Vergil, Petrarch, Shakespeare, Milton Leah Whittington A ...

Vergil, Petrarch, Shakespeare, Milton Leah Whittington A ... Vergil, Petrarch, Shakespeare, Milton Leah Whittington A ...

dataspace.princeton.edu
from dataspace.princeton.edu More from this publisher
05.06.2013 Views

implicit in the idea of ransom. At the same time, by attributing his refusal of ransom to Turnus’ killing of Pallas, Aeneas also suggests that before the death of Pallas, he would have consented to ransoming a suppliant instead of slaughtering him outright, as would have been consistent with the Roman practice of pardoning enemy combatants who offered complete surrender. Indeed, this is how the fourth-century commentator Tiberius Donatus glosses the passage: humanitatem, inquit, poscis, quae inter partis solet aliquando praestari, sed istam mihi tuus ille sustulit Turnus et inhumanitatem plenam morte Pallantis docuit. 79 you are asking for kind treatment, which sometimes exists between factions, but your Turnus took that away from me and with the death of Pallas he prescribed all-out cruelty. Coffee wants to see Aeneas’ rejection of the notion of strict commodity exchange implied by ransom as a moral improvement on the Homeric model, in which captives were routinely sold into slavery or ransomed for money, but a number of factors point to a different view of what is at stake in Aeneas’ rejection of Magus. Aeneas’ response clings to another Homeric precedent: Book 21 of the Iliad, where, in responding to Lycaon’s request for mercy, Achilles recalls a time before the death of Patroclus when it was his practice to ransom his captives rather than killing them in cold blood. For 79 Tiberius Claudius Donatus, Interpretationes Vergilianae, ed. Heinrich Georgii (Stuttgart: Teubner, 1969), 10.2. 55

Achilles, Patroclus’ death finally crystalizes the process that began when he withdrew from battle – he can no longer support the values of a system which equates human life with some form of compensation, whether it be the spoils of war or immortality in song. Achilles’ response to Lycaon represents one of the most comprehensive explanations for his alienation from heroic society. 80 In rejecting Magus’ supplication, Aeneas, like Achilles, rejects the idea of a possible commensurability between life and material commodity. But for Aeneas, we have no sense of a building dissatisfaction with the rules of combat or the ethical climate of exchange. Aeneas and his men repeatedly give gifts in exchange for alliance or hospitality, so Aeneas’ turn against commercium comes as something of a surprise. Given the Roman preference for exercising clemency with foreign captives, there would be a historical reason to expect Aeneas’ acceptance of Magus’ deditio in fidem. Similarly, Aeneas’ history of sympathy with the suppliant might lead us to expect him to respond favorably to Magus’ supplication. The stakes of Aeneas’ response, therefore, are literary: Vergil touches on the notion of a topos as a part of a text’s ritual relationship to its predecessors. The fact that Aeneas does not respond favorably to Magus stems from the pressure of Vergil’s literary tradition. Despite the Roman norm of practicing clemency on the battlefield and despite Aeneas’ general predilection for the suppliant, Magus cannot be spared because Achilles refused the supplication of Lycaon. The scriptedness of the scene is made clear by the fact that Aeneas does not respond to Magus’s third argument for mercy. The argument that one more death will not matter since the Trojans are going to win anyway is unlike anything in Lycaon’s petition to 80 On this episode in the Iliad, see especially Lynn-George, Epos, 159-60, 202-9. 56

implicit in the idea of ransom. At the same time, by attributing his refusal of ransom to<br />

Turnus’ killing of Pallas, Aeneas also suggests that before the death of Pallas, he would<br />

have consented to ransoming a suppliant instead of slaughtering him outright, as would<br />

have been consistent with the Roman practice of pardoning enemy combatants who<br />

offered complete surrender. Indeed, this is how the fourth-century commentator Tiberius<br />

Donatus glosses the passage:<br />

humanitatem, inquit, poscis, quae inter partis solet aliquando praestari, sed<br />

istam mihi tuus ille sustulit Turnus et inhumanitatem plenam morte Pallantis<br />

docuit. 79<br />

you are asking for kind treatment, which sometimes exists between factions,<br />

but your Turnus took that away from me and with the death of Pallas he<br />

prescribed all-out cruelty.<br />

Coffee wants to see Aeneas’ rejection of the notion of strict commodity exchange<br />

implied by ransom as a moral improvement on the Homeric model, in which captives<br />

were routinely sold into slavery or ransomed for money, but a number of factors point to<br />

a different view of what is at stake in Aeneas’ rejection of Magus. Aeneas’ response<br />

clings to another Homeric precedent: Book 21 of the Iliad, where, in responding to<br />

Lycaon’s request for mercy, Achilles recalls a time before the death of Patroclus when it<br />

was his practice to ransom his captives rather than killing them in cold blood. For<br />

79 Tiberius Claudius Donatus, Interpretationes <strong>Vergil</strong>ianae, ed. Heinrich Georgii<br />

(Stuttgart: Teubner, 1969), 10.2.<br />

55

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!