04.06.2013 Views

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Murray N. Rothbard vs. the Philosophers - Ludwig von Mises Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

MURRAY N. ROTHBARD VS. THE PHILOSOPHERS: UNPUBLISHED WRITINGS<br />

28 ON HAYEK, MISES, STRAUSS, AND POLYANI<br />

In a customary constitution, reason is immanent, but not<br />

<strong>the</strong> abstract reason of <strong>the</strong> rationalists; it is ra<strong>the</strong>r historical<br />

reason in which, in <strong>the</strong> English legal and political tradition,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is less of a rigid contrast between nature and history.<br />

In Matteucci’s opinion, even John Locke’s great work on<br />

natural law essentially speaks of a tradition that became<br />

rationalized and universal. Once again, we find <strong>the</strong> idea that<br />

what is natural is that which has evolved.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> question of <strong>the</strong> relationship between Hayek<br />

and natural law is certainly not easy to define. For example,<br />

Charles Covell came to place Hayek among <strong>the</strong> “defenders” of<br />

natural law, although he makes it clear that he considers<br />

Hayek a defender of natural law by virtue of his opposition to<br />

legal positivism, ra<strong>the</strong>r than for any connection with <strong>the</strong> natural-law<br />

tradition, which is totally lacking in Hayek’s work. 46<br />

Covell says that <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r perspective from which<br />

Hayek refers to a “natural” model, a perspective that is, in<br />

a certain sense, linked to Matteucci’s ideas. Covell writes,<br />

“Hayek constructed an essentially naturalistic model of law<br />

which looked back to <strong>the</strong> tradition in legal philosophy of<br />

Coke and Blackstone.” 47 In this way, Hayek rejects both legal<br />

positivism, for its constructivism, and also <strong>the</strong> idea of <strong>the</strong><br />

of <strong>the</strong> law nay <strong>the</strong> common law itself its nothing else<br />

but reason; which is to be understood of an artificiall<br />

perfection of reason, gotten by long study, observation,<br />

and experience. . . . This legal reason est summa<br />

ratio. And <strong>the</strong>refore if all <strong>the</strong> reason, that is dispersed<br />

into so many several heads, were united into one, yet<br />

could he not make such a law as <strong>the</strong> law of England<br />

is; because by many successions of ages it hath been<br />

fined and refined by an infinite number of grave and<br />

learned men, . . . and by long experience growne to a<br />

such perfection.<br />

46Charles Covell, The Defence of Natural Law: A Study in <strong>the</strong><br />

Ideas of Justice in <strong>the</strong> Writings of Lon L. Fuller, Michael Oakeshott,<br />

F.A. Hayek, Ronald Dworkin, and John Finnis (London: Macmillan,<br />

1992), p. xiii.<br />

47Ibid., p. xiv.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!