04.06.2013 Views

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

REVIEWS AND COMMENTS BY MURRAY N. ROTHBARD 63<br />

attribute <strong>the</strong> importance that it has for Hayek. Of course,<br />

this also means that if everyone knew in advance that he<br />

would be tortured and enslaved one year out of every three,<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r would this be coercion. From this ensues Hayek’s<br />

inordinate passion for <strong>the</strong> rule of law and equality under <strong>the</strong><br />

law, which he reveres to <strong>the</strong> exclusion of all o<strong>the</strong>r (and more<br />

important) aspects of liberty. If everyone were prohibited<br />

from drinking or from blaspheming Allah or forced into<br />

slavery one out of three years, <strong>the</strong>n Hayek could not say for<br />

a moment that this would be coercion or unjustified.<br />

His entire historical section <strong>the</strong>n becomes a mass of distortion,<br />

since he interprets <strong>the</strong> whole libertarian movement<br />

as simply a narrow advance toward equality under <strong>the</strong> law,<br />

which is only one, and a minor, aspect of libertarianism.<br />

Hayek is enabled to do this by his brusque and cavalier dismissal<br />

of <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>the</strong>ory of natural law (natural rights—<strong>the</strong><br />

great libertarian deduction from natural law—is not mentioned<br />

once in <strong>the</strong> Hayek discussion) as “intellectually unsatisfying.”<br />

Since natural law is dismissed as some sort of unimportant<br />

quirk, <strong>the</strong>n obviously only <strong>the</strong> form of law can be discussed,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> content: i.e., would everybody be<br />

equal under whatever law <strong>the</strong>re is? Granted, this restriction<br />

of form would, in fact, restrict <strong>the</strong> content of tyranny to some<br />

degree, but Hayek sees only <strong>the</strong> equality under <strong>the</strong> law as a<br />

value. And not only does he brusquely dismiss natural law<br />

and natural rights from his consideration, he acts as if <strong>the</strong><br />

seventeenth- and eighteenth-century libertarians were not<br />

really concerned about it ei<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

Tied up with his dismissal of natural law is Hayek’s continuous<br />

and all-pervasive attack on reason. Reason is his bête<br />

noire, and time and time again, from numerous and even<br />

contradictory standpoints, he opposes it. The true rationalist<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory was, and is, that reason can discover <strong>the</strong> natural law<br />

of man, and from this can discover <strong>the</strong> natural rights of liberty.<br />

Since Hayek dismisses this even from historical consideration,<br />

he is left with only two choices for <strong>the</strong> formation of<br />

a political ethic: ei<strong>the</strong>r blind adherence to custom and <strong>the</strong><br />

traditions of <strong>the</strong> “social organism,” or <strong>the</strong> coercive force of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!