<strong>and</strong> claims led to renewed efforts to<br />

277


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

reform <strong>the</strong> constitutional order in what has been called <strong>the</strong> “Canada round” of<br />

negotiations leading up to <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. To <strong>the</strong> surprise of many,<br />

most elements of <strong>the</strong> women’s movement united in opposition to <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Accord, although most women of <strong>the</strong> political class supported<br />

it. NAC organized ano<strong>the</strong>r, smaller women’s constitutional conference, in<br />

which fifty major groups took part, including <strong>the</strong> FFQ, <strong>the</strong> FNFCF, <strong>the</strong><br />

National Organization of Immigrant <strong>and</strong> Visible Minority Women, <strong>the</strong><br />

Business <strong>and</strong> Professional Women’s organizations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> NWAC (NAC,<br />

1991).<br />

Opposition to <strong>the</strong> Accord was directed at both process <strong>and</strong> substance. One<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> was for a “full seat at <strong>the</strong> constitutional table for aboriginal women,<br />

including NWAC <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> National Métis Women’s Association (NWMA),”<br />

(NAC, 1991:2). Substantive changes dem<strong>and</strong>ed included “full protection of<br />

equality rights for aboriginal women”; “racially representative gender equality<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Senate”; a “political accord” to establish “proportional representation in<br />

<strong>the</strong> House of Commons” within two years; proper protection from diminution<br />

for equality <strong>and</strong> language rights; <strong>and</strong> a regime of asymmetrical federalism<br />

which would require <strong>the</strong> federal government “to spend on social programs<br />

outside Quebec” <strong>and</strong> would prevent opt-outs from new social programs or <strong>the</strong><br />

“devolution of labour market training, immigration <strong>and</strong> culture” to <strong>the</strong><br />

provinces, except for Quebec. (NAC, 1991:2) Although women of <strong>the</strong> political<br />

class <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> media attempted to discredit NAC’s opposition (Vienneau, 1992;<br />

<strong>La</strong>framboise, 1992), it quickly became apparent that most women’s groups<br />

had too many concerns about <strong>the</strong> possible impact of <strong>the</strong> Accord to vote “yes.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> extensive decentralization envisioned in <strong>the</strong> Accord posed problems for<br />

women outside of Quebec for reasons which I have already outlined. A<br />

justiciable social charter, which could have allayed some of <strong>the</strong> fears of women<br />

about a more decentralized federation, was watered down into an<br />

unenforceable statement of intent. NAC’s decision to oppose <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

reflected <strong>the</strong> concerns of its most vulnerable members, minority, marginalized<br />

<strong>and</strong> non-status aboriginal women in particular, who feared <strong>the</strong> dilution of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> loss of strong programs of support guaranteed by <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government wherever <strong>the</strong>y might live. And it was feared that decentralization<br />

would mean that federal funding of movement groups would be withdrawn<br />

even fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> would not be replaced by provincial funding in most cases.<br />

Some women of <strong>the</strong> political class were particularly offended by opposition to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord <strong>and</strong> NAC’s support for <strong>the</strong> NWAC position. <strong>The</strong> Inuit Women’s<br />

Association (Pauktuutit) was represented on <strong>the</strong> Inuit “Yes” Committee <strong>and</strong><br />

Inuit believed <strong>the</strong>ir women leaders had acted to protect women’s<br />

constitutional rights (Moss, 1992:2,3). Political women of all parties urged<br />

women’s groups to be “realistic” <strong>and</strong> to accept <strong>the</strong> accord in a spirit of<br />

compromise. But <strong>the</strong>y were no more persuasive than <strong>the</strong>ir male colleagues.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> referendum debate, <strong>the</strong> Canadian women’s movement came to be<br />

recognized as a significant player in Canadian constitutional politics.<br />

Although women’s concerns were still often treated dismissively, it was now<br />

clear after a decade of effort that <strong>the</strong>re were distinctive women’s concerns.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re were also substantial gains made in this process for <strong>the</strong> women’s<br />

movement. English-Canadian feminists, in developing <strong>the</strong>ir new “three<br />

nations” constitutional vision, came to underst<strong>and</strong> collective rights better.<br />

Indeed, feminists of both majority cultures came to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> hurts of<br />

racism, ablism <strong>and</strong> homophobia more clearly. Many bridges were built,<br />

278


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

reducing <strong>the</strong> fragmentation of <strong>the</strong> movement which, in 1993, is stronger than it<br />

has ever been.<br />

Conclusions<br />

<strong>The</strong> outcome of this decade of women’s involvement in constitutional politics<br />

remains unclear as I write. It is possible that women in Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> First<br />

Nations will both seek <strong>and</strong> achieve greater autonomy, even sovereignty, in <strong>the</strong><br />

future. But it is also clear, as Linda Trimble argues, that “women, <strong>and</strong><br />

especially marginalized women, need power to make <strong>the</strong>ir interests<br />

interesting” (1991:90). And it is clear to all elements of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

movement that we have more power when we can co-operate in one ano<strong>the</strong>r’s<br />

projects. <strong>Constitution</strong>al politics was not an arena women chose to enter, at<br />

least in part because of its potential for conflict within <strong>the</strong> movement. While<br />

feminist leaders <strong>and</strong> lawyers (especially of <strong>the</strong> majoritarian cultures) have<br />

gained more profile, it is not clear that ordinary women have yet gained enough<br />

power to make <strong>the</strong>ir interests “interesting” enough to keep <strong>the</strong>m “on <strong>the</strong> table”<br />

when <strong>the</strong> final round of constitutional bargaining comes around again. Nor<br />

have women yet gained <strong>the</strong> clout to enforce on elites a more open process in<br />

which women can participate effectively.<br />

Francophone feminists in Quebec with <strong>the</strong>ir project of a society in which<br />

women’s powers <strong>and</strong> vision are fully integrated have set us on <strong>the</strong> path of<br />

constitutional transformation, ra<strong>the</strong>r than just reform. Aboriginal women with<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir often conflicting views challenge us to think of rights regimes which can<br />

encompass both individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights. Majoritarian feminists are<br />

learning to hear <strong>and</strong> respond to <strong>the</strong> constitutional needs of minority <strong>and</strong><br />

marginalized women. <strong>The</strong> past decade of engagement by progressive<br />

Canadian women in constitutional politics was possible because of <strong>the</strong><br />

movement’s strength, flexibility <strong>and</strong> energy. It is also true, however, that<br />

involvement in constitutional politics has streng<strong>the</strong>ned <strong>and</strong> energized <strong>the</strong><br />

movement fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> has been <strong>the</strong> catalyst for a quantum leap in <strong>the</strong><br />

movement’s intellectual flexibility.<br />

Notes<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> author wishes to acknowledge <strong>the</strong> financial support of <strong>the</strong> Social Science <strong>and</strong><br />

Humanities Research Council which permitted <strong>the</strong> conduct of this research.<br />

2. See for example, Kenneth Karst, “Paths to Belonging: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cultural<br />

Identity.” North Carolina <strong>La</strong>w Review, 64 (January, 198 ): 303-77. <strong>The</strong> ideal of <strong>the</strong><br />

disembodied constitutional citizen, however, is relatively new with modern liberalism.<br />

Certainly Aristotle, Machiavelli, Hegel <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs knew women could not be citizens<br />

because of <strong>the</strong>ir sex/gender characteristics.<br />

3. I introduce this distinction between majoritarian <strong>and</strong> minority feminists in “Notes Toward a<br />

Political <strong>The</strong>ory of Sex <strong>and</strong> Power” (forthcoming 1993). In it, I <strong>the</strong>orize that women <strong>and</strong><br />

men of secure, dominant cultures who have access to state instruments (i.e., media, schools)<br />

to protect <strong>the</strong>ir community identity underst<strong>and</strong> reproduction <strong>and</strong> its links to political power<br />

differently than members of threatened, minority communities.<br />

4. <strong>The</strong> newspapers surveyed were Broadside, Cayenne, Herizons, <strong>La</strong> Vie En Rose, <strong>The</strong> Emily,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Womanist, NAC Memo,Status <strong>and</strong> Feminist Action. My thanks to Marcella Munro for<br />

her assistance in this survey. For <strong>the</strong> views in Quebec, I relied more heavily on <strong>the</strong> views of<br />

feminist scholars. With <strong>the</strong> assistance of such scholars as Micheline Dumont <strong>and</strong> Micheline<br />

de Sève, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> staff of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Research Institute for <strong>the</strong> Advancement of Women<br />

(CRIAW), FFQ publications <strong>and</strong> briefs were located. My thanks to Dorine Chalifoux who<br />

undertook this research <strong>and</strong> precised translations.<br />

279


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

5. I was parliamentarian for NAC (an umbrella organization of 500-600 women’s groups)<br />

during <strong>the</strong> 1980s. I also attended women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al conferences <strong>and</strong> meetings <strong>and</strong> was<br />

invited to present briefs as an “expert” before <strong>the</strong> Boyer Committee.<br />

6. Many First Nations traditionalists <strong>and</strong> sovereigntists reject altoge<strong>the</strong>r a rights-based<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> relationship between individual <strong>and</strong> collectivity. I use <strong>the</strong> term “rights”<br />

here only to aid underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

7. For example, <strong>the</strong> Quebec government eventually stopped enforcing <strong>the</strong> old criminal code<br />

sections concerning abortion. <strong>The</strong> federal government jailed Dr. Henry Morgentaler after<br />

Quebec juries acquitted him. To Anglo-Canadian feminists, this was evidence that<br />

governments are patriarchal. To Francophone feminists in Quebec, it was evidence that <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government had over-ruled a more progressive Quebec government. Eventually, <strong>the</strong><br />

law was struck down under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> Canada currently has no criminal law concerning<br />

abortion.<br />

8. Throughout <strong>the</strong> decade, NAC dem<strong>and</strong>ed longer hearings, constitutional conferences,<br />

constituent assemblies <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> official representation of women as women at <strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional table. NAC opposed <strong>the</strong> national referendum process because of <strong>the</strong> absence<br />

of strict spending limits based on <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong> free trade election in 1988, in which<br />

<strong>the</strong> business lobby, unregulated by <strong>the</strong> electoral spending limits because of a court decision,<br />

poured huge sums of money into a last minute media blitz.<br />

9. This mattered to Quebec feminists in part because <strong>the</strong> federal government had rejected “le<br />

principe du divorce à l’amiable” while <strong>the</strong> provincial government was not opposed<br />

(<strong>La</strong>moureux, 1991).<br />

10. Women’s dependent mobility when in relationships, while no longer having <strong>the</strong> force of law,<br />

is re-inforced by <strong>the</strong> fact that women earn only two-thirds of men’s wages on average. Hence<br />

even an egalitarian family often can’t choose to follow <strong>the</strong> wife’s work.<br />

11. Geographically organized electoral systems disadvantage “interests” <strong>and</strong> groups which are<br />

geographically dispersed <strong>and</strong> reward those which are geographically concentrated.<br />

12. Women are now about 14% of both <strong>the</strong> elected House <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> appointed Senate. <strong>The</strong>y are<br />

represented at slightly higher rates in provinces like Quebec, Ontario, British Columbia <strong>and</strong><br />

P.E.I. Two of <strong>the</strong> nine members of <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court are currently women. Nowhere do<br />

<strong>the</strong>y constitute a critical mass, which is usually viewed as 35-40%, except in <strong>the</strong> Ontario<br />

cabinet.<br />

13. <strong>The</strong> lack of legitimacy of political parties, <strong>the</strong> well-documented gender gap on many issues<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> demonstrated differences among women which are, none<strong>the</strong>less, not <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong><br />

differences among men (regionalism, e.g.) all challenge <strong>the</strong>se views.<br />

14. Aboriginal leaders faced similar problems as <strong>the</strong>y attempted to insert <strong>the</strong> issues of selfgovernment<br />

<strong>and</strong> race into a discourse entirely organized around <strong>the</strong> dualism of “<strong>the</strong> founding<br />

nations.”<br />

15. <strong>The</strong> original Ad Hoc group also included a number of “ordinary” women in Ottawa who put<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> original conference. Strategy decisions, however, were taken by <strong>the</strong> Torontobased<br />

group <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> parliament hill “politicos.”<br />

16. Only <strong>the</strong>se women are usefully described as “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Canadians”; a concept has been used to<br />

described all women by some constitutional commentators, following Alan Cairns (1988,<br />

e.g.).<br />

Bibliography<br />

Primary Sources<br />

Basseletti, Teresa <strong>and</strong> Jacques Mehu. 1991 “Considérations inopportunes sur l’exclusion de la<br />

population immigrée des gr<strong>and</strong>s débats de la société québécoise,” in Myreille St-Onge, ed.,<br />

L’Avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec vu par des groupes de femmes. Québec: Le<br />

GREMF: 25-38.<br />

Bayevsky, Anne F. 1992 “<strong>The</strong> Effect of Aboriginal Self-Government on <strong>the</strong> Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms<br />

of Women.” Typescript dated 25 September.<br />

Bégin, Martine. 1991 “L’autonomie des femmes — l’autonomie du Québec,” in St-Onge: 19-21.<br />

Bonenfant, Claire. 1991a “<strong>La</strong> Fédération des femmes du Québec devant la Commission sur<br />

l’avenir politique du Québec,” in St-Onge: 5-18.<br />

——. 1991b “Présentation de notre mémoire à la commission Bélanger-Campeau,” Le féminisme<br />

en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2: 3.<br />

280


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

Brodsy, Gwen <strong>and</strong> Shelagh Day. 1989 <strong>La</strong> <strong>Charte</strong> canadienne et les droits des femmes : progrès ou<br />

recul? Ottawa, CCCSF.<br />

Busque, Ginette <strong>and</strong> Gingras, Anne-Marie. 1987 “Extraits d’une lettre au Premier ministre Brian<br />

Mulroney sur Le <strong>La</strong>c Meech et les femmes,” <strong>La</strong> petite presse, Newsletter of <strong>the</strong> Fédération<br />

des femmes québécoise, June.<br />

<strong>Conseil</strong> du statut de la femme. 1990. Les femmes, ça compte. Québec.<br />

CSN. 1990 Mémoire soumis à la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec.<br />

November.<br />

Dumont, Micheline. 1991 L’Expérience historique des femmes dans le présent débat<br />

constitutionel. Text presented to <strong>the</strong> Bélanger-Campeau Commission. January.<br />

Fédération des femmes du Québec. 1987 Presentation of <strong>the</strong> FFQ to <strong>the</strong> Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong><br />

Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> House of Commons on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord of 1987. (transl.) Feminist<br />

perspectives féministes No. 12a. CRIAW, Ottawa.<br />

——-. 1990 Mémoire présenté à la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du<br />

Québec. November.<br />

——-. 1991 Le féminisme en revue : Colloque 1991 — L’Avenir des femmes dans un Québec en<br />

devenir. Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

——-. 1992 Pour un Québec féminin pluriel : Dossier de consultation. March.<br />

Fédération nationale des femmes canadiennes-françaises. 1990 <strong>La</strong> Commission sur l’avenir<br />

politique et constitutionnel du Québec. November.<br />

——-. 1992 <strong>The</strong> Voice of Francophone Women Living in Minority Situations in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Debate: An Analysis of <strong>the</strong> Federal Proposals — Shaping Canada’s Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

January.<br />

Genaille, Sheila D. 1992 “Métis women endorse agreement.” Letter to <strong>the</strong> editor, Globe <strong>and</strong> Mail,<br />

30 September.<br />

Gingras, Anne-Marie. 1987 “<strong>La</strong> petite histoire politique du lac Meech,” <strong>La</strong> petite presse.<br />

Newsletter of <strong>the</strong> Fédération des femmes du Québec, September.<br />

Kuptana, Rosemarie. 1992 “Outst<strong>and</strong>ing Inuit Issues re: Charlottetown Accord <strong>and</strong> Gender<br />

Equality under <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>,” memo to Inuit Tapirasat of Canada Board of Directors.<br />

October.<br />

<strong>La</strong>framboise, Donna. 1992 “National group no longer speaks for women,” Toronto Star. D,21<br />

September.<br />

<strong>La</strong>joie, Andrée. 1991 Réponses aux questionx posées par la Commission sur l’avenir politique et<br />

constitutionnel du Québec. Text presented to <strong>the</strong> Bélanger-Campeau Commission. January.<br />

<strong>La</strong>moureux, Diane. 1991b Réponses aux questions posées par la Commission sur l’avenir<br />

politique et constitutionnel du Québec. Text presented to <strong>the</strong> Bélanger-Campeau<br />

Commission. January.<br />

Legault, Ginette. 1991 “Le projet de société féministe et l’option souverainiste : un débat à<br />

poursuivre,” Le féminisme en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

Moss, Wendy. 1992 “<strong>The</strong> Role of Inuit Women in Negotiating <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord.”<br />

Undated release.<br />

NAC. 1991 Response to Federal <strong>Constitution</strong>al Proposals, 25 October.<br />

——-. 1991 A Draft Women’s <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, 4 November.<br />

——-. 1992. Conclusions of Women’s <strong>Constitution</strong>al Conference. 25 August.<br />

Réseau d’Action et d’Information pour les Femmes (RAIF). 1987 L’Entente constitutionnelle de<br />

1987 et les femmes. September.<br />

Roberts, Barbara. 1988 “Smooth Sailing or Storm Warning? Canadian <strong>and</strong> Québec Women’s<br />

Groups <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord,” Feminist Perspectives, 12a CRIAW.<br />

Stacey-Moore, Gail. 1991 “Aboriginal Women, Self Government, <strong>the</strong> Canadian <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> Freedoms, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1991 Canada Package on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>.” Text for an Address to <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadian <strong>La</strong>bour Congress, Ottawa, 31 December.<br />

Vienneau, David. 1992 “Many Women just saying no to No” Toronto Star, O1F, 16, 10 October.<br />

Secondary Sources<br />

Andrew, Carolyn. 1984 “Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Welfare State”, Canadian Journal of Political Science<br />

17, no. 4.<br />

Ayim, Maryann. 1980 “Review of <strong>the</strong> Report of <strong>the</strong> Taskforce of National Unity,” Atlantis 5:2<br />

Bashevkin, Sylvia. 1985 Toeing <strong>the</strong> Lines. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

Begin, Monique. 1992 “<strong>The</strong> Royal Commission on <strong>the</strong> Status of Women in Canada: Twenty<br />

Years <strong>La</strong>ter,” in Constance Backhouse <strong>and</strong> David Flaherty (eds.) Challenging Times: <strong>The</strong><br />

Women’s Movement in Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, McGill-Queen’s Press.<br />

Black, Naomi. 1992 “Ripples in <strong>the</strong> Second Wave: Comparing <strong>the</strong> Contemporary Movement in<br />

Canada <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States,” in Backhouse <strong>and</strong> Flaherty.<br />

Busque, Ginette. 1991 “Why Women Should Care About <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform,” in David<br />

Schneiderman (ed.), Conversations Among Friends/Entre Amis: Proceedings of an<br />

Interdisciplinary Conference on Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform, University of Alberta<br />

Centre for <strong>Constitution</strong>al Studies.<br />

281


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Cairns, Alan. 1988 “<strong>The</strong> Limited <strong>Constitution</strong>al Vision of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke,” in K.E. Swinton <strong>and</strong> C.J.<br />

Rogerson (eds.) Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions: <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. Carswell.<br />

Clark, Lorenne. 1991 “Reconceptualizing <strong>the</strong> Agenda for Reform,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Clio Collective. 1987 Québec Women: A History, transl. Roger Gannon <strong>and</strong> Rosalind Gill, <strong>the</strong><br />

Women’s Press.<br />

Cole, Susan. 1987 “Meech <strong>La</strong>ke: Troubled Waters,” Broadside, Vol. 9, No. 2, November.<br />

Collin, Françoise. 1986 “Introduction,” Cahiers du GRIF 33.<br />

Day, Shelagh. 1991 “<strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform: Canada’s Equality Crisis,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Delphy, Christine. 1977 “Nos amis et nous,” Questions féministes 1.<br />

De Sève, Micheline. 1991 “<strong>The</strong> Perspectives of Québec Feminists,” in Backhouse <strong>and</strong> Flaherty.<br />

Dumont, Micheline. 1992 “<strong>The</strong> Origins of <strong>the</strong> Women’s Movement in Québec,” in Backhouse <strong>and</strong><br />

Flaherty.<br />

Ellis, Megan. 1986 “New <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>, Same Old Story,” Kinesis, November.<br />

Ellis <strong>and</strong> Findlay. 1986 “Hey It’s 1986! Aren’t We Equal Yet?” Kinesis, November.<br />

Eliot, Sarah. 1986 “Competing for Equality,” Broadside, Vol. 7, No. 6, April.<br />

Gidengil, Elisabeth. 1992 “A Different Voice? Gender <strong>and</strong> Political Behavior,” paper presented at<br />

<strong>the</strong> Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science Association, Charlottetown, P.E.I.,<br />

June.<br />

Greckol, Sheila. 1991 “<strong>The</strong> Pursuit of Equality for Women,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Greshner, Donna. 1991 “Conversations: A Talking Circle,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Hall, Tony. 1992 “<strong>The</strong>oretical Discourse in Native Studies,” ACS Newsletter, Vol. 14, No. 1,<br />

Spring.<br />

Hastings <strong>and</strong> <strong>La</strong>wrence. 1981 “Valentines Day Revenge,” Broadside, March.<br />

Hosek, Chaviva. 1983 “Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Process,” in Keith Banting <strong>and</strong> Richard<br />

Simeon, And No One Cheered: <strong>Federalism</strong>, Democracy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> Act, Methuen.<br />

<strong>La</strong>moureux, Diane. 1991a “Une majorité encore oubliée,” in Schneiderman.<br />

——-. 1990 “Le mouvement des femmes : entre l’intégration et l’autonomie,” Canadian Issues,<br />

<strong>The</strong>mes canadiens 12.<br />

——-. 1989 Citoyennes ? Femmes, droit de vote et démocratie. Éditions du remue-ménage.<br />

<strong>La</strong>nge, Lynda. “Rousseau: Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> General Will,” in Lynda <strong>La</strong>nge <strong>and</strong> Loreern M.G.<br />

Clark, eds. <strong>The</strong> Sexism of Social <strong>and</strong> Political <strong>The</strong>ory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1990 Continental Divide: <strong>The</strong> Values <strong>and</strong> Institutions of <strong>the</strong> United<br />

States <strong>and</strong> Canada. Routledge.<br />

Maillé, Chantal. 1991a “<strong>The</strong> Women’s Health Movement in Québec Society: An Analysis for <strong>the</strong><br />

Purpose of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Debate,” in Schneiderman.<br />

——-. 1991b “Femmes et politique: et pourquoi pas une constitution enchâssant notre droit à la<br />

représentation politique?” Le féminisme en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

——-. 1991c “<strong>La</strong> FFQ peut-elle prendre position sur l’avenir politique du Québec sans tomber<br />

dans la partisanerie?” Le féminisme en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

Maracle, Lee. 1991 “Conversations: A Talking Circle,” in Schneiderman.<br />

McLellan, Anne. 1991 “Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Process of <strong>Constitution</strong> Making,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Monture-Okanee, Patricia. 1992 “<strong>The</strong> Violence We Women Do: A First Nations View,” in<br />

Backhouse <strong>and</strong> Flaherty.<br />

——-. 1991 “Seeking My Reflection: A Comment on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Renovation,” in<br />

Schneiderman.<br />

O’Brien, Mary. 1981 “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> in Context,” Broadside, Vol. 2, No. 4, February.<br />

O’Leary, Véronique et Louise Toupin. 1982 Québécoises debouttes! Montreal: Tome I. Éditions<br />

du remue-ménage.<br />

O’Neill, Brenda. 1992 “Gender Gaps in Opinion: <strong>The</strong> Canadian Situation,” paper presented at <strong>the</strong><br />

Annual General Meeting of <strong>the</strong> Canadian Political Science Association, University of Prince<br />

Edward Isl<strong>and</strong>, Charlottetown, P.E.I., June.<br />

Okin, Susan. 1978 Women in Western Political Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.<br />

——-. 1986 “Are Our <strong>The</strong>ories of Justice Gender-Neutral?,” in Robert Fullinwider <strong>and</strong> Claudia<br />

Mills, eds. <strong>The</strong> Civil Rights. Totowa, N.J: Rowman <strong>and</strong> Littlefield.<br />

Pateman, Carole. 1989 <strong>The</strong> Disorder of Women. Cambridge: Polity/Basil Blackwell.<br />

——-. 1988 <strong>The</strong> Sexual Contract. Stanford: Stanford University Press.<br />

Payette, Lise. 1982 Le pouvoir? Connais pas! Québec-Amérique.<br />

Paquerot, Sylvie. 1991 “Vision féministe de la société québécoise,” Le féminisme en revue, Vol.<br />

4, No. 2.<br />

Razack, Sherene. 1991 “Issues of Difference in <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform: Say Goodbye to <strong>the</strong><br />

Universal Woman,” in Schneiderman.<br />

Roberts, Barbara. 1989 Beau fixe ou nuages à l’horizon? L’Accord du lac Meech jugé par les<br />

féministes du Québec et du Canada. Ottawa, ICREF/CRIAW, Collection “Perspectives<br />

féministes.”<br />

Tardy, Évelyne. “Autour du débat constitutionnel : quelques aspects économiques,” Le féminisme<br />

en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

——-. “Parlons stratégies,” Le féminisme en revue, Vol. 4, No. 2.<br />

282


<strong>The</strong> Canadian Women’s Movement <strong>and</strong> a Changing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Order<br />

Trimble, Linda. 1991 “<strong>Federalism</strong>, <strong>the</strong> Feminization of Poverty <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>,” in<br />

Schneiderman.<br />

Vickers Jill. 1992a “<strong>The</strong> Intellectual Origins of <strong>the</strong> Women’s Movements in Canada,” in<br />

Backhouse <strong>and</strong> Flaherty.<br />

——-. 1992b “You Can’t Get <strong>The</strong>re From Here: Women <strong>and</strong> Public Policy,” paper delivered at<br />

Memorial University, Newfoundl<strong>and</strong>, January.<br />

——-. 1991a “Why Should Women Care About <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform?,” in Schneiderman.<br />

——-. 1991b “Bending <strong>the</strong> Iron <strong>La</strong>w of Oligarchy: Debates on <strong>the</strong> Feminization of Organization<br />

<strong>and</strong> Political Process in <strong>the</strong> English-Canadian Women’s Movement,” in Jeri Dawn Wine <strong>and</strong><br />

Janice L. Ristock (eds.) Women <strong>and</strong> Social Change: Feminist Activism in Canada. James<br />

Lorimer.<br />

——-. 1986 “Equality-Seeking in a Cold Climate,” in Lynn Smith et.al. (eds.), Righting <strong>the</strong><br />

Balance: Canada’s New Equality Rights. <strong>The</strong> Human Rights Reporter, Inc.<br />

Vickers, Jill, Pauline Rankin <strong>and</strong> Christine Appelle. 1993 Politics As If Women Mattered,<br />

University of Toronto Press.<br />

Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Politics of Difference. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton<br />

University Press.<br />

——-. 1989. “Polity <strong>and</strong> Group Difference: A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Ideal of Universal Citizenship,”<br />

Ethics 99 (January): 250-74.<br />

283


Max Nemni<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec 1<br />

Résumé<br />

Depuis près d’un quart de siècle, l’idée de la sécession du Québec fait partie<br />

du paysage politique canadien. Pour expliquer ce phénomène il est essentiel<br />

d’identifier les effets de l’utilisation du nationalisme à des fins politiques.<br />

C’est dans cet esprit que cette étude analyse la démarche et les travaux d’une<br />

commission mise sur pied par le gouvernement québécois de Robert Bourassa.<br />

Née au lendemain de « l’échec du lac Meech », cette commission fut créée<br />

notamment pour instaurer un rapport de force plus favorable au Québec vis-àvis<br />

du reste du Canada.<br />

On verra que bien que cette commission n’ait pas contribué à accroître les<br />

pouvoirs de négociation du Québec, elle permit au gouvernement Bourassa de<br />

sortir du cul-de-sac politique dans lequel « Meech » l’avait placé. On verra<br />

surtout qu’un des effets les plus marquants de tout ce processus fut le<br />

renforcement de l’idée de sécession au Québec.<br />

Abstract<br />

For almost a quarter of a century, <strong>the</strong> idea of Quebec’s secession has been an<br />

integral part of <strong>the</strong> Canadian political l<strong>and</strong>scape. In order to underst<strong>and</strong> this<br />

phenomenon it is essential to assess <strong>the</strong> use of nationalism for political<br />

purposes.<br />

This study focuses on <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> political impact of an organism created by<br />

<strong>the</strong> Quebec government of Robert Bourassa. Born as a result of <strong>the</strong> failed<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, <strong>the</strong> political function of this body was to bolster Quebec’s<br />

negotiating position vis-à-vis <strong>the</strong> rest of Canada.<br />

<strong>The</strong> findings of this study are that while this organism did not streng<strong>the</strong>n<br />

Quebec’s position, it did allow Bourassa’s government to come out of <strong>the</strong><br />

political impasse created by Meech. More importantly, <strong>the</strong> fundamental effect<br />

of this entire process was to bolster <strong>the</strong> idea of secession in Quebec.<br />

<strong>La</strong> menace de la sécession du Québec hante l’univers politique canadien<br />

depuis plus d’un quart de siècle. Or, selon un classement des Nations Unies, le<br />

Canada offre la meilleure qualité de vie du monde. S’il est possible de<br />

comprendre l’émergence de féodalités ethniques qu<strong>and</strong> s’est brisé le joug de<br />

l’ancienne U.R.S.S., on s’explique plus difficilement les déchirements<br />

internes que subit le Canada 2.<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Après le référendum de mai 1980, où les Québécois dirent « non » à l’option<br />

sécessionniste que leur offrait le Parti québécois, voilà que douze ans plus tard,<br />

en octobre 1992, la question de la place du Québec au sein de la fédération<br />

canadienne a forcé le Canada tout entier à jouer son avenir sur un nouveau<br />

référendum.<br />

Mais avec, cette fois, une différence importante. Alors que jusque-là, le reste<br />

du Canada se dem<strong>and</strong>ait, avec un c<strong>and</strong>ide étonnement, « What does Quebec<br />

want? », c’était maintenant un Québec plein d’assurance qui lançait un double<br />

défi au reste du Canada. Premièrement, sous le titre frondeur Un Québec libre<br />

de ses choix, le Rapport « Allaire » traçait les gr<strong>and</strong>es lignes de la politique<br />

constitutionnelle du Parti libéral du Québec, dirigé par Robert Bourassa. Du<br />

fédéralisme, ce rapport ne retenait guère que le nom en exigeant le transfert<br />

massif de presque tous les pouvoirs du gouvernement central. Ce premier défi<br />

au reste du Canada fut lancé en mars 1991, lors du congrès annuel de ce Parti.<br />

Le deuxième ne tarda pas à venir.<br />

Quelques mois après le 23 juin 1990, date de l’échec de la ronde de<br />

négociations contitutionnelles dite du lac Meech, fut instituée, sous l’autorité<br />

de l’Assemblée nationale du Québec, la Commission sur l’avenir politique et<br />

constitutionnel du Québec. Dotée du vaste m<strong>and</strong>at « d’étudier et d’analyser le<br />

statut politique et constitutionnel du Québec et de formuler à cet égard des<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>ations », son rapport ne se fit pas attendre. En moins de six mois, la<br />

Commission « Bélanger-Campeau » fit le tour de la question qui divise le<br />

Canada depuis ses premiers jours. Non seulement elle identifia les problèmes,<br />

mais elle édicta un diagnostic radical. Le 27 mars 1991, la Commission<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>a à l’Assemblée nationale d’adopter une loi prévoyant la tenue<br />

d’un référendum sur la souveraineté du Québec à une date bien précise (entre<br />

le 8 et le 22 juin 1992 ou entre le 12 et le 26 octobre 1992). Advenant la victoire<br />

du « oui », cette loi prévoyait, avec la même précision, une date d’accession<br />

du Québec à l’indépendance, soit un an jour pour jour après la tenue du<br />

référendum. Le deuxième défi était lancé.<br />

Cependant, entre août et octobre 1992, le Parti libéral de Bourassa changea<br />

radicalement de cap. Reniant sa propre conception de la place du Québec au<br />

sein du Canada, définie dans le Rapport Allaire devenu la politique officielle<br />

du Parti, ainsi que la loi 150 qu’il avait fait adopter par l’Assemblée nationale à<br />

la suite du rapport de la Commission Bélanger-Campeau (qu’on appellera ici<br />

la « Commission »), le gouvernement Bourassa fit voter presque unanimement<br />

par ses membres, lors du congrès annuel d’août 1992, une résolution dictant la<br />

tenue d’un référendum sur un renouvellement relativement mineur du cadre<br />

fédéral existant, et non plus sur la souveraineté comme l’exigeait la loi 150.<br />

<strong>La</strong> preuve semblait ainsi faite que la sécession n’était qu’une menace, qu’un<br />

élément stratégique de négociation du gouvernement Bourassa. Cette<br />

stratégie, dite du « couteau sur la gorge », avait d’ailleurs été promue par de<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>es personnalités québécoises, dont Léon Dion. C’est en effet lui qui, lors<br />

de la présentation de son mémoire à la Commission le 12 décembre 1990,<br />

affirmait qu’il n’y avait qu’une façon de faire bouger le « Canada anglais » :<br />

« Il ne cèdera — et cela même n’est pas assuré — que s’il a le couperet sur la<br />

gorge3.» Onze mois plus tard, après avoir pris connaissance du texte de l’entente<br />

constitutionnelle négociée à Charlottetown, Léon Dion exprima son<br />

étonnement devant l’échec de la stratégie qu’il avait promue :<br />

286


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

Ici plane un mystère qu’il faudra dissiper un jour... Les Québécois<br />

avaient procuré à leur premier ministre un rapport de force à triple<br />

ressort en 1991 — la Commission Bélanger-Campeau, la loi 150 et le<br />

programme du PLQ (Rapport Allaire).... Cette force qui était entre<br />

ses mains, pourquoi l’a-t-il laissée s’échapper 4 ?<br />

Ce qui stupéfie cet éminent spécialiste, c’est, à première vue, le fait que le<br />

gouvernement Bourassa ait si mal utilisé un rapport de force qui semblait le<br />

favoriser. Mais au-delà de cet aspect stratégique, ce qui explique cet<br />

étonnement, partagé d’ailleurs par la plupart des spécialistes québécois à<br />

tendance nationaliste, ce fut la minceur des réformes acceptées par le<br />

gouvernement Bourassa eu égard à l’ampleur des dem<strong>and</strong>es « minimales » du<br />

Québec. L’étude de Guy <strong>La</strong>forest, présentée quelques mois avant le dépôt du<br />

rapport de la Commission, illustre bien ces attentes. Ce spécialiste,<br />

représentatif d’un point de vue prédominant alors dans les milieux<br />

intellectuels et politiques du Québec, affirmait en effet que « le régime fédéral<br />

canadien de 1867, partiellement rénové en 1982, a fait faillitte au Québec et ne<br />

peut être regénéré. » Le problème était d’autant plus profond, à ses yeux, que<br />

« l’idée de fédéralisme avait été détruite à tout jamais au Québec depuis<br />

l’échec de Meech5. » C’est ce qui amenait <strong>La</strong>forest à prévoir que le rapport de<br />

la Commission exclurait l’option fédéraliste et exigerait « soit un<br />

réaménagement de type confédéral, soit une forme d’association entre États<br />

souverains6. »<br />

Ainsi, non seulement la réforme du fédéralisme canadien était considérée<br />

comme hautement illusoire, mais la notion même de « fédéralisme » avait,<br />

affirmait-on fréquemment, perdu toute crédibilité au Québec. Tout comme<br />

<strong>La</strong>forest, de nombreux experts québécois à tendance nationaliste percevaient<br />

la Commission à la fois comme l’étape ultime vers la restructuration radicale<br />

de l’espace géopolitique canadien et comme un instrument stratégique en vue<br />

d’atteindre cet objectif. On comprend donc leur déception et leur étonnement<br />

lorsque Bourassa accepta avec enthousiasme l’entente de Charlottetown qu’ils<br />

percevaient au mieux comme un réaménagement mineur du cadre fédéral<br />

existant. D’où le « mystère » évoqué par Dion.<br />

Peut-on élucider ce mystère ou, plus modestement, peut-on soulever quelque<br />

peu le voile qui l’entoure ?<br />

Pour y parvenir, on analysera la démarche ainsi que les travaux de la<br />

Commission Bélanger-Campeau qui était au coeur des négociations<br />

constitutionnelles canadiennes. Ces travaux nous permettront de pénétrer dans<br />

un univers complexe où s’entrecroisent passion et raison. Car pour remplir son<br />

m<strong>and</strong>at qui lui dictait de se prononcer sur « l’avenir constitutionnel du<br />

Québec », cette Commission fonctionna sur deux registres. D’une part, elle<br />

prit le pouls des Québécois et, d’autre part, elle étudia systématiquement<br />

plusieurs aspects fondamentaux des rapports entre le Québec et le reste du<br />

Canada. Ainsi, elle était à la fois une commission d’étude et un forum qui<br />

permit à de nombreux Québécois d’exprimer leurs doléances. Mais avant<br />

d’aborder l’analyse des travaux de cette Commission, il est nécessaire de<br />

décrire brièvement les nombreux documents qu’ils ont engendrés.<br />

On y distingue nettement trois catégories de matériaux. Premièrement, le<br />

rapport final. Il s’agit là d’un texte de 180 pages, signé par tous les membres de<br />

la Commission ainsi que par le premier ministre, Robert Bourassa, et par le<br />

chef de l’opposition officielle, Jacques Parizeau. C’est à ce document<br />

287


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

ambivalent, recomm<strong>and</strong>ant soit le référendum sur la souveraineté, soit le<br />

renouvellement en profondeur du cadre fédéral, que sera consacrée la première<br />

partie de ce travail intitulée : « Le rapport Bélanger-Campeau et la stratégie du<br />

gouvernement Bourassa ».<br />

Une deuxième catégorie de matériaux comprend les mémoires, soumis à titre<br />

privé tant par des particuliers que par des associations de tous genres. Ces<br />

quelque 600 documents, qui totalisent environ 15 000 pages, représentent le<br />

produit final de la vaste consultation populaire mise en branle par le<br />

gouvernement Bourassa. Bien qu’exprimant les intérêts de leurs auteurs et que<br />

l’option fédéraliste y soit parfois préconisée, c’est dans ces mémoires qu’on<br />

trouve généralement l’expression des sentiments sur lesquels s’appuie le<br />

projet sécessionniste. Nous les étudierons dans la deuxième partie de ce travail<br />

intitulée : « <strong>La</strong> voix des citoyens ».<br />

Finalement, la troisième catégorie de matériaux qu’a fait naître la Commission<br />

comprend exclusivement des documents soumis par des experts. C’est<br />

généralement là qu’on trouve des analyses approfondies de diverses questions<br />

relatives aux rapports entre le Québec et ses voisins advenant l’accession à<br />

l’indépendance ou tout autre statut constitutionnel. Nous procédérons à l’étude<br />

de ces matériaux dans la troisième et dernière partie de ce travail intitulée:«<strong>La</strong><br />

voix des experts ».<br />

Cette examen en trois temps des travaux de la Commission tente de mieux<br />

cerner l’interaction complexe des facteurs émotifs et rationnels autour<br />

desquels se construit et se déconstruit depuis le 23 juin 1990, date de l’échec de<br />

la ronde constitutionnelle du lac Meech7, l’idée de sécession du Québec.<br />

Penchons- nous d’abord sur l’aspect stratégique de la démarche de la<br />

Commission en analysant brièvement son rapport final.<br />

Le rapport Bélanger-Campeau et la stratégie du gouvernement<br />

Bourassa<br />

En tant qu’instrument stratégique de négociation, le rapport final étonne par<br />

ses ambiguïtés et ses contradictions. Mais avant de l’analyser, décrivons-le<br />

brièvement.<br />

À part la liste des recomm<strong>and</strong>ations et les annexes incluant divers addenda des<br />

commissionnaires exprimant leurs réserves, ce rapport comprend en tout sept<br />

chapitres. De ceux-là, un présente les membres, un autre énonce le m<strong>and</strong>at de<br />

la Commission et deux autres sont consacrés à l’introduction et à la<br />

conclusion. Les éléments de fond se trouvent donc tous dans les chapitres 4, 5<br />

et 6, soit une cinquantaine de pages en tout, en gros caractères et à double<br />

interligne. Que disent ces trois chapitres ?<br />

Le chapitre 4, « Le Québec : une société moderne, une identité propre », brosse<br />

un tableau presque idyllique du dynamisme de la société québécoise<br />

contemporaine. L’idée maîtresse de ce chapitre est que, lorsqu’il l’a voulu, le<br />

Québec a réussi à devenir une société prospère, moderne et cultivée. On lit, en<br />

effet, qu’à partir des années soixante, les Québécois « marquent un tournant<br />

dans la prise en main de leur développement8 » et qu’en conséquence, « le<br />

Québec a donné le coup de barre nécessaire à l’émergence d’une société<br />

moderne, complète et ouverte sur le monde9. » On souligne de plus que « la<br />

place du français dans les communications, le travail, le commerce et les<br />

affaires est ainsi réaffermie et élargie10. »<br />

288


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

Ce chapitre étonne. On se serait attendu à ce qu’un rapport recomm<strong>and</strong>ant un<br />

référendum sur la sécession du Québec mette en relief les insuffisances du<br />

système politique actuel. Mais au lieu d’un constat d’échec, on y trouve une<br />

image reluisante des exploits du Québec sur tous les plans, allant de<br />

l’économie jusqu’à la langue et la culture en passant par le rôle bénéfique du<br />

gouvernement provincial. Ce chapitre surprend d’autant plus qu’au-delà de ce<br />

beau portrait du Québec et de ses institutions, on y trouve également un éloge,<br />

plus modéréré il est vrai, du cadre institutionnel actuel considéré dans sa<br />

globalité.<br />

Contrairement à ce qu’on lit à la page 12 de l’introduction de ce rapport, l’acte<br />

confédératif de 1867 n’est pas présenté ici selon la perspective nationaliste<br />

usuelle d’un « pacte entre deux peuples », mais plutôt à la manière<br />

« fédéraliste », c’est-à-dire comme un acte visant la création d’un « espace<br />

économique qui devait consolider les liens entre les quatre anciennes<br />

colonies11. » Quelques lignes plus loin, on reconnaît même la nécessité de la<br />

centralisation à Ottawa de certains pouvoirs, idée franchement antinationaliste.<br />

On lit, en effet, que « cet espace initial et son développement<br />

ultérieur... on les doit aussi au fait que la <strong>Constitution</strong> de 1867 accorda au<br />

Parlement fédéral de larges pouvoirs... 12 »<br />

L’étonnement gr<strong>and</strong>it qu<strong>and</strong> on voit quelques paragraphes plus loin la <strong>Charte</strong><br />

canadienne des droits et libertés recevoir sa part de louanges. Comme on le<br />

sait, cette <strong>Charte</strong> constitue une des pièces maîtresses de la <strong>Constitution</strong> de<br />

1982, rapatriée sans le consentement du Québec. C’est d’ailleurs pourquoi elle<br />

est souvent décriée, y compris dans ce rapport, comme étant « dépourvue de<br />

légitimité politique faute d’avoir jamais reçu la pleine et libre adhésion du<br />

Québec13. » Pourtant, à la page 25, on lui reconnaît certains effets heureux,<br />

notamment quant à la transférabilité du droit aux programmes sociaux<br />

fédéraux et à la liberté de circulation des citoyens.<br />

On trouve bien dans ce chapitre quelques critiques du cadre fédéral actuel,<br />

mais dans l’ensemble, on y fait surtout un éloge implicite, et parfois même<br />

explicite, de ce cadre si bien que le message central qui s’en dégage est que le<br />

Québec contemporain se porte très bien. Le lecteur est donc mal préparé à la<br />

mise en accusation du fédéralisme à laquelle se livre le chapitre 5 titré<br />

« L’évolution vers l’impasse ».<br />

Après avoir identifié comme origine de « l’impasse » l’échec de l’accord du lac<br />

Meech, le chapitre 5 lance une affirmation déconcertante. On y lit en effet que<br />

« les réformes majeures mises en oeuvre au Québec pendant les années 1960<br />

ont démontré combien était essentielle la révision du partage des<br />

compétences, rendu problématique par l’évolution du régime fédéral14. » Or,<br />

aucune démonstration n’accompagne cette affirmation. Au contraire, comme<br />

on vient de le voir, le chapitre 4 met en relief le fait que le Québec a<br />

parfaitement réussi son passage à la modernité.<br />

Loin de faire la « démonstration » de la nécessité d’un nouveau partage de<br />

pouvoirs, ce chapitre brosse une large fresque des transformations<br />

constitutionnelles récentes et, surtout, à la page 33, présente une liste assez<br />

brève des effets perçus comme négatifs de ces modifications. On y souligne<br />

deux points. D’abord, la réduction de la compétence du Québec dans la langue<br />

d’enseignement (sans noter la protection correspondante du français à travers<br />

le Canada ni la portée de la clause dérogatoire de la <strong>Charte</strong> fréquemment<br />

utilisée par le gouvernement québécois). On y relève ensuite la perte du droit<br />

de veto du Québec sur les modifications constitutionnelles (sans noter que ce<br />

289


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

« veto », purement conventionnel, n’avait pas été « perdu » mais plutôt « cédé »<br />

par le gouvernement Lévesque avant le rapatriement de la <strong>Constitution</strong> en<br />

1982 dans une manoeuvre politique qui arrangeait son Parti).<br />

Essentiellement, ce chapitre insiste bien plus sur la série de blocages dans les<br />

rondes de négociations subséquentes au rapatriement de la <strong>Constitution</strong> en<br />

1982 que sur la justification d’un nouveau partage de pouvoirs.<br />

Le chapitre 6, dernier des trois chapitres de fond, intitulé « Les voies de<br />

solution », trace dans un premier temps les gr<strong>and</strong>es lignes des exigences<br />

constitutionnelles dites « minimales » pour que le Québec demeure au sein du<br />

Canada. De cette première partie se dégage l’impression très nette que ces<br />

« exigences minimales » sont tellement élevées qu’il est improbable qu’elles<br />

soient acceptées par le reste du Canada. <strong>La</strong> conciliation des attentes du Québec<br />

et des intérêts des autres provinces dans le cadre fédéral actuel « nécessiterait,<br />

affirme-t-on, des efforts considérables de la part des membres de la<br />

fédération15. » Cette idée est soulignée en conclusion où il est noté que « les<br />

attentes de la population sont élevées : elle veut voir le Québec récupérer des<br />

compétences dans tous les secteurs, qu’ils soient du domaine économique,<br />

social ou culturel16. » Une fois cela établi — la légitimité des nombreuses<br />

revendications du Québec et l’improbabilité de leur acceptation par le reste du<br />

Canada —, émerge tout naturellement la deuxième voie de solution :«<strong>La</strong><br />

démarche du Québec vers la souveraineté... qui devrait se fonder sur une<br />

volonté populaire incontestable et clairement exprimée17. »<br />

L’ambiguïté ne cesse de gr<strong>and</strong>ir. Le chapitre 4 montre que le Québec se porte<br />

très bien dans le cadre actuel. Le chapitre 5 affirme, sans aucune<br />

démonstration, que le Québec ne contrôle pas dans le cadre fédéral canadien<br />

les pouvoirs essentiels à son développement. Le chapitre 6 d’un côté br<strong>and</strong>it la<br />

menace de la sécession et de l’autre, il se ravise en évoquant la possibilité<br />

d’une refonte du cadre fédéral actuel. C’est sur ces bases que repose la<br />

conclusion du rapport présentée au chapitre 7. Conclusion qui, comme on peut<br />

s’y attendre, s’avère tout aussi ambivalente que le raisonnement sur lequel elle<br />

s’appuie. En effet, la Commission affirme que : « deux voies seulement<br />

s’offrent au Québec : d’une part, une nouvelle et ultime tentative de redéfinir<br />

son statut au sein du régime fédéral et, d’autre part, l’accession à la<br />

souveraineté. »<br />

Ainsi, derrière l’idée maîtresse, et ambivalente, des « deux voies ultimes » se<br />

dessine en filigrane l’idée du renforcement du pouvoir de négociation du<br />

Québec. Étonnamment, le rapport trahit sa propre fonction stratégique dans un<br />

passage en conclusion où l’on affirme que, tout en se préparant pour la<br />

sécession, le Québec devrait mettre « à profit le temps dont il dispose et les<br />

arrangements en vigueur pour étayer son dossier tout en renforçant son<br />

pouvoir de négociation19. »<br />

Il est important de noter ici que ces recomm<strong>and</strong>ations furent explicitement<br />

endossées par le premier ministre lui-même et par son ministre délégué aux<br />

Affaires intergouvernementales canadiennes, Gil Rémillard. Dans une lettre<br />

intégrée au premier des deux addenda accompagnant le rapport, MM.<br />

Bourassa et Rémillard affirmaient qu’à « la croisée des chemins », le Québec<br />

était « non seulement... libre de ses choix mais... maintenant plus en mesure de<br />

les apprécier et de les arrêter grâce au rapport que nous recevons aujourd’hui. »<br />

Ces choix étaient d’après eux bien clairs:«Cerapport nous confirme que deux<br />

avenues doivent être considérées... : un réaménagement en profondeur du<br />

système fédéral actuel ou la souveraineté du Québec. Les autres solutions ne<br />

290


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

sauraient répondre aux besoins et aux aspirations de la société québécoise 20. »<br />

Cette notion des « deux voies»—leréaménagement en profondeur du cadre<br />

fédéral ou la sécession du Québec — fut reprise dans le cadre de la loi 150<br />

adoptée par l’Assemblée nationale selon la recomm<strong>and</strong>ation de la<br />

Commission. En effet, cette loi recomm<strong>and</strong>ait d’une part un référendum sur la<br />

souveraineté, suivi de l’accession proprement dite au statut d’Etat<br />

indépendant, et d’autre part l’institution d’une commission parlementaire<br />

spéciale « ayant pour m<strong>and</strong>at d’apprécier toute offre de nouveau partenariat de<br />

nature constitutionnelle faite par le gouvernement du Canada21. »<br />

Ainsi, le rapport de la Commission, tout comme l’interprétation qu’en<br />

faisaient Bourassa et Rémillard tout comme la loi 150 qui en découlait étaient<br />

marqués d’une double ambiguïté. Premièrement, on présentait une image<br />

contradictoire de la place du Québec au sein du Canada. En effet, alors qu’on<br />

affirmait que le cadre institutionnel actuel convenait parfaitement au Québec,<br />

on affirmait en même temps qu’il était nécessaire de s’en défaire.<br />

Deuxièmement, les « voies de solution » reflétaient cette même contradiction.<br />

Tout en semblant s’engager résolument sur la voie de la sécession, le Québec<br />

offrait au reste du Canada une dernière et « ultime tentative » de<br />

renouvellement du cadre fédéral. Comment expliquer ces ambiguïtés qui ne<br />

pouvaient passer inaperçues et qui risquaient d’affaiblir la position du<br />

Québec ? Comment expliquer que ce « couperet » que le Québec s’apprêtait à<br />

placer sur la gorge du reste du Canada était si mal emmanché ?<br />

Comme nous tenterons de le montrer, l’ambiguïté de ce rapport reflète<br />

l’ambivalence plus profonde qui imprègne l’ensemble des documents que<br />

cette Commission a engendrés. D’une part, le processus de consultation<br />

populaire, qui constituait l’une des deux assises des travaux de la Commission,<br />

déclencha des revendications de toutes sortes que seule la sécession pourrait<br />

satisfaire, disait-on généralement. D’autre part, la plupart des expertises<br />

soumises à la Commission tendaient à freiner ces élans sécessionnistes.<br />

Les deux prochaines sections de ce texte examinent ces tendances. <strong>La</strong><br />

première scrutera la voix des citoyens et la deuxième, celle des experts.<br />

<strong>La</strong> voix des citoyens<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission déclencha un vaste processus de consultation populaire. Elle<br />

se déplaça à travers la province pour écouter un gr<strong>and</strong> nombre d’individus et de<br />

groupes lors d’audiences publiques, souvent télédiffusées. Pendant plusieurs<br />

mois, tout le Québec et, dans une certaine mesure, le reste du Canada étaient à<br />

l’écoute de Bélanger-Campeau. Cette tribune connut un succès retentissant et<br />

plus de 600 mémoires, représentant un large éventail de revendications, furent<br />

reçus. Très souvent, la question du « statut constitutionnel du Québec » ne<br />

servait que de toile de fond à l’expression de doléances diverses. Il n’est donc<br />

pas étonnant que ces quelque 15 000 pages de texte furent résumées en un<br />

document officiel de 27 pages, inodores et sans vie, intitulé Les<br />

préoccupations et les perceptions se dégageant de la consultation populaire et<br />

catégorisé Document de travail numéro 3. S’il est en effet impossible de<br />

« résumer » ces centaines de mémoires, on peut néanmoins y trouver<br />

l’expression de diverses émotions sur lesquelles peut s’appuyer le projet<br />

sécessionniste. Cette section tentera de définir ces sentiments.<br />

291


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Notons d’emblée un fait intéressant. Alors que durant l’épisode « Meech », le<br />

sentiment dominant dans l’univers symbolique du Québéc était<br />

« l’humiliation », mal attribué à « l’exclusion » du Québec de la <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

de 198222, dans le nouvel épisode lancé par Bourassa en juin 1990, ce<br />

traumatisme semble avoir été exorcisé. Les nouveaux sentiments s’expriment<br />

généralement sur un régistre plus combatif.<br />

Dans une étude récente sur le nationalisme québécois, Stéphane Dion met en<br />

lumière deux sentiments en apparence contradictoires qui favorisent, selon lui,<br />

la montée du sécessionnisme :<br />

Any secessionist movement is rooted in two anti<strong>the</strong>tical feelings: fear<br />

<strong>and</strong> confidence. <strong>The</strong> fear is of being weakened or even disappearing<br />

as a distinct people...; <strong>the</strong> confidence is that it can perform as well, or<br />

even better, on its own 23 .<br />

En effet, ces deux sentiments de confiance en soi et de peur de disparaître<br />

marquent profondément l’univers symbolique de la vague récente du<br />

sécessionnisme au Québec. Cependant, la lecture des travaux de la<br />

Commission revèle également la force d’au moins deux autres sentiments : la<br />

foi en un Québec souverain et le dénigrement du Canada et de son cadre<br />

fédéral. Examinons de plus près la manifestation de ces sentiments dans les<br />

mémoires soumis à la Commission.<br />

Le mémoire du <strong>Conseil</strong> du patronat du Québec, une des rares voix<br />

profédéralistes, fait le point sur les progrès accomplis par les élites<br />

francophones. Rédigé par André Raynauld, qui a minutieusement décrit dans<br />

les années cinquante le contrôle anglophone et étranger de l’économie<br />

québécoise, ce mémoire met en relief un revirement absolument spectaculaire.<br />

Par exemple, alors qu’en 1961, les francophones ne contrôlaient que 47,1 p.<br />

100 de l’économie québécoise, ce contrôle passait à 61,6 p. 100 en 1987. Ces<br />

données, et de nombreuses autres, l’amènent à affirmer que « les francophones<br />

ont investi le monde de l’entreprise comme ils avaient investi l’agriculture<br />

autrefois. Sans attendre la souveraineté, ils sont devenus une collectivité<br />

normale dans un univers normal24. » Ce sont des constatations analogues que<br />

l’on retrouve souvent dans les analyses de l’économie québécoise25 et qui<br />

illustrent un aspect clé du modèle de développement appelé communément<br />

« Québec Inc. ».<br />

Il s’agit là de la montée d’une élite économique qui, dans les termes de<br />

Raynauld, est devenue « normale » en faisant la démonstration, surtout envers<br />

elle-même, que le monde des affaires n’avait rien de sorcier. Enivrée par<br />

l’expansion économique des années 1983 à 1987, alliée au gouvernement<br />

provincial dans sa conquête du monde des affaires, cette élite pensait, tant que<br />

l’expansion des années quatre-vingts durait, que rien ne pouvait l’arrêter.<br />

D’ailleurs, le rapport final, dans ses multiples louanges de la vitalité du Québec<br />

contemporain, souligne notamment le fait que « la vigueur économique du<br />

Québec repose aujourd’hui sur la compétitivité des entreprises du secteur<br />

privé26. »<br />

Ce thème revient très fréquemment dans de nombreux mémoires. <strong>La</strong> Chambre<br />

de commerce de Québec, par exemple, relève fièrement la réputation acquise<br />

par cette nouvelle élite :<br />

292


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

L’orientation récente de la politique économique au Québec lui<br />

confère déjà une solide crédibilité en matière de libertés<br />

économiques, d’appui à l’économie privée et de recherche de<br />

compétitivité législative et fiscale 27 .<br />

À ce sentiment de confiance en soi et de progrès, qui alimente l’idée<br />

d’indépendance, s’allie le sentiment que le Canada, lui, régresse. C’est ainsi<br />

que le mémoire de la Chambre de commerce, comme d’ailleurs de nombreux<br />

autres, établit un parallélisme hâtif entre l’essor du Québec et « l’échec » du<br />

Canada :<br />

Il est important que les changements constitutionnels proposés par le<br />

Québec contribuent à corriger les vices du système fédéral qui ont pu<br />

entraîner le gouvernement central dans la débâcle financière<br />

actuelle 28 .<br />

Ces mots « vices » et « débâcle », lourds de sens, font allusion, bien sûr, à<br />

l’énorme déficit du Canada, mais aussi au fait que le gouvernement fédéral<br />

aurait, selon la Chambre de commerce, « perdu le contrôle sur ses dépenses » et<br />

favorisé « d’une manière tout à fait disproportionnée des taux d’intérêt<br />

élevés. » Ce mémoire critique par ailleurs le principe même du fédéralisme qui<br />

favorise « un coûteux chevauchement des compétences législatives » et donc<br />

le grossissement des structures administratives. D’où l’accusation fracassante<br />

et conforme aux discours nationalistes de l’heure : « Le fédéralisme pratiqué au<br />

Canada est un échec économique. »<br />

Mais ce n’est pas seulement sur le plan économique que « l’échec » du<br />

fédéralisme est dénoncé. Nombreux sont les mémoires qui présentent le<br />

gouvernement central comme une grosse bureaucratie assoiffée de pouvoir. <strong>La</strong><br />

Société nationale des Québécois (section Richelieu- Yamaska), par exemple,<br />

présente l’histoire du Canada, de 1759 à 1990, sous l’angle de la lutte éternelle<br />

du Québec contre les empiètements injustifiés du « Canada anglais » :<br />

Le gouvernement fédéral n’a jamais cessé de prendre de plus en plus<br />

de place et de s’approprier des pouvoirs qui étaient pourtant réservés<br />

au Québec 31 .<br />

Cette idée apparaît à maintes reprises et de diverses manières tout au long du<br />

texte. Ainsi, loin d’en rappeler la « gr<strong>and</strong>e noirceur », on reconnaît au régime<br />

Duplessis le mérite d’avoir vaillamment résistéà«lasoif de centralisation du<br />

fédéral32. »<br />

Cette vision d’un Québec, véritable Sisyphe, qui lutte éternellement et<br />

futilement contre les ingérences d’Ottawa est très fréquente. On la retrouve,<br />

par exemple, dans les mémoires des trois centrales syndicales les plus<br />

influentes : la CEQ, la CSN et la FTQ. Rejetant « le carcan fédéral » la CSN<br />

affirme même que :<br />

L’idée d’un Canada incluant le Québec n’a toujours été qu’une<br />

illusion... implantée de force qui n’a jamais vraiment su s’incarner et<br />

répondre aux aspirations de la minorité francophone 33 .<br />

Pareillement, la C.E.Q. reproche au Canada d’être un régime quasi fédéral<br />

étouffant pour le Québec 34.<br />

293


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Sans s’encombrer de preuves, de nombreux mémoires présentent si<br />

fréquemment cette image d’un Québec résistant héroïquement à l’ingérence<br />

néfaste du pouvoir central qu’il serait fastidieux d’en énumérer ici les<br />

nombreuses variantes. Contentons-nous d’en signaler deux autres : l’une<br />

provenant d’un mouvement de jeunes et l’autre, du milieu universitaire.<br />

Selon le <strong>Conseil</strong> permanent de la jeunesse, la souveraineté du Québec<br />

s’impose parce que les jeunes Québécois souhaitent se développer dans une<br />

société qui « agit pour une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e équité et une plus gr<strong>and</strong>e justice<br />

sociale... qui priorise... la qualité de l’environnement... [la lutte contre le<br />

chômage et la pauvreté... et qui donne] aux gens des régions les pouvoirs<br />

nécessaires à leur plein épanouissement... » Or, affirment sans aucune<br />

démonstration les auteurs de ce mémoire, ceci ne peut se réaliser dans le cadre<br />

actuel parce que :<br />

L’histoire démontre clairement que le fédéralisme canadien, tel<br />

qu’on le connaît, ne peut répondre aux aspirations du Québec et que<br />

les multiples tentatives de modifier les choses... se sont soldées par<br />

des échecs 35 .<br />

L’Université du Québec, l’une des universités québécoises les plus<br />

importantes pour ce qui est de la population étudiante, semble partager cette<br />

opinion. En effet, d’après elle, en dépit de la résistance acharnée du Québec, le<br />

gouvernement central : « a malgré tout réussi à instituer les modes<br />

d’intervention qui perturbent le développement des universités<br />

québécoises 36. » D’ailleurs, ajoute-t-elle sans plus de démonstration, le<br />

« Canada anglais » n’a jamais rien compris au Québec :<br />

Le Québec constitue une société distincte. C’est là un fait avéré, que<br />

seules les instances politiques du Canada anglais s’obstinent à ne pas<br />

reconnaître 37 .<br />

On voit donc comment trois notions reviennent fréquemment pour rejeter et<br />

dénigrer tout ce qui a trait au Canada, au système fédéral et au gouvernement<br />

central : le Canada est une idée « imposée de force » aux francophones; le<br />

régime fédéral est essentiellement l’histoire d’un « échec » qui « étouffe » le<br />

Québec; le gouvernement central ne cherche qu’à « s’ingérer » dans ce qui ne<br />

le regarde pas et, en dépit de toute la vigilance des Québécois, ses interventions<br />

sont toujours « perturbantes. »<br />

D’un point de vue stratégique, ce type de discours peut aisément renforcer la<br />

voie sécessionniste préconisée par la Commission. Il est cependant important<br />

de noter que Léon Dion lui-même, qui préconisait la stratégie du « couteau sur<br />

la gorge », sentit le besoin de rappeler que : « contrairement à l’opinion reçue<br />

au Québec, le Canada est une fédération fortement décentralisée... » Il souligna<br />

également que le Québec avait bénéficié de son appartenance au Canada :<br />

Il ne faudrait pas oublier que les liens qui unissent le Québec au<br />

Canada lui ont été bénéfiques au cours de la décennie 1940 et de<br />

celles qui ont suivi 38 .<br />

Cette insistance sur la distanciation entre le Québec et le reste du Canada, qui<br />

semble au coeur du sentiment sécessionniste, se retrouve tant dans le mémoire<br />

de l’Université du Québec que dans ceux des centrales syndicales, des<br />

294


Chambres de commerce, du Mouvement des Caisses Desjardins, de l’Union<br />

des producteurs agricoles, des groupes de femmes des groupes de jeunes. Ces<br />

mémoires « oublient » régulièrement que c’est au sein du Canada que<br />

l’épanouissement du Québec s’est réalisé.<br />

De plus, souvent les intervenants sont tellement pris par leur propres<br />

problèmes qu’ils accordent peu ou pas de place à la question de l’heure, c’està-dire<br />

au statut constitutionnel du Québec. Professant leur foi en un Québec<br />

souverain, ils espèrent que celui-ci résoudra les problèmes qui leur tiennent à<br />

coeur.<br />

À titre d’exemple, le mémoire d’un groupe de centres de femmes affirme, sans<br />

aucune forme de démonstration, « qu’il ne fait aucun doute qu’un Québec<br />

indépendant est la solution à la sauvegarde de la langue et la culture39. » Cette<br />

confiance débordante ne les empêche pas cependant, deux pages plus loin de<br />

l’assortir de conditions : « Oui à un Québec souverain si... » Suit une très<br />

longue liste de revendications qui constitue l’essentiel du mémoire. Par<br />

exemple :<br />

UN QUÉBEC SOUVERAIN SI :<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

Il met en place des mesures sociales adéquates favorisant la place des<br />

femmes dans la société... 40<br />

Les auteures de ce mémoire imaginent un Québec indépendant doté d’un<br />

meilleur système de sécurité sociale.<br />

Dans un même élan de confiance, le Mouvement Desjardins imagine, lui, un<br />

Québec indépendant tout à fait en contradiction avec cette dernière vision. En<br />

effet, soutient-il, non seulement le Canada freine le Québec par sa rigidité et<br />

son incapacité de s’adapter au nouvel environnement international mais, en<br />

plus, ses programmes de sécurité sociale constituent un fardeau trop lourd à<br />

porter. Reconnaissant la générosité envers le Québec des programmes<br />

fédéraux dans ces domaines, le mémoire déplore cependant l’utilisation de<br />

sommes considérables à des fins si peu productives :<br />

Il faut souligner que ces dépenses ne font que soutenir le pouvoir<br />

d’achat de personnes démunies, de façon temporaire ou permanente,<br />

mais qu’elles sont loin d’être aussi productives, sur le plan<br />

économique, que des engagements consacrés à la recherche... 41 .<br />

Critiquant ainsi certains programmes d’assistance sociale, contrastant cette<br />

forme d’intervention du gouvernement central avec celle du gouvernement<br />

québécois, comme s’il s’agissait de deux pays distincts, le mémoire affirme<br />

que c’est l’encouragement des initiatives privées qui fut la source de<br />

l’expansion économique du Québec.<br />

Ce faisant, le Mouvement Desjardins passe sous silence deux aspects<br />

importants de cette question. Premièrement, s’il était souverain, c’est le<br />

Québec qui aurait eu à financer son système de sécurité sociale.<br />

Deuxièmement, la péréquation n’existant plus, ce système pourrait coûter plus<br />

cher au Québec surtout s’il décidait, par exemple, de répondre aux<br />

revendications du mémoire du groupe de femmes cité plus haut.<br />

Mémoire après mémoire, groupe après groupe, on retrouve cette même<br />

conviction qu’un Québec souverain solutionnerait ses propres problèmes.<br />

295


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Pour les femmes, un Québec souverain aurait des programmes de sécurité<br />

sociale plus généreux; pour le Mouvement Desjardins, il élaguerait l’État-<br />

Providence. Pour la Chambre de Commerce, il encouragerait davantage la<br />

liberté des échanges; pour les associations syndicales, il ferait le contraire. Ce<br />

qui étonne, c’est non la divergence des solutions proposées, mais la<br />

convergence fréquente dans l’identification de la source des problèmes.<br />

Autant on attribue à la structure fédérale actuelle la cause de tous les maux,<br />

sans que les intervenants n’en ressentent une responsabilité quelconque, autant<br />

on proclame sa foi dans la dynamique sociale positive qui prévaudrait dans cet<br />

hypothétique État indépendant.<br />

D’autre part, comme on l’a noté plus haut, un autre sentiment alimente aussi<br />

les poussées sécessionnistes : la crainte de « disparaître ». On sait que sur le<br />

plan démographique, le Québec subit les effets négatifs conjugués de deux<br />

phénomènes : la dénatalité et l’émigration. Dans le passé, la « revanche des<br />

berceaux », encouragée par le clergé, a donné au Québec un des plus hauts taux<br />

de natalité de l’Occident. Mais comme le constate le démographe Henripin, les<br />

moeurs ont changé avec une rapidité foudroyante et les Québécois et les<br />

Québécoises<br />

se sont... lancés avec une rare hardiesse dans le recours à la méthode<br />

la plus destructrice de la nature : la stérilisation 42 .<br />

Mais peu importe la méthode, le fait est que le taux de fécondité du Québec est<br />

tombé de 3,78 en 1951 à 1,43 en 1986, soit un des taux de fertilité les plus bas<br />

du monde43. Bien que ce taux soit récemment remonté à 1,7, il se situe encore<br />

bien en dessous du taux minimal de 2,1 requis pour maintenir la population à<br />

son niveau actuel. C’est ce qui explique qu’une étude comm<strong>and</strong>itée par le<br />

<strong>Conseil</strong> de la langue française prévoit que la part du Québec dans la population<br />

totale du Canada passera de 26,5 p. 100 en 1981 à 24,1 p. 100 en 202144. Il n’est pas étonnant que ces projections inquiètent les Québécois, et surtout les<br />

Québécois francophones. <strong>La</strong> décroissance démographique du Québec peut<br />

signifier une diminution de son poids politique et donc, possiblement, la perte<br />

de la vitalité du français en Amérique. Telle est la leçon que tirent, presque<br />

immanquablement, de nombreux organismes nationalistes.<br />

Le mémoire du Mouvement national des Québécois (section de Montréal) en<br />

est une frappante illustration. Près des deux tiers sont consacrés à ce problème<br />

qui, aux yeux de ce Mouvement, présente un double danger : d’abord sur le<br />

plan des relations externes du Québec avec ses voisins anglophones; danger<br />

également sur le plan interne, puisqu’un Québec vieillissant et stagnant serait<br />

moins productif et plus coûteux. S’appuyant sur des sources scientifiques<br />

fiables, les auteurs écrivent :<br />

Tous les signes apparaissent d’un rapide déclin démographique aux<br />

conséquences désastreuses.... [il faut] regarder en face le problème le<br />

plus troublant de notre histoire collective : celui de notre survie 45 .<br />

Notant la baisse du taux de natalité, les pertes du Québec en terme de<br />

migrations interprovinciales et le faible apport de l’immigration<br />

internationale, le mémoire ne camoufle pas le problème:<br />

296<br />

Bref l’immigration est nécessaire mais pas suffisante. <strong>La</strong> natalité est<br />

nécessaire mais peu assurée.


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

À ce problème bien réel, et fort complexe, analysé avec lucidité, les auteurs<br />

n’offrent comme solution que leur foi dans l’indépendance du Québec :<br />

Le Québec n’a pas le choix. S’il veut maîtriser son avenir, il lui faut<br />

rapidement disposer de tous les moyens d’un pays complet pour agir<br />

sur l’évolution de la population 46 .<br />

Ici, comme dans de nombreux autres mémoires, le lien entre le problème (par<br />

exemple, la crainte de disparaître), et la solution envisagée (la sécession), est<br />

affirmé plutôt qu’établi.<br />

Pour résumer cette première partie, rappelons qu’une diversité de sentiments<br />

sous-tendent les velléités sécessionnistes du Québec. D’une part, conscients<br />

de la fragilité du fait français et des progrès notoires du Québec francophone<br />

contemporain, nombreux sont les mémoires qui expriment simultanément la<br />

crainte des Québécois de disparaître et leur confiance en leur capacité de faire<br />

face à l’avenir tout seuls. D’autre part, le poids de la dette nationale, les<br />

déchirements internes autour de négociations constitutionnelles qui semblent<br />

sans issue et les nombreux autres problèmes auquels le Canada fait face<br />

légitiment la vieille habitude d’accuser « Ottawa » de tous les maux. On<br />

constate ainsi, dans la plupart des mémoires, une absence presque totale de<br />

référence aux bienfaits dérivés du Canada ainsi que du poids considérable dont<br />

jouit le Québec au sein de la fédération. Par exemple, le fait que, depuis plus<br />

d’un quart de siècle, le Premier ministre du Canada ait été québécois et que le<br />

Québec ait constitué l’axe central de la base électorale du parti au pouvoir<br />

n’occupe aucune place dans les analyses présentées.<br />

Au delà des faits, c’est la convergence de ces sentiments, et de beaucoup<br />

d’autres, qui accentue l’identification de nombreux Québécois à la « nation »<br />

québécoise et affaiblit le sentiment d’appartenance au Canada. Perçu, sinon<br />

comme un pays étranger, du moins comme une « super-structure politique » —<br />

dans les termes du premier ministre Bourassa —, le Canada doit ainsi faire tous<br />

les jours la preuve qu’il mérite de survivre. Alors que les sentiments affectifs<br />

sont canalisés vers le Québec, les calculs utilitaristes portent sur le Canada et<br />

son cadre fédéral.<br />

Il convient donc de voir si, aux yeux des experts consultés par la Commission,<br />

cette « super-structure » répond encore aux besoins et intérêts du Québec.<br />

<strong>La</strong> voix des experts<br />

Examinons maintenant le point de vue des spécialistes consultés par la<br />

Commission Bélanger-Campeau. Ce sont les « documents de travail » numéro<br />

1 et numéro 2 que nous privilégierons, car c’est surtout là que l’on trouve des<br />

analyses approfondies des questions touchant l’accession à l’indépendance.<br />

Le premier traite des questions économiques et le second, des questions<br />

juridiques, institutionnelles et démographiques. Nous examinerons d’abord<br />

les aspects « démolinguistiques » de la question, puis ses aspects économiques<br />

et, enfin, ceux d’ordre « juridique » et « institutionnel ».<br />

Les aspects démolinguistiques<br />

Comme nous l’avons vu, la « peur de disparaître » est étroitement liée au déclin<br />

de la population du Québec. Par contre, la solution préconisée, comme<br />

l’illustre le mémoire du Mouvement national des Québécois, est, elle, moins<br />

concrète et consiste souvent en un simple acte de foi dans l’indépendance du<br />

297


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Québec. Comment les spécialistes consultés par la Commission analysent-ils<br />

cette question ?<br />

Cette tâche fut confiée à Marc Termote, démographe bien connu à l’INRS.<br />

Celui-ci confirme la possibilité très réelle du déclin démographique :<br />

Tous les auteurs de perspectives récentes semblent donc arriver à un<br />

consensus : si le « cours des choses » ne se modifie pas rapidement et<br />

drastiquement, les effectifs de la population québécoise (et<br />

montréalaise) devraient commencer à décroître au cours du prochain<br />

demi-siècle 47 .<br />

Poursuivant son analyse, il examine les trois principales sources<br />

d’accroissement de la population — la fécondité, l’immigration internationale<br />

et les flux migratoires inter-provinciaux — afin d’évaluer les effets de la baisse<br />

de population sur les divers groupes linguistiques du Québec.<br />

Concernant le taux de fécondité, Termote confirme qu’en dépit d’une légère<br />

hausse, celui-ci reste nettement inférieur au niveau requis pour assurer le<br />

maintien de la population. De ce fait, dit-il, « le groupe français du Québec a<br />

perdu ce qui représentait son seul atout démographique par rapport au groupe<br />

anglais48. »<br />

Du point de vue de l’immigration internationale, l’auteur note que celle-ci<br />

apporte peu au groupe francophone : environ 20 000 en cinq ans (en 1981-<br />

1986) 49.<br />

Quant aux flux migratoires interprovinciaux, trois facteurs importants<br />

affectent négativement l’évolution démographique du Québec. D’abord, le<br />

groupe anglophone ne cesse de décliner tant relativement qu’absolument. Ce<br />

déclin, amorcé depuis les années 1930, s’est gr<strong>and</strong>ement accentué entre 1976<br />

et 1986, soit depuis l’arrivée au pouvoir du gouvernement sécessionniste du<br />

Parti québécois (de 12,8 p. 100 de la population en 1976 à 10,3 p. 100 en<br />

198650). D’autre part, étant donné que ce sont les personnes âgées de 20 à 39<br />

ans qui quittent le Québec, le groupe anglophone décline et veillit51. Enfin, l’apport, même faible, des immigrants se combine à un solde migratoire<br />

net en faveur des autres provinces. Termote ajoute un fait peu connu et bien<br />

surprenant :<br />

Les immigrants en provenance des pays francophones ne manifestent<br />

pas une propension plus élevée à rester au Québec, au contraire 52 .<br />

Non seulement le Québec n’attire pas assez d’immigrants, mais il n’arrive pas<br />

à les retenir, peu importe leur langue maternelle. Par ailleurs, Termote relève la<br />

très faible mobilité des francophones originaires du Québec contrairement à la<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>e mobilité des anglophones :<br />

Le Québec apparaît vraiment déconnecté du reste du Canada, sauf en<br />

ce qui concerne les anglophones (et encore est-ce pour en sortir...) 53<br />

Projetant toutes ces données vers l’avenir, il conclut :<br />

298<br />

Selon toute probabilité, on parlera de plus en plus le français au<br />

Québec... Mais ce sont des Québécois de moins en moins nombreux<br />

qui le parleront 54 .


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

Ainsi, l’analyse de Termote revèle que le vrai problème du Québec ne réside<br />

pas dans son « anglicisation », mais dans sa dépopulation. À ce grave<br />

problème, Termote n’offre pas de solution tranchée. Il se contente plutôt de<br />

suggérer quelques hypothèses qui pourraient faciliter la recherche de<br />

solutions.<br />

Premièrement, dit-il, même si le taux de fécondité remontait à des niveaux<br />

élevés et, hypothèse peu probable, s’y maintenait, « cela ne ferait que retarder<br />

de dix ans (2016) le début de la décroissance55. » Deuxièmement, même si<br />

l’immigration atteignait 42 000 personnes par an et qu’elle se maintenait à ce<br />

niveau, l’année 2016 marquerait toujours le début de la décroissance56. Selon<br />

Termote, le chiffre de 42 000 semble fort improbable, puisqu’il n’a été atteint<br />

que très rarement et seulement dans des périodes de forte expansion<br />

économique.<br />

L’étude scientifique rigoureuse de cet expert met en relief la complexité du<br />

problème qui se prête mal à une solution tranchée, comme celle que préconise<br />

la Société nationale des Québécois. C’est pourquoi Termote suggère qu’avant<br />

d’envisager des mesures draconiennes, le Québec devrait essayer, très<br />

sérieusement, d’enrayer l’exode de ses résidents :<br />

Un afflux majeur d’immigrants internationaux serait d’ailleurs moins<br />

nécessaire si l’on parvenait à au moins garder ceux que l’on a 57 .<br />

Alors que la voix des citoyens dictait un changement radical appuyé sur la foi<br />

en un Québec indépendant, la voix des experts évoque plutôt des réformes<br />

pondérées dans un climat social favorisant la tranquilité et la sécurité. <strong>La</strong><br />

sécession favorise-t-elle la réalisation d’un tel climat social ?<br />

Pour répondre à cette question, tournons-nous de nouveau vers les spécialistes<br />

consultés par la Commission. Nous examinerons d’abord les questions d’ordre<br />

économique, puis celles d’ordre « juridique » et « institutionnel ».<br />

Les aspects économiques<br />

On évalue souvent les conséquences économiques de la sécession du Québec<br />

en répondant à deux types de questions : le Canada est-il « rentable »?un<br />

Québec souverain serait-il « viable » ? Ces questions lancent les débats sur de<br />

mauvaises pistes. En effet, l’une renvoie à une guerre de chiffres et donc à des<br />

interprétations inévitablement très élastiques de données très complexes.<br />

L’autre présuppose qu’il suffit d’avoir démontré la « viabilité » de la<br />

souveraineté pour avoir démontré sa nécessité. Or, de toute évidence, un<br />

Québec souverain serait viable. Nombreux sont les pays souverains qui<br />

disposent de ressources matérielles et humaines bien inférieures à celles du<br />

Québec. D’ailleurs, et fort justement, la question qui se posait à la Commission<br />

n’était pas de savoir si un Québec souverain serait viable, mais si l’on vivrait<br />

mieux ou moins bien dans un Québec souverain que dans le Québec actuel.<br />

Quel est son verdict ?<br />

Les analyses des spécialistes consultés par la Commission permettent<br />

d’entrevoir une réalité autre que celle qu’on trouve dans les mémoires<br />

mentionnés plus haut. L’étude de Pierre Fortin, un des chapitres clés du<br />

Document de travail numéro 1 sur l’économie, en est une bonne illustration.<br />

Examinons-le.<br />

299


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Analysant le problème du chômage, Fortin note que même dans une bonne<br />

année, comme 1988, « le taux de chômage au Québec est demeuré parmi les<br />

plus élevés du continent (9,4 p. 100) 58. » Il note également que la situation<br />

s’aggrave et que, de 1966 à 1989, la hausse du chômage était « deux fois plus<br />

importante que la dérive qu’a connue l’Ontario59. »<br />

Fortin cerne systématiquement les sources de l’accroissement du chômage,<br />

dont certaines, selon lui, pourraient être indirectement attribuables au cadre<br />

fédéral. C’est ainsi qu’il déplore, par exemple, l’accès plus facile aux<br />

prestations d’assurance-chômage résultant de la refonte, en 1971, de la loi<br />

fédérale :<br />

Cette loi a considérablement allégé les conditions d’accès aux<br />

indemnités-chômage et fait augmenté... la fréquence et la durée du<br />

chômage... 60<br />

Fortin déplore également une autre source de chômage sous contrôle fédéral :<br />

« la persistance du chômage engendrée par la lutte incessante contre<br />

l’inflation61. »<br />

Cependant, parmi les nombreuses autres causes qu’il signale, certaines, selon<br />

lui, ne sont attribuables qu’au Québec, notamment l’effet « locomotive » de la<br />

hausse du salaire minimum, « la poussée des salaires de 1970 à 1980 dans les<br />

conventions collectives du secteur public62, » ainsi que l’exode de l’élite<br />

anglophone de Montréal qui aurait « accentué les difficultés de la<br />

métropole63. »<br />

Le portrait complexe et subtil qui se dégage de cette étude ne ressemble guère à<br />

celui des nombreux mémoires qui, comme on l’a vu, attribuent<br />

automatiquement tous les maux québécois au fédéralisme canadien à moins,<br />

bien sûr, que l’on ne suppose qu’un Québec indépendant s’en tirerait en<br />

réduisant les prestations d’assurance-chômage et en ab<strong>and</strong>onnant la lutte<br />

contre l’inflation. On trouve ces solutions simplistes dans certains mémoires<br />

(la première émanant souvent des milieux d’affaires, la deuxième, du monde<br />

syndical et des groupes populaires). Au contraire, Fortin présente une analyse<br />

rigoureuse et équilibrée.<br />

Tout au long du texte, Fortin met en relief le poids de ce qu’il appelle les<br />

« causes structurelles » du chômage. Selon lui, un Québec souverain, même<br />

s’il gérait d’une manière autonome sa politique monétaire et son taux de<br />

change, ne parviendrait pas « à maintenir le plein emploi de ses travailleurs<br />

dans le contexte inflationniste contemporain, puisque le chômage québécois<br />

est en partie élevé pour des raisons structurelles importantes64. » Toute<br />

l’analyse de fond du texte, développée dans les deux parties centrales du<br />

document, l’une intitulée « <strong>La</strong> photo » et l’autre « Le film », soit cinquante des<br />

soixante-quatorze pages, est consacrée à l’étude de ces causes structurelles.<br />

Ainsi, l’image qui se dégage de la lecture de ce document, c’est que la<br />

sécession ne constitue pas la solution au problème du chômage, puisque ces<br />

« causes structurelles » perdureraient. De plus, advenant la sécession, Fortin<br />

souligne, à plusieurs reprises, la nécessité pour le Québec d’établir des<br />

relations étroites avec le Canada et les États-Unis « en raison de sa forte<br />

intégration financière et commerciale au continent65. »<br />

En conclusion de cette analyse, Pierre Fortin note en passant que : « Bien que le<br />

fait soit encore peu connu, nous avons vécu depuis 1982 au Québec une forme<br />

spontanée d’action directe sur les salaires et les prix66. » Au Québec, affirme-t-<br />

300


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

il, sans avoir au préalable développé cette idée dans les sections analytiques,<br />

les syndicats et les entreprises ont déjà fait preuve d’esprit de modération et de<br />

conciliation. De plus, ajoute-t-il, toujours sans autre forme de preuve, l’esprit<br />

communautaire des Québécois s’épanouira encore plus dans un Québec<br />

indépendant et leur permettra de résoudre leurs problèmes mieux que le reste<br />

du Canada :<br />

Il n’est pas évident que la dynamique socio-politique canadienne se<br />

prêterait facilement à ce type de pratique. Mais l’esprit<br />

communautaire qui caractérise le Québec augmenterait certainement<br />

les chances de réussite d’une telle démarche chez nous 67 .<br />

Après un diagnostic très rigoureux du problème, Fortin évoque comme remède<br />

« l’esprit communautaire » des Québécois. Ce contraste entre la gr<strong>and</strong>e rigueur<br />

de l’analyse et la solution souhaitée est d’autant plus surprenant qu’il affirme,<br />

par ailleurs, que la politique canadienne des années soixante-dix du contrôle<br />

des prix et des salaires « a produit de bons résultats en permettant au taux<br />

d’inflation de baisser 68. » Ainsi, selon Fortin lui-même, « l’esprit<br />

communautaire » a déjà fait ses preuves dans l’ensemble du Canada et ne<br />

distingue donc pas le Québec du reste du Canada. Par ailleurs, Pierre Fortin<br />

affirmait :<br />

Mon mémoire à la Commission vise précisément à démontrer... que<br />

la menace de souveraineté politique br<strong>and</strong>ie par nos concitoyens est<br />

parfaitement crédible sur le plan économique et qu’il faut la prendre<br />

au sérieux 69 .<br />

Mais, comme on l’a vu, la « crédibilité économique » de la sécession n’a pas<br />

vraiment été établie dans la cinquantaine de pages d’analyse, elle a plutôt été<br />

évoquée en quelques lignes en conclusion. Pierre Fortin a peut-être contribué à<br />

rendre « la menace » plus crédible.<br />

Il est impossible d’examiner ici tout le Document de travail numéro 1 sur<br />

l’économie. Soulignons cependant que bien que la « viabilité » d’un Québec<br />

indépendant ne soit jamais mise en doute, immanquablement tous les auteurs<br />

soulignent la nécessité absolue du maintien de liens très étroits avec le reste du<br />

Canada.<br />

Par exemple, dans le chapitre 2, produit par le secrétariat de la Commission, on<br />

lit que l’espace économique canadien dans lequel le Québec est fortement<br />

ancré sert bien les intérêts des Québécois. Les auteurs rappellent, par exemple,<br />

le fait bien connu que l’industrie laitière du Québec, un des piliers de son<br />

économie, bénéficie gr<strong>and</strong>ement du cadre politique canadien70. Le secrétariat<br />

ajoute en outre que le Québec « est la province dont les industries<br />

manufacturières sont les plus protégées par la politique commerciale<br />

canadienne71. » On apprend d’ailleurs que l’intégration du Québec aux<br />

marchés canadien et américain est si profonde que celui-ci aurait tout intérêt,<br />

advenant sa sécession, à calquer sa politique monétaire sur celle du Canada.<br />

Autrement, « il verrait rapidement sa monnaie se déprécier, son inflation et ses<br />

taux d’intérêts augmenter72. » En fait, le secrétariat n’hésite pas à<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>er tout simplement que le Québec « poursui[ve] l’utilisation d’une<br />

monnaie commune73. » Ces faits, parmi bien d’autres, l’amènent à<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>er avec vigueur le maintien de liens très étroits entre le Québec et<br />

ses voisins :<br />

301


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

Le maintien de l’accès [aux marchés du Canada et des États-Unis] est<br />

une condition essentielle à la prospérité économique du Québec, et<br />

ce, quel que soit son statut politique et constitutionnel 74 .<br />

Dans un autre texte analysant « Les options monétaires d’un Québec<br />

souverain », l’auteur, Bernard Fortin, montre que l’adoption d’une monnaie<br />

québécoise produirait des coûts « non négligeables » qui, précise-t-il,<br />

« auraient tendance à s’accroître avec le degré d’indépendance monétaire du<br />

Québec vis-à-vis le Canada75. » Ainsi, plus le Québec s’éloigne du Canada<br />

plus les coûts augmentent. C’est ce qui amène l’auteur à recomm<strong>and</strong>er une<br />

union monétaire avec le Canada76. Daniel Racette reprend cette même idée dans un autre chapitre, mais cette fois<br />

sous l’angle de l’accès aux marchés financiers. Notant la gr<strong>and</strong>e mobilité des<br />

capitaux dans le monde contemporain, ainsi que la concurrence intense des<br />

divers marchés financiers, l’auteur insiste sur la nécessité pour le Québec de<br />

s’entendre avec le reste du Canada. Un nouvel État québécois aurait tout<br />

avantage, affirme-t-il, à adhérer [à une entente avec le reste du Canada] pour<br />

bénéficier dès le départ de la crédibilité que cette entente permettra77. Texte après texte toutes les recomm<strong>and</strong>ations vont dans le même sens. Le<br />

Québec devrait s’employer à maintenir le marché commun avec le Canada. Il<br />

devrait adopter sa monnaie, sa politique monétaire, sa politique financière, et<br />

ainsi de suite. On s’aperçoit même que, advenant la sécession, le traité de libreéchange<br />

avec les États-Unis et le Mexique, si souvent perçu comme essentiel<br />

au développement économique du Québec, ne s’appliquerait pas<br />

automatiquement ni dans les mêmes conditions. C’est ce que le secrétariat<br />

concède dans un style assez hermétique :<br />

Il y a donc tout lieu de croire qu’en l’absence d’un accord entre les<br />

États-Unis et le Canada pour modifier l’Accord de libre-échange<br />

existant en vue d’y intégrer le Québec, il ne saurait être question, pour<br />

ce dernier, d’une succession d’États de plein droit. Il n’est pas<br />

impossible cependant que l’Accord devienne applicable au<br />

Québec... 78<br />

Et c’est ainsi que texte après texte, on retrouve les mêmes mises en garde :<br />

advenant la souveraineté du Québec, la première tâche de ce nouvel État<br />

devrait être... de rétablir des liens très étroits avec le Canada ! Ou d’assumer<br />

des « coûts de transition » élevés.<br />

Pierre Fortin traite de cette dernière « option » avec humour dans un texte<br />

moins spécialisé intitulé « Le passage à la souveraineté et le déficit budgétaire<br />

du Québec ». Examinant les effets du partage de la dette fédérale advenant la<br />

sécession du Québec, Fortin évalueà7p.100duPIBledéficit budgétaire du<br />

nouvel État, déficit qui serait « le plus élevé des gr<strong>and</strong>s pays industriels<br />

avancés, à l’exception de l’Italie79; » ce qui l’amène à adresser des mises en<br />

garde très sévères aux gestionnaires des fonds publics. Il recomm<strong>and</strong>e en<br />

particulier, un « vigoureux programme de rationalisation budgétaire » et des<br />

réductions des dépenses de l’ordre de trois milliards de dollars. « L’État<br />

québécois devrait être maigre et souple, le plus rapidement possible »,<br />

souligne-t-il :<br />

302


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

Bref, le « party de l’indépendance » devrait être limité à une seule nuit<br />

et il faudrait avoir, au préalable, envoyé en détention préventive les<br />

politiciens patriotards portés à la dépense somptuaire 80 .<br />

Vu la propension de la fonction publique québécoise, comme peut-être celle de<br />

tout État, de grossir allègrement, et vu les promesses du Parti québécois<br />

d’absorber les quelque dizaines de milliers de fonctionnaires fédéraux<br />

québécois advenant la sécession cette remarque laisse perplexe.<br />

Comme nous venons de le voir, le Document de travail numéro 1, qui tente de<br />

déterminer si l’économie québécoise serait mieux gérée et plus prospère<br />

advenant la sécession, n’aboutit certainement pas à une conclusion tranchée en<br />

faveur de cette option. En fait, ce document établit plutôt que cette option, qui<br />

impliquerait des « coûts de transition » probablement élevés, serait possible.<br />

Néanmoins, tous les experts consultés soulignent la nécessité, advenant la<br />

sécession, du maintien de relations très harmonieuses et très serrées avec le<br />

Canada.<br />

Le maintien de telles relations est tenu pour acquis dans les milieux<br />

nationalistes québécois. L’idée que le Québec ne rencontrerait pas d’obstacles<br />

dans l’établissement de rapports sereins avec le Canada et ses autres voisins<br />

repose sur le postulat dit de la « rationalité économique ». Autrement dit, pour<br />

protéger leurs propres intérêts, les partenaires économiques traditionnels du<br />

Québec, devenus des États frontaliers, ne refuseraient pas une telle<br />

collaboration. Est-ce un modèle valable ?<br />

« Non », affirme l’ASDEQ, l’Association des économistes québécois dans son<br />

mémoire à la Commission :<br />

Cette définition d’un comportement « rationnel » en situation de<br />

choix interdépendant constitue une grossière simplification. Tous<br />

ceux qui sont familiers avec la théorie des jeux en percevront<br />

immédiatement les faiblesses 81 .<br />

Pour ces économistes, advenant la sécession, il n’est pas du tout « rationnel »<br />

de penser qu’un climat idyllique de coopération prévaudrait. Évoquant toute la<br />

série de désaccords qui ont marqué l’histoire récente du Canada, ils affirment<br />

que rien dans cette histoire ne prédispose à la coopération : « Tout, au contraire,<br />

suggère des stratégies d’affrontement82. » Or, pour eux, l’existence d’un<br />

climat favorable à la coopération constitue la condition si ne qua non du bienêtre<br />

des Québécois. C’est ce qui amène ces économistes, triés sur le volet, à<br />

affirmer qu’advenant la sécession du Québec, « le rôle des considérations non<br />

économiques doit donc être — et sera — déterminant83. » Car à leurs yeux,<br />

« l’essentiel tient à la présence ou l’absence d’un climat de coopération, de<br />

confiance mutuelle au moment où les choix stratégiques sont effectués84. »<br />

Pour évaluer « la présence ou l’absence d’un climat de coopération » advenant<br />

la sécession du Québec, tournons-nous, une dernière fois, vers les spécialistes<br />

consultés par la Commission.<br />

Les aspects juridiques et institutionnels<br />

Le chapitre 1 du Document de travail numéro 2 (plus de 100 page rédigées par<br />

José Woerhling) analyse très soigneusement toute une série de questions<br />

relatives à la nature du climat qui prévaudrait advenant la sécession du Québec.<br />

L’auteur présente deux scénarios possibles : accession à l’indépendance avec<br />

303


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

l’approbation et la collaboration du Canada; sécession sans l’accord du<br />

Canada. On pourrait croire que la première option pose si peu de problèmes<br />

qu’elle ne mérite pas notre attention, mais tel n’est pas le cas.<br />

L’auteur note, tout d’abord, qu’en cas de sécession, :<br />

la situation du Québec serait véritablement unique, puisqu’il s’agirait<br />

du seul cas contemporain de sécession d’un État membre d’une<br />

fédération faisant partie des démocraties libérales et des pays<br />

développés et riches 85 .<br />

C’est, comme on l’a vu plus haut, ce qui étonnait Francis Fukuyama. De plus,<br />

nous apprenons que cette situation serait non seulement unique mais illégale,<br />

puisqu’aucune disposition constitutionnelle canadienne ne prévoit la<br />

sécession d’une province. Il faudrait donc qu’au préalable la <strong>Constitution</strong> du<br />

Canada soit amendée de manière à reconnaître le principe de la sécession.<br />

Selon l’auteur, dans la meilleure hypothèse, une telle modification pourrait se<br />

faire en vertu de l’article 38 de la loi constitutionnelle de 1982 n’exigeant<br />

qu’une majorité des deux tiers des provinces. Aucune démarche propre au<br />

Québec, y compris un référendum, ne peut contourner cette barrière :<br />

Le fait qu’un gouvernement provincial sécessionniste obtienne<br />

l’appui de la population provinciale lors d’un référendum ne<br />

changerait rien aux données juridiques du problème 86 .<br />

Nous apprenons ainsi que le référendum sur la sécession recomm<strong>and</strong>é par la<br />

Commission n’aurait aucun poids légal. Mais nous apprenons aussi qu’une<br />

sécession légale du Québec exigerait qu’au préalable le gouvernement fédéral<br />

ainsi que sept des dix provinces canadiennes acceptent d’amender la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>.<br />

Considérant, comme le souligne très justement l’auteur, « l’extraordinaire<br />

complexité et la très gr<strong>and</strong>e rigidité de la procédure de modification de la<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong> du Canada », le défi serait de taille. Comme d’autre part une telle<br />

modification introduirait au sein de la <strong>Constitution</strong> un mécanisme<br />

désintégratif autorisant la sécession de toute autre province, cette première<br />

barrière semble, à toutes fins pratiques, infranchissable.<br />

Mais on se rend vite compte que là n’est pas le seul problème. En effet, dit<br />

l’auteur, même dans l’hypothèse d’une sécession « approuvée par le Canada<br />

anglais et réalisée en respectant la <strong>Constitution</strong> canadienne... les questions à<br />

résoudre resteront nombreuses et complexes87. » C’est à l’analyse de ces<br />

questions, que l’auteur se consacre.<br />

Selon Woerhling, l’un des problèmes les plus épineux a trait aux droits des<br />

peuples autochtones qui « soulèveraient sûrement des difficultés<br />

particulières88. » En effet, non seulement le Québec devrait-il respecter leurs<br />

droits, y compris leurs droits territoriaux, mais de plus il devrait s’adapter au<br />

fait que ces peuples autochtones voudront, très probablement, maintenir des<br />

liens avec le gouvernement fédéral. Le Québec ne pouvant s’y opposer, la<br />

coopération entre le Québec et le Canada devient essentielle. C’est pourquoi<br />

l’auteur suggère « un accord Québec-Canada confiant à un organisme mixte...<br />

le soin d’entendre et de trancher les litiges89. » Ainsi, pour les affaires<br />

autochtones, un Québec indépendant devrait très vite partager sa souveraineté<br />

avec le Canada.<br />

304


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

En fait, plus on avance dans la lecture de ce texte, plus on se rend compte de<br />

l’extrême complexité du processus d’accession à l’indépendance et plus<br />

augmente le nombre de sphères dans lesquelles le Québec devrait partager sa<br />

souveraineté avec le Canada. Par exemple, contrairement à ce qu’on pourrait<br />

croire, un Québec indépendant ne pourrait pas, à sa guise, ab<strong>and</strong>onner toute la<br />

législation relevant du gouvernement fédéral qui s’appliquait à son territoire<br />

en tant que province. Toutes les causes en cours dans les tribunaux<br />

d’obédience fédérale exigeraient une étroite collaboration entre les deux États.<br />

Ce n’est qu’ainsi qu’on éviterait le recours à « des principes complexes tirés du<br />

droit international90. »<br />

De plus, prévient l’auteur, un vide juridique dans des champs aussi importants<br />

que le droit criminel et le système bancaire, présentement de compétence<br />

fédérale, pourrait engendrer une situation chaotique. Pour l’éviter, l’auteur<br />

propose bien plus qu’une simple collaboration avec le Canada, puisqu’il<br />

suggère que le Québec garde les lois fédérales qui lui sont utiles :<br />

Il faudrait donc que l’Assemblée nationale adopte, dès l’accession à<br />

la souveraineté, une loi stipulant que... les lois fédérales existantes<br />

continueraient de s’appliquer au Québec 91 .<br />

Mais là ne s’arrête pas l’étroite collaboration entre les deux nouveaux États.<br />

Abordant la question délicate et très complexe de la citoyenneté, l’auteur note<br />

le fait bien évident que tous les citoyens canadiens domiciliés au Québec<br />

devraient recevoir la citoyenneté québécoise. Mais il laisse entendre, en plus,<br />

que les Québécois pourraient conserver la citoyenneté canadienne :<br />

Il serait préférable que le Québec et le Canada s’entendent... quant à<br />

la citoyenneté et à un éventuel droit d’option des personnes affectées<br />

par le changement de souveraineté 92 .<br />

Que les Québécois veuillent le meilleur des deux mondes, on le comprend.<br />

Mais pourquoi le Canada accorderait-il aux Québécois le droit de demeurer<br />

des Canadiens et donc de bénéficier des avantages politiques, institutionnels<br />

et sociaux que confère la citoyenneté du pays qu’ils auraient rejeté ? L’auteur,<br />

probablement conscient de l’improbalitié de cette option, se contente<br />

d’ailleurs de dire qu’une telle entente serait « préférable ».<br />

Woehrling identifie, en outre, toute une série de problèmes de divers ordres<br />

requérant une très étroite collaboration entre le Québec et le Canada, tels le sort<br />

des fonctionnaires fédéraux en poste au Québec, le sort des députés québécois<br />

au Parlement canadien, la disposition des biens fédéraux situés au Québec, la<br />

répartition des dettes, la succession aux traités, l’admission dans les<br />

organismes internationaux, et ainsi de suite. Pour résoudre ces problèmes :<br />

Dans tous les cas, il vaut évidemment mieux que la situation soit<br />

réglée par des accords bilatéraux de succession, afin d’éviter le plus<br />

possible les litiges après l’indépendance 93 .<br />

Mais en plus de cette étroite collaboration sur le plan interne, l’aide du Canada<br />

serait également requise sur le plan des relations internationales. En effet,<br />

l’auteur nous rappelle que le Québec ne serait pas automatiquement admis au<br />

sein des organisations internationales auxquelles appartient le Canada :<br />

305


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

<strong>La</strong> règle générale est que tout État nouveau doit dem<strong>and</strong>er son<br />

admission et se soumettre aux procédures habituelles d’acceptation<br />

de sa c<strong>and</strong>idature 94 .<br />

Le même principe régirait l’admissibilité du Québec aux traités internationaux<br />

négociés par le Canada. Ainsi, par exemple, les termes du traité de libreéchange<br />

nord-américain devraient être renégociés avec les États-Unis et le<br />

Mexique. Comme nous l’avons vu plus haut, Woerhling confirme de la sorte<br />

ce que le secrétariat de la Commission avait déjà établi à ce sujet. Or, il<br />

convient de rappeler que ce traité était fort apprécié par la plupart des élites<br />

québécoises. Woerhling note qu’un nouveau traité désavantagerait<br />

probablement le Québec, entre autres, parce que sa négociation inclurait de<br />

nouveaux intervenants :<br />

Le Canada et le Québec pourraient signer un accord de dévolution...<br />

Cependant, un tel accord ne pourrait pas être imposé aux États tiers<br />

sans leur consentement 95 .<br />

C’est pour toutes ces raisons que Woerhling souligne que la collaboration du<br />

Canada serait essentielle pour aider le Québec à se faire une place au soleil<br />

international :<br />

Les autorités fédérales pourraient assister gr<strong>and</strong>ement le Québec<br />

dans son entrée sur la scène internationale 96 .<br />

Reprenons, en conclusion, l’analyse du scénario 1 de Woerhling, laquelle<br />

suppose une collaboration des plus harmonieuses entre le Canada et le Québec<br />

tant avant qu’après la sécession. Le premier geste requis du Canada serait<br />

l’amendement de sa constitution de façon à accorder au Québec, et à toute<br />

autre province, le droit à la sécession. Une fois la <strong>Constitution</strong> modifiée, le<br />

Canada devrait aider le Québec à régler la question autochtone et à tempérer<br />

les revendications territoriales qui s’y rattachent. Cela fait, le Canada devrait<br />

permettre au Québec de conserver, à sa guise, toutes les lois fédérales et pour<br />

aussi longtemps qu’il le voudrait. Le Canada devrait également collaborer<br />

avec le Québec pour éviter un vide juridique et le chaos qui peut en découler.<br />

Cette étroite collaboration devrait s’étendre également au partage de la dette, à<br />

la répartition des biens publics, à la réintégration des fonctionnaires fédéraux<br />

travaillant au Québec, à la renégociation des traités internationaux, à<br />

l’admission du Québec aux organismes internationaux... Et, pour finir, le<br />

Canada devrait accorder aux nouveaux Québécois qui auraient rejeté leur pays<br />

le droit de rester Canadiens avec les privilèges qui s’y rattachent.<br />

Nous voyons donc que même selon le scénario d’une collaboration étroite du<br />

Canada — cas plutôt rare dans l’histoire récente des relations entre le Québec<br />

et le reste du Canada — la situation du nouvel État demeurerait fragile. Il est<br />

donc inutile de considérer ici le deuxième scénario de Woerhling, pourtant<br />

nettement plus probable, d’une sécession sans l’accord du Canada.<br />

L’analyse de Woerhling constitue un complément indispensable à celle des<br />

questions d’ordre économique présentée plus haut et, notamment, à la mise en<br />

garde servie dans le mémoire de l’ASDEQ. Rappelons que selon ce groupe<br />

d’économistes québécois de renom, incluant Pierre Fortin et André Raynauld,<br />

la faisabilité de la sécession dépend en dernière analyse de considérations non<br />

économiques. « L’essentiel, affirmaient-ils, tient à la présence ou l’absence<br />

306


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

d’un climat de coopération, de confiance mutuelle 97. » Woerhling a montré<br />

l’improbabilité d’une telle occurrence. On peut donc conclure que les analyses<br />

des experts ne justifient pas les risques d’une sécession.<br />

Stratégie et politique : les lendemains d’une Commission<br />

On a vu que la recomm<strong>and</strong>ation à « deux voies » de la Commission — la<br />

transformation « en profondeur » du fédéralisme canadien ou un référendum<br />

sur la sécession — ne constituait en réalité qu’une stratégie de négociation.<br />

Cette dimension proprement politique de la mission de la Commission<br />

Bélanger-Campeau est soigneusement notée par Woerhling lui-même dans la<br />

présentation de son rapport où il met en relief deux éléments. Premièrement,<br />

comme Fortin, il affirme qu’une des principales, sinon l’unique fonction, de la<br />

Commission consiste à renforcer la main du Québec dans ses négociations<br />

avec le reste du Canada :<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec a<br />

été créée notamment pour rechercher les moyens d’instaurer un<br />

nouveau rapport de force entre le Québec et le Canada anglais, afin de<br />

dénouer l’impasse créée par l’échec de l’Accord du lac Meech 98 .<br />

Deuxièmement, il souligne, à plusieurs reprises, la prépondérance des facteurs<br />

politiques. Pour utiliser sa terminologie, la « légitimité des positions en<br />

présence » prend le pas sur leur stricte « légalité », puisque, selon lui, pour les<br />

institutions démocratiques la « volonté populaire constitue leur justification et<br />

le véritable moteur de leur fonctionnement99. » Parallèlement, dit-il, « cette<br />

même réalité se constate dans l’application du droit international qui est fondé<br />

sur le principe de l’efficacité vaut titre100. » Ainsi, pour que la démarche<br />

sécessionniste réussisse, tant sur le plan interne que sur le plan externe, il faut,<br />

selon Woerhling, qu’essentiellement deux conditions « politiques » soient<br />

satisfaites. Premièrement, il faut que tous les changements au statut politique<br />

du Québec «soient endossés par une majorité suffisante de la population<br />

québécoise, de préférence à l’occasion d’un référendum » et, deuxièmement, il<br />

faut que le Québec s’assure de la collaboration du reste du Canada, tant avant<br />

qu’après la réalisation de ce changement.<br />

En dernier ressort, la « faisabilité » de la sécession, ou de tout autre<br />

changement de statut constitutionnel, relève de considérations d’ordre<br />

« politique ». Très clairement, Woerhling relance la balle dans le camp des<br />

politiciens :<br />

Il convient de souligner au départ que la mise en oeuvre du droit<br />

constitutionnel et du droit international est fortement conditionnée<br />

par des facteurs politiques tenant à la primauté des faits, aux rapports<br />

de force et à la légitimité des positions en présence 101 .<br />

On comprend donc l’échec de la stratégie de négociations axée sur la<br />

Commission Bélanger-Campeau : le gouvernement prit la balle au bond.<br />

En effet, plus avançait la date du référendum, plus il devenait clair que le<br />

premier ministre Bourassa, qui avait certainement scruté attentivement les<br />

travaux de la Commission et qui connaissait fort bien les enjeux, ne voulait à<br />

aucun prix faire la sécession. De plus, il devenait également clair que la<br />

majorité des Québécois n’auraient pas dit « Oui»àlasécession102. Coincé par<br />

sa stratégie du « couteau sur la gorge », le gouvernement Bourassa en était<br />

307


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

réduit à chercher une entente à tout prix. Selon le célèbre dossier publié par<br />

L’Actualité, lel er novembre 1992, Bourassa aurait dit lui-même au premier<br />

ministre Mulroney :<br />

Je suis coincé... Ou je reporte le référendum, et je me fais accuser de<br />

ne pas respecter ma parole et de tricher avec l’histoire, ou je fais un<br />

référendum auquel les Québécois ne sont pas prêts... 103<br />

Là se trouve la réponse au « mystère » évoqué par Léon Dion qui s’étonnait que<br />

Bourassa ait laissé s’échapper « le triple rapport de force qu’il avait entre les<br />

mains ». Bourassa savait que cette stratégie s’était retournée contre lui.<br />

Si la Commission Bélanger-Campeau a échoué sur le plan stratégique, elle a<br />

toutefois réussi à renforcer l’idée même de sécession au Québec.<br />

En effet, lorsque pendant des mois, se déplaçant à travers la province, elle a<br />

prêté l’oreille à tous ceux qui avaient matière à se plaindre, elle a canalisé leurs<br />

revendications dans le sens de la sécession. Après tout, la souveraineté du<br />

Québec, présentée comme souhaitable et imminente, devenait la réponse à<br />

tous les problèmes. En favorisant ainsi l’expression de tels sentiments, pour les<br />

utiliser à des fins stratégiques, le Parti libéral du Québec a réussi à légitimer la<br />

raison d’être de son adversaire : le Parti québécois. D’ailleurs, ce Parti, voué à<br />

la sécession, entend utiliser à ses propres fins la dynamique déclenchée par la<br />

Commission. En effet, comme on peut le lire dans un document distribué aux<br />

médias, ce Parti se promet d’utiliser toutes les occasions pour reconstruire « le<br />

formidable consensus établi dans la société québécoise au cours des travaux de<br />

la commission Bélanger-Campeau. » Ce « formidable consensus », c’est le<br />

gouvernement fédéraliste de Robert Bourassa qui l’a offert au Parti québécois;<br />

sur un plateau d’argent.<br />

Et c’est ainsi que, par le biais de la Commission « Bélanger-Campeau »<br />

s’unirent, dans un même élan, la stratégie d’un parti fédéraliste et les visées<br />

d’un parti indépendantiste pour ajouter une pierre de plus à la construction de<br />

l’idée de sécession au Québec.<br />

Notes<br />

1. C’est dans le cadre d’un séminaire sur le nationalisme, à <strong>La</strong>val, que les thèmes analysés ici<br />

ont germé. Comme toujours, je dois donc beaucoup à mes étudiants. Je tiens également à<br />

remercier Jean-Pierre Derriennic, Stéphane Dion et William Johnson pour leurs<br />

commentaires sur une première version de ce texte. Merci également aux rédacteurs ainsi<br />

qu’aux évaluateurs anonymes de cette revue. Merci enfin, et surtout, à Monique, sans qui ce<br />

texte n’aurait pas vu le jour.<br />

2. <strong>La</strong> situation canadienne constituant un cas d’espèce, elle étonne de nombreux observateurs.<br />

Francis Fukuyama, par exemple, y voit même une sorte de test des valeurs démocratiques et<br />

libérales face aux pressions du nationalisme ethno-culturel :<br />

<strong>The</strong> best test case of this in <strong>the</strong> world right now is Quebec... This is because Quebec is a<br />

subdivision within a prosperous <strong>and</strong> stable liberal democratic country... <strong>The</strong> breakup of<br />

Canada along national lines would be an interesting piece of evidence concerning <strong>the</strong><br />

adequacy of modern liberal democracy. (Journal of Democracy, octobre 1992, p. 28)<br />

3. « Pour sortir de l’impasse constitutionnelle » Document de travail, numéro 4. Les avis des<br />

spécialistes invités à répondre aux huit questions posées par la Commission, Québec, 1991,<br />

p. 279.<br />

4. <strong>La</strong> Presse, l er octobre 1992, p. B3.<br />

308


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

5. « Quebec Beyond <strong>the</strong> Federal Regime of 1867-1982: From Distinct Society to National<br />

Community » dans R. Watts et D. Brown, éd. Options for a New Canada, University of<br />

Toronto Press, 1991, p. 103.<br />

6. Ibid., p. 105.<br />

7. Presque tous les sondages montrent que la période de juin à octobre 1990, immédiatement<br />

« après Meech », marque le faîte de la vague sécessionniste. Les sondages Angus-Reid du 20<br />

juillet, par exemple, ou de Léger-Léger de la fin octobre 1990 ou encore l’étude d’Édouard<br />

Cloutier et de ses collaborateurs, Le virage, (Québec/Amérique, 1992) indiquent tous la<br />

même tendance. Selon la formulation de la question, entre 50 et 64 % des Québécois<br />

favorisaient la sécession.<br />

8. Rapport de la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, Québec, mars<br />

1991, p. 17.<br />

9. Ibid., p. 18.<br />

10. Ibid., p. 20.<br />

11. Ibid., p. 24.<br />

12. Ibid., p. 24<br />

13. Ibid., p. 35<br />

14. Ibid., p. 31. C’est moi qui souligne.<br />

15. Ibid., p. 58.<br />

16. Ibid., p. 84.<br />

17. Ibid., p. 60.<br />

18. Ibid., p. 81.<br />

19. Ibid., p. 83. C’est moi qui souligne.<br />

20. Ibid., p. 96.<br />

21. Ibid., p. 92<br />

22. Cet épisode et ce sentiment ont été longuement analysés dans M. Nemni, « Le ‘dés’accord<br />

du <strong>La</strong>c Meech et la construction de l’imaginaire symbolique des Québécois », paru dans L.<br />

Balthazar, G. <strong>La</strong>forest, V. Lemieux, Le Québec et la restructuration du Canada, 1980-<br />

1992 : enjeux et perspectives, Québec, Septentrion, pp. 167-197. Une étude plus succincte<br />

de cette même question a paru dans le Queen’s Quarterly, vol. 99, n o 1, printemps, 1992.<br />

23. « Explaining Quebec Nationalism » dans R. Kent Weaver <strong>The</strong> Collapse of Canada ?,<br />

Washington, D .C., <strong>The</strong> Brookings Institution, 1992, p. 78.<br />

24. « Les enjeux économiques de la souveraineté, » octobre 1990, pp. 37-38.<br />

25. On retrouve ces données non seulement dans les documents de la Commission mais aussi<br />

dans les statistiques gouvernementales. Voir, par exemple, Le Québec statistique, 59 e<br />

édition, Gouvernement du Québec, 1989.<br />

26. Rapport de la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, Québec, mars<br />

1991, pp. 18-19.<br />

27. L’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec : sa dimension économique, Montréal, 1 er<br />

novembre 1990, p. 9<br />

28. Ibid., p. 13.<br />

29. Ibid., p. 11.<br />

30. Ibid., p. 2.<br />

31. Moins de discours, plus d’action, 2 novembre 1990, p. 4.<br />

32. Ibid., p. 5.<br />

33. Un choix clair pour la CSN : L’indépendance du Québec, novembre 1990, p. 14.<br />

34. Centrale de l’enseignement du Québec (CEQ), Indépendance nationale et souveraineté<br />

populaire, novembre 1990, p. 37.<br />

35. Les jeunes et l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, novembre 1990, p. 25.<br />

36. Ibid.<br />

37. Mémoire de l’Université du Québec à la Commission parlementaire sur l’avenir politique et<br />

constitutionnel du Québec, 31 octobre 1990, p .2.<br />

38. « Pourquoi je voterai Non », dans <strong>La</strong> Presse, 1 er octobre 1992, p. B3.<br />

39. Centres de femmes du Saguenay-<strong>La</strong>c-St-Jean-Chibougamau, Mémoire soumis à la<br />

Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, octobre 1990, p. 3.<br />

40. Ibid., p. 5.<br />

41. Ibid., p. 19.<br />

42. Naître ou ne pas être, Québec, Institut québécois de recherche sur la culture, 1989, p. 78.<br />

309


IJCS/RIÉC<br />

43. Ibid., p. 73.<br />

44. Marc Termote et Danielle Gauvreau, <strong>La</strong> situation démolinguistique du Québec, Éditeur<br />

officiel du Québec, 1988, p. 253.<br />

45. Sans les moyens d’un pays complet, le Québec français ne fera bientôt plus le poids,<br />

novembre 1990, pp 23-24. Rappelons que cette question fit une entrée très remarquée dans<br />

l’univers médiatique, en hiver 1989, lorsque parut le documentaire Disparaître de l’Office<br />

national du film. M me Lise Payette, ex-ministre au sein du gouvernement Lévesque,<br />

présentait la dénalité comme la principale menace au fait français, et l’immigration comme<br />

un mal nécessaire vu la difficulté « d’assimiler » ces nouveaux arrivants.<br />

46. Ibid., p. 47.<br />

47. « L’évolution démolinguistique du Québec et du Canada », Éléments d’analyse<br />

institutionnelle, juridique et démolinguistique pertinents à la révision du statut politique et<br />

constitutionnel du Québec, Document de travail numéro 2, Québec, 1991, p. 270.<br />

48. Ibid., p. 256.<br />

49. Ibid., p. 254.<br />

50. Ibid., p. 239.<br />

51. Ibid., p. 247.<br />

52. Ibid., p. 273.<br />

53. Ibid., p. 253.<br />

54. Ibid., p. 276.<br />

55. Ibid., p. 271.<br />

56. Ibid., p. 270.<br />

57. Ibid., p. 273.<br />

58. « <strong>La</strong> question de l’emploi au Québec : la photo et le film », chapitre 4, Éléments d’analyse<br />

économique pertinents à la révision du statut politique et constitutionnel du Québec,<br />

Document de travail numéro 1, Québec, 1991, p. 167.<br />

59. Ibid., p. 169.<br />

60. Ibid., p. 231.<br />

61. Ibid., p. 170.<br />

62. Ibid., p. 172.<br />

63. Ibid., p. 231.<br />

64. Ibid., p. 176.<br />

65. Ibid., p. 176.<br />

66. Ibid., p. 234.<br />

67. Ibid., p. 237.<br />

68. Ibid., p. 235.<br />

69. « Le choix forcé du Québec : aspects économiques et stratégiques » Document de travail<br />

numéro 4, p. 342.<br />

70. Secrétariat de la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, « L’accès<br />

du Québec aux marchés extérieurs et à l’espace économique canadien », Document de<br />

travail numéro 1, p. 45.<br />

71. Ibid., p. 45.<br />

72. Ibid., p. 40.<br />

73. Ibid., p. 41.<br />

74. Ibid., p. 50.<br />

75. Ibid., Bernard Fortin, p. 287.<br />

76. Ibid., p. 299.<br />

77. « Intégration financière internationale et interdépendances des politiques macroéconomiques<br />

nationales » dans ibid., p. 273.<br />

78. Op. cit., p. 35, mes italiques. Notons, que la Commission admet là ce que de nombreux<br />

spécialistes, surtout anglophones, ont maintes fois répété. Voir, par exemple, les travaux du<br />

John Deutsch Institute for <strong>the</strong> Study of Economic Policy et, notamment, Robin W. Boadway<br />

et al., éd., Economic Dimensions of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Change, deux volumes, Kingston (Ont.),<br />

Queens’s University Press, 1991. Voir également <strong>The</strong> Gazette du 1 er octobre 1992, qui cite<br />

de hautes autorités américaines confirmant ce fait.<br />

79. Dans Alain-G. Gagnon et François Rocher, Répliques aux détracteurs de la souveraineté du<br />

Québec, Montréal, VLB éditeur, 1992, p. 457.<br />

80. Ibid., p. 458.<br />

310


<strong>La</strong> Commission Bélanger-Campeau et la<br />

construction de l’idée de sécession au Québec<br />

81. ASDEQ, Mémoire à la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec,<br />

novembre 1990, p. 40. Ce mémoire, approuvé par l’association, est le fruit des délibérations<br />

de sept économistes issus de divers milieux québécois. Parmi les auteurs, notons la<br />

participation de Pierre Fortin et d’André Raynauld.<br />

82. Ibid., p. 41.<br />

83. Ibid., p. 39.<br />

84. Ibid., p. 41.<br />

85. « Les aspects juridiques de la redéfinition du statut politique et constitutionnel du Québec »,<br />

Le rapport de la Commission sur l’avenir politique et constitutionnel du Québec, Éléments<br />

d’analyse institutionnelle, juridique et démolinguistique pertinents à la révision du statut<br />

politique et constitutionnel du Québec. Document de travail numéro 2, Québec, l er trimestre<br />

1991, p. 81.<br />

86. Ibid., p. 57.<br />

87. Ibid., p. 60.<br />

88. Ibid., p. 64.<br />

89. Ibid., p. 64.<br />

90. Ibid., p. 69.<br />

91. Ibid., p. 68.<br />

92. Ibid., p. 70.<br />

93. Ibid., p. 74.<br />

94. Ibid., p. 78.<br />

95. Ibid., p. 77.<br />

96. Ibid., p. 80.<br />

97. Op. cit., p. 40.<br />

98. Op. cit., p .2.<br />

99. Ibid., p. 1<br />

100. Ibid., p. 2.<br />

101. Ibid., p. 1.<br />

102. Un sondage très fiable du Centre de recherches sur l’opinion publique, effectué pour <strong>La</strong><br />

Presse et le réseau TVA, établit une chute considérable de l’option souverainiste (dans sa<br />

version « molle ») de 64 % en novembre 1990 à 40 % en octobre 1992.<br />

103. L’Actualité,l er novembre 1992, p. 71. Ce dossier, basé sur des documents secrets obtenus par<br />

ce périodique, parut quelques jours avant le référendum du 26 octobre 1992. Il contribua, très<br />

probablement, à la défaite du camp du « Oui » de Bourassa ainsi qu’à la chute de sa cote<br />

personnelle de popularité.<br />

104. <strong>La</strong> Presse, 15 janvier 1993, p. A8.<br />

311


Review Essays<br />

Essais critiques


Michael Oliver<br />

<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on<br />

Bilingualism <strong>and</strong> Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Thought <strong>and</strong> Practice in Canada<br />

Abstract<br />

<strong>The</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong> Biculturalism had an immediate<br />

impact on <strong>the</strong> status <strong>and</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> two official languages of Canada,<br />

especially at <strong>the</strong> federal level of administration. <strong>The</strong> federal Official<br />

<strong>La</strong>nguages Act, in particular, followed its recommendations very closely.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> key concept of <strong>the</strong> Commission,—equal partnership—had<br />

much less influence. Although accepted at <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s<br />

creation, it faded in influence <strong>and</strong> popularity during <strong>the</strong> 1970s <strong>and</strong> 1980s. It is<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown agreement of <strong>the</strong> Canadian provinces in August<br />

1992 may be seen as a return to an altered <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ed version of <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

of equal partnership.<br />

Résumé<br />

<strong>La</strong> Commission royale d’enquête sur le bilinguisme et le biculturalisme a eu<br />

une influence immédiate sur le statut et l’utilisation des deux langues<br />

officielles du Canada, en particulier au sein de l’appareil fédéral. <strong>La</strong> Loi sur<br />

les langues officielles, notamment, respectait scrupuleusement ses<br />

recomm<strong>and</strong>ations. Toutefois, la notion clé qui fondait la position de la<br />

Commission — l’égalité des deux partenaires — a eu une portée beaucoup<br />

plus limitée. Bien qu’admise au moment de la création de la Commission, sa<br />

popularité et son crédit n’ont cessé de diminuer au cours des années 1970 et<br />

1980. L’auteur estime que l’accord intervenu entre les provinces à<br />

Charlottetown en 1992 constitue une version modifiée et élargie de cette<br />

notion d’égalité entre les partenaires.<br />

Accomplishments<br />

<strong>The</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong> Biculturalism (henceforth B &<br />

B Commission) began its work in 1963 <strong>and</strong> completed publication of its<br />

reports in 1970. <strong>The</strong> Preliminary Report of early 1965 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> General<br />

Introduction <strong>and</strong> Book I on <strong>the</strong> Official <strong>La</strong>nguages, published toge<strong>the</strong>r in<br />

October 1967, carried <strong>the</strong> main <strong>the</strong>mes of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s findings.<br />

Although subsequent reports were far from unnoticed, <strong>the</strong>y did not attract <strong>the</strong><br />

same attention. <strong>The</strong> regional meetings which formed <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong><br />

Preliminary Report <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal public hearings of 1966 comm<strong>and</strong>ed at least<br />

as much media notice as <strong>the</strong> Commission’s publications, <strong>and</strong> much of <strong>the</strong><br />

importance of <strong>the</strong> Commission on public consciousness—on <strong>the</strong> way people<br />

defined <strong>and</strong> debated French-English <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r cultural <strong>and</strong> linguistic<br />

problems—came from <strong>the</strong>se meetings <strong>and</strong> media reports on <strong>the</strong>m. When <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

workwascompleted,<strong>the</strong>Commissionerscouldsee<strong>the</strong>irideastranslatedinto<br />

public policy in many different ways.<br />

<strong>The</strong>Official<strong>La</strong>nguagesActof1969embodies<strong>the</strong>substanceofwhat<strong>the</strong>B&B<br />

Commissionhadrecommendedas“<strong>the</strong>keystoneofanygeneralprogrammeof<br />

bilingualisminCanada”(RCBBI1967:138).Itlaidout<strong>the</strong>rulesforlanguage<br />

services <strong>and</strong> for language use. It established <strong>the</strong> Commissioner of Official<br />

<strong>La</strong>nguages <strong>and</strong> gave that officer am<strong>and</strong>ate that followed closely <strong>the</strong> B&B<br />

Commission’s ideas. Transforming amassively English-language federal<br />

publicserviceintoareasonablyeffectivebilingualonechanged<strong>the</strong>character<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> image of <strong>the</strong> Canadian government profoundly. To dismiss this<br />

achievement,asQuebecseparatists(<strong>and</strong>evensomenon-separatists[Guindon<br />

1978])arewonttodo,assomethingQuebecdidnotreallywant,isnonsense.It<br />

was not all that French-Canadians <strong>and</strong> especially Francophone Quebecers<br />

wanted; but it was wanted, <strong>and</strong> strongly dem<strong>and</strong>ed as brief after brief to <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission attested. Because afederal bilingual regime is not asufficient<br />

condition for <strong>the</strong> survival of Canada does not mean that it is not anecessary<br />

condition.<br />

<strong>The</strong> decision of New Brunswick to turn itself into an officially bilingual<br />

province is again a clear implementation of a B & B Commission<br />

recommendation. Ontario’s refusal to do <strong>the</strong> same was equally clearly a<br />

rejection of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s recommendation <strong>and</strong> had quite adifferent<br />

qualitythan<strong>the</strong>traditional sweepingof<strong>the</strong>questionunder<strong>the</strong>provincialrug.<br />

Radio<strong>and</strong>televisionweremadeavailableinbothofficiallanguagesunder<strong>the</strong><br />

auspicesof<strong>the</strong>CanadianRadio<strong>and</strong>TelevisionCommission(CRTC),abody<br />

that was fully cognizant of <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission’s recommendations <strong>and</strong><br />

accepted <strong>the</strong>m. In both federal <strong>and</strong> some provincial bodies, <strong>the</strong> language<br />

prescriptions of <strong>the</strong> Commission were a recognized guide (Frith 1978).<br />

Inalesspreciseway,<strong>the</strong>Commission’sreporthadanenormousinfluenceon<br />

<strong>the</strong>patternoflanguagelearningin<strong>the</strong>country. <strong>The</strong>vastprogramoflanguage<br />

instruction undertaken by <strong>the</strong> federal government followed directly from <strong>the</strong><br />

Official <strong>La</strong>nguages Act. But <strong>the</strong> flowering of French immersion courses<br />

across<strong>the</strong>country<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>widespreadimprovementin<strong>the</strong>teachingofFrench<br />

as asecond language deserve to be counted as indirect products of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission <strong>and</strong> its work, if not always <strong>the</strong> conscious implementation of its<br />

recommendations in <strong>the</strong> Book on education (RCBB II 1968).<br />

<strong>The</strong> B&BCommission pioneered <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> terms “Anglophone” <strong>and</strong><br />

“Francophone” 1 which have since become st<strong>and</strong>ard in <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

constitutionalvocabulary.<strong>The</strong>useof<strong>the</strong>setermsmadeiteasiertoconcentrate<br />

onlanguagera<strong>the</strong>rthanethnicity,avitalshiftofemphasisthat<strong>the</strong>Commission<br />

promoted to differentiate between <strong>the</strong> positions of <strong>the</strong> “two founding races”<br />

specifiedinitsm<strong>and</strong>ate<strong>and</strong>“o<strong>the</strong>rethnicgroups.” Itactivelydiscouraged<strong>the</strong><br />

use of <strong>the</strong> term “race,” an expression that occurred only in <strong>the</strong> Englishlanguagewordsofitsm<strong>and</strong>ate.<strong>The</strong>Frenchversion,inamuchmoreacceptable<br />

way, spoke of “peuples.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> Mainspring of <strong>the</strong> Commission<br />

Where<strong>the</strong>Commission’sperceptionofCanadahadmostdifficultyimprinting<br />

itselfon<strong>the</strong>politics<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>politicalthoughtof<strong>the</strong>countrywasin<strong>the</strong>concept<br />

of“equalpartnership.”In<strong>the</strong>workingpaperthat<strong>the</strong>Commissionpreparedto<br />

guide those who intended to submit briefs for <strong>the</strong> Commission, “Equal<br />

316


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

partnershipbetween<strong>the</strong>twofoundingraces”wasdescribedas<strong>the</strong>“mainspring<br />

(idée-force)”of<strong>the</strong>termsofreference,<strong>and</strong>consequentlyof<strong>the</strong>Commission.<br />

Yet<strong>the</strong>conceptofequalpartnershipfadedfromviewafter<strong>the</strong>endof<strong>the</strong>1960s<br />

in most English-language commentaries. It remained in some pro-federalist<br />

discourse in <strong>the</strong> French language; but in <strong>the</strong> rhetoric of many Francophone<br />

exponentsoffederalism,itreceivedlittleattention.Liberalswhofollowed<strong>the</strong><br />

intellectual lead of Pierre-Elliott Trudeau were particularly chary of it for<br />

reasons that will become apparent.<br />

Equal Partnership in <strong>the</strong> 1960s<br />

<strong>The</strong>termequalpartnershipwasverywidelyacceptedin<strong>the</strong>early1960swhen<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of <strong>the</strong> Commission <strong>and</strong> its terms of reference were<br />

announced. <strong>The</strong> Prime Minister wrote to each of <strong>the</strong> provincial Premiers<br />

eliciting comment on <strong>the</strong> enterprise <strong>and</strong> received replies that, with <strong>the</strong> one<br />

exceptionofPremierManningofAlberta(RCBB1965:App.III),variedfrom<br />

welcomingtoaccepting. Whatdidequalpartnershipmeantothosewhowere<br />

using it happily in <strong>the</strong> 1960s? And how did <strong>the</strong> Commission’s own<br />

amplification of <strong>the</strong> term fit in with <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ings of those who wrote<br />

about equal partnership?<br />

In seeking replies to <strong>the</strong>se questions, it is useful to turn to <strong>the</strong> late Donald<br />

Smiley, one of <strong>the</strong> most prolific <strong>and</strong> influential writers on <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>. He began his contributions to <strong>the</strong> constitutional debate in <strong>the</strong><br />

1960s <strong>and</strong> it is possible to follow <strong>the</strong> evolution of his ideas (<strong>and</strong> his use of<br />

variousterms)throughtohisdeathin1990.Hisendorsementof<strong>the</strong>conceptof<br />

equal partnership in 1967 was strong: “Whatever <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> New<br />

NationalPolicy<strong>and</strong>underwhateverpartyauspicesitisundertaken,itmust,to<br />

be successful, be pursued through ‘equal partnership’ between English- <strong>and</strong><br />

French-speaking Canadians” (Smiley 1967: 110-111). He immediately went<br />

ontocontrastindividualrights<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>claimsofcollectivities<strong>and</strong>madeitclear<br />

that<strong>the</strong>partnershehadinmindwereaggregationsofpersonswhohadmadean<br />

individualchoice<strong>and</strong>hadnomore“collective”claimtorecognitionthan,say,<br />

<strong>the</strong>Ascot-tiewearersof<strong>the</strong>country. Thishighlyindividualisticpositionisone<br />

heneverexplicitlymodified,butitprovedadifficultonetoarticulatewithout<br />

strayingintocollectivistterminology.Whileinsistingthatlanguagegroupsare<br />

simply aggregations of individual choosers (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir presumably minor<br />

children),Smileyalsotalkedoftwo“cultures”<strong>and</strong>of“culturalcommunities”<br />

as part of <strong>the</strong> partnership.<br />

Despite occasional slips, <strong>the</strong> equal partnership of <strong>the</strong> early Smiley was<br />

unflinchingly individualist. Partnership based on equality between cultures<br />

had to be rejected because it undermined majoritarian democracy: “If <strong>the</strong><br />

relevantequalityasdefinedisbetweenculturesoranyo<strong>the</strong>rkindofgrouping,<br />

<strong>and</strong>,asisalmostalways<strong>the</strong>case,<strong>the</strong>numbersofindividualsin<strong>the</strong>segroupings<br />

areunequal,<strong>the</strong>principleofindividualequality<strong>and</strong>itsmajoritariancorollary<br />

must perforce be sacrificed” (Smiley 1967:112). <strong>The</strong> “relevant equality” for<br />

Smiley was between English-speakers <strong>and</strong> French-speakers <strong>and</strong> did not<br />

threaten majoritarianism. <strong>The</strong> proper kind of partnership conferred rights on<br />

individuals to “practice” <strong>the</strong>ir language, much in <strong>the</strong> way that an individual<br />

mightpracticereligion.But<strong>the</strong>rewasanimportantdifferencein<strong>the</strong>obligation<br />

that language rights imposed on <strong>the</strong> state. Religious freedom simply meant<br />

tolerance, except in <strong>the</strong> still controversial field of denominational education<br />

where state subsidy (but not state provision) might be needed. <strong>La</strong>nguage<br />

rights, as Smiley envisaged <strong>the</strong>m, required that federal, provincial <strong>and</strong> local<br />

317


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

publicservicesbeprovidedinei<strong>the</strong>rlanguage.Thisnewpublicresponsibility<br />

requiredbilingualisminalargeproportionofpublicservants. <strong>The</strong>percentage<br />

wouldincreaseifFrench<strong>and</strong>Englishwererecognizednotonlyforserviceto<br />

<strong>the</strong> public but for internal communication.<br />

Smiley did not wince at any of this. For <strong>the</strong> predominantly unilingual<br />

Anglophone public servants, <strong>the</strong> transformation required of <strong>the</strong>m would be<br />

immense; but Smiley assumed <strong>the</strong>y would <strong>and</strong> should bear <strong>the</strong> social costs.<br />

When it came to proposals that gave recognition to a culturally-based<br />

collectivity—a French-Canadian or Québécois nation—his reaction was<br />

totally different. He asked: “under what conceivable set of circumstances<br />

couldEnglish-speakingCanadabeexpectedtofindsuchreformsacceptable?”<br />

(Smiley1967:118). HisanswerwasaquotationfromEugeneForsey:“Some<br />

French-Canadiansseemtobelievethat<strong>the</strong>restofusaresoenamouredof<strong>the</strong>m,<br />

or so convinced we cannot get on without <strong>the</strong>m, that we will pay almost any<br />

price to preserve even <strong>the</strong> most tenuous connection with <strong>the</strong>m. This is a<br />

dangerous delusion” (Forsey 1962:486).<br />

To many Francophone Québécois in <strong>the</strong> 1960s, equal partnership meant just<br />

what Smiley <strong>and</strong> those who thought like him rejected out of h<strong>and</strong>. Quebec<br />

should be recognized in anewly-conceived Confederation as <strong>the</strong> primary<br />

socialunittowhichFrancophonesbelonged,<strong>and</strong>itsgovernmentshouldhave<br />

vestedinit<strong>the</strong>powersnecessaryfor<strong>the</strong>realizationofcollectiveprojects. <strong>The</strong><br />

rightsofFrancophoneminoritiesoutsideQuebecwereofsecondaryconcern.<br />

ItwasutopiantothinkthatpartnershipinCanadaasawholecouldbe“equal”<br />

for Francophones. <strong>The</strong>y would constitute apermanent minority <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> best<br />

<strong>the</strong>y could hope for was areasonable set of minority rights. An equal<br />

relationship could only be achieved if Québécois had <strong>the</strong>ir own majority<br />

community armed with adequate powers. <strong>The</strong>se powers would logically be<br />

much more extensive that those of any o<strong>the</strong>r Canadian province, for <strong>the</strong><br />

citizensofthoseo<strong>the</strong>rprovincesalreadyhad,inCanadaasawhole,astate<strong>and</strong><br />

agovernmentinwhich<strong>the</strong>ywereamajority.<strong>The</strong>essenceofequalpartnership<br />

wasthus<strong>the</strong> provisionofnewpowersforQuebec,ei<strong>the</strong>rasanassociatestate<br />

or as a province with a “special status” (Morin 1965).<br />

Equal Partnership <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commission<br />

It was not surprising that <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission, h<strong>and</strong>ed am<strong>and</strong>ate that<br />

requireditto“recommendwhatstepsshouldbetakentodevelop<strong>the</strong>Canadian<br />

Confederationon<strong>the</strong>basisofanequalpartnershipbetween<strong>the</strong>twofounding<br />

races,”shouldtakesometimetodecidewhatequalpartnershipmeant. Itwas<br />

fully aware of <strong>the</strong> changes being rung on <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me of equal partnership in<br />

academic, political <strong>and</strong> media circles <strong>and</strong> fully conscious of <strong>the</strong> mutually<br />

exclusive character of individually-based <strong>and</strong> community-based discussions<br />

of<strong>the</strong>term.<strong>The</strong>definitionitworkedoutoveritsfirstmonthsofmeetingswasa<br />

blendofindividualistic<strong>and</strong>communitarianfeatures.Itcannotbeclaimedthat<br />

itwastotallyconsistentinitsuseofwordslike“society”orthatitreconciled<br />

collective <strong>and</strong> individual perspectives in afully satisfactory way. But in its<br />

initialplanofwork,itlaidoutawayofdefining<strong>and</strong>realizingequalpartnership<br />

that,haditbeenabletocompleteitswork,mighthavegivengreaterstrength<br />

<strong>and</strong> longevity to <strong>the</strong> concept of equal partnership.<br />

<strong>The</strong>Commissionersbelievedthatdevelopingequalpartnershipcouldonlybe<br />

achieved by combining atransformation in <strong>the</strong> language use patterns of<br />

Canada as awhole with afuller recognition of <strong>the</strong> crucial role of Quebec in<br />

318


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

sustaining French Canada. It refused to see action in Quebec alone as <strong>the</strong><br />

remedy to bilingual <strong>and</strong> bicultural imbalance in <strong>the</strong> country. With equal<br />

fervour,itstronglyrejected<strong>the</strong>ideathatofficiallanguagerecognitionwasall<br />

thatwasneeded.Whatitsaidwassomethinglikethis:whatcannotreasonably<br />

be changed at <strong>the</strong> country-wide level, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> composition <strong>and</strong> language<br />

practicesof<strong>the</strong>nationalgovernment,tomakeFrancophones<strong>the</strong>equalpartners<br />

ofAnglophonesmustbeattainedthroughanenlargedroleforQuebec<strong>and</strong>its<br />

government. If equal partnership meant roughly balancing <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>and</strong><br />

benefitsofbeingCanadianbetweenFrancophones<strong>and</strong>Anglophones,<strong>and</strong>if,at<br />

<strong>the</strong> national level, costs would always be higher <strong>and</strong> benefits less for<br />

Francophones,<strong>the</strong>ncompensatingactionhadtobetakeninQuebectoensure<br />

that benefits to Francophones living <strong>the</strong>re were high enough <strong>and</strong> costs low<br />

enough to get <strong>the</strong> overall balance right, or as nearly right as possible.<br />

<strong>The</strong>searenot<strong>the</strong>Commission’swords. None<strong>the</strong>less,acarefulreadingof<strong>the</strong><br />

“bluepages”thatintroduced<strong>the</strong>finalreport(RCBBI1967:xi-lii)bringsout<br />

<strong>the</strong> “balancing of costs <strong>and</strong> benefits” approach quite unmistakably. Those<br />

pages embody particularly <strong>the</strong> conception of ajust Canada held by André<br />

<strong>La</strong>urendeau who wrote most of this part of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s report. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

document his conviction that <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> Commission could not be<br />

completeifitdidnottackle<strong>the</strong>questionof<strong>the</strong>roleofQuebecin<strong>the</strong>bilingualbiculturalbalanceofCanada.<strong>The</strong>commitmenttolookinto<strong>the</strong>constitutional<br />

divisionofpowersbetweenQuebec<strong>and</strong>Ottawa,<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>relationshipbetween<br />

Quebec <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provinces of Canada, is laid out in <strong>the</strong>se terms:<br />

...as soon as ...[a]... minority [such as Canada’s Francophones] is<br />

awareofitscollectivelifeasawhole,itmayverywellaspireto<strong>the</strong><br />

mastery of its own existence <strong>and</strong> begin to look beyond cultural<br />

liberties. It raises <strong>the</strong> question of its political status. It feels that its<br />

future<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>progressofitsculturearenotentirelysecure,that<strong>the</strong>y<br />

are perhaps limited, within apolitical structure dominated by a<br />

majoritycomposedof<strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rgroup. Consequently,itmovesin<strong>the</strong><br />

direction of greater constitutional autonomy. Ideally, <strong>the</strong> minority<br />

desires<strong>the</strong>sameautonomyfor<strong>the</strong>wholeof<strong>the</strong>communitytowhich<br />

itbelongs;butwhereitcannotattainthisobjective,itmaydecideto<br />

concentrate on <strong>the</strong> more limited political unit in which it is<br />

incontestably <strong>the</strong> majority group.<br />

This viewpoint, so hotly opposed by some, is deeply entrenched in<br />

Quebec. Ithasevenbeen,inrecentyears,at<strong>the</strong>rootofsomeof<strong>the</strong><br />

mostspectacular,ifnot<strong>the</strong>mostserious,manifestationsof<strong>the</strong>crisis<br />

in Canada. To ignore it in this Report would not only constitute an<br />

error;itwouldverylikelymeanthatQuebecwouldrefusetolistento<br />

us, <strong>and</strong> that English-speaking Canada would be deprived of <strong>the</strong><br />

chancetobecomeawareofanespeciallygraveelementin<strong>the</strong>present<br />

situation. (RCBB I 1967: xlvii -xlviii)<br />

In fact, <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission did ignore <strong>the</strong> division of powers between<br />

Quebec <strong>and</strong> Ottawa <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent to which equal partnership dem<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

greater autonomy for Quebec. <strong>The</strong> death of André <strong>La</strong>urendeau was acrucial<br />

factorin<strong>the</strong>truncationof<strong>the</strong>Commission’sreport,buto<strong>the</strong>rfactors,including<br />

division <strong>and</strong> fatigue amongst <strong>the</strong> Commissioners, took <strong>the</strong>ir toll, (<strong>La</strong>coste<br />

1990[1] <strong>and</strong> [2]). 2 <strong>The</strong> full concept of equal partnership <strong>and</strong> its implications<br />

for Canadian federalism were <strong>the</strong>refore never fully developed. One can be<br />

319


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

reasonably certain where <strong>La</strong>urendeau himself would have wanted <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission to go, for Claude Ryan has reported that <strong>La</strong>urendeau told him:<br />

“J’ai l’impression qu’éventuellement, nos recherches actuelles pourraient<br />

déboucher sur une formule intermédiaire entre le statut particulier et l’État<br />

associé” (Ryan 1990). But carrying <strong>the</strong> Commission with him would have<br />

been ano<strong>the</strong>r matter.<br />

Distinct Societies <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r Ethnic Groups<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commission could have based its justification of <strong>the</strong> concept of equal<br />

partnershipbetweenFrancophones<strong>and</strong>Anglophonessimplyon<strong>the</strong>historical<br />

groundsthat<strong>the</strong>ywere<strong>the</strong>“founding”peoplesofCanada.<strong>The</strong>ychoseinstead<br />

todifferentiatebetween<strong>the</strong>“partners”<strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rethnicgroupsinsociological<br />

terms. <strong>The</strong> reason why Francophones were quite different from any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

language <strong>and</strong> cultural group in Canada (except Anglophones) is that<br />

Francophones constituted a “society”. <strong>The</strong> word “society” designated a<br />

complexoforganizations<strong>and</strong>institutionssufficientlyrichtopermit peopleto<br />

leadafulllifein<strong>the</strong>irownlanguage. InQuebec,Francophonescouldfindsuch<br />

a“distinct” society: asubstantial French-speaking population (about four<br />

million),withitsownlegalsystem,<strong>the</strong>CivilCode;itsowneducationsystem;<br />

hospitals,tradeunions<strong>and</strong>anetworkofvoluntaryorganizations;<strong>and</strong>,insome<br />

part,itsowneconomicinstitutions.German-,Ukrainian-,orItalian-speaking<br />

Canadians might have alanguage of <strong>the</strong>ir own, asense of group identity, a<br />

shared history, common customs, common cultural expression in literature,<br />

dance or music; but only English- <strong>and</strong> French-language groups had “distinct<br />

societies,” complete or nearly complete societies. Only English <strong>and</strong> French<br />

Canada could <strong>the</strong>refore be required to give recognition to one ano<strong>the</strong>r as<br />

“equal partners” in Canada.<br />

Citizenswhocamefromo<strong>the</strong>rlanguage<strong>and</strong>culturalgroupswerenot<strong>the</strong>reby<br />

excludedfrom<strong>the</strong>partnership,norrelegated,assomegroupswereclaiming,to<br />

<strong>the</strong> status of second-class citizens. This was because each of <strong>the</strong> two<br />

“societies”ofCanadawasanopensociety. “Whatweareaimingfor,<strong>the</strong>n,is<br />

<strong>the</strong>equalpartnershipofallwhospeakei<strong>the</strong>rlanguage<strong>and</strong>participateinei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

culture,whatever<strong>the</strong>irethnicorigin”(RCBBI1967:xxxix).Membershipin<br />

<strong>the</strong>“foundingpeoples”wasbasedonlearnable,choosableattributes:language<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> culture carried by that language. It did not depend on birth, on<br />

unchangeable,unsheddablecharacteristicslikeethnicoriginorcolour;noron<br />

attributesthatmightbechangeablebutweredeemedirrelevant,likereligion.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> Commission, <strong>the</strong> peoples of <strong>the</strong> partnership <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> societies <strong>the</strong>y<br />

constituted were thus fundamentally different from <strong>the</strong> baskets of individual<br />

atoms that Smiley <strong>and</strong> Forsey believed must be <strong>the</strong> sole objects of public<br />

“partnership” policy. <strong>The</strong>re were some circumstances, notably that of<br />

immigrantsforwhomnei<strong>the</strong>rFrenchnorEnglishwasmo<strong>the</strong>rtongue,when<strong>the</strong><br />

choice of anew “language group” <strong>and</strong> new culture might be acool decision<br />

basedonacalculusofself-interest. Butat<strong>the</strong>coreofbothEnglish-speaking<br />

Canada<strong>and</strong> French-speakingCanadawerepeopleforwhomlanguage,<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong><br />

cultureassociatedwiththatlanguage,weregiven,notchosen.<strong>The</strong>analysisof<br />

<strong>the</strong> Commission clearly implied that to create policy for <strong>the</strong> “partnership” by<br />

pretendingthatFrancophones<strong>and</strong>Anglophonewerechoice-basedaggregations<br />

riskedfailure<strong>and</strong>frustration.<br />

320


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

<strong>The</strong> Decline of Equal Partnership<br />

Shortly after <strong>the</strong> Commission had reported, <strong>the</strong> concept of equal partnership<br />

wentintoasteepdecline.At<strong>the</strong>scholarlylevel,<strong>the</strong>post-B&BCommission<br />

discussionsofFrench-Englishrelationstookastrangeturn. English-language<br />

writerson<strong>the</strong>wholewerefavourabletolanguagechange<strong>and</strong>especiallyto<strong>the</strong><br />

efforts to make <strong>the</strong> French-language capability of <strong>the</strong> federal public service<br />

muchgreater.<strong>The</strong>conceptofabilingualCanadawonmanyconverts,someof<br />

whom went far beyond <strong>the</strong> carefully demarcated official bilingualism of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission <strong>and</strong> called for personal bilingualism for all Canadians<br />

(Bercovitz<strong>and</strong>Logan1978:253).French-languagewriters,fascinatedby<strong>the</strong><br />

success of <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> revival of separatist thought,<br />

concentrated on problems of how much jurisdiction aQuebec government<br />

should have. <strong>The</strong> concept of equal partnership, with its roots in French-<br />

Canadian spokesmen like Henri Bourassa <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Quebec literature on a<br />

“compact between nations,” (Anglophone historians viewed any form of <strong>the</strong><br />

compact<strong>the</strong>orywithscepticism<strong>and</strong>suspicion),wasnowbeinghesitantly<strong>and</strong><br />

increasingly rarely enunciated—<strong>and</strong> only in its “linguistic parity” form—by<br />

Anglophones <strong>and</strong> by those federally-oriented Francophones who clustered<br />

around Pierre Trudeau. Equal partnership as aframe for <strong>the</strong> analysis of<br />

Quebec or Canadian politics was largely ignored by <strong>the</strong> history <strong>and</strong> political<br />

science departments of Quebec’s French-language universities.<br />

Whywas<strong>the</strong>possibilityofexaminingQuebec’sclaimsforautonomy<strong>and</strong>for<br />

enhanced powers within <strong>the</strong> framework of equal partnership so rarely<br />

exploited? Inlargepart,onemayconjecture,becauseof<strong>the</strong>failureof<strong>the</strong>B&<br />

BCommission to elaborate that framework as it had promised to do. A<br />

literature could have developed, one may speculate in retrospect, around <strong>the</strong><br />

trade-offs between power <strong>and</strong> recognition for Francophones across Canada<br />

<strong>and</strong>power<strong>and</strong>recognitionforQuebec.InEnglishCanada,comparisonscould<br />

have been made between <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> benefits of recognizing Quebec as a<br />

distinctsociety,apttogoitsownway,<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>costs<strong>and</strong>benefitsofincreased<br />

effortstomake<strong>the</strong>publicservicefullyrepresentativeofFrenchCanada<strong>and</strong>to<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong>institutionsof<strong>the</strong>French-languageminoritiesoutsideQuebec.<br />

In French Canada, <strong>and</strong> especially in Quebec, <strong>the</strong> risks of breaking <strong>the</strong><br />

partnership with English Canada ra<strong>the</strong>r than attempting to improve it could<br />

havebeenassessednotonlyineconomists’costs(<strong>the</strong>ineffable“bottomline”)<br />

but in terms of that rare study of Christian Dufour, which grasps <strong>the</strong><br />

interpenetration of French <strong>and</strong> English Canada <strong>and</strong> takes into account social<br />

<strong>and</strong>political(<strong>and</strong>indeedcultural)coststhatabreakin<strong>the</strong>partnershipwould<br />

probably entail (Dufour 1990).<br />

Whatever<strong>the</strong>reasonsmayhavebeen,<strong>the</strong>factof<strong>the</strong>neardisappearanceof<strong>the</strong><br />

concept of equal partnership by <strong>the</strong> late 1980s can readily be documented.<br />

Smiley himself, in <strong>the</strong> few years that separate his enthusiastic espousal of<br />

“individualistic”equalpartnership(1967)<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>publicationofhisstudyon<br />

Canadian federalism for <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission (1970) concentrated on<br />

categoriesofanalysisthatrequiredonlyacasualmention,inquotationmarks,<br />

of“twofoundingraces”(Smiley1970:119). Hisfearthatastatutparticulier<br />

for Quebec was becoming <strong>the</strong> main thrust of Francophone dem<strong>and</strong>s on <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>,apossibilitytha<strong>the</strong>hadrecognized<strong>and</strong>flatlyopposedin1967,<br />

perhaps induced afear that continued support for any concept of equal<br />

partnership might reinforce that trend. <strong>The</strong>nceforth, “equal partnership”<br />

disappears from Smiley’s political lexicon.<br />

321


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Wherediditsurvive?WecanfindreferencetoitinJohnMeisel’scontribution<br />

to <strong>the</strong> University of Toronto’s “Options” conference in 1977, where he<br />

described<strong>the</strong>resultsofasurveywhichshowedthatbetween80<strong>and</strong>90percent<br />

ofAnglophonesinCanada“tacitlyreject<strong>the</strong>notionthatthiscountryisbased<br />

on acompact between <strong>the</strong> two founding peoples” (Meisel 1977:16). It is<br />

resoundingly re-endorsed by Davidson Dunton, one of <strong>the</strong> B & B<br />

Commission’s Co-Chairmen, when he called for “a true mutual sense of<br />

equality<strong>and</strong>partnership”(Dunton1978). Butwhenoneturnstocompilations<br />

on Canada’s constitutional problems in <strong>the</strong> 1980s <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> first years of <strong>the</strong><br />

1990s, one is hard put to find “equal partnership” in any o<strong>the</strong>r form than a<br />

quotationfrom<strong>the</strong>B&BCommission’sm<strong>and</strong>ate,on<strong>the</strong>rareoccasionswhen<br />

that Commission is still referred to. 3<br />

<strong>The</strong> disappearance of <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission’s “mainspring” phrase from<br />

scholarlydiscussionsofCanadianpolitics,especiallyin<strong>the</strong>Englishlanguage,<br />

isprobablybestaccountedfor,however,byreasonsrelatingonlyremotelyto<br />

<strong>the</strong> incompleteness of <strong>the</strong> Commission’s final report. <strong>The</strong> following factors<br />

were telling: 1) opposition from anew Liberal Prime Minister of Canada,<br />

Pierre-ElliottTrudeau;2)<strong>the</strong>riseofmulti-culturalism,especiallyinitsinitial<br />

form as a“third force”; 3) <strong>the</strong> increased strength of Western regionalism; 4)<br />

Quebec’s repudiation of bilingualism for <strong>the</strong> province (<strong>and</strong> not just by Parti<br />

Québécoisindépendentistes);5)<strong>the</strong>thrustofclaimsfromindigenouspeoples;<br />

<strong>and</strong>6)<strong>the</strong>emergenceof“<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>”Canadianswithanewsenseofcitizenship.<br />

Prime Minister Trudeau<br />

Trudeau’sthoughton<strong>the</strong>Canadian<strong>Constitution</strong>coincideswiththatof<strong>the</strong>B&<br />

BCommission on <strong>the</strong> meaning of bilingualism <strong>and</strong> on its fundamental<br />

importance. When it comes to equal partnership, as defined by <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission, he is miles away. He summed up <strong>the</strong> difference succinctly in<br />

1988.“Bilingualismunitespeople;dualismdivides<strong>the</strong>m. Bilingualismmeans<br />

thatyoucanspeakto<strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r;dualitymeansyoucanliveinonelanguage<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>restofCanadawillliveinano<strong>the</strong>rlanguage...”(Senate1988). <strong>The</strong>B&B<br />

Commissioninsistedthateffectivepublicrecognitionoftwolanguagesmust<br />

becoupledwithrecognitionofaFrenchsocietyinQuebec,thuspermittinga<br />

duality based on an equilibrium of contexts in which two peoples are<br />

alternately majority <strong>and</strong> minority. Trudeau’s model is quite different <strong>and</strong> a<br />

shared belief in bilingualism as anational policy should not be permitted to<br />

cover up <strong>the</strong> contrasts between <strong>the</strong> two.<br />

Multiculturalism<br />

Canadians who did not come from <strong>the</strong> “two founding races” choked on <strong>the</strong><br />

conceptofequalpartnership.<strong>The</strong>Commissionmadeastrongefforttoexplain<br />

thatitrepudiated<strong>the</strong>word“race”;itsequalpartnershipwasbetweenlanguages<br />

groups into which <strong>the</strong>re was free entry <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, every citizen was<br />

potentiallyincludedin<strong>the</strong>partnership.Itsbiculturalismwasalsobasedonan<br />

open set of categories, for by adopting one or o<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> two official<br />

languages one could enter into <strong>the</strong> culture for which that language was <strong>the</strong><br />

major vehicle. Finally, <strong>the</strong> Commission proposed ways by which <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

cultural groups might maintain <strong>the</strong>ir vitality <strong>and</strong> contribute to Canadian<br />

enrichment.Indoingso,itwascarefulnottogivecredenceto<strong>the</strong>ideathatby<br />

adding toge<strong>the</strong>r all <strong>the</strong> “o<strong>the</strong>r” ethnic groups in Canada, one could identify a<br />

“third force,” non-French, non-English, that rivalled <strong>the</strong> founding peoples in<br />

significance. André <strong>La</strong>urendeau was particularly unconvinced by an<br />

322


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

arithmetic that added Chinese, Italian, Caribbean <strong>and</strong> Slavic Canadians<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>rtocreateasummedsocialentityequivalenttoFrenchCanada.<strong>The</strong>B<br />

&BCommission concluded that: “All <strong>the</strong> available evidence indicates that<br />

those of o<strong>the</strong>r languages <strong>and</strong> cultures are more or less integrated with <strong>the</strong><br />

Francophone <strong>and</strong> Anglophone communities, where <strong>the</strong>y should find<br />

opportunitiesforself-fulfilment<strong>and</strong>equalityofstatus. Itiswithin<strong>the</strong>setwo<br />

societiesthat<strong>the</strong>irculturaldistinctivenessshouldfindaclimateofrespect<strong>and</strong><br />

encouragement to survive” (RCBB IV 1970:10).<br />

None of this flattened <strong>the</strong> wave of resentment against equal partnership that<br />

came from <strong>the</strong> politicians <strong>and</strong> associations that spoke for <strong>the</strong> citizens <strong>and</strong><br />

descendants of citizens who came from non-Anglophone, non- Francophone<br />

countries. Shortly after Trudeau became Prime Minister, multiculturalism<br />

replacedbiculturalismasofficialpolicy<strong>and</strong>inofficialrhetoric.Thatelement<br />

of“equalpartnership”thatcamefromarecognitionof“founding”cultures—<br />

thosewhogave<strong>the</strong>originalshape<strong>and</strong>characterto<strong>the</strong>statethatwascreatedin<br />

1867<strong>and</strong>in<strong>the</strong>yearsbefore—wasthusundermined,<strong>and</strong>using<strong>the</strong>term“equal<br />

partnership”becamemoretouchy.AspokesmanforUkrainianCanadianswas<br />

using language quite acceptable to many ethnocultural minority associations<br />

when he referred to “<strong>the</strong> outdated <strong>and</strong> discredited concept of two founding<br />

nations” (Special Joint Committee 1987 [2]).<br />

Western Assertions<br />

Often <strong>the</strong> term “regionalism” is used to describe <strong>the</strong> campaign for greater<br />

recognition that became afixed (though by no means novel) part of western<br />

Canadian politics during <strong>the</strong> 70s, 80s <strong>and</strong> 90s. But though echoes of protest<br />

againstcentralCanadi<strong>and</strong>ominancecamefrom<strong>the</strong>Atlantic<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>North,<strong>the</strong><br />

constitutional position that regional equilibrium was just as important as<br />

French-Englishequilibriumgaineditsgreateststrengthin<strong>the</strong>West.Smileyis<br />

undoubtedlycorrectwhenheinterprets<strong>the</strong>1979Pepin-RobartsReport’supgradingof“regionalcleavage”toalmost<strong>the</strong>samelevelas<strong>the</strong>French-English<br />

cleavage as <strong>the</strong> consequence of primarily Western pressures (Task Force on<br />

Canadian Unity 1979). It is not tempting to base analysis of Canadian<br />

constitutional problems primarily on “equal partnership” between<br />

Francophones <strong>and</strong> Anglophones if regionalism is almost as important.<br />

Quebec’s Dilution of Quebec Bilingualism<br />

Among English-speaking Canadians, “equal partnership” meant putting <strong>the</strong><br />

French language on <strong>the</strong> same plane as English for federal government<br />

operations across Canada, <strong>and</strong> increased recognition of French by provincial<br />

governments with significant Francophone populations. Bilingualism as<br />

publicpolicywas“equalpartnership.”ForaQuebecgovernmenttoreduce<strong>the</strong><br />

extent to which it gave recognition to bilingualism thus meant that “equal<br />

partnership” was undermined in aradical fashion. Whatever temptation one<br />

mighthavehadtomakeuseof<strong>the</strong>conceptseemedtoevaporateifthatwasnot<br />

afterallwhatQuebecreallywanted.ThataseparatistpartyinpowerinQuebec<br />

passed alanguage law (Bill 101) that reduced Anglophone’s rights <strong>and</strong><br />

privileges might be underst<strong>and</strong>able: <strong>the</strong> separatist Parti Québécois had no<br />

interest in“equal partnership”within <strong>the</strong>Canadian federal system. Butfor a<br />

Liberal party government to override <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court <strong>and</strong> pass an only<br />

slightly less restrictive law (Bill 178) seemed to make nonsense of equalpartnership-as-bilingualism.<br />

323


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Claims from Indigenous Peoples<br />

<strong>The</strong>B&BCommissionwasquiteconsciousthatinclusionofCanada’snative<br />

peoplesin<strong>the</strong>fundamentalpartnershipcouldnotbeaccomplishedinexactly<br />

<strong>the</strong> same way as <strong>the</strong>y had deemed appropriate for “allophones.” <strong>The</strong>y noted<br />

that<strong>the</strong>ywere“lessintegratedin<strong>the</strong>lifeof<strong>the</strong>Canadiancommunitythanany<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rgroup<strong>and</strong>wouldthusrequirespecialstudy”(RCBB1965:22).InBookI<br />

of<strong>the</strong>finalreport,<strong>the</strong>“BluePages”referagainto“verycomplexproblems”of<br />

integration<strong>and</strong>urgethat“helpbegivento<strong>the</strong>nativepopulationstopreserve<br />

<strong>the</strong>irculturalheritage”<strong>and</strong>thatnecessarystepsbetakentoassure<strong>the</strong>survival<br />

of<strong>the</strong>Eskimolanguage<strong>and</strong>“<strong>the</strong>mostcommonIndi<strong>and</strong>ialects”(RCBB1967:<br />

xxvi-xxvii). How <strong>the</strong> special characteristics of indigenous cultures fit <strong>the</strong><br />

concept of partnership is left unexamined, although <strong>the</strong> use of “integration”<br />

seemstoprejudgethatquestion,<strong>and</strong>itisnotsurprisingthatthosewhospeak<br />

for<strong>the</strong>nativepeopleshavehad,since<strong>the</strong>n,littletimeorsympathyfor“equal<br />

partnershipbetween<strong>the</strong>twofoundingraces.”Recognitionin<strong>the</strong>Meech<strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord that <strong>the</strong> existence of English-speaking <strong>and</strong> French-speaking<br />

Canadians “constitutes afundamental characteristic of Canada” <strong>and</strong> that it is<br />

<strong>the</strong>roleof<strong>the</strong>ParliamentofCanada<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>provinciallegislaturestopreserve<br />

this fundamental characteristic (<strong>Constitution</strong> Act, 1987. 1.2.(1) (a) <strong>and</strong> 1.2)<br />

provokedanger<strong>and</strong>dismayin<strong>the</strong>leadersofindigenousgroups<strong>and</strong>adem<strong>and</strong><br />

for constitutional recognition of aboriginal peoples as distinct societies that<br />

constitute afundamental characteristic of Canada (Special Joint Committee<br />

1987[2}).<br />

“<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” Canadians<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is acertain irony in <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> late John Porter used to label<br />

English- <strong>and</strong> French-Canadians as <strong>the</strong> two “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” groups in Canadian<br />

society (Porter 1964). By <strong>the</strong> 1990s, references to <strong>the</strong> “<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>” meant <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>ofRights<strong>and</strong>Freedoms,<strong>and</strong>ProfessorCairnshadlaunched<strong>the</strong>ideaof<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>Canadians“whosee<strong>the</strong>mselvesascitizensofanationalcommunity”<br />

(Cairns 1989:118). Cairns identifies an “implicit <strong>and</strong> explicit assumption of<br />

groups <strong>and</strong> interests defined by gender, by ethnicity, by aboriginal<br />

background,bysocialpolicyconcerns,<strong>and</strong>bybasicconceptionsofanational<br />

communityofrightsbearersthat<strong>the</strong>Canadianconstitutionof<strong>the</strong>lateeighties<br />

withits<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>ofRightsisacitizens’constitution”(117).For<strong>the</strong>m,<strong>the</strong>idea<br />

of equal partnership is far from <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> Canadian state; it is close to<br />

being <strong>the</strong> anti<strong>the</strong>sis of what <strong>the</strong>y believe Canada should be. Cairns suggests<br />

that<strong>the</strong>ybegantodefine<strong>the</strong>mselvesthrough<strong>the</strong>battles<strong>the</strong>yfoughtagainst<strong>the</strong><br />

B&BCommission’s conception of equal partnership. <strong>The</strong> groups whose<br />

members are <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Canadians “have <strong>the</strong>ir separate histories of<br />

triumphs—memories of when biculturalism was replaced with<br />

multiculturalism,when<strong>the</strong>ywonS28[women’srights],when<strong>the</strong>iraboriginal<br />

rightsreceivedconstitutionalrecognition”(118).Inshort,memoriesofwhen<br />

<strong>the</strong>y eroded <strong>the</strong> concept of an equal partnership between <strong>the</strong> two founding<br />

peoples.<br />

With faulty interpretation, academic rejection (or at least neglect) <strong>and</strong> a<br />

complexofpoliticalforcessuchasthosedescribedabovearrayedagainstit,it<br />

would not be surprising if <strong>the</strong> concept of equal partnership was deemed to<br />

meritpermanentinterment.Iamgoingtoargueagainstburial.Forwithallits<br />

faults equal partnership provides astarting point, in its B&BCommission<br />

version, for a <strong>the</strong>oretical justification of <strong>the</strong> seemingly incoherent<br />

compromises in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Agreement of August 1992.<br />

324


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Agreement<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Agreement can be seen as acombination of just those<br />

elementsthat<strong>the</strong>B&BCommissioninsistedwouldhavetogointoanequal<br />

partnership. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Agreement can be seen as a more extensive<br />

embodiment of those principles than were <strong>the</strong> recommendations of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong>costsofbeingFrancophoneinCanadaasawholehavebeencontrolled<br />

<strong>and</strong> afloor has been put under <strong>the</strong>m. Each Canadian government has <strong>the</strong><br />

obligationtoprotectboth<strong>the</strong>English<strong>and</strong>Frenchlanguages;<strong>the</strong>representation<br />

ofQuebeccannotfallbelow25percentin<strong>the</strong>HouseofCommons;<strong>and</strong>double<br />

majorities in <strong>the</strong> new Senate are needed for <strong>the</strong> passage of bills on language<br />

questions. Quebec is recognized as constituting adistinct society within<br />

Canada. Quebec’s right to name <strong>the</strong> three Civil <strong>La</strong>w judges who sit on <strong>the</strong><br />

Supreme Court of Canada is spelled out.<br />

For indépendentistes, <strong>the</strong> Agreement is disastrous. It knits Quebec <strong>and</strong><br />

Francophone Canadians as awhole more closely into <strong>the</strong> fabric of <strong>the</strong><br />

Canadianstatethaneverbefore.But<strong>the</strong>Agreementisalsoworrisomeforthose<br />

Quebecerswhoarenotquiteseparatist.ThosewhowantQuebecuntil<strong>the</strong>last<br />

possiblemomenttobeunencumberedwithagreed-uponties<strong>and</strong>interlinkages<br />

withCanada,sothatQuebeccankeeponaddingtoitslevelofautonomy,keep<br />

movingeverclosertosovereignindependencewithouthavingtopay<strong>the</strong>final<br />

cost of getting <strong>the</strong>re—those Quebec nationalists too have greeted <strong>the</strong><br />

Agreement with dismay. Lise Bissonnette of Le Devoir, in her remarkable<br />

editorial“LeMur”called<strong>the</strong>Agreementa“triomphedel’espritminoritaire”<br />

(LeDevoir,24August1992).And,inonesense,indeeditwas.Francophones<br />

whoare<strong>and</strong>willbeaminorityinCanadaasawholeforaslongasitpersists<br />

have gained abroader set of minority rights than <strong>the</strong>y have ever enjoyed<br />

before. Nothing has been lost from <strong>the</strong> first great push towards reducing <strong>the</strong><br />

costs of being Francophone in Canada—marked by <strong>the</strong> federal Official<br />

<strong>La</strong>nguagesAct,byNewBrunswickbecominganofficiallybilingualprovince,<br />

<strong>and</strong>bygainsineducation<strong>and</strong> in<strong>the</strong>courts—<strong>and</strong>agreatdealhasbeenadded.<br />

Ifthatwereall,<strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong>Agreementcouldfinditsplacein<strong>the</strong>time-honoured<br />

categoryofminorityrights,<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>conceptofequalpartnershipcouldremain<br />

tuckedawayin<strong>the</strong>atticofoutmodedconstitutionalfashions.Butitisnotall.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Agreement preserves all <strong>the</strong> elements of community<br />

recognitionforQuebec’sdistinctsocietythatwerein<strong>the</strong>Meech<strong>La</strong>keaccord<br />

<strong>and</strong> embeds <strong>the</strong>m in a complex of o<strong>the</strong>r community recognitions. <strong>The</strong><br />

communities of native peoples have <strong>the</strong>ir inherent right to self-government<br />

acknowledged; provincial communities receive “partnership” recognition in<br />

<strong>the</strong> equal Senate, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> process, awestern community viewpoint is<br />

validated.Canadabecomesa“communityofcommunities”inaformalsense.<br />

<strong>The</strong>importofQuebecbeingrecognizedasadistinctsocietyisnotdiminished<br />

by <strong>the</strong> new recognitions of community. But <strong>the</strong> contextual change alters its<br />

significance. First, it becomes impossible for Anglophones to dismiss <strong>the</strong><br />

Agreementonadistinctsocietyasjustasano<strong>the</strong>r“concessionto<strong>the</strong>French,”<br />

forabroadlysimilar“concession”hasbeenmadetonativepeoples.Secondly,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Agreement underlines <strong>the</strong> obligation for Quebec as well as <strong>the</strong> rest of<br />

Canadatoaskitselfwhatapartnershipwithself-governingnativepeopleswill<br />

mean,<strong>and</strong>challengesQuebectofindwaysofreconciling<strong>the</strong>argumentsthatit<br />

hasusedfordem<strong>and</strong>ingpowersforitselfwiththosethatwillbepresented,in<br />

only slightly modified form, by indigenous peoples.<br />

325


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

<strong>The</strong>crucialinsightof<strong>the</strong>B&BCommissionwasthatastablebaseforFrench-<br />

English cooperation cannot be achieved just by increasing French minority<br />

rightsinCanadaasawhole(seenasasinglecommunity)butmustalsoinvolve<br />

<strong>the</strong> exercise of aset of powers, adequate for community development, by a<br />

community jurisdiction (Quebec) in which <strong>the</strong> country- wide minority<br />

(Francophones)isamajority.Thisinsight,<strong>the</strong>sensegivenby<strong>the</strong>Commission<br />

to<strong>the</strong>conceptofequalpartnership,hasnowbeenembodiedinnew,complex,<br />

but ultimately compatible ways, in <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord. Indeed, its<br />

approach to partnership has been extended to o<strong>the</strong>r communities—ethnic<br />

communities,provincialcommunities—<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>challengeofworkingout<strong>the</strong><br />

terms of different kinds of partnerships is thrust inexorably upon Canadians.<br />

Had <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Agreement, by referendum <strong>and</strong> by legislative<br />

enactment, become <strong>the</strong> new base for Canada’s <strong>Constitution</strong>, many people<br />

would have explained this fact as <strong>the</strong> acceptance of a hodgepodge of<br />

compromises by apopulation suffering from <strong>Constitution</strong>-fatigue. If that<br />

attitudepersists,<strong>the</strong>possibilityofanystablenewarrangementsfor<strong>the</strong>future,<br />

basedinsomemeasureon<strong>the</strong>Agreement,willbejeopardized,foreventually<br />

most of us want to find coherence in our behaviour. Any new constitution<br />

should reside in a“house of <strong>the</strong>ory.” 4 Are <strong>the</strong> architects’ drawings for that<br />

house available? Perhaps not, but preliminary sketches can be found.<br />

Individuals <strong>and</strong> Communities<br />

Recognition of community rights still arouses deep disquiet among many,<br />

especiallyEnglishCanadians,whobelievethatcommunityrightsnecessarily<br />

jeopardizeindividualrights.Thisdisquietemanatesfrom<strong>the</strong>classicalliberalindividualistposition<strong>and</strong>ithasatleasttwoaspects.<br />

First,itisarguedthat<strong>the</strong><br />

stateshouldnotsubsidizeparticularobjectivesofparticulargroupswithfunds<br />

thatcomefromcitizensmostofwhomdonotshare,<strong>and</strong>mayindeedbehostile<br />

to, <strong>the</strong>se objectives. For a country where public subsidization of<br />

denominationalschoolsisacommonplace,thispositionmayseemstrange;yet<br />

itsstrengthisundeniable. RecognitionofadistinctQuebecsociety<strong>and</strong>of<strong>the</strong><br />

inherentrightofaboriginalsocietiestoself-government,itissaid,willleadto<br />

public resources being diverted to particular groups to which most citizens<br />

cannot,ordonotwantto,belong.Secondly,itismaintainedthatrecognizing<br />

rightsforsomecommunities<strong>and</strong>noto<strong>the</strong>rsdividescitizensintofirst-class<strong>and</strong><br />

second-classcategories.IfFrancophonesinQuebecaretoberecognizedasa<br />

distinct society, why not Ukrainians in Manitoba? If aboriginals have an<br />

inherent right to self-government, why not Japanese Canadians?<br />

Justifying rights to communities means recognizing that diversity, more<br />

profound than <strong>the</strong> differences taken into account in pluralist <strong>the</strong>ory,<br />

characterizes <strong>the</strong> Canadian state. Charles Taylor argues cogently that<br />

Canadiansmustthinkthrough<strong>the</strong>implicationsof“deepdiversity”muchmore<br />

thoroughly than <strong>the</strong>y have done in <strong>the</strong> past (Taylor 1991). Historically,<br />

Anglophones especially were reluctant to do so because <strong>the</strong>y hoped that<br />

eventually all citizens would see <strong>the</strong>mselves in <strong>the</strong>ir relation to <strong>the</strong> state in<br />

roughly <strong>the</strong> same way. Industrialism, secularism, <strong>and</strong> urbanization were all<br />

supposedtoreduce<strong>the</strong>specificityinself-definitionofQuebec’sFrancophones<br />

<strong>and</strong>tomakeitpossibletotreat<strong>the</strong>masindividualslikeall<strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rindividuals<br />

inCanada.ButQuebecnationalismbecamestrongernotweaker;<strong>the</strong>hopefora<br />

homogeneity of outlook became more <strong>and</strong> more illusory.<br />

326


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

Liberal <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> Equal Partnership<br />

<strong>The</strong>reisawayoflookingatCanada’senduringdualism,awayofreconciling<br />

oneselftoarecognitionofQuebec’sdistinctness,thatdoesnotoffendliberal<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory. This is so because liberal <strong>the</strong>ory cannot specify <strong>the</strong> “right” body of<br />

citizens to constitute astate. If some part of <strong>the</strong> citizenry of astate decides<br />

to—<strong>and</strong>isableto—constituteanewstateinwhich<strong>the</strong>freedomofallisfully<br />

protected <strong>and</strong> individual rights are meticulously respected, liberal <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

cannotprovideareasonwhythisnewstateisinferiorto<strong>the</strong>onefromwhichit<br />

brokeaway. Indeed,mostliberal<strong>the</strong>orysimplyassumesthatanexistingstate<br />

is<strong>the</strong>frameworkinwhichindividualsassert<strong>the</strong>irrights,including<strong>the</strong>rightto<br />

haveallkeypublicinstitutionsrunin<strong>the</strong>irownlanguage<strong>and</strong>accordingto<strong>the</strong>ir<br />

culturalnorms<strong>and</strong>style. IfliberalscouldprovethatCanadaincludingQuebec<br />

was<strong>the</strong>unique“right”stateforallindividualswithinittorealize<strong>the</strong>irrights,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong>caseforsubsidizing<strong>the</strong>peculiarlanguagepreferences<strong>and</strong>ahighlevel<br />

ofautonomyforsomelargesubsetofindividualswouldindeedbedifficultto<br />

bringunder<strong>the</strong>liberal<strong>the</strong>oreticalumbrella. Sincenosuchproofisavailable<br />

<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>possibilityofaseparate(stillliberal)Quebecstateisfarfrombeinga<br />

chimera, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> problems of Francophone-Anglophone relations can quite<br />

properly be dealt with by <strong>the</strong> most libertarian of liberals as aproblem of <strong>the</strong><br />

termsofpartnership.BecauseFrancophoneQuébécoisdoconstituteadistinct<br />

society,capableofformingastateof<strong>the</strong>irown,<strong>the</strong>ycomm<strong>and</strong>recognitionas<br />

such in a way no o<strong>the</strong>r linguistic or cultural group does.<br />

<strong>The</strong> case for special recognition of <strong>the</strong> communities of indigenous peoples<br />

cannotbemadeinthisway,butWillKymlickahasshownhowit,too,isquite<br />

reconcilable with liberalism (Kymlicka 1989 <strong>and</strong> 1991). His arguments also<br />

applytoo<strong>the</strong>rculturalgroups. Hebeginsbysummarizing<strong>the</strong>orthodoxliberal<br />

position that asystem of universal individual rights is all that is needed to<br />

protectculturaldifferences. Freedomofassociationiseveryone’sright<strong>and</strong>it<br />

enablesaculturalgroupthatwantstopreserveitsdistinctnesstodoso,aslong<br />

asitcancompetein<strong>the</strong>“culturalmarketplace.”“Onthisview,givingpolitical<br />

recognition or support to particular cultural practices or associations is<br />

unnecessary<strong>and</strong>unfair.Itisunnecessary,becauseavaluablewayoflifewill<br />

havenodifficultyattractingadherents. Anditisunfair,becauseitsubsidizes<br />

some people’s choices at <strong>the</strong> expense of o<strong>the</strong>rs.” Kymlicka <strong>the</strong>n shows that<br />

somegroupsareunfairlydisadvantagedin<strong>the</strong>culturalmarketplace. Minority<br />

cultures are under constant pressure from <strong>the</strong> majority that surrounds <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y have to struggle to survive, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y do so since “language <strong>and</strong> culture<br />

provide <strong>the</strong> context within which we make our choices. Loss of cultural<br />

membership, <strong>the</strong>refore, is aprofound harm that reduces one’s very ability to<br />

make meaningful choices. Hence special rights compensate for unequal<br />

circumstances which put <strong>the</strong> members of minority cultures at asystematic<br />

disadvantagein<strong>the</strong>culturalmarketplace,regardlessof<strong>the</strong>irpersonalchoices<br />

in life (Kymlicka forthcoming).<br />

Ifclaimsforcommunityaremadeinei<strong>the</strong>rof<strong>the</strong>waysoutlined,<strong>the</strong>casefor<br />

constitutional recognition of Quebec’s distinct society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> case for selfgovernment<br />

for aboriginal peoples can be made without doing violence to<br />

liberal <strong>the</strong>ory. Both instances exemplify <strong>the</strong> fundamental premise that equal<br />

partnershipamongcommunities,achievedbychanging<strong>the</strong>balanceofcost<strong>and</strong><br />

benefits, is agoal that can be reconciled with <strong>the</strong> goal of personal equality<br />

amongst citizens <strong>and</strong> equal respect for <strong>the</strong> choices that persons make.<br />

327


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Aboriginal Communities <strong>and</strong> Multiculturalism<br />

Towhatextentcan<strong>the</strong>“equalopportunity”argumentthatjustifiesaboriginal<br />

community claims—<strong>the</strong> difficulty for aboriginal people of gaining access to<br />

<strong>the</strong> same range of personal choices available to members of <strong>the</strong> majority<br />

culture—also be used to advance claims for special cultural recognition by<br />

membersofimmigrantculturalgroups?Undeniably,immigrantswouldfindit<br />

easiertoleadfulllivesinCanadaif<strong>the</strong>yretained<strong>the</strong>culturalsupportsthatuse<br />

of<strong>the</strong>irlanguage<strong>and</strong>afamiliarculturalenvironmentprovide. In<strong>the</strong>nameof<br />

consistency, should some measure of community self-government be made<br />

available to o<strong>the</strong>r ethnic groups? Kymlicka suggests that <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

immigrants chose to come to Canada means that <strong>the</strong>y “<strong>the</strong>reby relinquished<br />

some of <strong>the</strong>ir rights to cultural protection that <strong>the</strong>y would have had in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

originalhomel<strong>and</strong>.”(Kymlicka1991).Thisdistinctionisnotfullysatisfactory<br />

since <strong>the</strong> “choice” made by at least one class of immigrants, refugees, is far<br />

from free. Tests of “practicability” (is <strong>the</strong>re apopulation concentration that<br />

permits alarge measure of community self-determination?) <strong>and</strong> will (how<br />

much cultural isolation, <strong>the</strong> concomitant of communal particularism, is<br />

desired?)maybepreferable. <strong>The</strong>B&BCommission’sdecisiontoconfineits<br />

discussions of partnership to Francophone/Anglophone relations <strong>and</strong> to be<br />

satisfiedwithminority/majorityrelationsforo<strong>the</strong>rethnicgroupsisnohelpasa<br />

guide to amore satisfying position. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Accord made no<br />

advanceoverSection27of<strong>the</strong><strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>ofRights<strong>and</strong>Freedoms,whichstates:<br />

“This<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>shallbeinterpretedinamannerconsistentwith<strong>the</strong>preservation<br />

<strong>and</strong> enhancement of <strong>the</strong> multicultural heritage of Canadians.” <strong>The</strong> house of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, quite sturdy where it covers a“distinct society” for Quebec <strong>and</strong> selfgovernment<br />

for aboriginals, has a ramshackle multicultural wing.<br />

Streng<strong>the</strong>ningitprobablyinvolvesacontinuingdialecticbetweenconceptsof<br />

cultural partnership <strong>and</strong> equal personal rights.<br />

A Complex of Equalities<br />

<strong>The</strong>CharlottetownAgreementnotonlydem<strong>and</strong>sthatliberalindividualismbe<br />

reconciled with acultural collective perspective, it also requires abridging<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r collectivities. <strong>The</strong> main thrust of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong><br />

Freedomsisundoubtedlythatofindividualrights,butindividualismhastolive<br />

withfederalism<strong>and</strong>with<strong>the</strong>pluralismthathasbecomesointegralapartof<strong>the</strong><br />

liberal-democratic state. Even <strong>the</strong> most fervent advocate of equal individual<br />

rightsdoesnotquestion<strong>the</strong>restrictionon<strong>the</strong>freedomofaSaskatchewancar<br />

driverwhomightwanttodisplayaNewBrunswicklicenceplateorobjectto<br />

one province’s sales tax being higher than ano<strong>the</strong>r. <strong>Federalism</strong> means that<br />

Canadians’rightsvaryaccordingto<strong>the</strong>provincialorterritorialcollectivitiesto<br />

which<strong>the</strong>ybelong.<strong>The</strong><strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>simplymakes“fundamental”rightsidentical<br />

throughoutCanada. Similarly,tradeunions,professionalassociations,clubs<br />

<strong>and</strong>societiesbestowspecialrights<strong>and</strong>responsibilitieson<strong>the</strong>irmembers,<strong>and</strong><br />

as long as <strong>the</strong>se collectivities can be entered <strong>and</strong> left without unreasonable<br />

barriers having to be crossed, we not only accept differential rights being<br />

bestowedon<strong>the</strong>irmembers,butvalue<strong>the</strong>differences.Fewliberal-democrats<br />

today share Rousseau’s worry that pluralism creates particular wills that<br />

threaten <strong>the</strong> general good.<br />

Alan Cairns’ contention that <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Canadians saw <strong>the</strong>ir rights trampled on<br />

by governments who met toge<strong>the</strong>r in secret at Meech <strong>La</strong>ke to redistribute<br />

rights, describes aposition held by many Canadians. <strong>The</strong> extensive hearings<br />

acrossCanadathatpreceded<strong>the</strong>negotiationsleading<strong>the</strong>1992Charlottetown<br />

328


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

Agreement were a needed response to <strong>the</strong> widespread feeling that <strong>the</strong><br />

procedures of executive federalism were sadly lacking. But if <strong>the</strong> contrast<br />

between “people” <strong>and</strong> “governments” is pushed as far as Cairns does in<br />

<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong> (Cairns 1992), it underestimates <strong>the</strong> strong<br />

attachmenttoprovince,<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>sensethat<strong>the</strong>provincialgovernmentis<strong>the</strong>ir<br />

government,thatmanyCanadiansdisplay<strong>and</strong>thatisgivennewsaliencein<strong>the</strong><br />

equalSenaterepresentationof<strong>the</strong>CharlottetownAgreement.<strong>The</strong>strengthof<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s for more direct democracy can be taken into account without an<br />

inference that representative democracy at <strong>the</strong> provincial level has been<br />

discredited. <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> Canadians give primacy to <strong>the</strong> single community of all<br />

Canadians. <strong>The</strong> Charlottetown Agreement, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> procedures leading to it,<br />

grantmuchto<strong>the</strong><strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>Canadianposition,but<strong>the</strong>Accordinsistsonrespect<br />

forthosemanyo<strong>the</strong>rCanadianswhomayseeo<strong>the</strong>rcommunities,o<strong>the</strong>rforms<br />

of collective identity—whe<strong>the</strong>r distinguished by language, province, region,<br />

religionorassociation—asvaluedframeworksfor<strong>the</strong>irself-realization.Intercommunity<br />

partnership models may seem much more appropriate, even<br />

thoughagreementsunder<strong>the</strong>mmustbeworkedoutbyindirect,representative,<br />

democratic forms, than <strong>the</strong> direct democracy of identical-rights-bearing<br />

Canadians.<br />

Cairns, of course, is fully aware that federalism, with its stress on provinces<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir governments, is something that even <strong>the</strong> most ardent <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong><br />

Canadians must <strong>and</strong> do accept. He identifies as <strong>the</strong> challenge for Canadian<br />

constitutional renewal—a challenge that was met for better or worse in<br />

Charlottetown in August 1992—<strong>the</strong> simultaneous realization of three<br />

equalities: of citizens, of provinces <strong>and</strong> of two nations (Cairns 1991:77).<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se are exactly <strong>the</strong> right, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> only right, kinds of equality that<br />

Canadamustseektoachieveismuchlessimportantthan<strong>the</strong>re-appearancein<br />

scholarly writing of <strong>the</strong> concept of equal partnerships. One can hope that it<br />

heraldsadecisivedeparturefrom<strong>the</strong>discourseofmajority-minorityrelations,<br />

<strong>and</strong> of asingle, st<strong>and</strong>ardized relationship between each citizen <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state,<br />

thatsoinhibits<strong>the</strong>searchfor“newequalities.” Canada’sfirststepawayfrom<br />

<strong>the</strong>singlecommunitymodelexemplifiedinparliamentarydemocracycamein<br />

1867 with its adoption of federalism. <strong>Federalism</strong> means co-ordinate powers<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than ahierarchy of decentralization, <strong>and</strong> recognizes <strong>the</strong> validity of<br />

communities,basedongeography,withinapolity. Taking<strong>the</strong>nextstep,<strong>and</strong><br />

recognizingFrancophone-Anglophonedualism;<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>ntakingano<strong>the</strong>rstep<br />

<strong>and</strong> recognizing <strong>the</strong> inherent right to self-government of communities of<br />

indigenous people; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n taking yet ano<strong>the</strong>r step <strong>and</strong> working out <strong>the</strong><br />

complexities of multiculturalism; <strong>and</strong> doing all this without destroying <strong>the</strong><br />

integrity of <strong>the</strong> community of all Canadians, exemplified by <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>—<br />

<strong>the</strong>se are <strong>the</strong> challenges which were accepted at Charlottetown. It will be<br />

fascinating to see whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> “house of <strong>the</strong>ory” that can accommodate <strong>the</strong><br />

various partnerships <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir various equalities can be built.<br />

Conclusion<br />

This essay was written before <strong>the</strong> rejection by referendum of <strong>the</strong><br />

Charlottetown Agreement <strong>and</strong> has been revised only very lightly. It is too<br />

early to predict when <strong>and</strong> precisely how <strong>the</strong> constitutional foundations of<br />

Canadawillagainhead<strong>the</strong>policyagenda.<strong>The</strong>problems<strong>the</strong>Agreementwas<br />

intended to answer have not disappeared, however, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> task of finding a<br />

satisfactory <strong>the</strong>oretic basis for <strong>the</strong> Canadian polity remains. Aconcerted<br />

intellectualefforttoreframe<strong>the</strong>elementsof<strong>the</strong> CharlottetownAgreementso<br />

329


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

thatitcannotbedismissedasanassemblageofincompatiblecompromisesis<br />

stillachallengetoCanadianscholars. <strong>The</strong>equalpartnershipdiscourseof<strong>the</strong>B<br />

&BCommission, in spite of its incompleteness, merits rediscovery in <strong>the</strong><br />

search for a new coherence.<br />

Notes<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> terms were not used in <strong>the</strong> Preliminary Report. <strong>The</strong>y appear first in <strong>the</strong> General<br />

Introduction, p. xxxiv.<br />

2. <strong>La</strong>costegivesafairaccountof<strong>the</strong>Commission’sdecisionnottopublish<strong>the</strong>finalvolume.<br />

3. For <strong>the</strong> period up to 1989, <strong>the</strong> Selected Bibliography in Behiels 1989 is useful. For 1990-<br />

1992,eachissueof<strong>the</strong>Newsletterof<strong>the</strong>Networkon<strong>the</strong><strong>Constitution</strong>,1991<strong>The</strong>Network,<br />

Ottawa: University of Ottawa, publishes a full listing of publications on <strong>the</strong> constitution.<br />

4. I borrow this phrase from <strong>the</strong> 1950s <strong>and</strong> Iris Murdoch.<br />

Bibliography<br />

Bercowitz, S.D. <strong>and</strong> Logan, R.K. (eds), 1978. Canada’s Third Option. Toronto: Macmillan.<br />

Cairns,AlanC.,1989.“Citizens<strong>and</strong><strong>The</strong>ir<strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong>:Democratizing<strong>the</strong>processofconstitutional<br />

reform”inMichaelD.Behiels(ed.),<strong>The</strong>Meech<strong>La</strong>kePrimer.Ottawa:UniversityofOttawa<br />

Press. (pp 109-124) p. 118.<br />

_____, 1991. “<strong>Constitution</strong>al Change <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Three Equalities” in Watts <strong>and</strong> Brown (eds.),<br />

Options for a New Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

_____, 1992. <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong>. Montreal <strong>and</strong> Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University<br />

Press.<br />

Dufour,Christian,1990.ACanadianChallenge/Ledéfiquébécois. Halifax<strong>and</strong><strong>La</strong>ntzville,B.C.:<br />

Oolichan Books <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Institute for Research on Public Policy.<br />

Dunton, Davidson, 1978. “Majority Must Bend to Quebec” (originally alecture at McGill<br />

University entitled “Equal Partnership”) in S.D. Bercowitz <strong>and</strong> R.K.Logan.<br />

Forsey,Eugene,1962.“Canada:TwoNationsorOne?”28CanadianJournalofEconomics<strong>and</strong><br />

Political Science, November.<br />

Frith, Royce, 1978. “<strong>La</strong>nguage Rights <strong>and</strong> Programs” in S.D. Bercowitz <strong>and</strong> Robert K. Logan,<br />

Canada’s Third Option. Toronto: Macmillan.<br />

Guindon,Hubert,1978.“<strong>The</strong>ModernizationofQuebec<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>Legitimacyof<strong>the</strong>CanadianState”<br />

in Glenday, Guindon <strong>and</strong> Turowetz, Modernization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian State. Toronto:<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Kymlicka, Will, 1989. Liberty, Community, <strong>and</strong> Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

_____, 1991. “Liberalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Politicization of Ethnicity,” Canadian Journal of <strong>La</strong>w <strong>and</strong><br />

Jurisprudence ,Vol 4/2.<br />

_____, (forthcoming). “Individual <strong>and</strong> Community Rights” in Judith Baker (ed.) Group Rights.<br />

Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

<strong>La</strong>coste, Paul, 1990 (1). “André <strong>La</strong>urendeau et la Commission sur le bilinguisme et le<br />

biculturalisme” in Comeau, Robert <strong>and</strong> Beaudry, Lucille (eds.), André <strong>La</strong>urendeau: un<br />

intellectuel d’ici. Québec: Presses de l’université du Québec .<br />

_____,1990(2).“André<strong>La</strong>urendeauetlaCommissionroyaled’enquêtesurlebilinguismeetle<br />

biculturalisme,” an introduction to <strong>La</strong>urendeau, André, Journal . Montréal: VLB éditeur.<br />

Le Devoir, 24 August 1992. Montreal.<br />

Morin, Jacques-Yvan, 1965. “Vers un nouvel équilibre constitutionnel” in Crépeau, P.-A. <strong>and</strong><br />

Macpherson, C.B. (eds.) <strong>The</strong> Future of Canadian <strong>Federalism</strong>/ l’Avenir du fédéralisme<br />

canadien. Toronto <strong>and</strong> Montreal: University of Toronto Press <strong>and</strong> Les Presses de<br />

l’Université de Montréal.<br />

Porter, John, 1964. <strong>The</strong> Vertical Mosaic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

RCBB,1965.APreliminaryReportof<strong>the</strong>RoyalCommissiononBilingualism<strong>and</strong>Biculturalism.<br />

Ottawa, Appendix III.<br />

_____,1967.Reportof<strong>the</strong>RoyalCommissiononBilingualism<strong>and</strong>Biculturalism.BookIGeneral<br />

Introduction <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> Official <strong>La</strong>nguages<br />

_____,1968. Book II, Education<br />

_____,1970. Book IV, <strong>The</strong> Cultural Contribution of <strong>the</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r Ethnic Groups.<br />

Ryan, Claude, 1990. “Il asoulevé les vraies questions et réfuté les réponses toutes faites” in<br />

Comeau <strong>and</strong> Beaudry.<br />

Senate, 1988. Debates of <strong>the</strong> Senate, vol. 132, March 20.<br />

Smiley, Donald V., 1967. <strong>The</strong> Canadian Political Nationality. Toronto: Methuen.<br />

_____,1970.<strong>Constitution</strong>alAdaptation<strong>and</strong>Canadian<strong>Federalism</strong>Since1945,Documentsof<strong>the</strong><br />

Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong> Biculturalism, #4. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer.<br />

330


<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Royal Commission on Bilingualism <strong>and</strong><br />

Biculturalism on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Though <strong>and</strong> Practice<br />

_____, 1987. <strong>The</strong> Federal Condition in Canada. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.<br />

Special Joint Committee of <strong>the</strong> Senate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> House of Commons on <strong>the</strong> 1987 <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Accord,1987(1).MinutesofProceedings<strong>and</strong>Evidence.TestimonyofInuitCommitteeon<br />

National Issues, Métis National Council <strong>and</strong> Native Council of Canada, August 5.<br />

_____,1987(2).Briefof<strong>the</strong>UkrainianCanadianCommitteeto<strong>the</strong>SpecialJointCommittee,No.<br />

7, August 13. (Presented by Thor Broda).<br />

Task Force on Canadian Unity, 1979. AFuture Toge<strong>the</strong>r. Ottawa: Minister of Supply <strong>and</strong><br />

Services Canada. Cited in Smiley 1987: 125.<br />

Taylor, Charles, 1991. “Shared <strong>and</strong> Divergent Values” in Watts, R.L. <strong>and</strong> Brown D. M.(eds).<br />

Options for a New Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.<br />

331


David R. Cameron<br />

Not Spicer <strong>and</strong> Not <strong>the</strong> B & B: Reflections of an<br />

Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts<br />

Task Force on Canadian Unity*<br />

Abstract<br />

<strong>The</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity, contrary to <strong>the</strong> preferences of <strong>the</strong><br />

Government of Canada, acted both as a mid-wife to a process of public<br />

discussion of national unity in <strong>the</strong> late seventies <strong>and</strong> as a source of independent<br />

policy ideas <strong>and</strong> recommendations. In developing its ideas, it drew<br />

syn<strong>the</strong>tically on what it learned from <strong>the</strong> public hearings <strong>and</strong> from its own<br />

research <strong>and</strong> analysis, <strong>and</strong> produced a Final Report which stood as <strong>the</strong> most<br />

coherent federalist alternative to <strong>the</strong> anti-nationalist individualism of Pierre<br />

Elliott Trudeau. Political events subsequent to <strong>the</strong> release of <strong>the</strong> Task Force's<br />

Report reduced its immediate impact, but its concepts of duality <strong>and</strong><br />

regionalism <strong>and</strong> its frank acknowledgment of <strong>the</strong> communitarian foundation<br />

of much of Canadian life have been significant factors in <strong>the</strong> country's<br />

national-unity debate since that time <strong>and</strong> have been reflected in both Meech<br />

<strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord.<br />

Résumé<br />

En dépit des préférences du gouvernement, le Groupe de travail sur l'unité<br />

canadienne a donné naissance à un vaste débat public sur l'unité nationale et à<br />

une manne d'idées et de recomm<strong>and</strong>ations indépendantes en matière<br />

d'orientations. Ses idées se sont développées à partir de ce qu'il a entendu lors<br />

des audiences publiques et dans la foulée de ses propres recherches et<br />

analyses. Son rapport final constituait la solution de rechange fédéraliste la<br />

plus cohérente à l'anti-nationalisme individualiste de Pierre Elliott Trudeau.<br />

<strong>La</strong> conjoncture politique entourant la publication du rapport du Groupe de<br />

travail en a restreint l'influence immédiate, mais ses concepts de dualité et de<br />

régionalisme et sa franche reconnaissance des assises communautaires de la<br />

vie des Canadiens ont depuis lors constitué des aspects importants du débat<br />

sur l'unité nationale; que l'on songe à l'entente du lac Meech ou à l'Accord de<br />

Charlottetown.<br />

A commission is chiefly remembered for its final report. <strong>The</strong> untold story,<br />

normally, is how <strong>the</strong> commission produced <strong>the</strong> thing for which it is<br />

remembered. My focus in <strong>the</strong>se reflections is principally on <strong>the</strong> how, not <strong>the</strong><br />

what—on <strong>the</strong> inner workings of <strong>the</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

<strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>and</strong> policy recommendations contained in <strong>the</strong> final report.<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

A New Kind of Commission? Relations Between <strong>the</strong> Government <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Task Force<br />

<strong>The</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity was established on 5 July 1977 in <strong>the</strong> wake<br />

of <strong>the</strong> October 1976 election of <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commission was set up by Prime Minister Trudeau to allow <strong>the</strong> public to<br />

air its views on national unity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government to buy some time. 1 <strong>The</strong><br />

government wanted to proceed cautiously in light of <strong>the</strong> PQ victory, to<br />

reassure <strong>the</strong> Canadian public that it was not on <strong>the</strong> edge of a precipice <strong>and</strong> to<br />

give <strong>the</strong> impression that <strong>the</strong> national-unity issue was being prudently<br />

managed. Although set up under <strong>the</strong> Inquiries Act, it was called a “task force,”<br />

not a commission, presumably to indicate that it was a horse of a different<br />

colour from <strong>the</strong> run-of-<strong>the</strong>-mill commission. I remember John Robarts, who<br />

was keen on <strong>the</strong> expression, saying early on in <strong>the</strong> life of <strong>the</strong> Commission that<br />

“task force” was a word used in World War II to designate a small number of<br />

ships given a limited, very specific mission. At <strong>the</strong> time of this remark, it was<br />

still perhaps possible to believe that <strong>the</strong> Commissioners would restrict<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves to <strong>the</strong> mission <strong>the</strong> government had assigned <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> beginning, <strong>the</strong>re was <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> Task Force would probably not<br />

make a final report in <strong>the</strong> conventional sense. <strong>The</strong> fact that it was initially given<br />

a one-year timetable within which to do its work reflected this view. It would<br />

hold hearings across Canada, allow Canadians to speak <strong>the</strong>ir minds <strong>and</strong> give an<br />

account of what it had heard. <strong>The</strong> medium would be <strong>the</strong> message. It would not<br />

do research, develop policy or offer substantive proposals about <strong>the</strong> means by<br />

which <strong>the</strong> crisis of Confederation might be resolved. <strong>The</strong> Prime Minister had a<br />

clear view of <strong>the</strong> challenge coming from Quebec <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong> national policies<br />

appropriate to addressing it; his government would not welcome <strong>the</strong><br />

articulation of an alternative approach by a federally established commission.<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government's own constitutional proposals—<strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Amendment Bill (Bill C-60)—were released in June 1978 <strong>and</strong><br />

must have been in preparation well before <strong>the</strong> Task Force completed its<br />

hearings in April of that year.<br />

So <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Task Force—for those who gave it life—was supposed<br />

to be ra<strong>the</strong>r like what <strong>the</strong> Spicer Commission became more than a dozen years<br />

later: a national exercise in public consultation reporting on public opinion but<br />

offering little or nothing in <strong>the</strong> way of policy proposals.<br />

This was not to be. Instead, <strong>the</strong> Task Force produced three publications at <strong>the</strong><br />

end of its life, one of which was a substantial report with an analysis <strong>and</strong> a set of<br />

recommendations far from congenial to <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government. What<br />

happened?<br />

I think one factor was <strong>the</strong> sheer force of tradition: a commission's work<br />

conventionally includes a final report <strong>and</strong> recommendations. How could this<br />

one do o<strong>the</strong>rwise? A second factor was <strong>the</strong> predisposition of <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners <strong>and</strong> some of <strong>the</strong> staff. It is difficult to imagine a Gerald<br />

Beaudoin, a Solange Chaput-Roll<strong>and</strong> or—after John Evans’ early<br />

resignation—a Ron Watts on a commission <strong>and</strong> not expect a substantive<br />

report. Jean-Luc Pepin, as co-chair, was a man with vital intellectual <strong>and</strong><br />

public-policy interests who was unlikely to be satisfied with simply reporting,<br />

largely unmediated by analysis, what o<strong>the</strong>r people said. Most of <strong>the</strong> key<br />

Commission staff were recruited from <strong>the</strong> academic, public service <strong>and</strong><br />

professional world <strong>and</strong> assumed that <strong>the</strong> job of <strong>the</strong> Task Force was to produce a<br />

334


Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity<br />

substantive report with recommendations. <strong>La</strong>stly, <strong>the</strong> Task Force was held in<br />

low regard by <strong>the</strong> public at <strong>the</strong> beginning of its life <strong>and</strong> confronted a good deal<br />

of scepticism; committing itself to <strong>the</strong> production of a first-class report was<br />

one way of coping with <strong>the</strong>se pressures.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r dimension here worthy of remark. While <strong>the</strong> government, as<br />

we shall see, found ways of making its views of <strong>the</strong> Task Force's approach<br />

quite clear, <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government of Canada scrupulously<br />

respected <strong>the</strong> tradition of independence in which Canadian royal commissions<br />

have functioned. It established <strong>the</strong> Commission, gave it its m<strong>and</strong>ate, named <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n stepped back <strong>and</strong> allowed <strong>the</strong> Task Force to operate<br />

freely as it saw fit. Indeed, Jean-Luc Pepin, <strong>the</strong> full-time co-chair <strong>and</strong> former<br />

Liberal cabinet minister, did not even talk to Prime Minister Trudeau during<br />

<strong>the</strong> life of <strong>the</strong> Commission between 1977 <strong>and</strong> 1979, even to discuss his own<br />

future political career plans.<br />

That <strong>the</strong> government got more than it bargained for from <strong>the</strong> Task Force is not<br />

surprising. When a government launches an enquiry into a large <strong>and</strong> illdefined<br />

field such as national unity, <strong>the</strong> degree to which it can shape <strong>the</strong><br />

commission's work by <strong>the</strong> definition of its m<strong>and</strong>ate is small. Resourceful<br />

minds <strong>and</strong> strong wills can find ample room to manoeuvre within even <strong>the</strong><br />

most cleverly constituted m<strong>and</strong>ate.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> m<strong>and</strong>ate which <strong>the</strong> government assigned to <strong>the</strong> Task Force, no mention<br />

was made of a final report; <strong>the</strong> conventional phrase “to inquire into <strong>and</strong> report<br />

upon” was notably absent. However, <strong>the</strong> injunctions “to contribute ... <strong>the</strong><br />

initiatives <strong>and</strong> views of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners” <strong>and</strong> to “be a source of advice to<br />

<strong>the</strong> government” were more than sufficient foundation to permit <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners to do as <strong>the</strong>y wished. As with o<strong>the</strong>r commissions, so with<br />

Pepin-Robarts: <strong>the</strong> personalities of commissioners, <strong>the</strong> unfolding of events<br />

during <strong>the</strong> life of a commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> impact on a commission of <strong>the</strong> data,<br />

people <strong>and</strong> organizations with which it comes in contact, all proved to be<br />

potent forces in shaping what it would do <strong>and</strong> how it would do it.<br />

As a kind of declaration of independence, <strong>the</strong> Task Force, at <strong>the</strong> end of its first<br />

full meeting, released a statement declaring that it saw its job as finding a “third<br />

way,” presumably between <strong>the</strong> status quo <strong>and</strong> sovereignty-association:<br />

It is our intention to assemble concepts <strong>and</strong> policies which could<br />

constitute some of <strong>the</strong> elements of a third option for Canada. <strong>The</strong><br />

Members of <strong>the</strong> Task Force do not feel bound by existing legislation<br />

or practices nor are <strong>the</strong>y committed to views of any federal or<br />

provincial political party....[we are] aware that our autonomy is<br />

essential to our credibility <strong>and</strong> usefulness. 2<br />

This was controversial, both because it evinced an intention to move beyond<br />

public consultation <strong>and</strong> into substance <strong>and</strong> because <strong>the</strong> policy direction <strong>and</strong><br />

implicit strategy it blocked out, however tentatively— “a third option”—were<br />

anti<strong>the</strong>tic to <strong>the</strong> direction in which <strong>the</strong> federal government appeared to wish to<br />

move.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re were clear indications that autumn that <strong>the</strong> Privy Council Office was<br />

increasingly worried about <strong>the</strong> Task Force getting out of control, <strong>and</strong> Prime<br />

Minister Trudeau rapped <strong>the</strong> Commission's knuckles in a statement in <strong>the</strong><br />

House of Commons on 19 October 1977 in which he said:<br />

335


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

...I submit respectfully to everybody, including members of my own<br />

party <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Commission, that this third option<br />

business is a trap we should not fall into.<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> choice between maintaining comfortable relations with <strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government <strong>and</strong> charting its own course, <strong>the</strong> Task Force chose <strong>the</strong> latter.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Culture of a Commission<br />

Commissions are temporary, project-driven organizations. 3<br />

By its very nature, a commission is set up to do a specific job—to fulfill its<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ate, to tackle a project. This project is clearly finite, even if <strong>the</strong> duration of<br />

some commissions suggests o<strong>the</strong>rwise. (<strong>The</strong>B&BCommission, for example,<br />

was brought to a halt, not having completed its work after 7 years of existence.)<br />

Once <strong>the</strong> project is completed, <strong>the</strong> commission disappears; it “goes out of<br />

commission.” <strong>The</strong> Task Force held its first full commission meeting on 31<br />

August 1977 <strong>and</strong> released its final report less than 18 months later, on 25<br />

January 1979. It formally went out of commission a couple of months later.<br />

<strong>The</strong> temporary, project-focussed nature of commission work in large measure<br />

defines <strong>the</strong> unique culture of a commission. People come from somewhere else<br />

to do a temporary job. Some are involved in a particular aspect of <strong>the</strong><br />

commission's work, such as <strong>the</strong> organization of hearings, <strong>and</strong> leave once that<br />

work is done; o<strong>the</strong>rs—<strong>the</strong> commissioners, commission executives <strong>and</strong> support<br />

staff—have tasks that keep <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong>re throughout. That <strong>the</strong>ir tenure at <strong>the</strong><br />

commission is temporary is known from <strong>the</strong> very beginning. Everyone leaves<br />

when <strong>the</strong> commission winds up. As <strong>the</strong> life of <strong>the</strong> commission moves to its<br />

conclusion, commissioners <strong>and</strong> staff increasingly turn <strong>the</strong>ir attention to what<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are going back to or where <strong>the</strong>y are going—or hoping to go—next.<br />

If <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Task Force is any indication, <strong>the</strong><br />

intensity of <strong>the</strong> work is fierce: long hours, unpredictible schedules;<br />

uncertainties which vein almost every working day; searing conflicts about <strong>the</strong><br />

largest issues <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> smallest slights; moments of giddy exhilaration <strong>and</strong><br />

matchless camaraderie. All of this occurs in a small but bubbling cauldron of<br />

experience, some of it very much in <strong>the</strong> public eye, but much of it confined<br />

within <strong>the</strong> walls of <strong>the</strong> commission itself. Few people who have given<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves up to this curious form of professional existence leave unaffected. 4<br />

Yet, if it is temporary, <strong>and</strong> if it is project driven, a commission is also an<br />

organization. It has a budget <strong>and</strong> a bureaucracy; it establishes positions; <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are financial <strong>and</strong> personnel management problems; records must be kept,<br />

hearings organized, travel schedules <strong>and</strong> meetings arranged. Most, if not all, of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se administrative <strong>and</strong> executive functions a commission holds in common<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r organizations. <strong>The</strong> chief difference, however, is that a commission<br />

literally starts from scratch; all of it has to be established <strong>and</strong> most of it, it<br />

seems, simultaneously. High policy <strong>and</strong> mundane bureaucratic procedures<br />

both have to be determined at once, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is a sense that everything enjoys<br />

<strong>the</strong> same priority; such matters as <strong>the</strong> recruitment of key staff, <strong>the</strong><br />

establishment of a budget <strong>and</strong> a practical means of paying <strong>the</strong> bills <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

organization of meetings get almost equal consideration as <strong>the</strong> m<strong>and</strong>ate, <strong>the</strong><br />

organization of a public hearings process <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> development of a research<br />

agenda.<br />

336


Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity<br />

Having watched <strong>the</strong> chaos flower at <strong>the</strong> Task Force <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n subside as<br />

professional administrative staff were brought in to reduce <strong>the</strong> day-to-day life<br />

of <strong>the</strong> commission to routines <strong>and</strong> more or less normal management practices,<br />

I have to conclude that <strong>the</strong>se difficulties must arise in every commission, that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are not in <strong>the</strong>ir nature politically charged or policy laden, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong><br />

skills <strong>and</strong> experience necessary to address <strong>the</strong>m are eminently transferrable.<br />

Given that <strong>the</strong>re are royal commissions in operation in Ottawa all <strong>the</strong> time, it<br />

seems to me a good case can be made for <strong>the</strong> establishment of a generic unit<br />

within <strong>the</strong> federal government which would provide <strong>the</strong> basic administrative<br />

<strong>and</strong> financial support necessary to allow <strong>the</strong> commission to get up <strong>and</strong> running<br />

faster <strong>and</strong> to do so with far less angst <strong>and</strong> roiling about in <strong>the</strong> early days than is<br />

currently <strong>the</strong> case. Federal officials from this unit could be seconded to a new<br />

commission to establish <strong>the</strong> necessary support functions <strong>and</strong> to recruit <strong>the</strong> staff<br />

with <strong>the</strong> skills required to carry <strong>the</strong> system on.<br />

One might learn from <strong>the</strong> experience of Parliament which has developed staff<br />

with omnibus administrative skills charged with supporting <strong>the</strong> various<br />

legislative committees which are regularly being set up. It seems to me that <strong>the</strong><br />

provision of neutral, professional infrastructure support would significantly<br />

improve <strong>the</strong> efficient conduct of national public inquiries, particularly in <strong>the</strong><br />

start-up period, <strong>and</strong> could be arranged to do so without compromising <strong>the</strong><br />

necessary independence of <strong>the</strong>se enterprises.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Hearings Process <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Research Function<br />

Some commissions are identified almost as much by <strong>the</strong>ir research <strong>and</strong><br />

research publications as by <strong>the</strong>ir final report <strong>and</strong> its recommendations. <strong>The</strong><br />

Macdonald Commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> B&BCommission seem to me to fall into<br />

that category. <strong>The</strong>B&BReport itself contained a substantial array of data <strong>and</strong><br />

research findings, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> research studies provided a significant range of<br />

more specialized analyses. <strong>The</strong> experience of working at <strong>the</strong>B&Bmarked a<br />

whole generation of Anglophone <strong>and</strong> Francophone social scientists with<br />

consequences that were felt over <strong>the</strong> next 15 to 20 years. Likewise, <strong>the</strong> 1900<br />

pages of <strong>the</strong> Macdonald Report are packed with data, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> 72 volumes of<br />

research reports give an extraordinarily comprehensive picture of Canadian<br />

academic thinking about <strong>the</strong> issues that <strong>the</strong> Commission was addressing.<br />

It was quite o<strong>the</strong>rwise with <strong>the</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity. <strong>The</strong> Task Force,<br />

in many ways, is its final report. Indeed, while <strong>the</strong>re was discussion within <strong>the</strong><br />

Commission about <strong>the</strong> possible release of some of <strong>the</strong> internal studies that had<br />

been carried out, that was never done.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Task Force, in fact, released only three documents in reverse order from<br />

what one would expect:<br />

A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Observations <strong>and</strong> Recommendations, published<br />

on 25 January 1979, <strong>the</strong> report proper, containing <strong>the</strong> Commission's<br />

analysis of <strong>the</strong> plight <strong>the</strong> country found itself in <strong>and</strong> offering a<br />

comprehensive set of proposals for addressing it.<br />

Coming To Terms: <strong>The</strong> Words of <strong>the</strong> Debate, published on 4 February<br />

1979, a glossary of key political terms <strong>and</strong> concepts, produced as a<br />

labour of love by several of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners <strong>and</strong> still used as a<br />

reference work in university classrooms.<br />

337


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

A Time to Speak: <strong>The</strong> Views of <strong>the</strong> Public, published in March 1979, a<br />

report on what <strong>the</strong> people who appeared before <strong>the</strong> Task Force had to<br />

say about <strong>the</strong>ir country <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> issues confronting it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that no working papers or studies were released does not mean that<br />

none was done. In fact, mountains of paper were produced over <strong>the</strong> short life of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Task Force, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fate of some of this material was not decided until very<br />

near <strong>the</strong> end. In <strong>the</strong> event, its chief function was simply to support <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners in <strong>the</strong>ir work.<br />

In this sense, research <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> hearings processes performed parallel functions.<br />

Both provided input to <strong>the</strong> Commissioners which was ultimately syn<strong>the</strong>sized<br />

in <strong>the</strong> final report. <strong>The</strong> research function was not a matter of doing original<br />

work nor, for <strong>the</strong> most part, contracting specialized projects out to scholars <strong>and</strong><br />

experts; it was ra<strong>the</strong>r to collect <strong>and</strong> display relevant information, syn<strong>the</strong>size<br />

<strong>and</strong> represent significant findings <strong>and</strong> expert opinion in key areas, arrange for<br />

direct consultation with key people <strong>and</strong> present coherent policy alternatives to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Commissioners. Executing this m<strong>and</strong>ate brought <strong>the</strong> research staff into<br />

fairly close contact with <strong>the</strong> hearings process.<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> hearings <strong>the</strong>mselves regularly included appearances before <strong>the</strong><br />

Task Force of people with real expertise <strong>and</strong> a substantial record of<br />

achievement in <strong>the</strong> matters being discussed. During <strong>the</strong> eight-month formal<br />

hearings period from September 1977 to April 1978, <strong>the</strong> Task Force held full<br />

sessions in fifteen cities. <strong>The</strong> normal pattern called for public sessions in <strong>the</strong><br />

evenings <strong>and</strong> consultations with groups <strong>and</strong> specialists during <strong>the</strong> day. In<br />

addition, <strong>the</strong>re were numerous private sessions with political figures <strong>and</strong><br />

experts along <strong>the</strong> way.<br />

In addition, <strong>the</strong> Commission engaged <strong>the</strong> services of “<strong>the</strong> three wise men”—<br />

Léon Dion of <strong>La</strong>val, Edward MacWhinney of Simon Fraser <strong>and</strong> John Meisel<br />

of Queen's. <strong>The</strong>y met with <strong>the</strong> Commissioners periodically to offer general<br />

counsel on <strong>the</strong> Task Force's work, to review draft material <strong>and</strong> to reassure <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners about <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong> information <strong>and</strong> advice <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

receiving from <strong>the</strong> research staff.<br />

During <strong>the</strong> summer of 1978, after <strong>the</strong> public hearings were completed, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

came what amounted to a private hearings process—an intensive round of<br />

consultations with a wide range of specialists designed to advance <strong>and</strong> enrich<br />

<strong>the</strong> thinking of <strong>the</strong> Commission. <strong>The</strong> research staff was intimately involved in<br />

this process which one of <strong>the</strong> academic Commissioners described as “<strong>the</strong> best<br />

seminar on Canada” anywhere.<br />

While it is true that <strong>the</strong> public hearings <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> research enterprise were<br />

distinguishable streams of activity in <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> Commission, <strong>and</strong><br />

depended on different sets of staff, <strong>the</strong>re was a good deal of overlap at certain<br />

points, <strong>and</strong> it is undeniable that <strong>the</strong> former helped support <strong>the</strong> latter.<br />

Fasten Your Seatbelts: <strong>The</strong> Preparation of <strong>the</strong> Final Report<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> initial one-year m<strong>and</strong>ate, combined with <strong>the</strong> Commissioners’<br />

decision to prepare a conventional final report, discussion of <strong>the</strong> shape of <strong>the</strong><br />

Task Force analysis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of its recommendations became a recurrent<br />

issue during <strong>the</strong> winter months of 1977-78. Consideration was given to <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility of producing an interim report, but it was fairly soon recognized<br />

338


Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity<br />

that some extension of <strong>the</strong> m<strong>and</strong>ate would be required <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> Task Force<br />

should concentrate its efforts on producing a good final report.<br />

With <strong>the</strong> completion of <strong>the</strong> public hearings in <strong>the</strong> spring of 1978 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> windup<br />

of <strong>the</strong> specialist consultations that summer, <strong>the</strong> Task Force turned its<br />

attention in earnest to <strong>the</strong> production of its final report.<br />

A great deal of effort was spent during <strong>the</strong> next four months, both attempting to<br />

settle on policy conclusions <strong>and</strong> recommendations <strong>and</strong> physically preparing a<br />

working draft of <strong>the</strong> final report. <strong>The</strong> territory to be covered was so vast <strong>and</strong> illdefined,<br />

it was difficult to give it shape <strong>and</strong> focus.<br />

For a number of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners <strong>and</strong> staff, <strong>the</strong> moment of truth was<br />

approaching. A final decision on recommendations, for example, concerning<br />

national language policy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> constitutional status of Quebec in<br />

Confederation could not be avoided much longer, <strong>and</strong> it was clear that<br />

conflicting views would have to be worked out. <strong>Constitution</strong>al matters were<br />

<strong>the</strong> rock on which <strong>the</strong>B&BCommission had foundered a decade before, or at<br />

least were left unresolved by <strong>the</strong> Commission when it folded in 1970, to <strong>the</strong><br />

evident satisfaction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n recently arrived Prime Minister, Pierre<br />

Trudeau. Pepin-Robarts Commissioners were acutely aware of what would<br />

<strong>and</strong> would not please Prime Minister Trudeau, now in office for ten years, but<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less were developing a diagnosis <strong>and</strong> approach materially different<br />

from his.<br />

Although some progress was made in <strong>the</strong> autumn of 1978, both on <strong>the</strong><br />

preparation of <strong>the</strong> report <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> recommendations, it did not feel much like<br />

progress at <strong>the</strong> time. <strong>The</strong> research staff produced fat, black, three-ring binders<br />

filled with draft chapters of <strong>the</strong> report which seemed to <strong>the</strong> staff, <strong>and</strong> I am sure<br />

to <strong>the</strong> Commissioners as well, ponderous <strong>and</strong> unwieldly.<br />

An experienced editor, brought in from Toronto expressed something close to<br />

horror at <strong>the</strong> unmanageable bulk of <strong>the</strong> chapter drafts. Ano<strong>the</strong>r writer/editor,<br />

who had had extensive experience in shaping copy for Reader's Digest, was<br />

recruited <strong>and</strong> hacked manfully at <strong>the</strong> accumulation of words, much to <strong>the</strong><br />

consternation of <strong>the</strong>ir writers. Nothing seemed to be working; nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

recommendations nor <strong>the</strong> text seemed to be coming into focus, <strong>and</strong> we were<br />

finding it hard to coherently express <strong>the</strong> integrating principles of regionalism,<br />

duality <strong>and</strong> powersharing that <strong>the</strong> Task Force had fashioned for itself in <strong>the</strong><br />

course of <strong>the</strong> previous twelve months. We were also finding it difficult to settle<br />

on a set of recommendations that adequately reflected those principles.<br />

Our salvation came from outside.<br />

In June, 1978 <strong>the</strong> government of Canada released proposals for constitutional<br />

change in <strong>the</strong> form of draft legislation (Bill C-60). <strong>The</strong> existence of that<br />

document, <strong>and</strong> provincial reaction to it <strong>and</strong> to a federal schedule for 12<br />

constitutional discussions, led <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister to convene a <strong>Constitution</strong>al<br />

Conference for 30 October to 1 November 1978. This was <strong>the</strong> beginning of<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r attempt at comprehensive constitutional reform seven years after <strong>the</strong><br />

aborted Victoria <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of 1971. Discussion at <strong>the</strong> October Conference<br />

appeared to disclose sufficient grounds to establish a ministerial<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Committee to prepare specific proposals for a second First<br />

Ministers' Conference on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>, to be held on 5 to 6 February 1979.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se events led members of <strong>the</strong> Task Force to believe that <strong>the</strong> February<br />

meeting was likely to be of critical importance to <strong>the</strong> country <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong><br />

339


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

resolution of <strong>the</strong> constitutional issue; <strong>the</strong>re was a sense that <strong>the</strong> Task Force, if it<br />

did not speak prior to that event, might very well miss <strong>the</strong> boat <strong>and</strong> its work be<br />

made largely irrelevant.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> event, this was far from true, as some of <strong>the</strong> Task Force members<br />

privately realized. While Prime Minister Trudeau appeared to be willing to<br />

consider proposals that were more generous to <strong>the</strong> provinces than had been <strong>the</strong><br />

case in <strong>the</strong> past, political considerations on <strong>the</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> provincial<br />

participants, given <strong>the</strong> prospect of a federal election in a few weeks or months,<br />

meant that <strong>the</strong> chances of reaching an agreement were slim. In addition, <strong>the</strong><br />

Parti Québécois government of Quebec was committed to sovereigntyassociation—a<br />

non-starter in English-speaking Canada—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> PQ had yet<br />

to test <strong>the</strong> acceptability of its ideas among its own electorate in a referendum.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> notion that a significant constitutional agreement might be<br />

possible in February was an extraordinarily helpful “activating fiction” that<br />

galvanized Commissioners <strong>and</strong> staff. At a meeting before Christmas, <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners committed <strong>the</strong>mselves to <strong>the</strong> preparation <strong>and</strong> release of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

final report including recommendations prior to <strong>the</strong> Vancouver constitutional<br />

meeting. For this reason, three volumes <strong>the</strong> Task Force produced came out in<br />

reverse order from what might have been expected.<br />

Setting a real deadline, credible to <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> authoritative so far as <strong>the</strong><br />

staff were concerned, was probably <strong>the</strong> most critical single decision <strong>the</strong><br />

Commissioners made with respect to <strong>the</strong> final report. All o<strong>the</strong>r matters for<br />

resolution became consequential on that prior commitment.<br />

Recommendations had to be decided; a satisfactory draft of <strong>the</strong> final report,<br />

reflecting <strong>the</strong> philosophy of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners, had to be produced. All of<br />

this—not to mention <strong>the</strong> editing, translation, printing <strong>and</strong> distribution—had to<br />

be completed within a space of seven weeks.<br />

<strong>The</strong> psychological impact on Commissioners <strong>and</strong> staff alike was dramatic; as<br />

one researcher said:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commissioners have fastened <strong>the</strong>ir seat belts <strong>and</strong> returned <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

chairs to <strong>the</strong> upright position. <strong>The</strong>y're getting ready to l<strong>and</strong>.<br />

At a stroke, <strong>the</strong> Commission members began to focus on essentials, not details.<br />

Setting a deadline helped <strong>the</strong> Task Force unburden itself of <strong>the</strong> unwieldly<br />

drafts of <strong>the</strong> final report produced in autumn, <strong>and</strong> to use <strong>the</strong>m simply as<br />

resource material to be drawn on as needed.<br />

<strong>The</strong> responsibility for preparing a draft of an entirely new version of <strong>the</strong> report<br />

was entrusted to one Commissioner <strong>and</strong> one member of <strong>the</strong> research staff; <strong>the</strong>y<br />

agreed between <strong>the</strong>mselves on <strong>the</strong> general areas each would be responsible for,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commission broke for Christmas.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first sentences of what was to become <strong>the</strong> final report were written on<br />

Boxing Day. A Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Observations <strong>and</strong> Recommendations, <strong>the</strong><br />

Final Report of <strong>the</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity, was released in both official<br />

languages one month later. This must surely set a record for <strong>the</strong> rapid<br />

production of a royal-commission report. Recently, one of my colleagues,<br />

currently laboring on ano<strong>the</strong>r royal commission, observed wearily:<br />

340


Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity<br />

Oh. commissions....Commissions are a lot like elephants. <strong>The</strong>y’re<br />

big <strong>and</strong> slow moving <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y tend to sit down <strong>and</strong> squash things. <strong>The</strong><br />

only difference is <strong>the</strong>y don't have memories.<br />

It is true that <strong>the</strong> pace set by many commissions has been painfully slow, but<br />

that certainly cannot be said of <strong>the</strong> final days of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Task Force,<br />

nor, I think, of its existence in general, given that its active life was less than a<br />

year <strong>and</strong> a half in total.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Commission reconvened at <strong>the</strong> beginning of January to review <strong>and</strong><br />

improve <strong>the</strong> draft, to finalize <strong>the</strong> recommendations <strong>and</strong> to oversee <strong>the</strong><br />

translation. Fortunately, <strong>the</strong> draft that <strong>the</strong> authors had prepared was generally<br />

to <strong>the</strong> liking of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners <strong>and</strong>, by <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> pressure of <strong>the</strong> looming<br />

deadline forced a consensus in even <strong>the</strong> most divisive areas in which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

intended to make recommendations.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se areas were many: decentralization, <strong>the</strong> Senate, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r contentious issues. But by far <strong>the</strong> most difficult matter was federal<br />

language policy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commissioners—particularly an active core group<br />

from Ontario <strong>and</strong> Quebec—spent hours during <strong>the</strong> days <strong>and</strong> nights of early<br />

January in an ultimately successful struggle to reach agreement on a set of<br />

language-policy recommendations. <strong>The</strong>se were among <strong>the</strong> most controversial<br />

when <strong>the</strong> Report was publicly released.<br />

<strong>The</strong> role of John Robarts was important here. He was nei<strong>the</strong>r troubled by nor<br />

terribly interested in <strong>the</strong> detailed recommendations with which several of <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r Commissioners were wrestling. However, he did care passionately about<br />

one thing: he thought his country was in very serious trouble <strong>and</strong> it needed to<br />

get fixed, <strong>and</strong> quickly. Robarts used to say, when confronted with yet ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

set of arcane policy proposals, that dealing with <strong>the</strong>se national-unity issues<br />

was like “shovelling fog.” He would also say that Canada need to “reach<br />

finality” on <strong>the</strong>se issues, that is to say, to settle <strong>the</strong> matter once <strong>and</strong> for all, get it<br />

over <strong>and</strong> done with, <strong>and</strong> stop talking about it. <strong>The</strong>se views, I think, allowed him<br />

to accept quite “comfortably” (a favourite Robarts' word) what must have<br />

been, for him, a fairly radical set of recommendations. <strong>The</strong>y also explain his<br />

insistence during <strong>the</strong> final discussions that <strong>the</strong> report be unanimous; if <strong>the</strong> Task<br />

Force’s recommendations were to be credible <strong>and</strong> authoritative, <strong>the</strong>re could be<br />

no minority report. And <strong>the</strong>re was none.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Impact of <strong>the</strong> Task Force<br />

<strong>The</strong> Task Force’s Final Report was given to <strong>the</strong> government a couple of days<br />

before its public release, <strong>and</strong> several of <strong>the</strong> Commissioners went to Prime<br />

Minister Trudeau's office to discuss it with him <strong>and</strong> Marc <strong>La</strong>londe. Trudeau<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>La</strong>londe had had very little time to review <strong>the</strong> Report. It came as no<br />

surprise to any of us that nei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>m liked it much, but what I found<br />

interesting was <strong>the</strong> way that each, given <strong>the</strong> limited time available, approached<br />

<strong>the</strong> Report.<br />

Marc <strong>La</strong>londe had flipped to <strong>the</strong> back <strong>and</strong> read through <strong>the</strong> recommendations;<br />

he <strong>the</strong>n proceeded to render his judgment of <strong>the</strong> document on that basis.<br />

Trudeau, for his part, had started at <strong>the</strong> beginning of <strong>the</strong> Report <strong>and</strong> read his<br />

way as far as he could into <strong>the</strong> substance of <strong>the</strong> argument; he <strong>the</strong>n discussed<br />

with <strong>the</strong> Commissioners <strong>the</strong>ir substantive approach <strong>and</strong> line of reasoning.<br />

While I thought it a pity—though not surprising—that <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister did<br />

341


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

not care for <strong>the</strong> Report's analysis <strong>and</strong> intellectual framework, it pleased me as a<br />

citizen <strong>and</strong> an academic that <strong>the</strong> Prime Minister of my country had a cast of<br />

mind that drove him to tackle arguments, not just recommendations.<br />

<strong>The</strong> government of Canada received <strong>the</strong> Task Force's Report publicly with<br />

restraint <strong>and</strong> circumspection. When Prime Minister Trudeau tabled it in <strong>the</strong><br />

House he stated carefully that <strong>the</strong> government of Canada “accepts <strong>the</strong> broad<br />

lines of <strong>the</strong> Task Force’s analysis of <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>and</strong> endorses <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

principles which it believes should underlie <strong>the</strong> renewal of <strong>the</strong> Canadian<br />

federation.” <strong>The</strong> opposition leaders, Joe Clark <strong>and</strong> Ed Broadbent, were more<br />

outspoken in <strong>the</strong>ir support. It was in <strong>the</strong> days which followed that <strong>the</strong> Prime<br />

Minister began to make it clear that <strong>the</strong> government had considerable<br />

reservations about <strong>the</strong> Report. <strong>The</strong>re was much in <strong>the</strong> Report to which he took<br />

exception, not least its positive emphasis on duality <strong>and</strong> regionalism, its<br />

support for some decentralization of social <strong>and</strong> cultural policy (although<br />

combined with some centralization in <strong>the</strong> economic field) <strong>and</strong>, in particular, its<br />

position on federal language policy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Report was made public just two weeks before <strong>the</strong> Vancouver<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Conference. As such, it became a central topic of conversation<br />

in Vancouver, but its release so close to <strong>the</strong> meeting meant that it did not have a<br />

structural impact on <strong>the</strong> agenda or <strong>the</strong> substantive discussions that took place.<br />

Some interest was expressed in <strong>the</strong> approach of Pepin-Robarts by several<br />

provinces, <strong>and</strong> it appeared that <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois government of Quebec was<br />

startled by <strong>the</strong> Report's forthright recognition of Quebec's distinct character<br />

<strong>and</strong> its willingness to give that distinctiveness some significant constitutional<br />

expression. Claude Morin, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> Quebec minister responsible for<br />

intergovernmental affairs, was reported to have said, apropos of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts approach: “We’re not in <strong>the</strong> same boat, but we're sailing down <strong>the</strong><br />

same river.”<br />

Probably <strong>the</strong> most concrete example of <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>the</strong> Report had in some<br />

quarters is <strong>the</strong> Beige Paper, <strong>the</strong> constitutional document put toge<strong>the</strong>r by <strong>the</strong><br />

Quebec Liberal Party under <strong>the</strong> leadership of Claude Ryan. It drew heavily on<br />

<strong>the</strong> Task Force approach. However, <strong>the</strong> defeat of Ryan <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> re-election of<br />

<strong>the</strong> PQ after <strong>the</strong> referendum meant that that stream of influence was effectively<br />

blocked off.<br />

Despite some internal advice to <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong> Trudeau government dealt<br />

with <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Report by ignoring it. This strategy was largely<br />

successful in reducing its immediate, practical impact, in part because no<br />

provincial government or governments took Pepin-Robarts up seriously as a<br />

cause célèbre <strong>and</strong> in part because <strong>the</strong> country was embarking on a tumultuous<br />

18 months in its history which saw <strong>the</strong> defeat of <strong>the</strong> Liberals in June 1979, <strong>the</strong><br />

nine-month reign of <strong>the</strong> Clark Conservative Government, <strong>the</strong> re-election of<br />

Trudeau <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liberal Party in February 1980 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Quebec referendum in<br />

May 1980.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Clark government, during its brief term of office, showed some interest in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Report, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> work that Arthur Tremblay, appointed to <strong>the</strong> Senate by<br />

Prime Minister Clark, had begun, made use of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Report as a<br />

significant policy resource.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Report of <strong>the</strong> Task Force on Canadian Unity came, <strong>the</strong>n, at <strong>the</strong> beginning<br />

of a series of national events that followed fast on <strong>the</strong> heels of one ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong><br />

which transformed <strong>the</strong> context in which Canadian unity <strong>and</strong> constitutional<br />

342


Reflections of an Insider on <strong>the</strong> Workings of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-<br />

Robarts Task Force on Canadian Unity<br />

reform were addressed. With <strong>the</strong> utterly unexpected re-election of a majority<br />

Liberal Government under a rejuvenated Pierre Trudeau followed by <strong>the</strong><br />

defeat of <strong>the</strong> Quebec referendum on sovereignty-association, <strong>the</strong> philosophy<br />

<strong>and</strong> proposals espoused by <strong>the</strong> Task Force were definitively set aside. From<br />

1980 to 1984, <strong>the</strong> Trudeau approach to national unity, constitutional reform<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> management of <strong>the</strong> federation held complete sway.<br />

Eloquent evidence of this reality is to be found in <strong>the</strong> fate of Jean-Luc Pepin,<br />

co-chairman of <strong>the</strong> Task Force, who was re-elected as a Liberal in <strong>the</strong> 18<br />

February 1980 federal election which brought Trudeau back to power. <strong>The</strong><br />

Prime Minister made Pepin Minister of Transport, at that time an active <strong>and</strong><br />

very heavy portfolio which was far removed from <strong>the</strong> referendum <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional action, <strong>and</strong> he was allowed to have no significant role in <strong>the</strong><br />

federal government's conduct of <strong>the</strong>se matters.<br />

What of <strong>the</strong> Task Force's general influence—its “atmospheric” impact—in <strong>the</strong><br />

fourteen years since it folded its tent? Any response to that question must be<br />

highly speculative. However, I have <strong>the</strong> impression that <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts<br />

Task Force accomplished in substantial measure what it had announced it<br />

intended to do at <strong>the</strong> beginning of its work, namely, to present a third option for<br />

Canada. In <strong>the</strong> event, it offered an approach which was different from both <strong>the</strong><br />

sovereignty-association proposal of <strong>the</strong> Parti Québécois government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Trudeau view of national unity <strong>and</strong> federalism.<br />

It constituted <strong>the</strong> most coherent, st<strong>and</strong>ing federalist alternative to <strong>the</strong> political<br />

ideas of Pierre Trudeau. His anti-nationalist individualism led him to foster <strong>the</strong><br />

recognition of individually-based language rights <strong>and</strong> to stoutly resist any<br />

exp<strong>and</strong>ed recognition of <strong>the</strong> community-based reality of <strong>the</strong> French fact in<br />

North America. While clearly a believer in federalism, his experience in<br />

government created in him a strong resistance to any streng<strong>the</strong>ning of <strong>the</strong><br />

provinces in Confederation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Pepin-Robarts Report recognized, accepted <strong>and</strong> sought to accommodate<br />

<strong>the</strong> very forces in Canadian life <strong>and</strong> politics that Trudeau was combatting. It<br />

accepted <strong>and</strong> celebrated diversity, <strong>and</strong> in its development of <strong>the</strong> concepts of<br />

duality <strong>and</strong> regionalism, <strong>the</strong> Task Force fashioned a view of Canada <strong>and</strong><br />

Confederation that comfortably acknowledged <strong>the</strong> communitarian foundation<br />

of much of what was most valuable <strong>and</strong> most strongly cherished in our national<br />

existence. What is more, <strong>the</strong> Report frankly accepted <strong>the</strong> structural role of <strong>the</strong><br />

Province of Quebec as <strong>the</strong> “foyer” of <strong>the</strong> Francophone community in North<br />

America <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r provinces in expressing <strong>the</strong> regional loyalties<br />

of Canadians in o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong> country.<br />

It was, I think, <strong>the</strong> first public body to advance this conception of Canada with<br />

such clarity <strong>and</strong> vigour. <strong>The</strong> Task Force was explicit in acknowledging that,<br />

politically, regions were best understood as provinces <strong>and</strong> that, with respect to<br />

duality, <strong>the</strong> key issue was <strong>the</strong> status of Quebec in Confederation. <strong>The</strong>re is no<br />

doubt that <strong>the</strong> Task Force was correct in designating <strong>the</strong>se as <strong>the</strong> two central<br />

forces in <strong>the</strong> country which required mutual accommodation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> failure to reconcile regionalism—transmuted into <strong>the</strong> principle of <strong>the</strong><br />

equality of <strong>the</strong> provinces—<strong>and</strong> duality—understood as <strong>the</strong> need to recognize<br />

Quebec as a distinct society—has, in <strong>the</strong> fourteen years since <strong>the</strong> Task Force<br />

published its Report, exposed <strong>the</strong> country to greater risk than any o<strong>the</strong>r single<br />

issue in our national life.<br />

343


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> Task Force’s conception of Canada; its frank acceptance of <strong>the</strong> central<br />

principles of duality <strong>and</strong> regionalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> determination to knit <strong>the</strong>m more<br />

creatively into <strong>the</strong> fabric of our national life, ra<strong>the</strong>r than to deny <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>the</strong><br />

recognition of Quebec as a distinct society; <strong>the</strong> willingness to tackle <strong>the</strong><br />

assignment of power between <strong>the</strong> two orders of government <strong>and</strong> to accept a<br />

degree of decentralization—all of <strong>the</strong>se bespeak an approach materially<br />

different from that which dominated our national life until 1984. <strong>The</strong> pressure<br />

to give <strong>the</strong>m some degree of constitutional accommodation, however, appears<br />

not to have diminished with time, although we have not so far been successful<br />

in addressing this matter, nor have we succeeded in giving constitutional<br />

expression to <strong>the</strong> aspirations of Canada's aboriginal peoples.<br />

Both Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord attempted to establish greater<br />

constitutional space for <strong>the</strong> communitarian realities of Canadian life; in this<br />

<strong>the</strong>y were at one with <strong>the</strong> central direction of <strong>the</strong> Pepin-Robarts Report. With<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment of <strong>the</strong> constitutional <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms in<br />

1982, we have given powerful expression to <strong>the</strong> voice of individualism to<br />

which Pierre Trudeau was so strongly committed <strong>and</strong> which unquestionably<br />

forms part of <strong>the</strong> very foundation of Canadian life. This is not <strong>the</strong> place for a<br />

review of <strong>the</strong> unhappy fortunes of Meech <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown, but it does seem<br />

to me that <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r voice—as thoroughly Canadian as that to which <strong>the</strong><br />

1982 <strong>Constitution</strong> gives expression—which is still calling for recognition.<br />

Notes<br />

* I am indebted to Ralph Heintzman, Ken McRoberts, Jean-Luc Pepin <strong>and</strong> Ron Watts who<br />

commented on an earlier draft of this paper.<br />

1. See Jean-Luc Pepin's comments on this subject in his delightful appreciation of John<br />

Robarts, given as <strong>the</strong> closing address of York University's May 1984 inaugural ceremonies<br />

for <strong>the</strong> establishment of <strong>the</strong> Robarts Centre for Canadian Studies, p. 111.<br />

2. <strong>The</strong> Role of <strong>the</strong> Task Force, 1 September 1977. Reproduced in <strong>the</strong> Task Force's final report, A<br />

Future Toge<strong>the</strong>r: Observations <strong>and</strong> Recommendations, pp. 139-43.<br />

3. Alan Cairns has spoken of this commission culture in ‘Reflections on Commission<br />

Research’, Commissions of Inquiry, ed. Paul Pross et al. (Toronto: Carswell, 1990), pp.91-3.<br />

4. Alan Cairns speaks of <strong>the</strong> atmosphere of <strong>the</strong> Macdonald Commission in ‘Reflection’, p. 93.<br />

344


Allan Tupper<br />

English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

Accord *<br />

Michael D. Behiels (ed.). <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer : Conflicting Views of <strong>the</strong><br />

1987 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord. Ottawa : <strong>The</strong> University of Ottawa Press,<br />

1987.<br />

Alan C. Cairns. Disruptions : <strong>Constitution</strong>al Struggles, from <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> to<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, edited by Douglas E. Williams. Toronto : McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Stewart, 1991.<br />

Roger Gibbins (ed.) with Howard Palmer, Brian Rusted <strong>and</strong> David Taras.<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Canada : Perspectives from <strong>the</strong> West. Edmonton :<br />

Academic Printing <strong>and</strong> Publishing, 1988.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. Canadian Public Policy. Supplement (1988) XIV.<br />

Patrick J. Monahan. Meech <strong>La</strong>ke : <strong>The</strong> Inside Story. Toronto <strong>and</strong> Buffalo :<br />

University of Toronto Press, 1991.<br />

David E. Smith, Peter MacKinnon <strong>and</strong> John C. Courtney (eds.). After Meech<br />

<strong>La</strong>ke : Lessons for <strong>the</strong> Future. Saskatoon : Fifth House Publishers, 1991.<br />

K.E. Swinton <strong>and</strong> C.J. Rogerson (eds.). Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions :<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. Agincourt, Ontario : <strong>The</strong> Carswell Co. Ltd.,<br />

1988.<br />

This essay critically evaluates <strong>the</strong> English-language literature on <strong>the</strong> Meech<br />

<strong>La</strong>ke Accord. Several caveats are necessary. First, <strong>the</strong> literature’s boundaries<br />

are imprecise. Scholarship abounds in journal articles <strong>and</strong> books. Such works<br />

are enriched by an array of commissioned works, briefs to governments <strong>and</strong><br />

transcripts of public hearings to cite just a few sources. Second, <strong>the</strong> formal<br />

literature is itself diverse. Several important volumes were written soon after<br />

<strong>the</strong> Accord’s birth while o<strong>the</strong>rs are post mortems. Some contributions are<br />

designed to influence events <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs are motivated by <strong>the</strong> conventional<br />

scholarly goals of explanation <strong>and</strong> education. Third, as a political scientist, I<br />

will stress, but not restrict myself to, my discipline’s extensive contributions.<br />

Finally, I appreciate <strong>the</strong> varying needs of my diverse audience. My strategy is<br />

<strong>the</strong> bold one of trying to say things that will interest most of my readers.<br />

In this essay, I say a little about many different ideas with <strong>the</strong> full<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing that I am plumbing a substantial literature, that <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

exceptions to my generalizations <strong>and</strong> that several arguments require<br />

elaboration. My conclusions are critical. Social scientists are active<br />

participants in Canadian constitutional life. We counsel governments <strong>and</strong><br />

interest groups, actively express our views about proposed changes <strong>and</strong><br />

passionately advocate reforms. But social scientists have remained close to <strong>the</strong><br />

policy makers’ agenda, have failed to provide new prisms through which to<br />

interpret <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>and</strong> have undertaken little research which links<br />

constitutional politics with o<strong>the</strong>r important Canadian issues. I also believe that<br />

International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d’études canadiennes<br />

7-8, Spring-Fall/Printemps-automne 1993


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

Canadian political scientists are too generous in <strong>the</strong>ir public assessments of<br />

each o<strong>the</strong>rs’ work to <strong>the</strong> detriment of its quality. Political scientists are<br />

consistently dem<strong>and</strong>ing, often intemperate, when evaluating <strong>the</strong> constitutional<br />

performance of public officials.<br />

My essay comprises three sections. First, I highlight <strong>the</strong> English-Canadian<br />

literature’s strengths <strong>and</strong> weaknesses. I <strong>the</strong>n examine <strong>the</strong> contributions of Alan<br />

C. Cairns <strong>and</strong> Patrick J. Monahan. In distinguished essays, Cairns fashions a<br />

powerful, yet incomplete, picture of our recent constitutional life. Monahan’s<br />

book, Meech <strong>La</strong>ke : <strong>The</strong> Inside Story, presents an iconoclastic, but apologetic,<br />

assessment of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke. I conclude with some thoughts about scholars’<br />

roles in constitutional controversies.<br />

<strong>The</strong>mes, Strengths <strong>and</strong> Weaknesses<br />

<strong>The</strong> literature is competent <strong>and</strong> intelligent. It is sometimes creative <strong>and</strong><br />

occasionally rouses such powerful emotions as anger, despair <strong>and</strong> genuine<br />

concern about an unsettled national future. Canadian scholars adeptly capture,<br />

describe <strong>and</strong> analyze <strong>the</strong> visions of Canada that Meech <strong>La</strong>ke ei<strong>the</strong>r reflected or<br />

ignored. In this vein, <strong>the</strong> Accord was criticized by many scholars as an<br />

imprecise, irrelevant or wrong characterization of <strong>the</strong> contemporary Canadian<br />

condition (Gibbins 1988 ; Whyte 1988). For critics, Meech’s agenda was too<br />

rooted in <strong>the</strong> notion that Canadian politics still revolved around questions of<br />

Quebec’s position, federal-provincial relations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> status of two founding<br />

peoples. How could constitution makers ignore <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>and</strong> aspirations of<br />

aboriginals, women <strong>and</strong> Canadians whose ancestry was nei<strong>the</strong>r British nor<br />

French? Meech’s advocates, both governmental <strong>and</strong> academic, reacted<br />

defensively to such criticism. <strong>The</strong>y often admitted <strong>the</strong> critique’s validity but<br />

argued that o<strong>the</strong>r constitutional questions could be better tackled after<br />

Quebec’s status had been settled (Simeon 1988). Scholars also contributed<br />

substantially to <strong>the</strong> often passionate debate about <strong>the</strong> possible impact of <strong>the</strong><br />

distinct society clause on <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms. Several careful<br />

essays plumb this complex topic (MacKay 1988; Smith 1988).<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke’s impact on <strong>the</strong> balance of power within federalism was widely<br />

discussed, a hardly surprising fact given <strong>the</strong> continuing importance of federal<br />

issues for governments, citizens <strong>and</strong> political scientists. Some hyperbole was<br />

employed, notably by Pierre Trudeau, by those who worried that Meech would<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r restrain Ottawa’s capacity to act (Trudeau 1988). On balance, scholars<br />

concluded that Meech was “decentralizing” through its provisions on Senate<br />

reform, appointments to <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court, immigration policy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

spending power (Cairns 1991 : 148-61 ; Johnson 1988). <strong>The</strong> literature<br />

captures <strong>the</strong> “provincializing” thrust of a federal constitutional strategy based<br />

on offering to all provinces that which was necessary to accommodate Quebec.<br />

Scholars dispatched <strong>the</strong> myth of Meech <strong>La</strong>ke as a “Quebec round” <strong>and</strong><br />

captured its reality as a “provincial round.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> literature highlights Canadians’ serious complaints about <strong>the</strong> democratic<br />

quality of <strong>the</strong> processes employed to formulate, to conclude <strong>and</strong> to legitimate<br />

<strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord. “Executive federalism” is almost universally decried<br />

as an unacceptable forum for <strong>the</strong> development of major constitutional reforms,<br />

although critics attacked it on different grounds (Cairns 1992 : 102-8). An<br />

excess of secrecy, a failure to provide clear arguments in support of <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

<strong>and</strong> efforts to limit public debate are among <strong>the</strong> offending features. Ottawa’s<br />

particular insistence that <strong>the</strong> Accord could be discussed, but not changed, was<br />

348


English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

seen as a singular affront to a democratic people. Scholars noted how some<br />

Canadians also questioned <strong>the</strong> representativeness of political elites <strong>and</strong><br />

challenged <strong>the</strong>ir capacity to speak for <strong>the</strong> country. <strong>The</strong> unflattering description<br />

of <strong>the</strong> First Ministers as “eleven, able bodied white males” was incessantly<br />

echoed.<br />

Critical assessments of <strong>the</strong> process are numerous <strong>and</strong> convincing but not<br />

hegemonic. Scattered through <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature <strong>and</strong> centrepiece in<br />

Patrick J. Monahan’s book are defences of, <strong>and</strong> explanations for, <strong>the</strong> processes<br />

<strong>and</strong> strategies employed (Simeon 1989 : 128). Meech’s supporters argued that<br />

critics of <strong>the</strong> process employed procedural arguments as smoke screens to<br />

cover opposition to <strong>the</strong> Accord’s content. While self-interested, this point<br />

raises broad issues about <strong>the</strong> interplay between democratic procedures <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

content of major constitutional reforms. Are Meech’s defenders correct when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y assert that procedural arguments, while important, cannot be allowed to<br />

trump substantive ones? Tradeoffs between proper procedure <strong>and</strong> desirable<br />

substance are not troubling for ardent supporters or passionate critics. <strong>The</strong>y are<br />

probably deeply worrisome for Canadians who are receptive to <strong>the</strong> content of<br />

proposed changes but appalled by <strong>the</strong> processes employed.<br />

A virtue of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature, one perhaps so obvious that it is<br />

forgotten, is that it reveals <strong>the</strong> range of opinions <strong>and</strong> passions about <strong>the</strong> Accord<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> principal arguments in its defence <strong>and</strong> opposition. Its record of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

views <strong>and</strong> emotions will become more important as time passes <strong>and</strong> as our<br />

memories fade <strong>and</strong> become more selective. <strong>The</strong> reader interested in<br />

recapturing <strong>the</strong> arguments must delve into <strong>the</strong> literature as no author provides a<br />

panorama. <strong>The</strong> edited volumes are particularly helpful in this task especially<br />

Michael Behiels’s tome which collects <strong>the</strong> positions of some interest groups,<br />

several important statements by public officials <strong>and</strong> scholars’ views (Behiels<br />

1989).<br />

Alan Cairns has noted some substantial omissions in Canadian constitutional<br />

scholarship including its failure to think dispassionately about “Canada<br />

without Quebec” or <strong>the</strong> dynamics of aboriginal self-government (Cairns 1991:<br />

207-14). Many o<strong>the</strong>r important issues are ignored or dealt with<br />

unsatisfactorily. Ra<strong>the</strong>r ironically given <strong>the</strong> debate about <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown<br />

Accord, Senate reform is not prominently discussed in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

literature (Meekison 1988). Those concerned with <strong>the</strong> underlying philosophy,<br />

logic <strong>and</strong> effectiveness of alternative reforms must look elsewhere.<br />

<strong>The</strong> constitutional politics of Canada’s provinces <strong>and</strong> territories are not probed<br />

exhaustively. 1 Observers are content to view provincial government<br />

behaviours as a function of such general forces as dominant personalities <strong>and</strong><br />

partisan calculations, perennial provincial interests as shaped by <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

economic bases <strong>and</strong> social structures <strong>and</strong> Ottawa’s strategy of making a<br />

“Quebec round” a de facto “provincial round.” We get little sense of <strong>the</strong> range<br />

of intraprovincial opinions, <strong>the</strong> precise constraints imposed upon provincial<br />

leaders or <strong>the</strong> genesis of such provincial ideologies as “equality of <strong>the</strong><br />

provinces.” <strong>The</strong> territorial governments are ei<strong>the</strong>r ignored or mentioned in<br />

passing as irate byst<strong>and</strong>ers to a constitutional renewal whose content <strong>and</strong><br />

politics <strong>the</strong>y opposed. <strong>The</strong> English-Canadian literature on Meech <strong>La</strong>ke says<br />

little about Quebec’s internal politics, a topic which if better explained might<br />

permit non-Quebecers to appreciate <strong>the</strong> province’s complexity <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong><br />

broad contours of its constitutional positions. Despite <strong>the</strong> perennial <strong>and</strong><br />

continuing centrality of governments in Canadian constitutional politics <strong>and</strong><br />

349


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

scholarship, <strong>the</strong> literature provides few convincing <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> empirical<br />

accounts of <strong>the</strong>ir behaviour. In light of <strong>the</strong>se flaws, a careful inventory of <strong>the</strong><br />

literature’s assertions about governments’ behaviour, a critical assessment of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir validity <strong>and</strong> a clear research agenda would be valuable contributions to<br />

future scholarship.<br />

Canadian scholars seldom discuss <strong>the</strong> impact of constitutional reform on <strong>the</strong><br />

substance of public policy, a noteworthy exception being Keith Banting’s<br />

assessment of Meech’s implications for <strong>the</strong> welfare state (Banting 1988).<br />

Meech’s alterations to <strong>the</strong> constitutional basis of immigration policy, a<br />

politically contentious topic, was, except for a single substantive article,<br />

ignored or mentioned merely as <strong>the</strong> constitutional entrenchment of <strong>the</strong><br />

political <strong>and</strong> administrative status quo (Kruhlak 1988). Meech’s provision for<br />

annual First Ministers’ conferences on <strong>the</strong> economy—a proposal with<br />

obvious, albeit indirect, policy consequences —was also given short shrift.<br />

<strong>The</strong> failure to link constitutional change with <strong>the</strong> activities of governments<br />

reflects Canadian political science’s failure to embrace policy studies as an<br />

integral part of its undertakings. This disciplinary weakness has direct<br />

consequences for constitutional studies by removing policy effectiveness as an<br />

important criterion for <strong>the</strong> evaluation of democratic constitutions. When <strong>the</strong><br />

policy consequences of constitutional reform are ignored or downplayed,<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r more accessible yardsticks, like <strong>the</strong> impact on <strong>the</strong> federal balance of<br />

power, assume unwarranted prominence.<br />

As a major contribution, <strong>the</strong> literature highlights <strong>the</strong> advent <strong>and</strong> proliferation<br />

of non governmental constitutional actors. In particular, Alan Cairns has<br />

documented <strong>the</strong> roles of aboriginal peoples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir organizations, women’s<br />

groups <strong>and</strong> spokespersons for Canada’s visible minorities (Cairns 1991).<br />

Much more work is required before we underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional views<br />

<strong>and</strong> roles. In this vein, we might consider studying <strong>the</strong> emergent nongovernmental<br />

forces as interest groups per se. Such a perspective<br />

acknowledges <strong>the</strong> elemental point that <strong>the</strong> organizations in question perform<br />

many roles besides <strong>the</strong>ir explicitly political, let alone constitutional, ones.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y have personalities, internal dynamics <strong>and</strong> little understood histories that<br />

shape <strong>the</strong>ir constitutional personae but also reflect <strong>the</strong>ir continuing<br />

performance of o<strong>the</strong>r important undertakings. <strong>The</strong>ir policy making, <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

funding, <strong>the</strong>ir links with governments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir decisions about constitutional<br />

strategy all require investigation. Political scientists can undertake such<br />

studies armed with a set of propositions about constitutional behaviour <strong>and</strong> a<br />

substantial literature on interest groups. <strong>The</strong> range of non-governmental<br />

constitutional actors must be exp<strong>and</strong>ed to include research organizations like<br />

<strong>the</strong> Canada West Foundation, trade unions, business organizations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

diverse groups that arise during <strong>the</strong> constitutional deliberations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n fade<br />

from prominence. <strong>The</strong>ir roles, <strong>the</strong>ir strategies <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir influence must be<br />

probed if we are to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “new politics” of constitutional reform.<br />

Such inquiries might bring new life to constitutional studies by injecting <strong>the</strong><br />

views of scholars who have abstained from participation <strong>and</strong> by providing<br />

dispassionate analysis of <strong>the</strong> roles of non-governmental actors. A fuller grasp<br />

of <strong>the</strong> patterns of influence at work might also challenge <strong>the</strong> literature’s still<br />

strong assumption that constitution making is an area of considerable<br />

governmental autonomy from societal pressures.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature often notes <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong> mass media on<br />

constitutional events. Yet only David Taras, his debaters <strong>and</strong> a few o<strong>the</strong>rs deal<br />

explicitly with <strong>the</strong> topic (Alboim 1988; Meisel 1991; Raboy 1991; Taras 1988<br />

350


English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1991). Taras employs modern communications <strong>the</strong>ories to argue that<br />

television, while influential, is a poor medium for serious constitutional<br />

analysis. While media are assumed to be influential, <strong>the</strong>ir role will not become<br />

central in Canadian constitutional studies. Few social scientists, let alone<br />

constitutional lawyers, are familiar with <strong>the</strong> complex literature that must<br />

underpin a serious discussion of media influence.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature is dominated by <strong>the</strong> contributions of law <strong>and</strong><br />

political science. O<strong>the</strong>r disciplines, especially economics, anthropology,<br />

philosophy <strong>and</strong> sociology, are little represented. Nor has much genuinely<br />

interdisciplinary work emerged, although political scientists <strong>and</strong> lawyers often<br />

share insights. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a growing fusion between <strong>the</strong>se two disciplines is<br />

desirable is an open question in both fields.<br />

Economists’ abstinence from constitutional debates is regrettable. 2 <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

greater engagement would probably lessen <strong>the</strong> concern with democratic<br />

processes <strong>and</strong> heighten concern with policy effectiveness as a criterion for<br />

assessing constitutional change. Philosophers are not regular contributors to<br />

<strong>the</strong> detriment of <strong>the</strong> literature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> debates. 3 Few thinkers coherently probe<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> through <strong>the</strong> lens of classical or modern political thought. As<br />

noted earlier, a strong suit of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature is its ability to capture<br />

<strong>the</strong> visions of Canada that underpin public debate. But, revealingly, <strong>the</strong><br />

scholarship says little systematically or <strong>the</strong>oretically about visions of Canada<br />

as a political democracy. A fuller philosophical engagement will not magically<br />

guarantee a more satisfying constitutional life <strong>and</strong> scholarship. It might result<br />

in a deeper attention to <strong>the</strong> principles that should guide democratic<br />

constitutional reform, in a heavier emphasis on criteria for judging proposed<br />

changes <strong>and</strong> in a richer assessment of such questions as <strong>the</strong> tensions between<br />

individual <strong>and</strong> collective rights. A stronger philosophical str<strong>and</strong>, by posing<br />

questions differently, might also shift debate away from <strong>the</strong> agenda as defined<br />

by <strong>the</strong> protagonists.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Canadian left is a byst<strong>and</strong>er in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debates <strong>and</strong> its attendant<br />

scholarship, although this assertion raises complex questions of definition <strong>and</strong><br />

measurement of influence. <strong>The</strong> social democratic left has generally defended a<br />

strong federal government <strong>and</strong> championed constitutionally recognized social<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic rights. But <strong>the</strong>se views are nei<strong>the</strong>r distinctively social<br />

democratic nor perceived to be such. <strong>The</strong>y are articulated by o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

constitutional actors who do not necessarily define <strong>the</strong>mselves as part of <strong>the</strong><br />

left, some women’s groups for example, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r partisans, some federal<br />

Liberals for example. <strong>The</strong> federal New Democratic Party’s support of <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Charlottetown Accords mutes its impact on constitutional<br />

events as does <strong>the</strong> left’s continuing suspicion of constitutional debates as mere<br />

distractions in <strong>the</strong> face of a dreary economic l<strong>and</strong>scape. In <strong>the</strong> event, Meech<br />

<strong>La</strong>ke was seldom probed from <strong>the</strong> perspectives of class relations or <strong>the</strong>ories of<br />

political power. This neglect is unfortunate as a constitutional reordering of<br />

immigration power <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> federal spending authority within <strong>the</strong> context of a<br />

“provincializing” credo are important topics for those outside <strong>the</strong> ideological<br />

mainstream. <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debate was conducted within <strong>the</strong> grasp of<br />

implicit <strong>and</strong> unchallenged assumptions about <strong>the</strong> character <strong>and</strong> power<br />

structure of Canadian society.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dominance of political science <strong>and</strong> law, <strong>the</strong> neglect of certain topics <strong>and</strong><br />

ideological homogeneity are easily demonstrated. Ano<strong>the</strong>r essential<br />

characteristic of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature is more elusive. That is, <strong>the</strong><br />

351


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

literature is better characterized as sophisticated public affairs analysis ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than scholarly research as conventionally understood. It rests on commentaries<br />

about, <strong>and</strong> evaluations of, governments’ constitutional proposals. Such are<br />

principally derived from authors’ general knowledge of Canadian government<br />

<strong>and</strong> society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir strong views about our national future. <strong>The</strong>ir scholarship<br />

is not rooted in <strong>the</strong> definition of precise research problems or <strong>the</strong> articulation<br />

<strong>and</strong> implementation of research designs. To <strong>the</strong> degree that controversy<br />

occurs, it concerns <strong>the</strong> conclusions drawn <strong>and</strong>/or <strong>the</strong> prescriptions offered.<br />

Support for <strong>the</strong>se observations is best drawn from <strong>the</strong> remarkable absence in<br />

<strong>the</strong> scholarship of controversy about how <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> should be studied<br />

with emphasis on questions of evidence, assumptions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> suitability of<br />

dominant questions. Such debates, even if too sporadic or tame for some of our<br />

tastes, are found in most mature areas of scholarship where dominant<br />

methodologies, topics <strong>and</strong> conclusions are invariably challenged. In <strong>the</strong><br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke debate, English-Canadian scholars sparred with each o<strong>the</strong>r as<br />

committed citizens.<br />

Meech <strong>La</strong>ke : Some General Interpretations<br />

A highlight of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke literature is <strong>the</strong> wide-ranging scholarship of<br />

Alan C. Cairns who coherently interprets <strong>the</strong> constitutional experience. His<br />

rich scholarship cannot be easily or satisfactorily summarized. It must be read.<br />

He captures a new Canadian constitutional culture, one characterized by <strong>the</strong><br />

mobilization of many non-governmental actors who see formal constitutional<br />

change as a principal arena for <strong>the</strong> pursuit of <strong>the</strong>ir political visions. Inspired by<br />

<strong>the</strong> powerful impact of <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> of Rights <strong>and</strong> Freedoms on Canadian<br />

society, Cairns demonstrates <strong>the</strong> treacherous course of a constitutional order<br />

now defined by two, often conflicting, agendas. During Meech <strong>La</strong>ke,<br />

governments stressed a traditional agenda which emphasized federalprovincial<br />

questions <strong>and</strong> Quebec’s position in Canada. New actors, <strong>the</strong> “rights<br />

bearers,” were driven by a concern with individual <strong>and</strong> group rights. Through<br />

this prism, Cairns explains <strong>the</strong> debates about <strong>the</strong> process, about <strong>the</strong> interplay<br />

between <strong>the</strong> distinct society clause <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> <strong>and</strong> about <strong>the</strong> Accord’s<br />

failure.<br />

Cairns’ work should be acknowledged as excellent but not worshipped. His<br />

provocative portrait is incomplete. As perhaps driven by his methodological<br />

focus on <strong>the</strong> public statements of constitutional actors, he sees <strong>the</strong> modern<br />

constitutional order as shaped by a multiplicity of competing elites. He pays<br />

little explicit attention to <strong>the</strong> broader patterns of public opinion that shape,<br />

reflect <strong>and</strong> restrain elite opinions in little understood ways. Moreover, Cairns<br />

generally sees constitutional affairs as operating in isolation from o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

pressing political matters. He has not yet linked constitutional controversies<br />

with debates about <strong>the</strong> changing economic role of <strong>the</strong> state. His work could<br />

profitably be extended to employ <strong>the</strong> Canadian case as a springboard for<br />

thinking about <strong>the</strong> essence of constitutional orders in modern democracies.<br />

Patrick J. Monahan’s Meech <strong>La</strong>ke : <strong>The</strong> Inside Story is an ambitious book. It is<br />

literate, often provocative <strong>and</strong> sometimes stimulating. It is also incomplete,<br />

imprecise <strong>and</strong> confusing in important aspects. <strong>The</strong> book’s subtitle is<br />

misleading for several reasons. First, Monahan explicitly criticizes accounts<br />

that stress personalities; he writes as an insider but also as an intellectual driven<br />

by a desire to rise above <strong>the</strong> everyday clash of political emotion <strong>and</strong><br />

personalities. Seen in this light, Andrew Cohen’s accessible <strong>and</strong> intelligent<br />

352


English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

account of Meech’s politics, as based on interviews with key actors, is<br />

recommended for insight into <strong>the</strong> personalities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> bargaining (Cohen<br />

1990). Second, Monahan says little about <strong>the</strong> anxieties <strong>and</strong> role conflicts that<br />

might befall a legal scholar <strong>and</strong> professor—an “outsider” in one sense—who<br />

temporarily occupies a senior advisory position to a key actor, in this case <strong>the</strong><br />

Premier of Ontario. <strong>The</strong> neglect of this aspect of “insider” status is unfortunate<br />

as academics, who are thought to be influential in such roles, seldom write<br />

about <strong>the</strong>ir experiences. Third, Monahan’s core arguments—about <strong>the</strong><br />

process, about <strong>the</strong> Accord’s symbolism <strong>and</strong> about leaders as prisoners of past<br />

agreements—could have been constructed by a non-participant. <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

articulation does not require “insider” status.<br />

Monahan wants to destroy <strong>the</strong> idea that Meech <strong>La</strong>ke was merely a failure of<br />

Canadian political leadership, a “total bungle” as Pierre Trudeau called it<br />

(Monahan 1991 : 8-9). This argument is surely a straw man as no serious or<br />

influential academic, political or journalistic observers subscribed to it. 4 In his<br />

zeal to undercut <strong>the</strong> “total bungle” <strong>the</strong>sis, Monahan fashions a deterministic<br />

counter <strong>the</strong>sis—that Meech’s architects were prisoners of <strong>the</strong> 1982<br />

constitutional settlement. Taken to its extreme, this line of reasoning is an<br />

obstacle to, <strong>and</strong> conservative substitute for, serious constitutional analysis.<br />

Finally, Monahan does not transcend <strong>the</strong> personality-centered accounts he<br />

claims to abhor. <strong>The</strong> dissenting Premiers of Newfoundl<strong>and</strong>, New Brunswick<br />

<strong>and</strong> Manitoba—Clyde Wells, Frank Mckenna <strong>and</strong> Gary Filmon<br />

respectively— are consistently criticized while <strong>the</strong> errors <strong>and</strong> sins of <strong>the</strong> Prime<br />

Minister <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “on side” Premiers are ignored or downplayed. Wells, for<br />

example, is vilified as an opponent of democracy for failing to bring a Meech<br />

resolution before <strong>the</strong> Newfoundl<strong>and</strong> legislature. Prime Minister Mulroney’s<br />

abdication of his responsibility to educate Canadians about Meech <strong>La</strong>ke is<br />

satisfactory to Monahan because <strong>the</strong> agreement raised conflicting<br />

expectations in different parts of <strong>the</strong> country <strong>and</strong> was thus difficult to<br />

communicate. An elemental feature of drama—<strong>the</strong> construction of a story<br />

through <strong>the</strong> creation of heroes <strong>and</strong> villains—is central to Monahan’s analysis.<br />

Contrary to many interpretations, Monahan portrays <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

as a substantial intergovernmental compromise in which all <strong>the</strong> players,<br />

including Quebec, gave ground. Ottawa capitulated to no one—<strong>the</strong> federal<br />

government was not <strong>the</strong> provinces’ “head waiter.” To this end, Monahan<br />

provides an excellent syn<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>and</strong> evaluation of <strong>the</strong> complex<br />

intergovernmental constitutional negotiations between 1982 <strong>and</strong> 1987. But his<br />

analysis is more compelling <strong>and</strong> valuable than <strong>the</strong> political case that flows<br />

from it. Perhaps Meech <strong>La</strong>ke was a wise compromise. But how were citizens<br />

supposed to discern <strong>the</strong>ir leaders’ wisdom when Meech’s underlying<br />

compromises <strong>and</strong> philosophy were not shared with <strong>the</strong>m?<br />

Monahan bravely confronts <strong>the</strong> battalions of critics who attacked <strong>the</strong> Meech<br />

process as unacceptable in a democracy. His counterattack is more spirited<br />

than persuasive. For one thing, Monahan’s defence of <strong>the</strong> process is<br />

sidetracked into arguments about secrecy. His case also rests on three weakly<br />

related propositions. First, he implies that Meech’s excessive secrecy was a<br />

function of <strong>the</strong> process itself <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “political inheritance of 1982” (Monahan<br />

1991: 9). But Cairns’ case—that <strong>the</strong> Meech process flowed from conscious<br />

political choice not immutable technical or legal requirements—is more<br />

powerful (Cairns 1991 : 259). Second, Monahan moves from seeing secrecy as<br />

an unpleasant necessity to justifying it as requisite to effectiveness in most<br />

human endeavours, not only politics. But to be convincing, Monahan must<br />

353


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

demonstrate why <strong>and</strong> when information should be withheld from citizens.<br />

What must we know? He ignores <strong>the</strong> harder question of whe<strong>the</strong>r democratic<br />

constitution making by its very nature dem<strong>and</strong>s extraordinary openness. In<br />

short, we require a careful democratic <strong>the</strong>ory of information not assertions<br />

about decision making which merely justify an excess of secrecy. Finally,<br />

Monahan argues that Meech critics employed process arguments to mask<br />

substantive disagreements. To a degree, this assertion raises empirical<br />

questions about <strong>the</strong> constitutional strategies employed. Perhaps Monahan’s<br />

“smoke screen” <strong>the</strong>sis is correct. But is <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke process<br />

democratically acceptable simply because several antagonists strategically<br />

blurred democratic critiques with substantive ones? By what criteria should<br />

we measure constitutional processes? To return to an earlier question, how<br />

should citizens respond when <strong>the</strong>y worry about <strong>the</strong> process but concur with <strong>the</strong><br />

substance of reform? Compelling answers to <strong>the</strong>se questions must flow from<br />

explicit democratic arguments. Monahan disappoints in this important task.<br />

Monahan’s volume reflects <strong>the</strong> competing, perhaps irreconcilable, pressures<br />

on scholars who try to be simultaneously relevant, iconoclastic, analytical <strong>and</strong><br />

prescriptive. He submits to <strong>the</strong> dictates of too many dem<strong>and</strong>ing taskmasters.<br />

Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

What roles should professors play in national constitutional debates? Should<br />

<strong>the</strong>y be “activists” as variously defined or is <strong>the</strong>ir primary duty to <strong>the</strong> pursuit of<br />

knowledge? How close should scholars be to governments <strong>and</strong> interest<br />

groups? Such questions irritate those colleagues for whom answers are selfevident,<br />

for whom “activism” is necessary <strong>and</strong> desirable <strong>and</strong> for whom<br />

“activism” <strong>and</strong> effective scholarship are complementary not competitive<br />

pursuits. My view is that answers to such questions are nei<strong>the</strong>r obvious nor<br />

easily arrived at. A serious dialogue is warranted.<br />

We need a serious research project on scholars as Canadian constitutional<br />

actors. Such a study, whose details cannot be explored here, would stress <strong>the</strong><br />

range of roles assumed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent of scholarly involvement. What links<br />

exist between academics, governments, political parties, research institutes,<br />

<strong>the</strong> mass media <strong>and</strong> interest groups? Second, what is <strong>the</strong> range of scholarly<br />

views <strong>and</strong> how are <strong>the</strong>y shaped? Do certain disciplines “favour” particular<br />

constitutional solutions? Finally, how do professors <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r actors perceive<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir influence?<br />

<strong>The</strong> arguments in favour of scholarly activism are ascendant if not necessarily<br />

correct. In a troubled world, a monastic, self-directed <strong>and</strong> generally well-paid<br />

scholarly life can sometimes seem self-indulgent, wasteful <strong>and</strong> irrelevant even<br />

to its dedicated devotees. As Canadians, indeed North Americans, we are<br />

incessantly reminded that our society prizes action over introspection (Payne<br />

1981: 187). Second, <strong>the</strong> sociology <strong>and</strong> traditions of disciplines may propel<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir practitioners to action. My guess is that many political scientists, as<br />

practitioners of a diverse <strong>and</strong> ill-defined discipline, feel “impractical” when<br />

compared to a profession like law or to a “hard” social science like economics.<br />

Such a view lingers even in light of our discipline’s extensive contributions to<br />

important royal commissions, to debates about federal <strong>and</strong> provincial<br />

electoral boundaries <strong>and</strong> of course to constitutional controversies to cite a few<br />

telling examples. Viewed in this light, <strong>the</strong> Canadian political science<br />

community can arguably be seen as part of <strong>the</strong> state not an independent<br />

observer of it. Finally, although seldom studied, <strong>the</strong> modern university itself<br />

354


English-Canadian Scholars <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

pressures its members towards social activism. <strong>The</strong> demonstration of <strong>the</strong><br />

“relevance” of scholarly research is a preoccupation of modern universities.<br />

Social science <strong>and</strong> humanities research creates problems as its influence is<br />

difficult to demonstrate. Viewed from this angle, a stable of visible, committed<br />

<strong>and</strong> influential constitutional advisors is a prized university possession which<br />

merits nurture <strong>and</strong> encouragement. Finally, we must not presume that activism<br />

necessarily yields greater influence on events than more detached <strong>and</strong><br />

reflective scholarship. Over <strong>the</strong> long haul, independent scholarship may shift<br />

<strong>the</strong> agenda <strong>and</strong> reorient thought as new ideas are slowly transmitted to society<br />

<strong>and</strong> new generations.<br />

Conclusions<br />

As I write in early 1993, Canadians are in an eerie constitutional no man’s l<strong>and</strong>.<br />

We face a long list of unresolved constitutional business which now emits no<br />

siren call. <strong>The</strong> constitutional agenda is apparently on hold pending <strong>the</strong> results<br />

of important elections in Canada <strong>and</strong> Quebec. Or will an unforeseen event<br />

spark a constitutional blaze <strong>and</strong> arouse us from our state of alleged<br />

constitutional fatigue?<br />

<strong>The</strong> future of constitutional studies is likewise uncertain. <strong>The</strong> lull means that<br />

<strong>the</strong> moving constitutional target is momentarily stationary. Scholars can catch<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir breath, focus <strong>the</strong>ir energies <strong>and</strong> put complex events in context. <strong>The</strong><br />

national referendum on <strong>the</strong> Charlottetown Accord adds more ground to an<br />

already complex research terrain. Yet we cannot even gauge <strong>the</strong> breadth <strong>and</strong><br />

depth of scholarly commitment to Canadian constitutional studies. Will even a<br />

short-term decline in political interest lead to a scholarly exodus as o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

problems compete for scarce research time <strong>and</strong> commitment? Will a tiny<br />

contingent of constitutional stalwarts face <strong>the</strong> daunting task of interpreting a<br />

decade of constitutional turmoil? Will <strong>the</strong>ir dedication be enough to generate<br />

<strong>the</strong> iconoclastic <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical scholarship that <strong>the</strong>ir task dem<strong>and</strong>s?<br />

Notes<br />

* I would like to thank Professor Kenneth McRoberts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> journal’s Editorial Board for<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir constructive criticisms.<br />

1. Some noteworthy exceptions are Donald W. Stevenson’s valuable essay “Ontario <strong>and</strong><br />

Confederation : A Reassessment” in R. Watts <strong>and</strong> D. Brown, eds., Canada : <strong>The</strong> State of <strong>the</strong><br />

Federation (Kingston, Ontario: Institute of Intergovernmental Relations,1989), 53-74 <strong>and</strong><br />

Gerald Friesen,“Manitoba <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord” in R. Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong><br />

Canada : Perspectives from <strong>the</strong> West, 51-62. For a stimulating discussion of <strong>the</strong> inadequate<br />

scholarship on <strong>the</strong> constitutional positions of Atlantic Canadian governments, see David<br />

Milne,“Challenging <strong>Constitution</strong>al Dependency : A Revisionist View of Atlantic Canada”<br />

in J. McCrorie <strong>and</strong> M. MacDonald, eds., <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>al Future of <strong>the</strong> Prairie <strong>and</strong><br />

Atlantic Regions of Canada (Regina : Canadian Plains Research Center, 1992), 308-17. In<br />

lamenting <strong>the</strong> inadequate study of provincial <strong>and</strong> territorial governments, I am not arguing<br />

that <strong>the</strong> federal government’s constitutional policy making is satisfactorily understood or<br />

studied.<br />

2. <strong>The</strong> obvious exception to this argument is <strong>the</strong> creative scholarship of Thomas J. Courchene.<br />

See, for example, “Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Socio-Economic Policy,” Canadian Public Policy,14<br />

supplement (September 1988), 63-80. See also R. Boadway, J. Mintz <strong>and</strong> D. Purvis, “<strong>The</strong><br />

Economic Policy Implications of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord” in K. Swinton <strong>and</strong> C. Rogerson,<br />

eds., Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions : <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord, 225-238.<br />

3. An exception is Charles Taylor’s work. See, for example, his “Shared <strong>and</strong> Divergent Values”<br />

in R. Watts <strong>and</strong> D. Brown eds., Options for Canada (Toronto: University of Toronto<br />

Press,1991), 53-76.<br />

355


IJCS / RIÉC<br />

4. If Andrew Cohen’s book is <strong>the</strong> principal object of Monahan’s displeasure, his ire is<br />

misplaced. Cohen’s book rests on a clear political grasp of Canadian constitutional life. See<br />

Andrew Cohen, A Deal Undone: <strong>The</strong> Making <strong>and</strong> Breaking of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord<br />

(Vancouver : Douglas <strong>and</strong> McIntyre, 1990).<br />

Bibliography<br />

Alboim, E. “Inside <strong>the</strong> News Story : Meech <strong>La</strong>ke as Viewed by an Ottawa Bureau Chief” in R.<br />

Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Canada, 235-46.<br />

Behiels, Michael D., ed. <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer.<br />

Cairns, Alan C., edited by Williams, Douglas, E. Disruptions.<br />

Cairns, Alan C. <strong><strong>Charte</strong>r</strong> versus <strong>Federalism</strong> : <strong>The</strong> Dilemmas of <strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform. Montreal<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kingston : McGill Queen’s University Press, 1992.<br />

Cohen, Andrew. A Deal Undone : <strong>The</strong> Making <strong>and</strong> Breaking of <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord Vancouver<br />

<strong>and</strong> Toronto : Douglas <strong>and</strong> McIntyre, 1990.<br />

Gibbins, R. “A Sense of Unease: <strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong>-making in Canada” in<br />

Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Canada, 121-30.<br />

Johnson, A.W. “<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bonds of Nationhood” in Swinton <strong>and</strong><br />

Rogerson, eds., Competing Consitutional Visions, 145-54.<br />

Kruhlak, O. “<strong>Constitution</strong>al Reform <strong>and</strong> Immigration” in Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Canada,<br />

201-14.<br />

MacKay, W. “Linguistic Duality <strong>and</strong> Distinct Society in Quebec : Declarations of Sociological<br />

Fact or Legal Limits on <strong>Constitution</strong>al Interpretation?” in Swinton <strong>and</strong> Rogerson, eds.,<br />

Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions, 65-80.<br />

Meekison, J. Peter. “Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Future of Senate Reform” in Swinton <strong>and</strong> Rogerson,<br />

eds., Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions, 113-20.<br />

Meisel, J. “Mirror? Searchlight? Interloper? : <strong>The</strong> Media <strong>and</strong> Meech” in Smith, MacKinnon <strong>and</strong><br />

Courtney, eds., After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, 147-68.<br />

Monahan, Patrick J. Meech <strong>La</strong>ke : <strong>The</strong> Inside Story.<br />

Payne, B. “Devices <strong>and</strong> Desires : Corruption <strong>and</strong> Ethical Seriousness” in Fleishman, J. et al eds.,<br />

Public Duties: <strong>The</strong> Moral Obligations of Government Officials. Cambridge, Mass. :<br />

Harvard University Press, 1981, 175-203.<br />

Raboy, M. “Canadian Broadcasting, Canadian Nationhood : Two Concepts, Two Solitudes, <strong>and</strong><br />

Great Expectations” in Smith, MacKinnon <strong>and</strong> Courtney, eds., After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, 181-98.<br />

Simeon, R. “Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Visions of Canada” in Swinton <strong>and</strong> Rogerson, eds., Competing<br />

<strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions, 295-306.<br />

Simeon, R. “Political Pragmatism Takes Precedence Over Democratic Process” in Behiels, ed.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Primer, 119-31.<br />

Smith, Lynn. “<strong>The</strong> Distinct Society Clause in <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Accord : Could it Affect Equality<br />

Rights for Women?” in Swinton <strong>and</strong> Rogerson, eds., Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions, 35-<br />

54.<br />

Taras, D. “Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Television News” in Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke <strong>and</strong> Canada, 219-34.<br />

Taras, D. “How Television Transformed <strong>the</strong> Meech <strong>La</strong>ke Negotiations” in Smith, MacKinnon <strong>and</strong><br />

Courtney, eds., After Meech <strong>La</strong>ke, 169-80.<br />

Trudeau, Pierre Elliott. “Say Goodbye to <strong>the</strong> Dream of One Canada” in Gibbins, ed., Meech <strong>La</strong>ke<br />

<strong>and</strong> Canada, 65-72.<br />

Whyte, J. “<strong>The</strong> 1987 <strong>Constitution</strong>al Accord <strong>and</strong> Ethnic Accommodation” in Swinton <strong>and</strong><br />

Rogerson, eds., Competing <strong>Constitution</strong>al Visions, 263-70.<br />

356

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!