25.04.2013 Views

Promise of Time.pdf

Promise of Time.pdf

Promise of Time.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE PROMISE OF TIME


SAITYA BRATA DAS<br />

Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong><br />

Towards a Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> <strong>Promise</strong><br />

INDIAN INSTITUTE OF ADVANCED STUDY<br />

RASHTRAPATI NIVAS, SHIMLA


First published 2011<br />

© Indian Institute <strong>of</strong> Advanced Study, Shimla<br />

All rights reserved.<br />

No part <strong>of</strong> this book may be reproduced<br />

or transmitted, in any form or by any means,<br />

without the written permission <strong>of</strong> the publisher.<br />

ISBN: 978-81-7986-091-5<br />

Published by<br />

Th e Secretary<br />

Indian Institute <strong>of</strong> Advanced Study<br />

Rashtrapati Nivas, Shimla-171005<br />

Typeset at Sai Graphic Design, New Delhi<br />

and printed at Pearl Off set Pvt. Ltd., Kirti Nagar, New Delhi


For<br />

My dear father<br />

Who fi rst taught me to love<br />

Th e love <strong>of</strong> wisdom: philo-sophia


Acknowledgements<br />

We never come to thoughts. Th ey come to us.<br />

—Martin Heidegger<br />

What does it mean to be thankful, and to say ‘thanks’? Th is question,<br />

which is at the very heart <strong>of</strong> an essential thinking, <strong>of</strong> language and <strong>of</strong><br />

our relation to the others, is what has always been a matter <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

for me, as if, as it were, to think itself is to thank, to be thankful for<br />

the arrival <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th erefore, thinkers like Martin Heidegger<br />

see the connection, nay, discover at the very heart <strong>of</strong> thinking—for<br />

thinking too has its heart, it too has its tears and ecstasy—the light<br />

<strong>of</strong> thankfulness: to think is to thank, to be thankful, thankful for the<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> thinking, for the event <strong>of</strong> thinking coming to us. Th erefore,<br />

a thinker does not possess thinking, even less knowledge: thinking is<br />

what is gifted to the thinker for which he says, simply, ‘thanks’. Th ere<br />

lies the dignity and nobility <strong>of</strong> thinking itself.<br />

So I thank, not only for the gift <strong>of</strong> thinking coming to me, for<br />

this mournful joy <strong>of</strong> the experience <strong>of</strong> thinking, but all those and all<br />

that who inspired me have continued to inspire me to open myself<br />

to the joyous coming <strong>of</strong> thinking; all those who shared the ecstasy<br />

and tears <strong>of</strong> my thinking. Th ere is Franson Manjali, under whose<br />

inspiration I have written from the day I met him, and I will write<br />

in the days to come, whatever will come to me as gift, this event <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking. Th ere is Soumyabrata Choudhury, my loving brother, from<br />

whom I have learnt so much, learning never to lose myself in despair<br />

and hopelessness. Renowned French Philosopher Gérard Bensussan,<br />

who was my mentor during my stay at Université Strasbourg and at


viii • Acknowledgements<br />

Maison des Sciences de L’Homme, Paris where I was a post doctorate<br />

fellow during 2006-2007, the one who has never ceased to be<br />

my mentor, my philosopher and teacher for all these years. From<br />

him I have learnt a great deal, namely, to ‘philosophize’. To him I<br />

acknowledge hereby my deepest gratitude. Th anks to the advent <strong>of</strong><br />

Sarita, my beloved wife, who has inspired me to live my life anew;<br />

from whom once more I have learnt to see the open sea and the blue<br />

sky. Th ese people have had hopes in me and this manuscript recounts,<br />

in its own way, the story <strong>of</strong> such a hope contra all hopelessness, and<br />

the necessity <strong>of</strong> such an affi rmation.<br />

Th anks to this beautiful Shimla and this wonderful Institute that<br />

have both soothed my wounded soul at a diffi cult period <strong>of</strong> life; all the<br />

lovely people with whom I lived, joyously; all the local, lovely friends<br />

I have made at Shimla—Mridula and Pankaj above all—who gave<br />

me company in my lonely hours, away from home and away from<br />

Delhi. Th e Director, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Peter Ronald deSouza has inspired me<br />

in his own peculiar way, without words, silently, whose language I<br />

felt I understood. I wish to thank hereby Dr. Debarshi Sen for his<br />

patience and pr<strong>of</strong>essional effi ciency with which he brought out this<br />

book in so little time. Mr. Ravi Shankar, the typesetter, has made this<br />

book look so beautiful; thanks goes to him as well!<br />

Th ere is my father who gifted me this life, whom I now gift this<br />

book, which has already been given to me by him. And thanks<br />

goes to the loveliest and sweetest mother <strong>of</strong> mine, and my siblings<br />

who have silently inspired me all these years, to whom I can return<br />

nothing but love and my infi nite gratitude. And, lastly, thanks to<br />

this manuscript itself, which henceforth will have its own life, which<br />

will now onwards live without me, outside and away from me, forget<br />

me and leave me without a name. Th is book, for some intimate<br />

reason, is dear to me, for somehow in it I have sought to translate<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> my own soul. But since now it is going out to the<br />

world, its language is no longer the language <strong>of</strong> my soul but I hope it<br />

will become the language <strong>of</strong> the world-soul where human beings live,<br />

suff er and hope for redemption.


Beginning at the moment <strong>of</strong> deepest catastrophe<br />

Th ere exists the chance for redemption.<br />

—Gershom Scholem


Th e following chapters have been published previously<br />

1. Th e fi rst chapter <strong>of</strong> the fi rst part Th e Open originally appeared in<br />

Kritike http://www.kritike.org/journal/issue_6/das_december2009.<br />

<strong>pdf</strong><br />

2. An earlier version <strong>of</strong> the second part Th e Lightening Flash<br />

appeared in Philosophical Forum (Willey Blackwell, fall 2010)<br />

vol. 41, issue 3, p. 315-345.<br />

3. Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom is published in Journal <strong>of</strong> Indian<br />

Council <strong>of</strong> Philosophical Research, October-December 2010, vol.<br />

XXVII, no 4, p.91-104.<br />

4. Of Pain is published in Journal <strong>of</strong> Comparative and Continental<br />

philosophy (New York: Equinox Publishers, May 2011), vol. 3: 1.<br />

5. A revised version <strong>of</strong> the chapter Th e Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

is published as Th e Destinal Question <strong>of</strong> Language in Kriterion<br />

(Spring 2011, issue 123).<br />

6. Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love: Messianicity and Exemplarity in<br />

Franz Rosenzweig is read as paper at the 6 th Annual Philosophy<br />

Conference at Athens Institute for Education and Research, held<br />

at Athens, Greece, held during 30 May - 2 June 2011.<br />

7. Fragments in Epilogue section is read as paper called Of Fatigue, Of<br />

Patience – Finitude, Writing, Mourning in a seminar on ‘Levinas<br />

– Blanchot: Penser La Diff erence’, organized by UNESCO, Paris<br />

from 13-16 November 2006.


Contents<br />

Acknowledgements vii<br />

Foreword by Gérard Bensussan xv<br />

Premise 1<br />

PROLOGUE<br />

§ Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong><br />

To Come/Th e Claim <strong>of</strong> Redemption and the Question<br />

<strong>of</strong> History/Truth beyond Cognition/Existence/Messianic/<br />

Th e Lightning Flash <strong>of</strong> Language/Wandering, Th inking/<br />

Confi guration Saying<br />

5<br />

§ Radical Finitude<br />

Th e Immemorial/Th e Mournful Gift/the Logic <strong>of</strong> the World/<br />

Mortality/Introducing this Work<br />

20<br />

PART I – CONFIGURATION<br />

§ Th e Open 39<br />

§ Judgement and History:<br />

Of History/ Metaphysics and Violence/Th e Passion <strong>of</strong><br />

Potentiality<br />

51<br />

§ Transfi guration, Interruption 76<br />

§ Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin 87<br />

Of Beginning/Madness/Astonishment


xii • Contents<br />

§ Repetition 108<br />

Repetition and Recollection/ Moment<br />

§ Language and Death 119<br />

Th e States <strong>of</strong> Exception/Th e Facticity <strong>of</strong> Love and Th e<br />

Facticity <strong>of</strong> Language/Th e Gift <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

§ Confi guration 132<br />

Caesura/Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption/ Discontinuous Finitude/<br />

En-framing, Revelation/Lightning, Clearing/ Constellation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Temporalities/ Transfi nitude<br />

PART II – THE LIGHTNING FLASH<br />

§ Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals<br />

Th e Presupposition//Kierkegaard’s Indirect Communication<br />

161<br />

§ Pain<br />

Work and Pain/Th e Melancholic Gift/ Naming and<br />

Overnaming/Th inking and Th anking<br />

175<br />

§ Apollo’s Lightning Strike<br />

Th e Lightning Flash/Th e Divine Violence<br />

201<br />

§ Revelation<br />

Th e Argument/Synthesis without Continuum/Language as<br />

Revelation in Schelling’s Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Freedom<br />

210<br />

PART III – EVENT<br />

§ Of Event 225<br />

Th e Question <strong>of</strong> Event and the Limit <strong>of</strong> Foundation/<br />

Freedom, <strong>Time</strong> and Existence/Origin, Leap, Event<br />

§ Love and Death 243<br />

§ Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom 251<br />

§ Th e Irreducible Remainder 267<br />

§ Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom 291<br />

Th e No-Th ing <strong>of</strong> Freedom and the Finitude <strong>of</strong> Man/<br />

Causality as a Problem <strong>of</strong> Freedom/Philosophy as Strife


PART IV – MESSIANICITY<br />

§ Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love 305<br />

Exemplarity <strong>of</strong> Translation/the Aporia <strong>of</strong> Love/Revelation <strong>of</strong><br />

Love/Th e Th eologico-Political<br />

PART V – ON PHILOSOPHY<br />

Contents • xiii<br />

§ Erotic and Philosophic 343<br />

§ On Philosophical Research 354<br />

Th e Th ought <strong>of</strong> Death/ Philosophical Research/Notes on this<br />

Work<br />

EPILOGUE<br />

Fragments 381<br />

Notes 399<br />

Bibliography 407<br />

Index 415


Foreword<br />

Between End and Beginning:<br />

The <strong>Time</strong> <strong>of</strong> Speech<br />

Th e beautiful book <strong>of</strong> Satya Das is committed to a phenomenology<br />

<strong>of</strong> promise and explores manifold ways in it. What animates this<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> promise is explicitly inspired by a paradoxical<br />

‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent that the later Heidegger had<br />

named his aspirations. It can be said that the pages you are going<br />

to read contribute to it in a remarkable manner because they lean<br />

towards the exercises <strong>of</strong> it from a very singular angle and access. Th e<br />

developments devoted here to the question <strong>of</strong> the promise have a<br />

force and a fl ash which come to them from an indisputable source<br />

which supports them: the fecundity <strong>of</strong> time, the temporality bursting<br />

forth and stratifi ed by waiting, opening to the event, and the fi nitude<br />

opened to infi nity, wherein the idea that appears in us, according to<br />

Descartes, signifi es in the fi nal analysis this very opening. Th us the<br />

promise, this astonishing object if one can put it this way, evokes<br />

a style, a writing, a strategy <strong>of</strong> presentation (Darstellung) about<br />

which Satya Das explicates in the fi rst part, where one sees how the<br />

deployment <strong>of</strong> this enterprise here is held together with the rigour<br />

<strong>of</strong> a true philosophical research while also being able to emancipate<br />

oneself from one’s most forceful constraints, which results in the<br />

most remarkable originality.<br />

It is under this double and confl icting exigency according to<br />

which an ‘object’ commands a writing that messianism as such, and


xvi • Foreword<br />

especially its very paradigm, the messianic as the index <strong>of</strong> time comes<br />

to be <strong>of</strong> help in the most lively part <strong>of</strong> this work (I am thinking<br />

particularly <strong>of</strong> the fourth part <strong>of</strong> the book) and brings it relief with<br />

its counter-dialectical resources. For this ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the<br />

promise’ is necessarily a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the event and, therefore, a<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the impossible, which is not far from signifying (but<br />

that would indeed be a point that could be discussed—as we used to do<br />

together in Strasbourg not long ago!) an impossible phenomenology.<br />

What is really an event if not an aff ectivity preceding its own<br />

possibility? How, then, can such impossible, impossible before being<br />

real, allows it to be thought, and furthermore, phenomenological<br />

thought? Satya Das does this according to the time <strong>of</strong> the end and<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> beginning and he does it again as well on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

language.<br />

Th e author here explains in particular that the event bears together<br />

and supports the end and the beginning ‘in a monstrous coupling’<br />

which would signify something like a logic <strong>of</strong> the world. Th ere is,<br />

in fact, between the end and beginning a complex pairing that the<br />

messianism alone can achieve to determine it without elucidating it,<br />

according to a causal knowledge. Th e end promises. Th e beginning<br />

begins only from a kind <strong>of</strong> impossibility; because it promises the<br />

promise. Th us, what messianism names fi rst and foremost is an<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> temporality <strong>of</strong> the awaiting and <strong>of</strong> the decision, and <strong>of</strong><br />

the relation to the expected event and its reversal. Th us, messianism<br />

would be an irremissible impossibility <strong>of</strong> thinking whatever is referred<br />

to as the ‘origin’. ‘Th e origin’ will always be older than the objects we<br />

want to genealogize by retracing them to their point <strong>of</strong> departure. It<br />

forbids or interrupts the possibility <strong>of</strong> linking the beginning and the<br />

end as two ‘moments’, two given ‘points <strong>of</strong> time’ that are indiff erent<br />

and interlinked by virtue <strong>of</strong> their being having qualitatively similar<br />

presents. Formalized representations <strong>of</strong> time force us to consider that<br />

what happens in the present at a given ‘point <strong>of</strong> time’ could also<br />

happen in an ‘other’ present having the same quality <strong>of</strong> presence,<br />

at a given ‘point <strong>of</strong> time’ that is anterior and similar. It is against<br />

these representations that messianism has its signifi cance. And that’s<br />

where we grasp its fundamental diff erence in relation to teleology,<br />

eschatology, progressivism and all types <strong>of</strong> fi nalism. Freedom,<br />

existence and experienced time from then on appear as the very


Foreword • xvii<br />

endurance <strong>of</strong> the unexpected and unconditional <strong>of</strong> the messianic<br />

arrival and it is Satya Das’ own style <strong>of</strong> working with this messianic<br />

paradigm that I on my part have tried to elaborate as a novel thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> the event.<br />

To say that the beginning promises the promise is to say that it<br />

puts it ahead <strong>of</strong> itself. Th e beginning is the diff erence, altogether the<br />

coming <strong>of</strong> the promise (without beginning, there’s no promise) and<br />

the projection that dismisses its very appearance (without beginning,<br />

the promise would always be accomplished ipso facto). It is the<br />

promise itself that is promised and it is time itself which is structured<br />

like promise.<br />

As the title Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> suggests, this promising structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> time is co-originarily associated with the question <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

a paradisiacal language in which the spoken language <strong>of</strong> naming is<br />

restrained and reserved. Here the inspiration comes from Rosenzweig<br />

who was able to link time and the waiting for language and<br />

the alterity <strong>of</strong> the other man, who is speaking and awaiting. Th e<br />

delinking, or in the fi nal analysis, redemption itself commands the<br />

‘never ultimate’ <strong>of</strong> the relation to the other, <strong>of</strong> the speech addressed<br />

to him, <strong>of</strong> time and <strong>of</strong> the absolute indetermination <strong>of</strong> the Messiah.<br />

Rosenzweig’s ‘never ultimate’ intends an arrival but without ever<br />

leaving for the assured departure <strong>of</strong> a language to be translated. Such<br />

is the fi ne line along which all speech moves. We always counter pose<br />

the ceaseless overcoming faced with absolute confusion (as many<br />

languages as there are subjects to speak) and the uncertain promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> absolute comprehension (one language for all subjects). Speaking<br />

is thus caught in the momentum that proceeds from an impossible<br />

origin to an event promised but not yet happened. Th is promise <strong>of</strong><br />

speech, this Versprechen has nothing to do with belief, with values,<br />

with an intention or a reference. It is speech itself, language itself,<br />

das Versprechen spricht, the promise speaking. And as Derrida says<br />

in Monolingualism <strong>of</strong> the Other, where I see a certain proximity<br />

to Rosenzweig, it is not possible to speak outside or without that<br />

promise.<br />

Language is, therefore, the rare singular power <strong>of</strong> aff ect and<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. It exceeds itself; it is not adequate to the beingness <strong>of</strong> its<br />

object, and even less to the being that it intends. Th is power is its<br />

impotence—or rather, simply the opposite: it does not know that


xviii • Foreword<br />

it is power-less to know, that it is the very fragility that gives it the<br />

power to say that it can not say, not what she can not say, but its very<br />

ineff ability. Language is self-transcendence par excellence.<br />

It is not that this dense intertwining does not produce a series<br />

<strong>of</strong> specifi c philosophical eff ects which the fi fth part <strong>of</strong> this book<br />

particularly echoes while refl ecting upon the link, knotted around<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> death that passes through so many developments <strong>of</strong><br />

Satya Das, between philosophy and what is named called here as the<br />

‘ethics <strong>of</strong> fi nitude’. It is possible, I think, to determine its fi gure while<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> the Walter Benjamin’s Angel in Th eses on the Philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

History. Th e Angel <strong>of</strong> History can’t be allowed to be pushed towards<br />

radiant tomorrows and toward a future where the mechanical storm<br />

<strong>of</strong> progress drives it. It neither can nor wants to leave without justice<br />

those who are dead and defeated, without providing them a redressal,<br />

whereas pure mechanical progress runs the risk <strong>of</strong> ignoring disasters<br />

and ruins for the sake <strong>of</strong> an end, a fi nality and a conclusion. Th e<br />

experience to come, the future happiness that is legitimate to wait<br />

for, therefore, must be based on the past failures. Th e past asserts its<br />

rights; the past, i.e., the dead who were the living. Benjamin links<br />

large chunks <strong>of</strong> historical time with contents that are not reducible<br />

to historical causality, to progress, to the concept, with experiences<br />

<strong>of</strong> suff ering, I would rather say with passions. In Benjamin, there is<br />

no passion for the past, in the sense <strong>of</strong> a backward looking pastism,<br />

a politics <strong>of</strong> nostalgia, but there is an ever passionate past, that is to<br />

say, never dead. As a result, the contents <strong>of</strong> the three dimensions<br />

<strong>of</strong> historical time are thereby distorted. Th e past can’t be reduced<br />

to the thought <strong>of</strong> its necessity. Th e present is not exhausted in the<br />

mere signifi cance <strong>of</strong> my full presence in this present. Th e future is<br />

not predetermined by historical reason. Th ese torsions are worked<br />

by a thought <strong>of</strong> the return <strong>of</strong> time upon itself, no doubt, but it does<br />

not correspond literally to the ‘abyssal thought’ <strong>of</strong> Zarathustra—<br />

but yet I see here somehow an echo, an attempt to speak in the<br />

somewhat unspeakable language <strong>of</strong> Nietzsche. Th is attempt stays<br />

close to the eternal return <strong>of</strong> the same. What Benjamin thinks<br />

and <strong>of</strong>f ers us to think is the tragedy <strong>of</strong> a past that is irremovable,<br />

surrounded by an absolute immutability or something that would<br />

never return to be identical to the same temporality. He comes up<br />

for and against Nietzsche, with something like a hope <strong>of</strong> the past,


Foreword • xix<br />

as much as a remembrance <strong>of</strong> the future. Th e weakness <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

waits for a possible rectifi cation, to come, promised by time. Th e<br />

present is thus never contemporary to itself, purely adequate to<br />

a full presence, heedless <strong>of</strong> the past and headed for the future. If<br />

all that happens happened in the pure present, time would never<br />

be a surprise, a grasping <strong>of</strong> the subject. But time is precisely this<br />

dispossession <strong>of</strong> mastery, the subject seized in the moment. Between<br />

the two allegories, namely the Angel <strong>of</strong> Benjamin, and Nietzsche’s<br />

Postern, there is a kind <strong>of</strong> repulsive affi nity, both challenging and<br />

diffi cult.<br />

It seems incontestable to me that the ethics <strong>of</strong> fi nitude according to<br />

Satya Das cannot be anything other than an ethics <strong>of</strong> the temporality<br />

and <strong>of</strong> the temporalization magnetized by the ever impossible<br />

fulguration <strong>of</strong> the ethical moment. I see in this one <strong>of</strong> the richest<br />

areas <strong>of</strong> this beautiful book and I hope it will have numerous and<br />

diverse readers.<br />

Gérard Bensussan<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Strasbourg


§ Premise<br />

Th is mortal called ‘man’ is an open existence, exposed to mortality and<br />

free towards the coming that is revealed to him in lightning fl ash. Free<br />

towards the ever new possibility <strong>of</strong> beginning, the mortal is endowed with<br />

the gift <strong>of</strong> time, as if an eternity that remains beyond his death, a time<br />

always ‘to come’. In this messianic remnant <strong>of</strong> time alone lies redemptive<br />

fulfi llment for the mortals—in the possibility <strong>of</strong> the ever new beginning<br />

in the time ‘to come’.<br />

It is this question <strong>of</strong> time to come, the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a redemptive<br />

future that is pursued in this work. It occurs as and in a confi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

questions, which is not a system but rather, let’s say, a gesture or style <strong>of</strong><br />

pursuing a thought which is repetitively and, therefore, discontinuously<br />

seized as questions. Th ese are the questions <strong>of</strong> mortality and temporality,<br />

<strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> language that reveals man, beyond any predicative<br />

historical closure, his fi nitude and the Openness where man fi nds<br />

himself exposed to the event <strong>of</strong> coming, to the redemptive fulfi lment in this<br />

coming itself, which he anticipates in an existential attunement <strong>of</strong> hope.<br />

All these questions are introduced in the movement <strong>of</strong> confi guration, or<br />

constellation that affi rms the coming time, and feels the requirement <strong>of</strong><br />

redemption in hope, beyond all that is given to our historical existence.<br />

Th ese exercises <strong>of</strong> thinking are to be called: ‘confi guration thinking’.


Prologue


§ Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong><br />

To Come<br />

Th is is an attempt to elaborate upon the notion <strong>of</strong> coming time, the<br />

coming into existence, not what has come as ‘this’, or ‘that’, but the<br />

coming itself, the messianic promise <strong>of</strong> the redemptive arrival. In a<br />

phenomenological and deconstructive manner, which is a gesture<br />

<strong>of</strong> reading and seizing a truth rather than a method here, I will<br />

attempt to reveal the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> what is meant in<br />

the dominant sense <strong>of</strong> ‘politics’, ‘history’, or even ‘logic’, to loosen<br />

this structure—<strong>of</strong> what Heidegger calls Abbau and Destruktion der<br />

Ontologie in Sein und Zeit—so that outside the closure <strong>of</strong> the Struktur<br />

to affi rm and to welcome the coming, the future Not Yet. Th is is a<br />

movement towards a messianic affi rmation that problematizes the<br />

dominant metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> history whose immanence<br />

is guaranteed by an immanent self-grounding subject. Th is will<br />

be shown in the subtle, extremely complex connection between a<br />

certain metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> history and the dominant<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> logic based upon predicative proposition. In so far<br />

as predicative proposition determines the truth on the basis <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

already revealed and opened history, understood speculatively, that is<br />

based upon predicative proposition cannot think <strong>of</strong> any event as event,<br />

this coming into existence itself as coming. Hence, the immemorial<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the ‘time to come’, this gift <strong>of</strong> the taking place <strong>of</strong> time<br />

is always attempted to be closed in the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence<br />

that <strong>of</strong>ten assumes the form <strong>of</strong> a mythic foundation. If the task <strong>of</strong><br />

politics and history is to be thought in a more originary manner, and


6 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

if politics and history is not to be mere reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> this<br />

promise in the name <strong>of</strong> the task <strong>of</strong> an immanent negativity (since it<br />

must already presuppose the originary promise <strong>of</strong> their redemptive<br />

fulfi lment), then it will be necessary here to think another notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> history and politics outside this given sense <strong>of</strong> these concepts that<br />

means, outside their ground in metaphysics—history that opens itself<br />

up to the intensity <strong>of</strong> the messianic fulfi lment, to the redemption <strong>of</strong><br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> history itself.<br />

What is to think ‘to come’, understood in the verbal resonance <strong>of</strong><br />

the infi nitive ‘to’? What does it mean ‘now’ or, what is this ‘now’?—<br />

to think this ‘to come’ again, to think <strong>of</strong> the promise and the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> event, to think again the remnant <strong>of</strong> time after the end <strong>of</strong> time,<br />

after each end and after each completion, after each ‘after’, this hope<br />

for an infi nite after only because it is already an infi nite before? Is<br />

it necessary now, more than ever before and more than ever after,<br />

precisely here and now, with an urgency <strong>of</strong> the moment, which is<br />

also urgency <strong>of</strong> each moment and each place, to be borne with ‘the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> hope’—as Ernst Bloch (1995) names this principle—<br />

till and beyond, till and after death when the large-scale devastation<br />

and devaluation <strong>of</strong> all values seemed to have been accomplished, and<br />

seem to be accomplishing all the time? What, whence, is the necessity<br />

<strong>of</strong> hope now when all hopes seemed to have vanished from life, and<br />

life appears now more unredeemed and damaged than ever before,<br />

and yet whose claim <strong>of</strong> redemption has remained, precisely because<br />

<strong>of</strong> its utter impoverishment, undiminished, whose distant light is not<br />

yet extinguished?<br />

The Claim <strong>of</strong> Redemption and<br />

the Question <strong>of</strong> History<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> ‘to come’ is essentially about the claim <strong>of</strong> redemption<br />

in our historical destinal existence which is heard in its utmost<br />

intensity and urgency when a certain metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong><br />

history seems to have come to its gathering force and to its exhaustion.<br />

As if now the claim <strong>of</strong> redemption must enter anew, if the above<br />

questions have still retained their sense today, into the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

death and exhaustion, outside any thanatology and outside ontology,<br />

and outside death’s service into the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong>


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 7<br />

politics and history, not to take side <strong>of</strong> death against life, nor to take<br />

side <strong>of</strong> life against death, but to take side <strong>of</strong> future, to take the side from<br />

future which is always coming. Th is necessity <strong>of</strong> an ‘after’ after every<br />

‘after’, this ‘not yet’ that must remain ‘not yet’ is a necessity <strong>of</strong> another<br />

faith, <strong>of</strong> another promise and another thought <strong>of</strong> revelation. Th is faith<br />

is the one that is not satisfi ed merely being attached as an appendix<br />

to reason, nor merely with positing another being as a transcendental<br />

object somewhere in a transcendental world beyond this ‘world’. It<br />

is, rather, a thought <strong>of</strong> promise in the not yet which is rescued from<br />

the womb <strong>of</strong> the damaged present; it is to gather together again those<br />

sparks after the vessel is broken once into thousand pieces.<br />

Th is thought <strong>of</strong> the affi rmative, which is perhaps the most<br />

urgent task <strong>of</strong> thinking that we call ‘philosophical’, demands that<br />

the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> our history and politics be made<br />

manifest and un-worked so that thinking can inaugurate another<br />

history which is not satisfi ed merely with grasping what has happened<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> its apophansis, but one that ecstatically remains open<br />

to the immemorial and to the incalculable and the unconditional<br />

arrival. Th is is to envisage an ecstatic history without monuments<br />

or monumentality whose the historical task <strong>of</strong> inauguration must<br />

accompany the un-working <strong>of</strong> the closure <strong>of</strong> immanence <strong>of</strong> selfpresence.<br />

In this sense, this historical task <strong>of</strong> rescuing the redemptive<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> the advent from any immanence <strong>of</strong> apophantic closure<br />

is inseparable from the question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> truth, truth<br />

that releases in philosophical contemplation that element <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial from the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition.<br />

Truth beyond Cognition<br />

At stake in these labours <strong>of</strong> thought is an attempt <strong>of</strong> a discovery, or<br />

un-covery <strong>of</strong> the moments <strong>of</strong> the originary event <strong>of</strong> the historical<br />

when history itself makes momentary pauses. It is to welcome the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> history during those fl eeting moments <strong>of</strong> lightning fl ash<br />

that illumine the taking place <strong>of</strong> history itself as a phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

unapparent apparition that defi nes it as the phenomenality <strong>of</strong> any<br />

phenomenon par excellence. We are concerned here with this taking<br />

place <strong>of</strong> history itself and not what is ‘presently given’ within the realm<br />

<strong>of</strong> a given historical totality. Philosophical truth, if it does not have to


8 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

be saturated with the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon ‘presently given’,<br />

is only rescued truth, ‘wrested truth’. It is truth that momentarily<br />

advents in the midst <strong>of</strong> existence, like what Benjamin says <strong>of</strong> ‘pr<strong>of</strong>ane<br />

illumination’ that makes its sudden apparition felt when ‘dialectics<br />

comes to a standstill’ (Benjamin 2002, p. 10). Th is truth, in contrast<br />

to the categorical cognition <strong>of</strong> ‘given presences’, calls forth an entirely<br />

diff erent notion <strong>of</strong> temporality and historicality, an entirely diff erent<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> phenomenality: not the phenomenality that is categorically<br />

grasped in the apophantic judgement but a phenomenality when the<br />

unapparent in a lightning fl ash makes itself felt, that dispropriates us,<br />

that takes away from us the foundation <strong>of</strong> language and judgement<br />

and exposes us to the openness <strong>of</strong> time, opening to the immemorial<br />

and to the Not Yet. Th is open is not a topological or ontological site<br />

but the monstrous site <strong>of</strong> history where event arrives as an event, the<br />

coming comes into presence. Th is coming cannot be predicated on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> what has come, or what would come to pass by. It is a coming<br />

that moves history or better inaugurates history out <strong>of</strong> a fundamental<br />

fi nitude <strong>of</strong> our being.<br />

What, then, does it mean ‘to come’? Let’s say, ‘to come’ is the<br />

occurring <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> existence, the truth <strong>of</strong> the occurring <strong>of</strong><br />

existence, the truth <strong>of</strong> the occurring itself, or still better, the occurrence<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth itself. It is this occurring, this event before anything that has<br />

occurred is the true and genuine notion <strong>of</strong> the historical. In this sense<br />

truth is essentially historical, but more originally understood, no<br />

longer as that is assimilable to the periodic breaks belonging to the<br />

accumulative gathering <strong>of</strong> truth, but truth as this epochal break itself,<br />

which for that matter is to be thought as historical before history,<br />

before memory and before monumentality.<br />

Existence<br />

To come: it is in this infi nitive <strong>of</strong> the verbal lies the resonance <strong>of</strong><br />

existence, not as an accidental property <strong>of</strong> existence, but existence in<br />

its existential character in its ecstasy and exuberance <strong>of</strong> advent. In this<br />

sense, this infi nitive verbal character <strong>of</strong> existence is more originary<br />

than any categorical predication <strong>of</strong> existence as ‘given presence’.<br />

Th erefore Heidegger at the beginning <strong>of</strong> his Being and <strong>Time</strong> (1962)


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 9<br />

distinguishes the existential analytic <strong>of</strong> Dasein from the predicative,<br />

categorial grasp <strong>of</strong> ‘the given presence’ (Vorhandenheit) in so far as<br />

existence, in the infi nitive <strong>of</strong> its verbal resonance is open to its own<br />

coming to presence, which is at each moment irreducible to what is and<br />

what has become present as ‘given presence’, as ‘constant presence’.<br />

Th e infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the verbal resonance which is the existentiality<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence as such, therefore, lies in a more originary manner: in<br />

‘the there’ <strong>of</strong> the verbal, as ex-sistence, which means, its ecstatic<br />

exceeding <strong>of</strong> any ‘-sistence’. Existence is essentially excessive. Herein<br />

lies the transcendence <strong>of</strong> Dasein, the essential non-closure <strong>of</strong> Dasein,<br />

Dasein which is each time fi nite and mortal. Here, ‘to come’ is not one<br />

particular mode <strong>of</strong> the three modes <strong>of</strong> time, but a ‘to come’ which is at<br />

each time a ‘to come’ without which there is neither past, nor presence,<br />

nor future for Dasein. At each moment <strong>of</strong> existing, Dasein is to come to<br />

itself, is to come to presence, because at each moment <strong>of</strong> existing Dasein is<br />

fi nite and mortal in its innermost ground. Unlike the ‘entities presently<br />

given’ (Vorhandenheit), Dasein ex-sists ecstatically, i.e., as an opening<br />

to the coming whose facticity, its ‘the there’ (Da <strong>of</strong> Da-sein), must<br />

already always be manifested if there is to be predicative, categorical<br />

grasp <strong>of</strong> presently given entities. How then, or when its ‘Da’ appears<br />

itself as ‘Da’ to Dasein if not as that which not merely, unlike<br />

‘presently given entities’, is the apparition <strong>of</strong> the apparent, but <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent in lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> the immemorial? In his later works,<br />

Heidegger attempts to develop a ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent’,<br />

a phenomenology that is more originary than the phenomenology<br />

<strong>of</strong> consciousness’ self-presence. Such a ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent’ is concerned with phenomenon that, being more<br />

originary than ‘constant presence’ <strong>of</strong> given present, is the event <strong>of</strong><br />

being, the coming to presence, or rather, presencing <strong>of</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong><br />

being, which for that matter, cannot be thought within the reductive<br />

totalization <strong>of</strong> the dominant metaphysics which is the history <strong>of</strong><br />

being as presence. Th is presencing <strong>of</strong> presence or, coming to come: ‘the<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent’ precedes and is more originary<br />

than dialectical mediation, and is, in a certain sense, a tautology. Th e<br />

unapparent is the letting or giving (‘es gibt’) <strong>of</strong> Being—the open ‘Da’ <strong>of</strong><br />

Dasein—where the presencing presences. In his Zähringen seminar <strong>of</strong><br />

1973, Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> this ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent’:


10 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

What is to be thought is ’presencing namely presences’.<br />

A new diffi culty arises: this is clearly a tautology. Indeed! Th is is a<br />

genuine tautology: it names the same only once and indeed as itself.<br />

We are here in the domain <strong>of</strong> the unapparent: presencing itself<br />

presences.<br />

Th e name for what is addressed in this state <strong>of</strong> aff airs is: which is<br />

neither being nor simply being, but … :<br />

Presencing presences itself (Heidegger 2003, p.79)<br />

And little later, again,<br />

I name the thinking herein question tautological thinking. It is the<br />

primordial sense <strong>of</strong> phenomenology. Further, this kind <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

is before any possible distinction between theory and praxis. To<br />

understand this, we need to learn to distinguish between path and<br />

method. In philosophy, there are only paths; in sciences, on the<br />

contrary, there are only methods, that is, modes <strong>of</strong> procedure.<br />

Th us understood, phenomenology is a path that leads away to come<br />

before… and it lets that before which it is led to show itself. Th is<br />

phenomenology is a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. (Heidegger<br />

2003, p. 80).<br />

What Heidegger calls ‘facticity’ <strong>of</strong> existence (<strong>of</strong> the ‘Da’ <strong>of</strong> Dasein) with<br />

which ‘the phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent’ is concerned, Schelling<br />

calls it ‘actuality’ which is ‘un-pre-thinkable’ (Unvordenkliche) that<br />

must already hold sway beforehand even in order for a ‘speculative<br />

judgement’ which Hegel elaborated dialectically speculatively in<br />

Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit (1998). In this way Schelling distinguishes the<br />

‘metaphysical empiricism’ <strong>of</strong> his positive philosophy from Hegelian<br />

speculative empiricism <strong>of</strong> negative philosophy (Schelling 2007a).<br />

While negative philosophy can only grasp in a categorial-predicative<br />

manner what is the result <strong>of</strong> a process by retrogressively recuperating<br />

what has become <strong>of</strong> it, Schelling seeks the beginning in the ‘un-prethinkable’<br />

actuality (the ‘Da’ <strong>of</strong> Dasein, the event <strong>of</strong> ex-sisting) which<br />

must already always manifest itself before thematizing, predicative,<br />

categorical cognition, opening thereby existence to its coming as it were<br />

for the fi rst time. Th e exposure to the immemorial is what Schelling


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 11<br />

calls ‘irreducible remainder’, a ‘not yet’ <strong>of</strong> a past, an irrecuperable past<br />

that continuously exposes existence to its inexhaustible outside, to its<br />

un-predicative past <strong>of</strong> promise. What renders existence an ‘irreducible<br />

remainder’—its originary non-closure is nothing but its inextricable<br />

mortality—its radical fi nitude that refuses to be lifted up unto<br />

thought completely. Th is fundamental incompletion <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

its originary un-accomplishment and non-work refuses Hegelian<br />

Aufhebung, the consolation <strong>of</strong> the concept, and the concept’s false<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> infi nitude and Absolute. Th e coming is the advent <strong>of</strong> time<br />

itself cannot be thought within any reductive historical-metaphysical<br />

totalization, or within the immanence <strong>of</strong> a self-presencing Subject.<br />

It is the positive beyond any immanence <strong>of</strong> negativity. Such is the<br />

presencing <strong>of</strong> presence.<br />

So it is with Rosenzweig. If the concept, the Absolute Concept’s<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> infi nite and immortality is a false, vain consolation for the<br />

mortal beings, it is because philosophy, as the cognition <strong>of</strong> the All<br />

presupposes—at the same time denying this presupposition—that<br />

death is Nothing for the mortals if it cannot be made into work for the<br />

sake <strong>of</strong> the universal. In this way, the multiple singularities <strong>of</strong> mortal<br />

cries will not be heard in the universal pathos <strong>of</strong> the One Absolute,<br />

for Absolute can only be One and be One only. What would the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a system be, a system <strong>of</strong> philosophy (for it is question <strong>of</strong> value<br />

and not <strong>of</strong> knowledge) for the mortal beings who are individuated<br />

and singularized by its mortality, and yet this morality is foreclosed<br />

in order to make possible <strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> categories? Since existence,<br />

which is fi nite and mortal, is not enclosed within any philosophical<br />

discourse <strong>of</strong> totality or is not consoled by the vain consolation <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept, existence is thereby granted the gift, in its mortality,<br />

<strong>of</strong> a time to come which Rosenzweig thinks in a messianic manner<br />

as ‘redemption’ that is beyond the concept and beyond any closure,<br />

which is an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> time, or a time <strong>of</strong> remnant that is to<br />

arrive eternally. It is always to come because it is the event <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

itself.<br />

Schelling, Heidegger, and Rosenzweig—in their irreducibly<br />

singular manners—are thinkers <strong>of</strong> coming and <strong>of</strong> mortality, <strong>of</strong><br />

promise and <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, <strong>of</strong> future and <strong>of</strong> the gift. One can name<br />

them as ‘the thinkers <strong>of</strong> fi nitude’.


12 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Messianic<br />

Th e messianic affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the coming has nothing <strong>of</strong> the theological<br />

messianism about it, at least in the given recognizable form <strong>of</strong> a<br />

religious tradition. It is, to say with Jacques Derrida, a ‘messianicity<br />

without messianism’, a messianicity that affi rms unconditionally the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the other, or opens itself, outside totality or system, to<br />

this promise <strong>of</strong> the other who is always ‘to come’ in each hic et nunc.<br />

In his Monolingualism <strong>of</strong> the Other or Prosthesis <strong>of</strong> Origin, Derrida<br />

writes about the untotalizable promise <strong>of</strong> future and its prosthetic<br />

origin:<br />

But the fact that there is no necessarily determinate content in this<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the other, and in the language <strong>of</strong> the other does not make any<br />

less indisputable its opening up <strong>of</strong> speech by something that resembles<br />

messianism, soteriology, or, eschatology. It is structural opening, the<br />

messianicity, without which messianism itself, in the strict or literal<br />

sense, would not be possible. Unless, perhaps, this originary promise<br />

without any proper content is, precisely, messianism. And unless all<br />

messianism demands for itself this rigorous and barren severity, this<br />

messianicity shorn <strong>of</strong> everything (Derrida 1998, p. 68).<br />

In so far as the task <strong>of</strong> thinking this messianic promise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

future demands that the reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> the dominant<br />

metaphysical tradition be opened up and radically put into question,<br />

this task itself is inseparably bound up with experience <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

as mortality. Th is thinking itself, in this innermost manner, is fi nite<br />

and mortal. If the dominant metaphysics has made death into the<br />

service <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-universal history and made death to retain a<br />

mere sacrifi cial signifi cance, it has its supplement in the theologicopolitical<br />

totalization that has made death a work, a kind <strong>of</strong> production<br />

<strong>of</strong> death through calculative technological manner, that has made our<br />

politics and ethics bereft <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> future. Th is means that our<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> politics and history derive their metaphysical foundation from<br />

a certain tacit theological determination <strong>of</strong> death, i.e., the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

foundation without any given foundation. Th is death does not know<br />

true mourning.<br />

All movement <strong>of</strong> totalization seeks to denude the future <strong>of</strong> its<br />

sense and to rob our mortality <strong>of</strong> its aff ection. It does not know


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 13<br />

true mourning, and knows not the movement <strong>of</strong> hope. In order to<br />

counter this movement <strong>of</strong> totalization that is permeating in all aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> our lives to such an extent that such a totality today does not<br />

know any totality that has limits, territory or locality, it is necessary<br />

to introduce another movement—without thetic, positing dialectical<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> concept—the redemptive movement <strong>of</strong> unconditional<br />

promise and the gift <strong>of</strong> time where time itself times, or ‘presencing<br />

itself presences’, a promise <strong>of</strong> coming outside violence <strong>of</strong> immanence<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-consuming presences.<br />

To introduce this movement, that means to expose philosophical<br />

thinking to the non-conditional outside, to the promising remnant<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, is the highest task <strong>of</strong> thinking today. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

today, at the accomplishment <strong>of</strong> certain metaphysics, is no longer<br />

to constitute epochal historical totality that sublates historical<br />

violence into a form <strong>of</strong> reconciliation, as a kind <strong>of</strong> speculativetragic<br />

atonement. Th is reconciliatory movement <strong>of</strong> the speculativetragic-historical<br />

that founds epochal totality has lost its redemptive<br />

sense today, since this totalizing movement can begin and end its<br />

process only with pure, autochthonous, thetic positing that carries<br />

its violent character (<strong>of</strong> positing) right to the end in a manner <strong>of</strong><br />

circular re-appropriation. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking is no longer that<br />

<strong>of</strong> reconciliation, dialectically accomplished, which begins with<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> pure positing that in order to reach beyond this<br />

violence, posits its other which—ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is still positing—is once<br />

more mere conditioned, once more mere thetic, and so on and so<br />

forth. Th e circular movement <strong>of</strong> the positing never attains to the<br />

unconditional forgiveness beyond the violence <strong>of</strong> pure positing. It<br />

would be necessary to think <strong>of</strong> an originary, unconditional promise<br />

before any power <strong>of</strong> positing, a non-positing positive <strong>of</strong> coming, a<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the unapparent presencing that itself presences, an ecstasy<br />

that ex-tatically escapes the circular re-appropriation <strong>of</strong> predicates<br />

and conditions. Th e tautological presencing presences or coming comes<br />

that no phenomenology or ontology <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness’ selfpresence<br />

attains, is essentially a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> promise. It is on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> this originary promise <strong>of</strong> a radical futurity which is not an<br />

apparition like other phenomenon, but that advents each time each<br />

hic et nunc, may there arrive an ‘unconditional forgiveness’ beyond<br />

any immanent result <strong>of</strong> a dialectical-tragic reconciliation.


14 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

It is here that Derrida’s (2001) messianic thought <strong>of</strong> an<br />

‘unconditional forgiveness’, which is to be distinguished from any<br />

immanent result <strong>of</strong> a dialectical-tragic reconciliation, demands our<br />

careful attention. Th e ‘messianicity without messianism’ is to be<br />

connected with the possibility <strong>of</strong> an ‘unconditional forgiveness’ which<br />

demands another thinking <strong>of</strong> mortality itself, mortality whose refusal<br />

to work clamours for another inception rather than the dialectical. It<br />

is the demand <strong>of</strong> a redemptive forgiveness beyond reconciliation. Th e<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> forgiveness and the messianic affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the coming must<br />

pass through an experience <strong>of</strong> non-condition, or mortality on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

which the unapparent appears.<br />

The Lightning Flash <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

In what sense has the tragic-heroic pathos <strong>of</strong> reconciliation today<br />

lost its redemptive meaning if not in the sense that the immemorial<br />

promise and gift is only thought within the notion <strong>of</strong> an epochal<br />

totality? When the notion <strong>of</strong> promise is appropriated and is sought to<br />

be mastered by inscribing it into a categorical conceptual apparatus,<br />

then language—bereft <strong>of</strong> remembrance and promise—reifi es<br />

what has become <strong>of</strong> presence, ‘the given presence’, and forgets the<br />

immemorial promise given in the language <strong>of</strong> naming, in the dignity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the name. Th en the categorical task <strong>of</strong> cognition, its labour <strong>of</strong><br />

predication robs language its linguistic essence, that <strong>of</strong> welcoming<br />

the advent to arrive that lies outside the predicative proposition. Th e<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> confi guration that outside the cognitive categorical<br />

totality rescues the promise in saying and welcomes in a messianic<br />

hope the advent to come without violence is what Rosenzweig calls<br />

‘language-thinking’ (Rosenzweig 2000, pp. 109-139). What arrives<br />

in philosophical language, according to Rosenzweig, is not the<br />

universal essence <strong>of</strong> the One, but the linguistic essence <strong>of</strong> the fi nite<br />

singulars which is the multiple singulars’ exposure or abandonment<br />

to their singularly irreducible fi nitude. Th e linguistic essence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fi nite beings, who are irreducibly multiple and singulars, is in this<br />

intrinsic intimacy with those beings’ pure exposure to their fi nitude.<br />

Similarly for Heidegger too, ‘the phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent’ has an essential relation to the naming the language <strong>of</strong><br />

man who is essentially this fi nite being. Th inking too, ins<strong>of</strong>ar it comes


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 15<br />

to us and that we never go to thinking and is a gift from a site wholly<br />

otherwise than man, arrives on the basis <strong>of</strong> our fi nitude that demands<br />

that it is to be thanked. Th e dignity and nobility <strong>of</strong> thinking lays in<br />

this recognition. With this thankfulness there is receptivity—in so<br />

far our fi nitude renders us, like an open wound, being receptive—<br />

welcoming the advent <strong>of</strong> coming, or to the presencing <strong>of</strong> the presence.<br />

Language, even before it is categorical cognition <strong>of</strong> ‘given presences’<br />

in apophansis, is the naming-saying that welcomes the unapparent<br />

apparition, i.e., the letting being as such to appear. With thankfulness<br />

and gratitude, mortals welcome the coming and receive the future.<br />

Th is promise <strong>of</strong> future is what the wanderer-thinker, in his path <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking, contemplates and is intimated at during sudden lightning<br />

fl ashes, for the advent <strong>of</strong> which he must be ready to take a leap,<br />

and open his soul to the future <strong>of</strong> thinking itself, without making a<br />

system out <strong>of</strong> it, without totalizing it. Language is this exposure, or<br />

this abandonment to the excessive light <strong>of</strong> the sudden apparition <strong>of</strong><br />

the otherwise that in the lucidity <strong>of</strong> the coming blinds him with its<br />

brilliancy.<br />

In traditional messianic religions, the coming <strong>of</strong> Messiah is<br />

something like violence. It is violence unlike any other violence,<br />

violence without the violence <strong>of</strong> law, <strong>of</strong> what Benjamin calls ‘divine<br />

violence’ as distinguished from law-positing and law-preserving<br />

violence. It is such a lightning fl ash that the poet Hölderlin speaks as<br />

the strike <strong>of</strong> Apollo: in relation to this momentary apparition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent, the poet-wanderer or the philosopher is always belated.<br />

Hence he must arrive beforehand, like the Nietzschean philosopher<br />

<strong>of</strong> heralding, announcing the unapparent apparition, implying the<br />

presencing that itself presences, the coming itself that comes, and not<br />

like the owl <strong>of</strong> Minerva taking its fl ight at the dusk <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

Wandering, Thinking<br />

In philosophy, there are only paths; in sciences, on the contrary, there<br />

are only methods, that is, modes <strong>of</strong> procedure.<br />

Heidegger (2003, p. 80)<br />

Th erefore, sonority or rhythm <strong>of</strong> wandering is caesural. One who has<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> wandering in mountain paths knows the fragmented


16 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

joining <strong>of</strong> those mountain paths. Th ese joints are co-junctions <strong>of</strong><br />

the disjointed without any prior principle. One may call such an<br />

experience a constellation or confi guration <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th e experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> wandering on the path <strong>of</strong> thinking refuses gathering, or collecting<br />

into unity, even if it is unity with diff erence. Th inking moves in<br />

pathways and not in methods, i.e., ‘modes <strong>of</strong> procedures’ (Ibid.). It<br />

is tempered with its own dispersal and fragmentation, and thereby<br />

refuses to have to do with the unity <strong>of</strong> a thesis. Th e temporality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wandering is like relation to a time that has already happened, occurred<br />

to which it is joined as a heterogonous assemblage, a constellation <strong>of</strong><br />

paths, or a confi guration <strong>of</strong> discontinuous ways. What is to come must<br />

have happened, already always, at a moment <strong>of</strong> lucid darkness<br />

wherefrom time itself begins its journey, and spacing emerges. Th is is<br />

to say: ‘presencing itself presences’. Unlike the dialectical-speculative<br />

process <strong>of</strong> a history leading straight to the Absolute, wandering is not<br />

succession <strong>of</strong> instants though, because <strong>of</strong> his fi nitude and mortality,<br />

the wanderer relates to himself as a point in-between. To exist is to<br />

fi nd oneself in this in-between which is, for that matter, absence <strong>of</strong><br />

time’s presence and absence <strong>of</strong> space’s presence, the in-between that<br />

opens itself on both sides to the indefi nite, incalculable lengthening<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, as if time stretches out without beginning and without end.<br />

Th inking, philosophical thinking is this exposure to this time before<br />

time that advents as lightning fl ash where the immemorial presents<br />

itself as unapparent apparition.<br />

Th e wanderer-thinker therefore constantly exposes himself to his<br />

non-condition. It is in this sense that Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> Dasein as<br />

‘the placeholder <strong>of</strong> nothing’ (Heidegger 1998, p. 91), the placeholder<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘outside’. It is like the caesura <strong>of</strong> a resonance, which in resonating,<br />

inscribes an interval in the pathway <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th inking is this great<br />

caesural resonance that astonishes the wanderer-thinker as he moves<br />

along in the great winding paths <strong>of</strong> solitary mountains. Wandering,<br />

the poet-thinker makes the movement, the movement <strong>of</strong> infi nity<br />

outside the dialectical thesis and anti-thesis. Th erefore, wandering<br />

is non-dialectical movement par excellence. Th is wandering, which<br />

itself is caesural resonance, repeats itself and through this repetition<br />

brings something new that in its advent astonishes him, surprises<br />

him, throws him outside <strong>of</strong> himself, unto the open, unto that site<br />

<strong>of</strong> encounter with the advent. Repetition here never mimetically


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 17<br />

reproduces the same truth at a diff erent level but welcomes truth<br />

that each time suspends the law <strong>of</strong> the dialectical. Th inking, if it has<br />

to open itself in its ecstasy to the space <strong>of</strong> the outside where truth<br />

advents, this manifestation <strong>of</strong> the unapparent must have a diff erent<br />

logic than the logic <strong>of</strong> a scientifi c method.<br />

Configuration Saying<br />

Th erefore, the necessity: to repeat the truth <strong>of</strong> the advent, to repeat<br />

the advent <strong>of</strong> truth, repetitively, to be seized by the advent this is<br />

coming and always remaining to come. Th ere is always something like<br />

a universality <strong>of</strong> thinking, not the universality <strong>of</strong> the concept but the<br />

universality <strong>of</strong> the ‘singular each time’. Language <strong>of</strong> thinking bears this<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> the universal through its multiple repetitions. Th e task,<br />

through this diff erential repetition, and universalizing the singular<br />

‘presencing <strong>of</strong> presence’, is to preserve each time anew the excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> this event <strong>of</strong> unapparent apparition without reducing it to any<br />

immanence <strong>of</strong> predicates and ‘presently given’ presents. Th erefore,<br />

there arises the necessity to say, again and again, each time anew,<br />

in the poetic naming-language <strong>of</strong> mortals that lets the unapparent<br />

appear, without reducing it to the universality <strong>of</strong> the categorical<br />

cognitive grasp. Since the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming in its momentary<br />

apparition discontinues, suspends, interrupts itself, it does not belong<br />

to any discourse <strong>of</strong> totality or system. It does not fi nd itself as to its<br />

own ground and condition. Such an advent that resonates in every<br />

poetical saying says the whole and yet remains outside <strong>of</strong> any totality.<br />

It is what the present writer shall call confi guration saying, which is<br />

not a method, for it does follow any ‘ism’ as such but a gesture, a<br />

sonority, a resonance <strong>of</strong> saying that says over and over again, which<br />

is at each moment fi nite and new, something that heralds rather than<br />

gives the result <strong>of</strong> a process in the form <strong>of</strong> predicative propositions.<br />

Th e confi guration saying is an attempt to think the whole without<br />

totality, repetition without recuperation, and universality without<br />

universalism. Each coming is a coming singularly universal, a coming<br />

itself which is promised as gift given to beings mortal and fi nite. It is<br />

a gift complete, a completed gift in itself and therefore there is in it a<br />

universality whose completeness completes our speech. Silence is the<br />

beatifi c recognition <strong>of</strong> this completeness <strong>of</strong> speech, a silence which is not


18 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

defi ance nor recalcitrance <strong>of</strong> speech but the completeness <strong>of</strong> speech itself<br />

wherein consists the dignity <strong>of</strong> the language <strong>of</strong> the mortals. It is not<br />

the silence <strong>of</strong> the mythic-heroic tragic man as defi ance because he<br />

is superior to the God in his mortality, because <strong>of</strong> his capacity <strong>of</strong><br />

death can defy even the God. Th e ‘divine mourning’ that resonates in<br />

silence is the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the immemorial gift, remembrance <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial promise, that is, the promise <strong>of</strong> the unthought that<br />

is already always given to man as a gift. Th erefore, in silence language<br />

itself, at its limit, as it were mourns, or mournfully remembers the<br />

immemorial promise, because it fails itself to name the name. Th ere<br />

is, therefore, always certain mournfulness in silence and a silence in<br />

mournfulness, which is distinguished from the silence <strong>of</strong> the tragicmythic<br />

heroic man who asserts at the face <strong>of</strong> his own death his<br />

solitude and his self denuded <strong>of</strong> contingent features <strong>of</strong> his character. 1<br />

What follow in the following pages are confi guring <strong>of</strong> sayings<br />

<strong>of</strong> what the wanderer-thinker is exposed, in his path <strong>of</strong> wandering,<br />

to the appearing <strong>of</strong> unapparent, the coming itself. What kind <strong>of</strong><br />

appearing is this which is appearing <strong>of</strong> the unapparent? What kind <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenon is this whose phenomenality lies in its un-apparition?<br />

What is this coming, which is not any ‘this’ or ‘that’ coming, which is<br />

not exhausted in anything that has come to pass, that has appeared<br />

to disappear and that has become a phenomenon so that it no longer<br />

appears to us anymore? Is there a coming that is the appearing <strong>of</strong><br />

the non-apparent and phenomena <strong>of</strong> the non-phenomenal? Th e<br />

wandering the poet-thinker, wandering in his solitary winding path<br />

<strong>of</strong> a mountain, is seized by the perplexity, or aporia <strong>of</strong> this question.<br />

If there is an essential thinking, or if thinking is to attain the essential,<br />

then thinking must not shy away from this aporia, but rather must<br />

allow this aporia to move thinking itself and in this pathway <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking, attain the essential. All philosophical thinking is essentially<br />

fi nite and incomplete. Out <strong>of</strong> this essential incompleteness, the poetthinker<br />

repeats himself here and there, as the wanderer must renew<br />

his leaps, because repetition always arises out <strong>of</strong> an essential fi nitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking itself.<br />

What is presented in this work is nothing but the ‘wrested truth’,<br />

spoken in a confi guration that emerges out <strong>of</strong> the experiences <strong>of</strong><br />

wandering. Th erefore, no claim here been made that the truth is to<br />

be presented as completed truth. Once such a claim is made, the


Th e <strong>Promise</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong> • 19<br />

truth no longer remains the truth but becomes an imbecile, castrated<br />

cognition <strong>of</strong> given phenomenon commensurable with a settled mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence. Truth is only to be wrested, seized in its movement, in its<br />

becoming by going under, in its point <strong>of</strong> beginning or starting, but not at<br />

the moment <strong>of</strong> settled result. Th at, however, does not mean that truth<br />

in itself is always incomplete, but only the claim <strong>of</strong> saying the truth—<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the mortal—in its absolute completeness<br />

remains only a false claim. Truth in its absolute presentation and<br />

arrival as an event is the destruction <strong>of</strong> a language. It ruins language<br />

and abandons it to fainting murmur, or to the lament <strong>of</strong> music.<br />

Th erefore, the attempt to say ‘the wrested truth’ can only be a<br />

regulated form <strong>of</strong> divine madness which must constantly be solicited<br />

to. Th ere is always the possibility, not merely by going astray, but <strong>of</strong><br />

madness itself as far as truth is never <strong>of</strong> settled mode <strong>of</strong> cognition but<br />

that which when once seizes the philosopher, it makes him into what<br />

Plato calls a ‘horsefl y’.<br />

Truth in itself is never only a totality <strong>of</strong> the successive moments <strong>of</strong><br />

gradated cognition. In other words, there is no method in philosophy<br />

but only constellation <strong>of</strong> paths. Constellation is an assemblage but<br />

never a totality, a whole that makes sudden, momentary appearance<br />

that in its lightning fl ash seizes the thinker. It is only on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

this prior seizure, the thinker can seize and wrest truth, for truth is<br />

not property <strong>of</strong> the mortal called ‘man’ but man belongs to truth, is<br />

claimed by truth and makes him fi rst <strong>of</strong> all what he is, the one who<br />

seizes and wrests truth from the immemorial that founds him and<br />

dispropriates him in advance. Th is is the promise <strong>of</strong> thought itself,<br />

ins<strong>of</strong>ar as—to speak with Heidegger—‘we never go to thinking,<br />

thinking comes to us’ (Heidegger 2001, p.6), in its sudden advent,<br />

like a lightning fl ash.


§ Radical Finitude<br />

If the emergence <strong>of</strong> modern philosophy is marked by the<br />

materialization <strong>of</strong> the question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude (once it becomes the<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> recounting the genesis and structure <strong>of</strong> subjectivity that<br />

has to emerge without any given ground, since no condition is given<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> ‘substance’) that is because this fi nitude is essentially<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the question <strong>of</strong> the subject. Th e question <strong>of</strong> the subject in its<br />

fi nitude becomes the question <strong>of</strong> modernity and its determination <strong>of</strong><br />

historical breaks belonging to the accumulative movement <strong>of</strong> history<br />

itself. In Hegel’s case, therefore, the destinal question <strong>of</strong> history as<br />

he recounts in Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit becomes the metaphysical<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the subject whose fi nitude is grasped as the labour <strong>of</strong><br />

negativity. At the limit <strong>of</strong> this metaphysics <strong>of</strong> history, when the whole<br />

history <strong>of</strong> that metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity comes to a ‘standstill’ (in<br />

the sense <strong>of</strong> what Benjamin calls ‘dialectics at a standstill’), it reveals<br />

itself to be that where the claim <strong>of</strong> redemption is not fulfi lled. It<br />

then becomes necessary to think <strong>of</strong> a radical notion <strong>of</strong> fi nitude as<br />

the task <strong>of</strong> inaugurating another thought <strong>of</strong> history which should at<br />

the same time articulate a radical critique <strong>of</strong> the violence <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

Th e notion <strong>of</strong> history is bound with the question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude where<br />

fi nitude is seen less as a labour <strong>of</strong> negativity but as a gift on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> which mortals are placed in the open site <strong>of</strong> the inauguration <strong>of</strong><br />

history itself.<br />

The Immemorial<br />

What would our existence be if its days and months and years are to<br />

pass away in monotonous succession like the Hegelian ‘homogenous


Radical Finitude • 21<br />

succession <strong>of</strong> empty instants’ (Benjamin 1977, pp. 251-261) which,<br />

like the leaves <strong>of</strong> trees, appear in Spring only to disappear in Autumn<br />

and return in Spring, or like the infi nite nameless waves <strong>of</strong> the Sea—<br />

without hope, meaning and promise—bringing to us nothing but the<br />

eternal murmur <strong>of</strong> what is already become fi nished, accomplished,<br />

when each moment is like any other moments, an eternal Now, like<br />

the eternal Now <strong>of</strong> the waves, if there is no ‘not yet’ to become, no<br />

‘not yet’ to come, and no hope for the ‘not yet’ to accomplish? If the<br />

great Hegelian dialectical-historical time is none but this eternally<br />

un-redemptive, eternally boring return to the same, without any<br />

ecstatic outside, without the redemptive advent <strong>of</strong> future outside,<br />

then how despairing and desolate our existence would be? What<br />

would the meaning <strong>of</strong> our existence, and our being with others, our<br />

politics and our ethics, our mortality and our natality, the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> our history and our fate be if mortals in its history appear only<br />

to earn his recognition through violent life and death struggle and<br />

through a sacrifi cial, negative relation with other mortals, if not such<br />

a history but be an eternal, eternally unredeemed melancholy, like<br />

sighs <strong>of</strong> Abraham if he is to lose his faith (imagine Kierkegaard’s sighs<br />

too!), or the melancholic wind <strong>of</strong> this vast desert <strong>of</strong> history which<br />

has become <strong>of</strong> our existence? Our relationship with us, with other<br />

mortals, to the divine and the rest <strong>of</strong> created existence would only<br />

have the meaning <strong>of</strong> an un-redemptive negativity.<br />

It would then be necessary, if the sense <strong>of</strong> mortality <strong>of</strong> the mortals<br />

not to be exhausted by the meaning that negativity gives to it, to open<br />

up this metaphysically-negatively determined closure <strong>of</strong> dialecticalhistorical<br />

time to another notion <strong>of</strong> a temporality which remains as<br />

a time <strong>of</strong> hope and fulfi lment, <strong>of</strong> a positive outside negativity, <strong>of</strong><br />

an infi nity outside totality. If the great metaphysician <strong>of</strong> the West<br />

thinks the historicity <strong>of</strong> history as the work <strong>of</strong> negativity, then one<br />

wonders further: Is the historicity <strong>of</strong> history for the mortals, who<br />

as mortal existence is in need <strong>of</strong> a redemptive future, exhausted in<br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> history that the dialectic <strong>of</strong> negativity gives to it?<br />

What would the ‘human’ and the meaning <strong>of</strong> being ‘human’ be<br />

if he is only the product <strong>of</strong> his own death and death <strong>of</strong> the other<br />

mortals, he whose consciousness <strong>of</strong> his own existence and that <strong>of</strong><br />

the Absolute is nothing but his own ‘work <strong>of</strong> death’ (Hegel 1998, p.<br />

270), accomplished by death’s negative labour? Can the meaning <strong>of</strong>


22 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

being ‘human’ exhaustibly be determined on the basis <strong>of</strong> death alone,<br />

death which is nothing but negativity? What would the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

his mortality and meaning <strong>of</strong> his existence be if the mortal were not<br />

open to his own mortality and other created existence, in so far as<br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> mortality consists in opening to other mortals, to<br />

the divine and the elemental depth <strong>of</strong> the sky and to the animals and<br />

the earth and being exposed to the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> his coming to existence?<br />

Would it not be necessary, then, that the negativity <strong>of</strong> death to be<br />

opened up to the open which fi rst <strong>of</strong> all places man in relation to<br />

himself, to the divine, to nature and to the rest <strong>of</strong> created existence?<br />

What would the meaning <strong>of</strong> a historical task for a historical man be<br />

if he is not the space which is the space <strong>of</strong> opening and the beginning<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own historicity and its destinal fate which, for that matter,<br />

exceeds any closure that is earned through his ‘work <strong>of</strong> death’ (Ibid.)<br />

and through the labour <strong>of</strong> his negativity? Th e negativity <strong>of</strong> death,<br />

and the meaning <strong>of</strong> history which the negativity <strong>of</strong> death gives to<br />

it, would neither be the originary meaning <strong>of</strong> mortality, nor be the<br />

originary meaning <strong>of</strong> history. If the sense <strong>of</strong> mortality for the mortals<br />

is exhausted in the negativity <strong>of</strong> his death, then death would leave to<br />

nothing <strong>of</strong> a time to come for him beyond this death. Th ere would<br />

not be then the advent <strong>of</strong> future outside an enclosed dialectical<br />

historical totality; nor there will have redemption <strong>of</strong> what remained<br />

unredeemed in the world? Th ere will only be an incessant laments<br />

<strong>of</strong> unfulfi lled hopes and <strong>of</strong> a past whose injustice is not yet rectifi ed.<br />

Th ese are the questions opened up by Franz Rosenzweig’s Th e Star<br />

<strong>of</strong> Redemption. Th ese are also our questions here. Th ere is good deal<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason—and one does not need to evoke the empirical facts <strong>of</strong><br />

history here—to suspect with Rosenzweig that the dialectical-negative<br />

time <strong>of</strong> history, instead <strong>of</strong> affi rming a redemptive future, is content<br />

to enclose the event <strong>of</strong> coming into an immanent totalizing process.<br />

Th erefore, it would be necessary here is to renew the question already<br />

implicit in Rosenzweig, which is, that <strong>of</strong> rethinking the question <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude.<br />

Th e thought <strong>of</strong> future and the messianic, redemptive fulfi lment is<br />

always a question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, which is, mortal’s radical openness<br />

in respect to his ground, condition and possibility on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

a freedom which is granted to him in advance, as pure gift, as


Radical Finitude • 23<br />

pure <strong>of</strong>f ering. Th is gift is without any economy <strong>of</strong> equivalences and<br />

without any possibility <strong>of</strong> measurement, the immeasurable par<br />

excellence that dispropriates him in advance, and that lies as a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> abyss, an inscrutable, unfathomable secret which, in so<br />

far it is secret, makes at all possible something like manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world. Th is revelation <strong>of</strong> the secret is that phenomenon<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unapparent that opens the world for the fi rst time. Th e<br />

‘presencing that itself presences’ is not an originary presence that<br />

can be apophantically traced back. It is the spacing that is before<br />

any presence-absence; it is what exposes the mortal to his truth,<br />

to his human temporality and inaugurates history. If the mortals<br />

understand anything like what exists in the world on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> temporality, this temporality must already always be revealed<br />

to him in advance so that he understands his being as being, his<br />

existence as existence. Th is revelation is not the revelation <strong>of</strong> a given<br />

presence, but a coming to presence which while appearing, conceals<br />

itself. It is this that we call ‘secret’.<br />

Th erefore we have this strange feeling within us that we always existed<br />

from eternity. In relation to the coming to presence which, while being<br />

unapparent, opens to us the world—or, the world is opened for us<br />

where for the fi rst time temporality makes itself manifest—in relation<br />

to this originary presencing-presence, it appears as if our existence<br />

is always belated, as if in relation to our existence there always<br />

precedes an immemorial past which cannot be appropriated in our<br />

self presence. Schelling’s Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World (2002) an eternal past<br />

which has never been present, an immemorial origin is seen precisely<br />

as the source <strong>of</strong> divine mournful joy that fundamentally attunes<br />

a fi nite existence. An eternal past which has never been present<br />

opens the world to the mortals, as if for the fi rst time, a past that<br />

can never be appropriated and recuperated in the mortals’ historical<br />

memory only because it is the condition <strong>of</strong> memory as such. What<br />

opens the world for the mortals is that <strong>of</strong> an originary forgetting<br />

before any memory since this opening has never come to pass as a<br />

‘passed presence’. Hence, it is the groundlessness <strong>of</strong> our past, like<br />

our mortality, that opens the pure futurity for us, and makes human<br />

history as such possible. Th is mortality, beyond the immanence <strong>of</strong><br />

self-presenting negativity, is more originary promise <strong>of</strong> futurity to


24 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

which existence is exposed or (to say with Heidegger) ‘thrown’. It is<br />

this exposure to this abyss <strong>of</strong> forgetting or to the immemorial, this<br />

peril <strong>of</strong> existence fi rst opens the world and the temporality in its pure<br />

advent makes its unapparent apparition.<br />

In his Th e Unforgettable and the Unhoped For (2002), Jean Louis<br />

Chrétien attempts to think this gift <strong>of</strong> the immemorial that fi rst opens<br />

existence to truth, and makes human temporality as such possible. It<br />

is to think that the originary loss that already always departing founds<br />

the world by exposing us to ‘the peril <strong>of</strong> being’ (Chrétien 2002, p.<br />

22), sending us forward to what is yet to come. ‘Th e peril <strong>of</strong> being’ is<br />

at the same time a sending to the pure future, ‘a loss that founds us’.<br />

Forgetting is the dimension according to which being sends us, calls<br />

to us, and promises us, throws us forward...there is indeed a loss that<br />

founds us, and this loss only gives and gives us (Chrétien 2002, p. 37)<br />

Th is excess <strong>of</strong> the immemorial in us, this unsaturated past that we<br />

can never return to as an origin is the future <strong>of</strong> the origin, for it can<br />

only be anticipated, out <strong>of</strong> forgetting, an origin to come. ‘We can and<br />

must’, says Chrétien, ‘always seek and always learn what is not yet<br />

known, in human time and according to human future, indefi nite<br />

and fi nite at once, by reason <strong>of</strong> the fact that all seeking is built on to a<br />

past that is absolute and other than human. We are the future <strong>of</strong> the<br />

absolute past, the future <strong>of</strong> the immemorial, and it is in this that it<br />

gives us what is ours concerning thought’ (Ibid., p. 12). Th is excess <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial in us that can never be returned unto makes each <strong>of</strong><br />

us, while giving us time and truth, essentially and irreducibly fi nite.<br />

Th is non-contemporaneity and non-co-incidence <strong>of</strong> the mortal in<br />

relation to his condition and ground defi nes the mortality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mortals which precedes as a non-conditional condition, or even as an<br />

unfathomable past that can only be seen by the mortals who live each<br />

time in-between, as ahead <strong>of</strong> itself, as not yet. In his Being and <strong>Time</strong><br />

Heidegger examines the idle chatter <strong>of</strong> the inauthentic existence<br />

that covers up the non-conditional character <strong>of</strong> mortality by making<br />

mortality merely as an event ‘not yet’. Hence, it is a consolation for<br />

a philosopher like Epicurus: ‘if death is there I am not there, if I am<br />

there death is not there’. As if death is already always not there.<br />

Th e already always is this immemorial gift which is also the<br />

forgetting <strong>of</strong> other origin. Our fi nitude is not an immanent fi nitude


Radical Finitude • 25<br />

that encloses us in the ever encircling destiny or fate <strong>of</strong> negativity<br />

where the mortals are exposed to each other’s violence <strong>of</strong> negativity, to<br />

the force or power <strong>of</strong> pure positing. Our fi nitude, on the other hand,<br />

arising out as the immemorial gift, is an excess in us, and that fi rst<br />

<strong>of</strong> all opens us to the promise <strong>of</strong> a future not yet. What is excess in us<br />

is not so much excess <strong>of</strong> a pure positing, thetic presence that we win<br />

by the power <strong>of</strong> our negativity, but the excess <strong>of</strong> a loss that we never<br />

keep losing each time, that never keep departing from us and never<br />

keep abandoning us, exposing us at each moment <strong>of</strong> our existence to<br />

the peril <strong>of</strong> forgetting, and yet that, while disappropriating us from<br />

ourselves gives, and gives us to ourselves as presence so that we may<br />

come to the presencing <strong>of</strong> our presence. Th is gift <strong>of</strong> presence is the<br />

gift that arises out <strong>of</strong> an essential loss, what is already always lost<br />

even before memory, even before anything that has been gained, even<br />

before there is anything like ‘being’ or ‘existent’.<br />

The Mournful Gift<br />

Mortality is not that which serves as a ‘work’ <strong>of</strong> negativity that the<br />

mortals appropriate as the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> history and<br />

his politics, but an originary opening <strong>of</strong> time for the mortals on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone something like history and politics make<br />

manifest. Th e task <strong>of</strong> philosophy is to open the sense <strong>of</strong> our history<br />

and politics outside its metaphysical closure to the open-ness <strong>of</strong> time,<br />

to the originary revelation and disappropriating manifestation <strong>of</strong> our<br />

ground and condition. In other words, the philosophical thinking<br />

as originary opening to our non-conditional condition is also an<br />

originary opening to the originary gift character <strong>of</strong> our existence, to<br />

the presencing <strong>of</strong> presence before any immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence, to<br />

the immemorial excess that founds us, which for that matter never<br />

cease disappearing us, departing from us, for it has already always<br />

departed while giving us and exposing us at the same time to the<br />

peril <strong>of</strong> existence.<br />

Th is gift character, the originary donation-character <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

haunts our mortal life, like the spectres <strong>of</strong> a more ancient past which<br />

does not allow itself to be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> the ‘metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence’ (Derrida 1994, p. 74). Since only the mortals hear the<br />

echoes <strong>of</strong> the past haunting the presence, like the spectres <strong>of</strong> an


26 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

immemorial being haunting our life, it is to such a mortal being<br />

existence comes as gift, as a donation before memory and before time .<br />

Th is mortal ‘man’ is not the origin and end <strong>of</strong> his own existence, but<br />

his existence arises as an unsaturated gift from a destination or origin<br />

which is elsewhere, which is not yet ‘human’ and not yet ‘being’. Th e<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> the originary gift and the radical fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the mortals,<br />

which in so far is gift is outside man’s power <strong>of</strong> appropriation, can<br />

only be thought at the limit <strong>of</strong> the ‘metaphysics <strong>of</strong> presence’ (Ibid.).<br />

For the divine, uncreated being, his existence is not gift, because the<br />

God spaces himself at his own space and times himself at his own<br />

time. Th erefore, God is understood to be that being in whom his<br />

essence coincides his existence, and, as the medieval theologians tell<br />

us, his existence is pure actuality without possibility. Only the mortal<br />

whose existence lies in pure donation is belated in relation to his<br />

own ground, his condition and his past; only in the mortal, the<br />

excess <strong>of</strong> his existence lies in an immemorial gift or in the gift <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial. Th erefore, man has something like a past which is a<br />

past before any passed past, an immemorial past beyond memory<br />

that unconditionally deprives us the foundation <strong>of</strong> our own being<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> its own self-grounding. It is in this sense existence is<br />

inextricably, in the innermost manner, is fi nite. Yet it is only on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the originary fi nitude mortals are open to something like the<br />

incalculable arrival <strong>of</strong> future and to his immemorial past, as if here<br />

time itself lengthens itself to the infi nity outside any immanence <strong>of</strong><br />

self-presence.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> the philosophical thinking is, to open us, outside any<br />

metaphysical totalization, to the sudden lightning fl ashes <strong>of</strong> the pure<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> the future and to the immemorial past without mastery<br />

and without appropriation and to attune ourselves to that beatifi c<br />

joy inseparable from an attunement <strong>of</strong> a fundamental mourning,<br />

which Hölderlin speaks as Grundstimmung (1980). In a certain text,<br />

Schelling too speaks <strong>of</strong> this in-experienciable experience <strong>of</strong> mortality,<br />

which is the non-conditional condition <strong>of</strong> experience, itself as the<br />

occasion <strong>of</strong> the birth <strong>of</strong> thinking:<br />

He who wishes to place himself in the beginning <strong>of</strong> a truly free<br />

philosophy must abandon even God. Here we say: who wishes to<br />

maintain it, he will lose it; and who gives up, he will fi nd it. Only he<br />

has come to the ground <strong>of</strong> himself and has known the whole depth


Radical Finitude • 27<br />

<strong>of</strong> life who has once abandoned everything, and has himself been<br />

abandoned by everything. He for whom everything disappeared and<br />

who saw himself alone with the infi nite: a great step which Plato<br />

compared to death.<br />

(Quoted in Heidegger 1985, pp. 6-7)<br />

Th e beatifi c joy <strong>of</strong> this ‘divine mourning’ that Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> is<br />

not the joy <strong>of</strong> cognition but participation in the Infi nite, a partaking<br />

<strong>of</strong> the divine joy in the mode <strong>of</strong> philosophical contemplation without<br />

yet being damaged by the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition. It is a partaking<br />

in the immemorial from where knowledge itself arises, and yet to<br />

which no knowledge attains its self-fulfi lment. It is participation<br />

with an absolute past which only comes to us from an incalculable,<br />

an equally eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> future, and an eternal remainder <strong>of</strong><br />

time. Th is possibility alone is redemptive when on the basis <strong>of</strong> an<br />

originary dispropriation mortals partake <strong>of</strong> the eternity and infi nite<br />

in an unsaturated gift, in an excess <strong>of</strong> promise given beforehand,<br />

beyond being and beyond any time <strong>of</strong> presence. In a letter after the<br />

death <strong>of</strong> Caroline, Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> this ‘divine mourning’ as what<br />

existence in its inextricably mortal condition is aff ected with, attuned<br />

with, that is a fundamental attunement, an essential aff ection: ‘I now<br />

need friends who are not strangers to the real seriousness <strong>of</strong> pain and<br />

who feel that the single right and happy state <strong>of</strong> the soul is the divine<br />

mourning in which all earthly pain in immersed’ (Schelling 1975).<br />

Philosophical contemplation, instead <strong>of</strong> evading the thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> mortality, must allow itself to be seized by it, to be dispossessed<br />

by it, to be abandoned by it, to be tempered by it, for only then,<br />

at the limit <strong>of</strong> thinkability and cognitive mastery, thinking opens<br />

itself to the non-condition, and to the unsaturated excess <strong>of</strong> the<br />

gift. Th erefore, philosophical thinking is always a thinking that, in a<br />

necessary manner, by a logic innermost to it, is tempered with its own<br />

impossibility that forever haunts the philosophical contemplation. It<br />

is in the pure state <strong>of</strong> exception, in pure abandonment, in the nudity<br />

<strong>of</strong> an abandonment where being is exposed to its peril that something<br />

appears that strikes the philosopher, claiming his entire existence. He<br />

then loses, as Hölderlin speaks, ‘his tongue in a foreign land’, where<br />

lightning strikes him, separates him from himself, throws him outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> himself, rather than this lightning belonging to him as possession.<br />

Exposed, abandoned, denuded, the mortal is the ‘un-accommodated,


28 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

bare being’. One remembers here King Lear in Shakespeare’s great<br />

Storm scene <strong>of</strong> his great play where being stripped <strong>of</strong> his veil <strong>of</strong> false<br />

being-as king, Lear is exposed to the pure humanity <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’<br />

who is none but a ‘perilous being’ (Chrétien 2002, p.22), whose<br />

being essentially is this exposure to the peril. ‘For us’, to say with<br />

Chrétien again, ‘all truth is exposed to the peril <strong>of</strong> forgetting and we<br />

relate to it only in and through this same peril. A human being is not<br />

only a being in peril, a perilous being, but also the peril <strong>of</strong> being, that<br />

in which being risks itself’ (Ibid.).<br />

Th e philosopher or the poet—whom Aristotle (1971) calls ‘the<br />

melancholic spirits’—whose task is to articulate the opening <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world and the polis is, therefore, also the being who is the most<br />

a-polis. He is <strong>of</strong> all beings the most perilous being, who losing his<br />

‘tongue in a foreign land’, must articulate on the basis <strong>of</strong> this loss<br />

what is always to come and what is already always the immemorial.<br />

He is thereafter thrown into the search for that which constantly<br />

eludes him, to which his thinking fails to attain, for it has already<br />

always lost in an immemorial time. Th is failure is not a failure like<br />

any other, but that bestows upon thinking a feeling <strong>of</strong> sublime awe.<br />

It is the destiny, or fate <strong>of</strong> thinking, if it seeks the essential that it<br />

must constantly fail to think the unthought <strong>of</strong> the immemorial, for<br />

it is what is the excess <strong>of</strong> thought, and for that, is the beginning<br />

<strong>of</strong> all that is thinkable. Immanuel Kant calls this experience ‘awe’<br />

that elicits from the thinker ‘respect’ (Achtung). Th is experience, in<br />

its sublimity, is a gift bestowed upon the thinker, which is for that<br />

matter never a possession. Heidegger calls this gift as the gift <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unthought, the unthought itself as the gift that thinking bears as<br />

its essential failure, in the sense that it is already always departed<br />

from each and every measurement <strong>of</strong> thought. It is the immeasurable<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unthought that is the immemorial past <strong>of</strong> all thought, and<br />

thereby is the beginning <strong>of</strong> thought, <strong>of</strong> opening thought to being and<br />

being to thought.<br />

The Logic <strong>of</strong> the World<br />

Mortality and fi nitude is neither a component part <strong>of</strong> a mortal’s<br />

existence in totality, nor an accidental property <strong>of</strong> existence as such,<br />

but his innermost, essential groundlessness. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this


Radical Finitude • 29<br />

radical fi nitude, on the basis <strong>of</strong> his non-condition, that man is open<br />

to what he himself is and what he is not. Th e radical fi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

mortal existence lies in the inscrutable nature <strong>of</strong> its ground that is<br />

already always, in an immemorial past, fallen outside, diverted itself. If<br />

existence is always already outside its own ground, then it means that<br />

a mortal existence is always in relation (without any relation) to its<br />

outside to which it is open, like an open wound, that de-constitutes,<br />

dispropriates it in advance. Th is originary ‘irreducible remainder’ is<br />

that immemorial forgetting that while never attaining memory opens<br />

us to being and time. As such, this ‘irreducible remainder’ is also<br />

the principle <strong>of</strong> pure potentiality that opens up future, that arrives<br />

from future that is already always ahead <strong>of</strong> itself. Th e ahead-ness <strong>of</strong><br />

the always already cannot be understood dialectically as negativity<br />

<strong>of</strong> death that converts itself into being and sublates itself into<br />

the Absolute concept. It is rather that, beyond being and beyond<br />

negativity, precedes the speculative memory <strong>of</strong> the dialectical. It is<br />

the immemorial which never attains the memory <strong>of</strong> the speculative<br />

history. It is the pure potentiality <strong>of</strong> future, arising from immemorial<br />

past that never attains complete being without remainder. Unlike the<br />

negativity <strong>of</strong> death, this pure potentiality <strong>of</strong> future is not the work <strong>of</strong><br />

Aufhebung—that <strong>of</strong> preservation, elevation and negation. It does not<br />

convert the nothing into being, for this conversion to be possible,<br />

which is negativity’s terrible power, the immemorial must already<br />

always grant a time to come. In other words, there must be the<br />

already always <strong>of</strong> the immemorial which is not yet negative, and not<br />

yet work. Th e positivity <strong>of</strong> the non-work, which is the immemorial<br />

donation <strong>of</strong> ‘presencing that presences’ precedes the work <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

without having itself its own world founded upon its immanent<br />

ground, for it must grant the gift <strong>of</strong> the world by giving in advance the<br />

world its coming to come to itself.<br />

Th erefore, mortality and fi nitude is essentially historical in a<br />

more originary sense than dialectical-speculative essence <strong>of</strong> history<br />

constituted by the labour <strong>of</strong> the negative. Th e pure facticity <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality is not a historical fact which is arrived as a result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dialectical historical process at the end, which is also the process <strong>of</strong><br />

predication. Th is facticity, a positive more originary than negative,<br />

and more originary than predication, cannot be sublated into pure<br />

thought bereft <strong>of</strong> language in the conceptual cognition, but that


30 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

already adheres in language in its infancy. Language is our exposure to<br />

the immemorial donation, to the peril <strong>of</strong> the unapparent apparition<br />

that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens being to language on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone<br />

the mortals speak. In speaking this naming-language, the mortals<br />

are touched by the tremor <strong>of</strong> the unnameable, the immemorial loss<br />

that founds unconditionally the ground <strong>of</strong> our existence. Th is prepredicative<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> the world in language that hears in speaking<br />

the trembling <strong>of</strong> the unground is more originary than the language <strong>of</strong><br />

negativity and judgement that founds dialectical historical totalities.<br />

Similarly if the notion <strong>of</strong> the historical is to be opened to a far more<br />

originary sense than the speculative determination <strong>of</strong> the dialectical,<br />

then it must be seen as opening to the immemorial: a history, as<br />

facticity <strong>of</strong> spacing that keeps to itself the promise <strong>of</strong> the immemorial,<br />

that keeps to itself the secret <strong>of</strong> forgetting, that keeps to itself the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unapparent. Th is is the memorial task <strong>of</strong> history: not to remember<br />

a lost origin that has come to pass by, but to remember the immemorial<br />

that has never come to pass by, that has never been present, that has never<br />

been memorial.<br />

Our world is never contemporary with its immemorial origin.<br />

Th at there is this world is only basis <strong>of</strong> the originary separation from<br />

its immemorial origin to which the world never returns, but which<br />

always comes to it from a future incalculable. Th e coming into existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world is also a moment <strong>of</strong> separation, or an inscription <strong>of</strong><br />

a partition or division that erases itself, that it does not belong to<br />

the world, for it is the world’s condition <strong>of</strong> its coming into existence,<br />

for it is the founding <strong>of</strong> the world, or the world presencing itself to its<br />

own presence. Th e world is born, and has come into existence in a<br />

partition <strong>of</strong> itself and its immemorial, unapparent ground that is<br />

already always departed, diverted from all memory and lost from all<br />

appropriation. It is because <strong>of</strong> this world’s departure from its own<br />

origin as its condition <strong>of</strong> existence that the world cannot be wholly<br />

the world <strong>of</strong> works, even if it is death’s supreme achievement. It is<br />

rather mortality’s pure gift which is inscrutable and is unfathomable.<br />

What is thought in the thought <strong>of</strong> fi nitude and mortality is<br />

the opening <strong>of</strong> the world, its originary logic <strong>of</strong> origin, its event<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming to presence which cannot be thought in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

existing predicates about the world, or in terms <strong>of</strong> the being <strong>of</strong> the


Radical Finitude • 31<br />

world understood in its nominative, which, as such, exceed all our<br />

reductive metaphysical totalization. Th e fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the world, or<br />

rather, the worlding <strong>of</strong> the world, and its attunement <strong>of</strong> mourning<br />

for a non-appropriable, non-totalizable, absent, excluded,<br />

expelled, separated, partitioned, departed origin, makes our history<br />

and politics essentially fi nite and non-totalizable, which, in so far<br />

it is non-totalizable, is at once tempered with the possibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

redemptive joy, because this fi nitude is the condition <strong>of</strong> the world’s<br />

coming into existence.<br />

Hope and melancholy are not two opposite attunements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. Th ey attune the world in its coming into presence, in the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence as fundamental moods or attunements, bearing the gift<br />

and promise <strong>of</strong> its coming to come, ‘presencing to presence’. Th is coming<br />

is not a progressive realization <strong>of</strong> the past in a successive manner,<br />

nor a kind <strong>of</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a process that lifts, elevates unto itself this<br />

process. Th ought historically, that means non-dialectically, the world<br />

is to be attuned to melancholy as possible mood <strong>of</strong> its existence. Th e<br />

verbal infi nitive <strong>of</strong> the possible is the not yet <strong>of</strong> the world, which<br />

in its infi nitive is an infi nitive ‘not yet’. Th e eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> the<br />

not yet demands infi nite, joyous affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the world that affi rms<br />

the advent <strong>of</strong> future. With the possibility <strong>of</strong> mourning, joy is too<br />

given at the same time, at the same time when time times and space<br />

spaces, when past, presence and future come together in a momentary<br />

presentation that illumines all that has been, all that is and will be.<br />

Th is redemptive illumination <strong>of</strong> the moment that presents eternity<br />

in a momentary, sudden apparition falls outside any reductive<br />

totalization achieved by the negative labour <strong>of</strong> universal history. Th e<br />

moment when the unapparent appears, and the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> eternity<br />

monstrously couples with temporality: this moment does not belong<br />

to any self-presentation <strong>of</strong> dialectical historical instant, nor is it<br />

accomplished as the absolute concept <strong>of</strong> universal history. It remains<br />

as the eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> history that keeps in remembrance the messianic<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the advent.<br />

Melancholy and joy are not understood here as psychological<br />

states, nor they are to be anthropologically understood. Th ey are<br />

the fundamental attunements <strong>of</strong> the world and existence to its own<br />

condition and coming into presence. Th erefore one can say: as there


32 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

is a hope for the not yet, a future that is already always given in an<br />

immemorial past, so there is a melancholy already given as possibility<br />

to come, a possibility and not yet completely attained actuality.<br />

Th erefore, melancholy is an originary attunement <strong>of</strong> the world to its<br />

own origin. Th e world attunes itself to its origin in a melancholic song<br />

that has not become a language yet, a mute lament before language<br />

that laments its own mortality. In philosophical contemplation and<br />

in poetic saying that preserves the excess <strong>of</strong> the immemorial promise<br />

in language, this melancholy is transformed at once into a divine,<br />

paradisiacal joyousness. It refl ects, in a weak illumination, the joy <strong>of</strong><br />

the animals when Adam fi rst gave their names to them. Th e world<br />

and existence’s relation to its time is not succession <strong>of</strong> past and<br />

presence and future <strong>of</strong> the same banal, monotony <strong>of</strong> the vacant Now,<br />

but the world’s temporality is ecstatically attuned to melancholy<br />

and hope as moods <strong>of</strong> the world’s existence, or existence’s mood <strong>of</strong><br />

existing in the world in so far as the world opens itself ecstatically and<br />

simultaneously to the abyss <strong>of</strong> its immemorial past and to the<br />

astonishing arriving <strong>of</strong> its not yet. Mortality opens the language <strong>of</strong><br />

the world to a language before language, and to a language after<br />

language, to a language <strong>of</strong> an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> language that bears<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> its fulfi lment.<br />

Mortality<br />

A thinking that confronts this mortality, its own mortality,<br />

ecstatically—for thinking itself is fi nite, disruptive, interruptive <strong>of</strong><br />

itself, a fi nite thinking—must go beyond the closure <strong>of</strong> dialecticalspeculative<br />

philosophy. If thinking has to open itself to its outside,<br />

which is other than the thinkable, to open itself to the advent <strong>of</strong><br />

coming into existence, then the transcendence <strong>of</strong> this advent has to<br />

be thought otherwise than the death’s immanent negative product,<br />

but in relation to a radical fi nitude as a gift and a promise. Th is gift<br />

is not a product and, therefore, it does not belong to the economy <strong>of</strong><br />

the universal history. Th is gift is rather the gift <strong>of</strong> the immemorial.<br />

At the heart <strong>of</strong> existence, at the depth <strong>of</strong> the world, thousand<br />

melancholic voices cry out, the cries <strong>of</strong> an abyssal mortality which<br />

cannot be appeased in a world that is constituted by the negative work<br />

<strong>of</strong> death. It can only be addressed by keeping open the inaugurating


Radical Finitude • 33<br />

promise, which has always already opened the world, by transforming<br />

the past <strong>of</strong> the inauguration unto the future yet to come, by keeping<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> the future alive, by constantly renewing that opening in<br />

an ever new present. Th erefore, the immemorial promise needs to be<br />

renewed at ever new present as the endless, interminable presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this promise, at each moment, here and now, not so that one<br />

day there will some one come or something will come to pass, but<br />

that at each here and now we affi rm there a yet to come. Th is radical<br />

fi nitude, this groundless ‘presencing <strong>of</strong> the presence’ that is beyond any<br />

concept and any cognition, whose imminence ecstatically exceeds<br />

any predication, which by tearing asunder the historical depth <strong>of</strong><br />

our existence, it is this radical fi nitude that welcomes in its lightning<br />

fl ash that which transforms our historical existence into its messianic,<br />

redemptive fulfi lment.<br />

Th is fi nitude is that which is beyond the capacity to be or not to<br />

be <strong>of</strong> man. In each <strong>of</strong> the mortal existence, in each <strong>of</strong> a mortal being’s<br />

work, there lies, in advance, a non-work that exposes the totality <strong>of</strong> our<br />

existence, as a whole, to its outside, to its transcendence. Because the fate<br />

<strong>of</strong> the works transcends these works—like Oedipus’ destiny whose<br />

fate befalls on him despite the result <strong>of</strong> his works for him is supposed<br />

to evade this fate—so the historical destiny <strong>of</strong> the mortals transcends<br />

the accumulated labours <strong>of</strong> the world and the mortals. What comes<br />

to the world opens in an immemorial transcendence that can never<br />

be enclosed in the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence, for it can never be the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> immanence <strong>of</strong> negativity. It is what Schelling<br />

calls the ‘un-pre-thinkable’, the possible, which is the potency <strong>of</strong><br />

the world as the world’s incalculable becoming <strong>of</strong> itself. One can,<br />

therefore, say: the world is possible or existence is possible ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as the world is fi nite and mortal; or, the world is possible because<br />

the possible belongs to mortality. It is the immemorial promise that<br />

incessantly calls us to transform our historical existence by placing<br />

us unto that opening, that inauguration where the future comes to<br />

us incalculably. Th ere lies the necessity <strong>of</strong> work, to create something<br />

new out <strong>of</strong> an essential creative freedom, granted to us as gift by<br />

mortality itself. Because the works <strong>of</strong> the mortals arise out <strong>of</strong> this<br />

essential freedom (this freedom, because this is freedom, can never<br />

be grounded in a concept <strong>of</strong> thought), there always remains that<br />

incalculable, un-pre-thinkable character in each work <strong>of</strong> creative act.


34 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

In other words, there always remains the possibility <strong>of</strong> the otherwise.<br />

To affi rm this coming, the possible is the same thing as affi rming<br />

the un-pre-thinkable and the un-predicative. Th e future, in its<br />

incalculability and in its un-predicative character, is not a negation <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude but rather that the essence <strong>of</strong> human freedom ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it has<br />

its ground in an immemorial past. Finitude is not the annulment <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom, or impossibility <strong>of</strong> freedom, but an unconditional ground<br />

that grants the mortals in advance the creative task <strong>of</strong> transformation<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence.<br />

It is in relation to this non-work <strong>of</strong> mortality alone there lies the<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> a creative work <strong>of</strong> transformation in a historical world,<br />

for there to be creative work for the historical mortals, mortality<br />

must grant beforehand this revelation <strong>of</strong> the not yet. Th is revelation<br />

is not granted to us in predicative thoughts in the form <strong>of</strong> a logical<br />

judgement, even if it is speculative judgement that Hegel speaks <strong>of</strong>,<br />

but in the lightning fl ash that seizes the mortals and make claims upon<br />

his existence as the innermost concern <strong>of</strong> his existence, by exposing<br />

him to the depth <strong>of</strong> his existence his own abyss, i.e., his immemorial<br />

forgetting where being risks its being. It is here that begins the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> a whole life-time, in fear and trembling, and in the astonishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin: that is, to transform one’s own existence, to transfi gure<br />

one’s own existence so that there be ethics, there be politics, and there<br />

be the works <strong>of</strong> the world, even if they are the works <strong>of</strong> negativity.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> politics derives its sense from its opening to this nonwork<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> works, and to transform, out <strong>of</strong><br />

this essential abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom, granted by mortality, this historical<br />

existence as creative work <strong>of</strong> transformation. Here the sense <strong>of</strong> ‘work’<br />

itself is transformed: not as a negative labour <strong>of</strong> death, a work in<br />

relation to death’s negativity and its predication; but it is a positive,<br />

creative task <strong>of</strong> opening to mortality, which is non-predication par<br />

excellence, out <strong>of</strong> an essential freedom.<br />

Th is brings to us the complex relation <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> event with<br />

the notion <strong>of</strong> Abyss. If the creative task <strong>of</strong> the mortal, fi nite, historical<br />

being is to welcome the coming, the event <strong>of</strong> the ‘un-pre-thinkable’,<br />

which is promised and gifted in the immemorial past, then event has<br />

to be thought together with abyss <strong>of</strong> being which is for that matter is<br />

not a pure void, or a pure Nothing but to be thought as the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> pure potentiality.


Introducing this Work<br />

Radical Finitude • 35<br />

Th is present volume is divided into fi ve parts. Th e fi rst part,<br />

called Confi guration, presents within a constellation an assemblage<br />

<strong>of</strong> problems, questions, and stakes and thereby describing this<br />

presentation itself as confi guration. In this manner the traditional<br />

academic notions such as methodology, the distinction between form<br />

and content, theory and application (notions that are grounded in<br />

metaphysics) are given over to the praxis <strong>of</strong> a presentation where the<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> ‘praxis’ itself is re-thought.<br />

Th e second part attempts to think the relation <strong>of</strong> language with<br />

mortality and the possibility <strong>of</strong> the paradisiacal, redemptive, messianic<br />

language <strong>of</strong> naming beyond the language <strong>of</strong> predicative, categorical<br />

at cognitive disposal. Th e third part attempts to think the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

event in its three fold—the event <strong>of</strong> freedom, the event <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

and the event <strong>of</strong> time—to open up these three metaphysically<br />

burdened notions to its affi rmation <strong>of</strong> an unconditional arrival,<br />

which for that matter can never be thought within the predicative,<br />

categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> the ‘presently given entities’ (Heidegger 1962).<br />

Th ey are thereby released and freed, which is the <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

itself, from the closure <strong>of</strong> various immanence <strong>of</strong> self-consumption<br />

and self-appropriation. Reading the works <strong>of</strong> Schelling, Heidegger<br />

and Rosenzweig, with Bloch and Kierkegaard behind, the event is<br />

understood here as the messianic leap or spring to an origin not yet,<br />

diff erential, multiple, singular that does not allow itself to be thought<br />

within the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity or with the help <strong>of</strong> the apophantic<br />

judgement. Instead, the event is seen as ‘the monstrous copulation’<br />

Hölderlin (1988, p. 96-100) <strong>of</strong> end and inauguration, completion<br />

and inception, accomplishment and beginning simultaneously. Th e<br />

event brings together the end as well as beginning, completion and<br />

inception so that the event is each time fi nite and mortal, inaugurating<br />

something wholly otherwise precisely at the limit, at the end, at the<br />

accomplishment <strong>of</strong> the presently given mode <strong>of</strong> a world. ‘Where<br />

there is an end, there lies another beginning’, so a great poet said<br />

once. Th e question <strong>of</strong> the event is inseparable from the logic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world.<br />

Th e fourth part takes up the question <strong>of</strong> messianicity. Taking<br />

Franz Rosenzweig’s Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption as its main concern, it


36 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

attempts to think an ethics <strong>of</strong> exemplarity in Rosenzweig’s messianic<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> love’s commandment as irreducible facticity <strong>of</strong> revelation<br />

that renews the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> redemption, and opens the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> promise to its fulfi lment in a messianic coming which is<br />

always coming, an eternity which may come today. Th is demands<br />

deconstruction <strong>of</strong> the dominant historical determination <strong>of</strong><br />

temporality as merely successive, and accumulative, to open up to<br />

a wholly otherwise notion <strong>of</strong> temporality and eternity where the<br />

unforeseeable arrival <strong>of</strong> eternity may disrupt the immanent closure<br />

<strong>of</strong> historical reason, opening and wounding the veil <strong>of</strong> immanence to<br />

the pure event <strong>of</strong> a coming from the extremity <strong>of</strong> time. Th e fi fth part<br />

is devoted to the question <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, where philosophical<br />

thinking is seen to be an existential task that is concerned with<br />

the questions concerning the value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence rather<br />

than cognition or clarifi cation <strong>of</strong> the already given world. it not so<br />

much knowledge but existence is seen to be the highest question<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking whose fundamental task consists <strong>of</strong> its<br />

releasement <strong>of</strong> the unconditional character <strong>of</strong> its transcendence from<br />

the immanence <strong>of</strong> various self-consuming predicates. To exist is to<br />

remain open; to seek to enclose this essential openness <strong>of</strong> existence to<br />

the immanence <strong>of</strong> various self-consuming predicates results in radical<br />

evil. Th e question <strong>of</strong> existence has essentially an ethical implication<br />

whose meaning and sense arises from the inextricable character <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude <strong>of</strong> existence that defi nes existence in its existentiality. As<br />

such, an ethics <strong>of</strong> existence is essentially a fi nite ethics, or an ethics <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude from which the task <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking is inseparable.


Part I<br />

Configuration


§ Th e Open<br />

Th inking means venturing beyond.<br />

Ernst Bloch (1995, p. 5)<br />

Th is mortal creature called ‘man’, in so far as s/he is mortal, is an<br />

open existence, which means that as an existing being, s/he already<br />

always belongs to his own coming into existence. Here begins our<br />

voyage <strong>of</strong> thinking, for thinking too is a kind <strong>of</strong> voyage, which must<br />

venture forth ceaselessly, to what is beyond and Not Yet. Th inking<br />

must affi rm this ‘Not yet’, this messianic, redemptive fulfi llment, if<br />

it has to affi rm this open-ness <strong>of</strong> existence itself.<br />

In the open darkness and light, remembrance and oblivion, coming<br />

into existence and disappearing in death, all play their originary cobelonging,<br />

or co-fi guration. Existence belongs to this opening and<br />

is exposed to its coming to presence. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this originary<br />

opening, this originary historical which is revealed to this mortal<br />

being called ‘man’, on the basis <strong>of</strong> this revelation, that man founds<br />

something like politics and history. Th ere comes into existence out <strong>of</strong><br />

this freedom, out <strong>of</strong> this ‘play space’ 1 , this fi eld called ‘polis’ 2 , where<br />

there takes place war and festival, where historical revolutions tear<br />

apart history, bring ruptures and discontinuities in the mode <strong>of</strong> his<br />

existence, where man seeks the foundation <strong>of</strong> his own foundation<br />

(which is his metaphysical task), where occur the dialectics <strong>of</strong><br />

negativity between man and man, where man puts at stake his own<br />

death, his own dissolution, and by the power <strong>of</strong> his own dissolution<br />

stands in relation to the total world that he seeks to dominate. Th is<br />

means that man’s attempts to metaphysically found his own political


40 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and historical existence must presuppose a far more originary nonfoundation,<br />

the diff erentiating revealing <strong>of</strong> the open, the ungrounded<br />

spacing play, or playing space <strong>of</strong> natality and mortality.<br />

Would a politics and metaphysics, a history and polis be possible<br />

if there would not already hold sway the open? Would such a polis<br />

and man’s metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> his own ground be possible if<br />

there were not already given the promise <strong>of</strong> the coming, the opening<br />

which thereby is intimated, not in the predicative logic <strong>of</strong> his<br />

metaphysics and his history, but in the pre-predicative lightning fl ash<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, in a poetic saying? Th is pre-predicative lightning, this<br />

‘un-pre-thinkable’ must have already placed man in relation to his<br />

outside, to the outside <strong>of</strong> his foundation, exposing him to his fi nitude<br />

and abyssal mortality, to the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> coming into<br />

existence that precedes the negativity <strong>of</strong> death that man undertakes<br />

on his own behalf. How does one name this historical before history,<br />

this emergence <strong>of</strong> history, or, the birth <strong>of</strong> history itself, the open<br />

which is otherwise than and before the ‘meta’ <strong>of</strong> his ‘metaphysics’?<br />

What would the naming <strong>of</strong> this time be if this time must already<br />

occur before time (before man come to present himself to himself)<br />

and, therefore, before the name, this time that must already occur<br />

as simultaneity <strong>of</strong> all times so that the whole eternity <strong>of</strong> time reveals<br />

to man beforehand, on the basis <strong>of</strong> which man gives himself his<br />

own time, the time <strong>of</strong> his history and the time <strong>of</strong> his politics? As<br />

if already always there must be granted to the mortal a time before<br />

his time, before the time <strong>of</strong> his own—not ‘this’ or ‘that’ time, nor<br />

another time, but time temporalizing itself—in so far as it is on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> time temporalizing itself, on the basis <strong>of</strong> this eternity there<br />

manifests for man his historicity and his politics, his metaphysics<br />

and his ethics? As if there occurs before all naming a name which is<br />

itself without the name, and is the event <strong>of</strong> naming itself, the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> language itself? Which naming language <strong>of</strong> the mortal would be<br />

able to name this name outside the name, let alone exhausting it in<br />

the name? As if there occurs a historical opening before history, a<br />

promise beyond metaphysics and beyond politics, a confi guration<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming into existing and mortality that is outside the labour <strong>of</strong><br />

death which man undertakes on his own behalf, a revelation to him<br />

<strong>of</strong> his outside which is outside his domination and mastery, outside<br />

his power and labour, a name which is outside the naming language


Th e Open • 41<br />

<strong>of</strong> mortals, yet which while fi rst depriving man his foundation and<br />

power, gives him the task to name the nameless, bestowing upon him<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> language on the basis <strong>of</strong> which he knows his world, and<br />

grasps the entities that has become and is given in the world.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> the mortal naming language <strong>of</strong> this linguistic being<br />

called ‘man’ would, then, be the task <strong>of</strong> the impossible. If that is so,<br />

then the essence <strong>of</strong> this mortal language is not primarily a categoricalpredicative<br />

grasp <strong>of</strong> what has presently become <strong>of</strong> the historical world<br />

and entities therein constituting the historical totality, nor would<br />

it be to exhaust the name without name in the signifi cation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. We neither know the open on the basis <strong>of</strong> history (what we<br />

generally know as history), nor we know the world’s coming into<br />

existence on the basis <strong>of</strong> predication. We would then have to say<br />

rather that language is the event <strong>of</strong> the world, this mortal existential<br />

world for this existent ‘man’, or, even better, the event <strong>of</strong> language—<br />

before any predicative-categorical cognition and before the historical<br />

foundation <strong>of</strong> the historical world—intimates that coming or birth<br />

(which is to be understood before any biological determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> it) by throwing mortals to his outside, by exposing him to his<br />

outside, which is outside his presence and power, outside politics<br />

and even outside history. Th e event <strong>of</strong> language already always inserts<br />

this mortal being called ‘man’, in an immemorial past, into this c<strong>of</strong>i<br />

guration <strong>of</strong> mortality and natality, <strong>of</strong> past and future and presence<br />

in a simultaneity that is called ‘eternity’. Th is eternity, which is not<br />

the mere void <strong>of</strong> time, precedes and follows the historical totalities,<br />

outside the speculative historical time, and remains as an eternal<br />

remnant, irreducibly keeping us open to the promise <strong>of</strong> coming time<br />

beyond violence and beyond the negativity <strong>of</strong> historical reason. 3<br />

Th e open is the spacing and timing as play which grants beforehand<br />

the name <strong>of</strong> this promise or promise <strong>of</strong> the name. In this way, this<br />

mortal being called ‘man’ is open to the coming where the eternity<br />

<strong>of</strong> his future, this remnant <strong>of</strong> time announces itself. Th erefore this<br />

mortal called ‘man’ has a relation to that which is more than, outside<br />

<strong>of</strong>, otherwise than what he has made himself out <strong>of</strong> his own capacity<br />

and possibility, for he is not only what he has founded on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

his own ground; a basis otherwise his basis must granted to him, or, as<br />

Schelling (1936) says, must be ‘loaned’ to him as pure, incalculable,<br />

non-conditional, non-economic gift. Finding himself in the midst


42 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> the created existence where the entirety <strong>of</strong> existence and entirety<br />

<strong>of</strong> time is revealed to him, granted to him in the lightning fl ash, he<br />

confi gures, weaves into time the possibility <strong>of</strong> his existence and waits<br />

for redemption. It is the demand <strong>of</strong> the non-conditional that there<br />

must be condition for him: hence he has his politics, his history, and<br />

his dialectics.<br />

Th inking too takes place, or presupposes this originary opening,<br />

not the opening <strong>of</strong> this or that, not the opening <strong>of</strong> something as this<br />

thing, or someone as this one, but more originary opening where<br />

something or someone arrives. Plato calls this originary experience that<br />

alone enables experience itself, which is the possibility <strong>of</strong> experience<br />

itself as such, where the beginning begins in the open—as ‘Wonder’,<br />

or ‘Astonishment’ at the origin. Th ere lies the birth <strong>of</strong> thinking and,<br />

henceforth, is called philosophy. If that is so, philosophy begins a nonconditional<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> thinking itself. Th at means philosophy must<br />

already presuppose the holding sway <strong>of</strong> the open, thinking that must<br />

already be promised to man in the open, out <strong>of</strong> his fi nitude, that<br />

means, out <strong>of</strong> his exposure to the open. For philosophical thinking<br />

fi nitude or mortality is not one question among others, because<br />

questioning itself begins as a non-conditional experience <strong>of</strong> fi nitude<br />

or mortality. Th erefore, all the questions that man raises are fi nite<br />

questions. Man philosophizes not because he is capable <strong>of</strong> the faculty<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking, but because he is fi rst <strong>of</strong> all mortal and fi nite that strikes<br />

him, surprises him, astonishes him. Th is event <strong>of</strong> thinking attunes<br />

the mortals to a fundamental mood, or fundamental attunement <strong>of</strong><br />

astonishment, astonishment at the event <strong>of</strong> thinking.<br />

Th e coming <strong>of</strong> thinking, the event <strong>of</strong> thinking astonishes the<br />

mortals—since (as Heidegger says) 4 we do not go to thinking, but<br />

thinking comes to us—and promises him the gift <strong>of</strong> time, the time<br />

to come, the future <strong>of</strong> thinking. It is this promise <strong>of</strong> future, granted<br />

to us by the event <strong>of</strong> thinking and that attunes us to the fundamental<br />

mood <strong>of</strong> astonishment, abandons us, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, to abandonment,<br />

to an originary non-condition—which Plato calls ‘death’. It is this<br />

experience, or, non-experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment, or mortality’s gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, the gift that astonishes us: it is this non-condition that is<br />

the birth <strong>of</strong> thinking called philosophy. Th is non-conditional event <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking that surprises us, astonishes us and bestows upon us the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking, is more originary than the system <strong>of</strong> that philosophical


Th e Open • 43<br />

logic that claims to begin with the immediate that immediately<br />

passes into the mediation. It is because the event <strong>of</strong> thinking, and its<br />

fundamental mood <strong>of</strong> astonishment exceeds any categorical grasp <strong>of</strong><br />

a philosophical logic that is based upon predicative proposition, for<br />

the movement <strong>of</strong> a predicative proposition can only be a negative,<br />

and hence, an immanent movement ; in itself it is no movement at<br />

all. But the movement <strong>of</strong> mortality is a movement transcendent and,<br />

therefore, it is movement at all. In this sense, Schelling, preceding<br />

and infl uencing Kierkegaard denies movement in Hegelian<br />

speculative logic, though the eff ort <strong>of</strong> the speculative logic is to<br />

include movement into it. In so far as Hegel understood movement<br />

only as a negative, it can only be an immanent movement, hence<br />

based upon the predicative proposition. Th e event that begins the<br />

movement is a leap outside, for all coming into presence is transcendence,<br />

and hence is outside <strong>of</strong> all predication and judgement that constitute the<br />

speculative historical totality. Th erefore, it is not surprising that Hegel’s<br />

Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit begins its movement, or rather Hegel likens<br />

(which is not mere analogy) this phenomenological movement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dialectical-historical to the movement <strong>of</strong> a speculative proposition,<br />

which is an immanent movement. Nothing surprises, astonishes us<br />

in Hegelian speculative-historical system, for what is missing there is<br />

the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the event, the leap <strong>of</strong> the outside, and the thinking <strong>of</strong> the<br />

inception which is outside <strong>of</strong> a logical generation <strong>of</strong> a monotonous,<br />

dull immediate immediately passing into the mediation.<br />

Th is is the reason that Franz Rosenzweig, following Schelling,<br />

begins his Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption with the complaint that the<br />

philosophical system that claims to be the cognition <strong>of</strong> the all, is<br />

deaf to the cries <strong>of</strong> mortality, for in that speculative philosophical<br />

discourse <strong>of</strong> totality, nothing and nobody dies. Th e speculative<br />

system for which singulars are reduced to the particular moments <strong>of</strong><br />

the One, there is no place for the singulars, the singulars for whom<br />

their deaths are <strong>of</strong> utmost existential interest that refuses to serve<br />

the interest <strong>of</strong> the anonymous Universality. What is missing in the<br />

Hegelian speculative-dialectical determination <strong>of</strong> history is none else<br />

but death, death that is outside and otherwise than the negative,<br />

death which cannot persist while carrying its predicates in the way<br />

that Hegel’s subject carries its own dissolution as its predicate. If<br />

speculative proposition is like the Subject that persists as the same


44 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

even in its own dissolution and accidents, then death that does not<br />

persist in its apparition is a proposition without predicate. Th is<br />

death refuses to work, it refuses to produce its own predicates, if the<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> work in Hegelian metaphysics is none but production <strong>of</strong><br />

predicates. It is because <strong>of</strong> this, though it is the eff ort <strong>of</strong> a speculative<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> history to think death or mortality, it has made death only<br />

a result or the process <strong>of</strong> negativity, a death no longer event but<br />

work that serves the interests <strong>of</strong> the Universal. Such a speculative<br />

discourse <strong>of</strong> universality, founded upon the predicative proposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> a speculative judgement is devoid <strong>of</strong> the event, for event does not<br />

have the character <strong>of</strong> persistence <strong>of</strong> negativity. By taking away the<br />

‘poisonous sting’ <strong>of</strong> death (Rosenzweig 2005, p. 9), such a speculative<br />

totalization allows itself to forget the immemorial open and the<br />

promise, the non-conditional gift loaned therein. Th e remembrance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the immemorial inception, <strong>of</strong> the open before totality, <strong>of</strong> the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality before the negative work <strong>of</strong> death and the promise given in<br />

a beginning before any beginning, and therefore given in a historical<br />

coming into existence before history: this remembrance is renewed at<br />

moments when history interrupts itself, pauses itself, or when history<br />

itself claims to have accomplished its own end and to have exhausted<br />

its innermost resources and possibilities.<br />

Th e questions <strong>of</strong> promise and gift, <strong>of</strong> inception and future arise only<br />

in relation to the questions concerning exit from such a metaphysics<br />

that marks the dominant thinking <strong>of</strong> the Greco-Roman civilization.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> the pause <strong>of</strong> history is, as it is clear, is the question <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality and the open, when each time history itself has to leap over<br />

the abyss that is yawning wide open. Th is history is not the history<br />

what Hegel the metaphysician dreamt <strong>of</strong>; it is not the history where<br />

abysses are like transitional moments that simultaneously bridge<br />

themselves. Th e pauses or interruptions <strong>of</strong> history are not diff erential<br />

epochal moments belonging to the homogenous, universal unity<br />

<strong>of</strong> a speculative proposition that tarries with its own dissolutions,<br />

thereby making these dissolutions as moments <strong>of</strong> the bridge. Th ey<br />

are, rather, in their radical fi nitude, singular epochal ruptures that<br />

refuse to be gathered into a logical principle <strong>of</strong> unity. Th eir logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> becoming is not the dialectical-speculative logic <strong>of</strong> speculative<br />

proposition. Th eir caesural logic is more like what Hölderlin calls<br />

as ‘becoming in perishing’ (Hölderlin 1988, pp. 96-100). Th ey are


Th e Open • 45<br />

epochal ruptures whose becoming is simultaneous with their own<br />

dissolution so that no self-same subject <strong>of</strong> universal history carries<br />

its accidents and predicates to the dusk <strong>of</strong> its process. Th ese epochal<br />

ruptures, which are caesural, do not follow the transitional logic <strong>of</strong><br />

generation and therefore unlike the movement <strong>of</strong> Hegelian concepts;<br />

they do not belong to the undying self-same fl ow <strong>of</strong> eternity. Th ey<br />

rather form what both Schelling and Hölderlin already before Hegel<br />

came to constitute the system call Zusammenhang (Schelling 2000):<br />

the caesural confi guration, a cohesion, a holding together <strong>of</strong> what do<br />

not make transition into the other, each rhythm in relative autonomy<br />

from the other, not because each rhythm in itself has its ontological<br />

ground, but each rhythm brings simultaneously its counter thrust,<br />

a counter pressure, its dissolution, in a kind <strong>of</strong> lightning fl ash that<br />

arrive simultaneously to bring its disappearance. Such a mortality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the epochal ruptures is not the negativity <strong>of</strong> death which the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> the speculative proposition brings into. Th e mortality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash does not maintain its own dissolution within it<br />

and does not make itself into the work <strong>of</strong> producing universal history.<br />

Much before Hegel came to constitute his system, Hölderlin in<br />

1800 wrote an essay called Becoming in Dissolution. Not the world,<br />

‘this’ or ‘that’ world, but ‘the world <strong>of</strong> all words’ presents itself in a<br />

time which itself, each time, a beginning <strong>of</strong> time, or, ‘in the decline,<br />

the instant or more genetically, in the becoming <strong>of</strong> the instant and in<br />

the beginning <strong>of</strong> time and world’. ‘Th is decline... is felt... at precisely<br />

that moment and to precisely that extent that existence dissolves,<br />

the newly entering, the youthful, the potential is also felt’. Each<br />

such moment is this ‘heavenly fi re’, is this infi nite interweaving <strong>of</strong><br />

becoming and dissolution when ‘everything infi nitely permeates’<br />

each other ‘the pain and joys, discord and peace, movement and<br />

rest, form and formless’ (Hölderlin 1988, pp. 96-100). Here,<br />

unlike the Hegelian notion <strong>of</strong> infi nity that has fi nitude within it,<br />

the infi nite and fi nite forms the ‘monstrous coupling’ which is not<br />

‘system’, but Zusammenhang—<strong>of</strong> mortality and natality, becoming<br />

and dissolution, presentation and the unpresentable, infi nite and<br />

fi nitude, excess and containment, mourning and joy. Th e open is<br />

the ‘play space’ where there occurs ‘this monstrous coupling’ which<br />

is the event <strong>of</strong> history itself as disjunctive, caesural, non-conditional<br />

opening, and not events that belong to history as fi nite, attenuated


46 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

fi gures <strong>of</strong> discontinuities. Commenting on Hölderlin, Francoise<br />

Dastur writes,<br />

What Hölderlin wants to think is not the development <strong>of</strong> a thing<br />

from its initial stage to its fi nal stage, even via the intermediary <strong>of</strong> a<br />

‘qualitative leap’ which would introduce here a relative discontinuity,<br />

but rather the entire refl ux <strong>of</strong> disappearance into appearance and <strong>of</strong><br />

death into life. What he wants to understand is not the succession<br />

<strong>of</strong> epochs and the interval that separates the break but the epochal<br />

break itself and the radical discontinuity <strong>of</strong> history. (Dastur 2000,<br />

pp. 62-63)<br />

What is at stake is not events that are successive, attenuated, and<br />

relative fi nite realization <strong>of</strong> the One, the Universal, like the succession<br />

<strong>of</strong> diff erential nows that are the diff erential and immanent variations<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Now. 5 Th e Universal, One Now will be then determined as<br />

contraction <strong>of</strong> the plurality <strong>of</strong> nows, and is continuous in all through<br />

its relative variations as nows. 6 But the epochal ruptures and abysses<br />

<strong>of</strong> history are not mere relative realization <strong>of</strong> the Universal history.<br />

Th ey are not merely immanent product <strong>of</strong> this history nor a result<br />

<strong>of</strong> that speculative dialectical process. Th e caesura which Hölderlin<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> is the mortality which is outside the immanent negativity<br />

<strong>of</strong> history. It is the non-conditional condition <strong>of</strong> history, given as gift<br />

at the inception <strong>of</strong> that history where inception and fi nitude, natality<br />

and mortality, becoming and dissolution are united in a ‘monstrous<br />

coupling’. Mortality, which is the non-negative condition, is not a<br />

consequence <strong>of</strong> that history, but premise whose judgement cannot be<br />

delivered in the name <strong>of</strong> what is only consequent and the derivative.<br />

In so far as judgement derives its judgement character only from<br />

predication, it is outside any predicative logic. If the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event is to be thought anew here which not mere relative realization<br />

<strong>of</strong> universal history is, then the event has to be thought outside the<br />

closure <strong>of</strong> the speculative historical logic <strong>of</strong> predication. Th e event<br />

is to be thought, then, in relation the immemorial gift <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

itself, in relation to that originary disjunction and caesura, belonging<br />

neither to the economy <strong>of</strong> work, nor to the work <strong>of</strong> negativity. To<br />

think <strong>of</strong> the event is to think not what has become as a result <strong>of</strong><br />

the work <strong>of</strong> negativity, but the not yet inception <strong>of</strong> a fi nite history<br />

where mortality and natality, becoming and dissolution occur


Th e Open • 47<br />

simultaneously. It is here the question <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong> coming for<br />

the mortal being called ‘man’ is to be posed.<br />

If man is opened towards the coming, if his existence is not to<br />

be consummated by the mere given-ness <strong>of</strong> what has become, if he<br />

does not end his voyage as an already fi nished and accomplished<br />

existence—for he exists in the promise <strong>of</strong> future—it is so far as<br />

his existence already belongs to the originary holding sway <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opening, which is each time, (that means singularly, without belonging<br />

to universal history) fi nite and caesural.<br />

How to think <strong>of</strong> the opening more originary than any genesis and<br />

generation (because it must already be granted to man, as it were a<br />

gift), an in-ception or beginning before any beginning that comes to<br />

pass by, a coming before anything that comes and vanishes? Does this<br />

coming and inception, this opening before genesis and generation,<br />

appear like any other phenomenon in the world that has become,<br />

in so far as this unapparent enables the apparition as such, on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> which mortals constitute their politics and history, their<br />

world and their meanings? In each product <strong>of</strong> labour that constitutes<br />

the historical artifi ce and manifests for mortals his fi eld <strong>of</strong> polis,<br />

polis where he enjoys his feasts and suff ers his death, in each such<br />

historical product and in such historical manifestation <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

the unapparent phenomenon which we call ‘mortality’ haunts and<br />

an unspeakable mourning watches over. If the world history and its<br />

politics is the product <strong>of</strong> the negative labour <strong>of</strong> man who puts at<br />

stake his life and death by making his own death, his own absence,<br />

his own disappearing itself appear as history and manifest as politics,<br />

would this manifestation be possible without the more originary<br />

polemos, a more originary revelation, the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality, but that is without violence and before any negativity, the<br />

polemos between opening and the exigency <strong>of</strong> closure that fi rst <strong>of</strong><br />

all reveals the mortals the unapparent <strong>of</strong> all appearing, the event as<br />

such? In what language and naming <strong>of</strong> the mortals— since for the<br />

mortals the world opens itself to them only on the basis <strong>of</strong> language<br />

and the name— this opening be named, if this inception makes<br />

manifest fi rst <strong>of</strong> all something like ‘politics’ and ‘history’, which for<br />

that matter precedes anything like ‘politics’ and ‘history’? In what<br />

language <strong>of</strong> naming man must address what is outside ‘history’<br />

and outside ‘politics’ if that originary promise <strong>of</strong> the outside, the


48 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

originary opening in non-violence must fi rst <strong>of</strong> all call mortals to<br />

the task <strong>of</strong> naming? Or, rather, how not to name if naming is not to<br />

be exhausted only in naming the nameable? If the naming language<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortals is not exhausted in naming only the nameable, if the<br />

naming language <strong>of</strong> the mortals is promised in the opening outside<br />

the activity and the negative labour <strong>of</strong> history and politics, then this<br />

passivity outside being passive and being active, this inception <strong>of</strong> time<br />

must precede the temporality that is then predicated and predicted in<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> logic. Hence, there arrives and comes a temporality<br />

<strong>of</strong> language without death, a remnant time <strong>of</strong> language (or a remnant<br />

language <strong>of</strong> time) that remains after each and every predication, a<br />

faintly fainting away, barely audible, <strong>of</strong> a mournfulness, which is<br />

more originary than the predicative-apophantic language <strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

‘Th e irreducible remainder’ <strong>of</strong> language is not a consequence to the<br />

predicative-apophantic proposition, and therefore is not a result <strong>of</strong> a<br />

series <strong>of</strong> subtractions <strong>of</strong> predications. In other words, ‘the irreducible<br />

remainder’ is not negative remainder, but a positive given as gift, since<br />

a series <strong>of</strong> subtraction to begin an affi rmative positive must already<br />

always be there, which no predication can apophantically recuperate.<br />

In the same way, there occurs an irreducible caesura <strong>of</strong> history which<br />

is not a consequence <strong>of</strong> already realized universal history.<br />

It is the language <strong>of</strong> naming that is always the outside the language <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement and the outside the judgement <strong>of</strong> history. It is rather what calls<br />

history to fulfi ll its promise, which happens irreducibly there at the<br />

inception <strong>of</strong> history, at the inception <strong>of</strong> anything like politics. Th e<br />

remembrance <strong>of</strong> this inception, its fi nitude, its incessant renewal in<br />

any presencing <strong>of</strong> presence, and hence fulfi llment <strong>of</strong> this immemorial<br />

promise means that the historical task <strong>of</strong> politics and the political task<br />

<strong>of</strong> history is not merely the dialectical-speculative memory <strong>of</strong> what<br />

has become <strong>of</strong> the world, but rather to remember the immemorial,<br />

to fulfi ll in the future and in the not yet what is promised in the past.<br />

To remember the immemorial: this distinction between<br />

remembrance and memory is co-relative to the distinction between<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> naming and the language <strong>of</strong> judgement, between<br />

the originary epochal caesura <strong>of</strong> history and relative epochal<br />

ruptures, in so far as language <strong>of</strong> the naming remembers, at the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> cognition and judgement, at the limit <strong>of</strong> memory and its


Th e Open • 49<br />

genesis what is immemorial promise, not yet unimpaired by the<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> cognition.<br />

Th is logic <strong>of</strong> origin and <strong>of</strong> inception, which is not the logic <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement (in so far as it precedes, as it were, any predication and<br />

any predication apophantically recuperating the origin) is, in a<br />

certain sense, outside time, if time is grasped and inscribed in the<br />

speculative logic <strong>of</strong> a genesis predicated on the basis <strong>of</strong> an recuperative<br />

apophansis. As if a kind <strong>of</strong> eternity, an immemorial inception, which<br />

then, renders time itself open wound, tearing open to the coming<br />

and arriving, to a future without horizon and without ground, to<br />

the ‘monstrous coupling’ <strong>of</strong> infi nitude and fi nitude. Th e immemorial<br />

inception <strong>of</strong> time is not recovered in the recuperating labour <strong>of</strong> a<br />

speculative-dialectical memory, nor is sublated in a speculative-logical<br />

thought. It is there as yet to come, as future origin, as the possibility to<br />

begin anew through renewal <strong>of</strong> time that is opened in the lightning<br />

fl ash to which man is exposed.<br />

Th is time without time, or, rather the timing <strong>of</strong> time, this inception<br />

<strong>of</strong> time itself, which is to be rigorously distinguished from the<br />

dialectical-speculative logic <strong>of</strong> genesis and generation, this eternity<br />

<strong>of</strong> time itself must be renewed in our historical presence so that our<br />

historical remembrance gives itself the task <strong>of</strong> the more originary<br />

astonishment at the origin, exposing us to the monstrous event <strong>of</strong><br />

history. Remembrance is then nothing but the renewal <strong>of</strong> the inception.<br />

History must remember not historical memory or memory in history,<br />

but what for history, by a necessary logic, is outside memory that must<br />

have already always erased from memory as a necessary precondition. If<br />

historical remembrance begins with astonishment at the origin, and is<br />

not satisfi ed with what has arrived, what time has made <strong>of</strong> a historical<br />

existence—cleared existence, a cleared time which has now sunk into<br />

the banality <strong>of</strong> knowable and graspable—then remembrance must<br />

have a relation to a time outside memory. While memory is memory<br />

<strong>of</strong> a past as that what has happened, remembrance, understood<br />

in a pr<strong>of</strong>ound sense, is simultaneity <strong>of</strong> past, presence and future.<br />

It is this eternity alone makes a historical being happy. It attunes<br />

us to a certain joyous mourning, <strong>of</strong> what Schelling once called<br />

‘divine mourning’. 7 While memory makes us unhappy, remembrance<br />

is the promise <strong>of</strong> happiness, because in the possibility <strong>of</strong> repetition, <strong>of</strong>


50 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

renewal and remembrance, the possibility <strong>of</strong> future is also given. It is<br />

the happiness in the future alone, in the promise <strong>of</strong> a coming time,<br />

and not in what has become a past, and what is presently available<br />

as these things, as this world, as this history, as this politics. Instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> mere tarrying with what has become, and confi ning himself with<br />

‘the gallery <strong>of</strong> images’ (Hegel 1998, p. 492), which Hegel thinks<br />

as the memorial task <strong>of</strong> History—he holds himself ahead towards<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> future, gifted to him by time, endowed him with<br />

the immemorial. <strong>Time</strong>, opening him to the coming and future,<br />

promises redemption. Th is gift <strong>of</strong> time is not a historical gift, nor a<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> history, but rather, man is opened to his history by a time that<br />

redeems history itself, and renders history itself an open existence,<br />

towards its redemption in the coming.<br />

Redemption is then, the originary openness <strong>of</strong> history itself<br />

towards its ex-tatic outside. Man experiences this outside, but without<br />

being able to appropriate it, in astonishment, in wonder that opens<br />

historical memory to the far more originary remembrance <strong>of</strong> wonder,<br />

or wonder itself as remembrance. In astonishment man is opened to<br />

his opening: he sails beyond, ventures outside, and begins himself<br />

anew by renewing himself. In astonishment, man remains as what<br />

he is essentially, that means, does not remain as what he already has<br />

made <strong>of</strong> himself. His is a conditioned, fi nite and mortal existence, but<br />

because <strong>of</strong> this fi nitude, opening to the non-condition, infi nite and<br />

free; he is conditioned but also creative, mortal but also open to a time<br />

yet to come. Both at once, united in him in such a monstrous coupling.<br />

He is a historical being, but also open to redemption, temporal but<br />

also open to a time beyond time, arrived but also opening that is yet<br />

to arrive, an incessant beginning <strong>of</strong> himself but also whose beginning<br />

lies outside his subjective power <strong>of</strong> appropriation, a realized existence<br />

and yet open to the not yet realized, belonging to the possible,<br />

belonging to the arriving, memorial being but also astonished by the<br />

immemorial origin not yet come. Th e mortal being is at the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the one, and opening to the other, belonging to the, as it were,<br />

undecidable line where the line constantly limits each from the other.<br />

It is the undecidable between memory and remembrance, history<br />

and redemption, time and eternity, immanence and transcendence.


§ Judgement and History<br />

What concerns us here, once more, is the relationship between the<br />

logical judgement and history. If a certain dominant metaphysical<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> history dreams the fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> its self-presence<br />

despite the epochal ruptures so that beneath the discontinuities and<br />

ruptures <strong>of</strong> history the unity <strong>of</strong> self-presence fl ows as a discontinuous<br />

self-same, as self-persisting truth in face <strong>of</strong> its own dissolution, it<br />

thereby derives its ground from the authority <strong>of</strong> the logical form <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement, that is, the apophansis <strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition.<br />

Hegelian speculative logic <strong>of</strong> history, which is based upon the<br />

dominant logic <strong>of</strong> judgement as predicative, constitutes itself as the<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> history that subsumes epochal ruptures as its mere<br />

attenuated discontinuities. What is necessary, if epochal ruptures<br />

are to be thought irreducible to the universal, self-persisting logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> movement, a diff erent logic <strong>of</strong> origin, a radical re-thinking <strong>of</strong> the<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> judgement that enables us to think the event as the event <strong>of</strong><br />

history. It is the monstrous site <strong>of</strong> history the advent <strong>of</strong> which alone<br />

brings redemptive fulfi lment outside the closure <strong>of</strong> historical violence.<br />

Th en the judgement <strong>of</strong> history would no longer be authoritative and<br />

fi nal, for it is in the name <strong>of</strong> a redemptive fulfi lment that history will<br />

be judged.<br />

*<br />

Th e deepening <strong>of</strong> the inner life can no longer be guided by the<br />

evidences <strong>of</strong> history. It is given over to the risk and to the moral<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> the I—to horizons more vast than history, in which<br />

history itself is judged.<br />

—Emmanuel Levinas (1969, p. 246)


52 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Of History<br />

For a long time, from the inception <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, philosophers<br />

have cherished the dream <strong>of</strong> an origin that is pure, autochthonous<br />

beginning <strong>of</strong> itself, self-identical and immanent. It is an origin which<br />

releases the movement <strong>of</strong> history, the history <strong>of</strong> a community, race,<br />

nation, etc. In its perseverance, in its purity and autochthony, it is such<br />

as to be able to bear its self-identity in its face <strong>of</strong> its own disjunction<br />

and suff ering, its being in the face <strong>of</strong> its own dissolution, like Phoenix<br />

that arises from its ashes. Beneath the upheavals <strong>of</strong> history, beneath<br />

the epochal ruptures, beneath the unquiet manifestations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

various elemental forces <strong>of</strong> the sky, there is the dream <strong>of</strong> metaphysics:<br />

it is the dream <strong>of</strong> the imperturbable serenity, eternal rest, at the<br />

depth <strong>of</strong> the nourishing earth which maintains itself, as a great<br />

system making philosopher speaks <strong>of</strong>, in the face <strong>of</strong> its death. Th is<br />

metaphysically founded logic <strong>of</strong> origin is also logic <strong>of</strong> earth and soil,<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cunning <strong>of</strong> a history that fulfi ls its Parousia despite or through<br />

the unreason, a history that human beings capable <strong>of</strong> their own<br />

power <strong>of</strong> death found by toil and sweat. What they found—namely,<br />

the rational institutions that constitute the universal, anonymous<br />

totality called ‘history’—appears to have arrived (or, at least, have this<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong>) redemptive fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> the violence that found these<br />

institutions. What then this universal history claims to fulfi ls itself,<br />

by revealing itself to itself, by coming to presence to itself, is this<br />

Parousia <strong>of</strong> reason. History appears to be the continuous, immanent<br />

satisfaction <strong>of</strong> this Parousia <strong>of</strong> reason which, precisely on account<br />

<strong>of</strong> achieving this Parousia, assumes the authority <strong>of</strong> judgement.<br />

History, metaphysically determined, is the gathering <strong>of</strong> the past into<br />

the Parousia <strong>of</strong> immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence so that nothing essential<br />

really is thought to be lost <strong>of</strong> the past promise which is not fulfi lled,<br />

for everything essential that is past is traced back by the apophansis<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement. From this essential metaphysical determination,<br />

history derives its character <strong>of</strong> judgement. It passes judgement on<br />

those multiple singulars that cannot be enclosed within its totality,<br />

on that immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> the immemorial past that cannot<br />

be traced back by the memorial authority <strong>of</strong> apophansis and which<br />

for that matter, cannot be enclosed within the immanence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Parousia <strong>of</strong> reason. Th is judgement <strong>of</strong> the anonymous, universal


Judgement and History • 53<br />

history manifests itself in the thetic violence <strong>of</strong> law that the rational<br />

institutions ensure its execution.<br />

In his Totality and Infi nity (1969), Emmanuel Levinas attempts to<br />

think <strong>of</strong> a more originary ethical responsibility in justice that exceeds<br />

this judgement <strong>of</strong> history. Th ere is always something excess or surplus<br />

in justice which is not the Parousia <strong>of</strong> reason, but what is suppressed<br />

in the visibility <strong>of</strong> the judgement <strong>of</strong> history. It is the invisible itself<br />

whose passage <strong>of</strong> manifestation is not the progressive, accumulative<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> history, which is not mere ‘provisionally invisible’<br />

and therefore not mere privation <strong>of</strong> the visible. It is rather that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

singularity that escapes totality, which cannot be annihilated by the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> judgement, by the force <strong>of</strong> law which the rational institutions<br />

execute. Th e order where the invisibility <strong>of</strong> the singularity manifests<br />

itself is the order <strong>of</strong> infi nity in which ‘history itself is judged’ (Ibid.).<br />

It is an infi nite judgement because it comes from the infi nity (what<br />

Levinas calls ‘diachrony’) <strong>of</strong> the immemorial promise itself which the<br />

apophansis <strong>of</strong> the speculative historical memory cannot trace back<br />

to. It is in the name <strong>of</strong> this immemorial promise that escapes all the<br />

measurement <strong>of</strong> the economy <strong>of</strong> judgement that the tyranny <strong>of</strong> the<br />

universal history is to be judged. Th is infi nite judgement (or, the<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> infi nity) is not evidenced by the documents <strong>of</strong> history,<br />

for it passes judgement in the name <strong>of</strong> an immemorial past that is<br />

already always lost and in the name <strong>of</strong> that which is always yet to<br />

come. Th is infi nite judgement—infi nite in the sense that its exceeds<br />

‘judgement’ itself—this justice in-excess is not, unlike the judgement<br />

<strong>of</strong> history, the maintenance <strong>of</strong> the ‘work <strong>of</strong> death’ (Hegel 1998, p.<br />

270) ensured by the rational institutions on the basis <strong>of</strong> thetic law<br />

(<strong>of</strong> what Benjamin calls ‘law preserving violence’ and ‘law positing<br />

violence’). Justice here belongs to the order <strong>of</strong> the divine 1 where man<br />

in his singularity is affi rmed, not as mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> a universal<br />

reason but as the other who cannot be annihilated. Levinas speaks:<br />

Objective judgement is pronounced by the existence <strong>of</strong> rational<br />

institutions, in which the will is secured against death and against its<br />

own perfi dy. It consists in the submission <strong>of</strong> the subjective will to the<br />

universal laws which reduce the will to its objective signifi cation… it<br />

henceforth exists as though it were dead and signifi ed only in its own<br />

heritage, as though everything that was existence in the fi rst person in<br />

it, subjective existence, were but the after-eff ect <strong>of</strong> its animality.


54 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

And,<br />

Th ere exists a tyranny <strong>of</strong> the universal and <strong>of</strong> the impersonal, an order<br />

that is inhuman though distinct from brutish. Against it man affi rms<br />

himself as an irreducible singularity, exterior to the totality into which<br />

he enters, and aspiring to the religious order where the recognition <strong>of</strong><br />

the individual concerns him in his singularity, an order <strong>of</strong> joy which<br />

is neither cessation nor antithesis <strong>of</strong> pain nor fl ight before it. (Ibid.,<br />

p. 242)<br />

What Levinas is attempting to think is not that these ‘visible forms’<br />

are to be done away with—the visible forms that ‘tend to form’ a<br />

totality—but rather that these visible forms must not forget the<br />

unforgettable, that is, the immemorial promise that opens time,<br />

that means, the pure future <strong>of</strong> presencing that alone can redeem<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> the visible order <strong>of</strong> history. Beyond any eidetic<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> consciousness that makes manifest a reality in<br />

visible forms, justice and truth must evoke a phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

the invisible and <strong>of</strong> promise that opens the judgement <strong>of</strong> history<br />

beyond historical time. Th e thought <strong>of</strong> a redemptive justice evokes a<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> promise and hope that opens itself to the extremities<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, to a before any before and to a last after the last. ‘Th e<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> consciousness’, says Levinas ‘must refer to a reality<br />

beyond the sentence pronounced by history, which is also a cessation<br />

and an end. Hence truth requires as its ultimate condition an infi nite<br />

time, the condition for both goodness and the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

face’ (Ibid., p. 247).<br />

Th e dominant metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> history that presents<br />

itself as the continuous manifestation <strong>of</strong> the Parousia <strong>of</strong> reason that<br />

progressively, accumulatively unfolds itself belongs to the economy<br />

<strong>of</strong> the phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the visible. Hegel’s phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

history is such a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the visible, where reason presents<br />

itself as self-persisting movement <strong>of</strong> self-present Parousia. Hegel’s<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> history is this phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the continuous<br />

upliftment (Aufhebung) <strong>of</strong> the invisible unto the visible in the straight<br />

line <strong>of</strong> conversion by ‘the energy <strong>of</strong> thought’ (Hegel 1998, p. 19)<br />

which is the negativity <strong>of</strong> judgement where what comes never ceases<br />

to recapture what is already gone, in the manner <strong>of</strong> apophansis that<br />

traces itself back to its origin, so that for the Absolute <strong>of</strong> Parousia


Judgement and History • 55<br />

nothing essential is really lost. In this speculative-apophantic<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> history where the end reaches back its own<br />

origin, there remains neither immemorial nor the pure futurity that<br />

cannot be traced back to its origin. Hegel’s speculative-apophantic<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> history—without the advent <strong>of</strong> the pure presencing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the presence and without the promise <strong>of</strong> the immemorial—is<br />

based upon the predicative proposition whose task is to recapture, by<br />

preserving, what has departed as ‘the gallery <strong>of</strong> images’ (Ibid., p. 492).<br />

Th is speculative-apophantic labour <strong>of</strong> the speculative judgement<br />

enables the Hegelian subject <strong>of</strong> History to maintain itself as selfsame<br />

parousia in the dissolution <strong>of</strong> its own accidents and predicates<br />

where the predicates and the subject no longer remain in the fi xity,<br />

or inertness <strong>of</strong> their given positions, but passes onto the other, and<br />

yet while passing into the other, in this restlessness, remains eternally<br />

restful (Ibid., § 60), and never giving way to the ‘bad infi nity’.<br />

Th e subject <strong>of</strong> history is the speculative subject <strong>of</strong> the predicative<br />

proposition that gives itself to its own perishing. It is as perishing, or<br />

throwing itself to the peril <strong>of</strong> being that the speculative subject rescues<br />

its Parousia. Th e discontinuities <strong>of</strong> the predicates, their dissolutions<br />

and perishing alone enables, unlike a formal predicative proposition,<br />

the unity <strong>of</strong> the ground, the Parousia <strong>of</strong> the subject’s satisfaction,<br />

the memorial recapture <strong>of</strong> the past. Nothing essential is really lost<br />

that the speculative subject would hope for in the coming to come<br />

as unhoped return from a pure future, for there is no immemorial<br />

for it that its apophansis could not preserve and recuperate it. Hegel’s<br />

speculative-apophantic determination <strong>of</strong> history has remained the<br />

predicative task: that <strong>of</strong> grasping the ‘presently given presence’ and<br />

not the event <strong>of</strong> being as manifestation <strong>of</strong> the invisible that remains<br />

to come, not ‘this’ or ‘that’ coming, but the coming itself.<br />

What cannot be thought within the immanence <strong>of</strong> the speculative<br />

subject’s Parousia which is based on the predicative form <strong>of</strong> speculative<br />

judgement, is the radical epochal discontinuities <strong>of</strong> history which<br />

advents, in lighting fl ash, as unapparent phenomenon that tears,<br />

or hollows out, wounds the veil <strong>of</strong> the totality <strong>of</strong> the visible forms.<br />

Th e exposure <strong>of</strong> the speculative determination <strong>of</strong> history and its<br />

phenomenological visibility to the radical discontinuities or breaks<br />

where the event <strong>of</strong> unhoped for future erupts, demands the exposure<br />

<strong>of</strong> apophantic basis <strong>of</strong> the predicative, speculative judgement to the


56 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

event <strong>of</strong> truth which is the advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. If our dominant<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> ‘politics’ and ‘history’ is based upon the metaphysical<br />

foundation <strong>of</strong> the self-grounding immanence <strong>of</strong> Parousia that reduces<br />

the advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent into the mere attenuated variation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

apophantic logic <strong>of</strong> the visible, so that the radical breaks are levelled<br />

<strong>of</strong>f to the already given-ness <strong>of</strong> the visible forms, then it would be<br />

necessary to open such an apophantic phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the givenness<br />

to the more originary phenomenology <strong>of</strong> exposure at the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-grounding consciousness.<br />

Th at the judgement <strong>of</strong> such a universal history upon the singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the multiple (that reduces such multiplicity and singularity to the<br />

variations <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s necessary diremption) is derived from the<br />

apophantic basis <strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition can be shown by an<br />

exposition <strong>of</strong> what Hegel calls ‘speculative judgement’. Th e job <strong>of</strong> the<br />

speculative judgement is the same as the job <strong>of</strong> history. It is to bear<br />

its accidents, its own dissolutions and epochal ruptures straight right<br />

to the end <strong>of</strong> this movement, so that beneath the disquietude <strong>of</strong> its<br />

movement, beneath the suff erings <strong>of</strong> its fi nitude, it still sinks down<br />

its teeth into its autochthonous, its immanent pure soil from where<br />

history originates. Th e ruptures <strong>of</strong> history will only be then relative<br />

disjunctions by means <strong>of</strong> which uniform, universal history cunningly<br />

realizes itself. Th e speculative propositional movement <strong>of</strong> history has<br />

in its womb such cunning imposture that it realizes its totalization<br />

precisely through its own dissolutions, by sacrifi cing itself. Just as the<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> this speculative judgement is a sacrifi cial logic, so the logic <strong>of</strong><br />

history is a sacrifi cial history. Its logic is the theodicy <strong>of</strong> a resurrection and<br />

divine embodiment on the pr<strong>of</strong>ane order, for which death does not and<br />

must not go in vain, that gives itself back the serenity and quietitude <strong>of</strong><br />

the earth, <strong>of</strong> community <strong>of</strong> historical people who gather together to the<br />

innermost unity <strong>of</strong> its ground through the relationships <strong>of</strong> blood and soil.<br />

Th e logic <strong>of</strong> copula <strong>of</strong> the judgement, which is the passage <strong>of</strong><br />

death, will then serve the innermost ground <strong>of</strong> a community’s and<br />

history’s Parousia. Th e copula is the site, the centre, where history<br />

gathers unto itself, where people bearing swords and cross gather<br />

together to celebrate victory over others, the site where there takes<br />

places celebration <strong>of</strong> victory and festivity <strong>of</strong> being-one-with-oneself.<br />

Like the copula that unites the separated, disjoined elements into its<br />

innermost ground <strong>of</strong> unity, and therefore gives the disquiet, suff ering


Judgement and History • 57<br />

elements the joyous being with oneself, so the depth <strong>of</strong> the earth is the<br />

site <strong>of</strong> history which preserves, and at the same time gives a form <strong>of</strong><br />

eternity and unity to the dispersed, disconnected, disjoined elements.<br />

Th e depth <strong>of</strong> the earth nourishes in its womb the perishable mortals,<br />

and by denuding the individuals <strong>of</strong> its accidental, contingent features<br />

<strong>of</strong> its individuality, bestows upon these perishable mortals the sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘immortality’ and universality. Th is denuding or disrobing is the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> death, which death performs in the interests <strong>of</strong> the universal.<br />

Th e name <strong>of</strong> this deed is called ‘funeral’. In Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit,<br />

Hegel writes,<br />

Th e deed, then which embraces the entire existence <strong>of</strong> the bloodrelation,<br />

does not concern the citizen, for he does not belong to the<br />

family, nor the individual who is to become a citizen and will cease<br />

to count this particular individual; it has as its object and content<br />

this particular individual who belongs to the family, but is taken as<br />

a universal being freed from his sensuous, i.e., individual, reality.<br />

Th e deed no longer concerns the living but the dead, the individual<br />

who, after a long succession <strong>of</strong> separate disconnected experiences,<br />

concentrates himself into a single completed shape and has raised<br />

himself out <strong>of</strong> the unrest <strong>of</strong> the accidents <strong>of</strong> life into the calm <strong>of</strong><br />

simple universality. But because it is only as citizen that he is actual<br />

and substantial, the individual, so far as he is not a citizen but belongs<br />

to the family, is only an unreal impotent shadow. (1998, pp. 269-70)<br />

Death here is ‘the supreme work’, the ‘supreme achievement’, 2<br />

the innermost ground <strong>of</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> the individual that sublates the<br />

accidental, dispersed individuals into the concentrated form <strong>of</strong><br />

universality, that is, universal history. Death is the copula <strong>of</strong> the<br />

speculative-apophantic judgement. It is the passage <strong>of</strong> the speculative,<br />

the threshold that unites in its innermost ground the individual and<br />

universal, the subject and the predicate by denuding, disrobing the<br />

accidental features <strong>of</strong> the subject and predicates. By denuding and<br />

disrobing what it considers to be the accidental and contingency<br />

<strong>of</strong> the singulars, it lifts and sublates them unto the universality <strong>of</strong><br />

the Concept, just as through the works <strong>of</strong> death individuals sublate<br />

themselves unto the universality <strong>of</strong> History. Th e accomplishment or<br />

the end (Telos) <strong>of</strong> speculative judgement is the end <strong>of</strong> History itself:<br />

it is to subsume the singulars unto the totality <strong>of</strong> history. Th is speculative<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> history must pass through death, or must enable death to


58 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

traverse through its passage in such a way that the substantiality <strong>of</strong><br />

the subject-predicate position <strong>of</strong> the formal proposition is dissolved,<br />

and there comes into presence the Subject bearing itself as speculative<br />

proposition reaching its Parousia. Th is Subject <strong>of</strong> History is a Subject<br />

<strong>of</strong> predication and is a predicative subject at once who passes through<br />

its own dissolution and yet maintains itself through this passage and<br />

as this passage. Th is logic <strong>of</strong> origin enables metaphysically to found<br />

history in so far as it is the question <strong>of</strong> the historicity <strong>of</strong> the history<br />

itself, and not what passes as events in history. At the heart <strong>of</strong> the<br />

speculative logic <strong>of</strong> history operates certain logic <strong>of</strong> death, a thanaonto-theological<br />

constitution <strong>of</strong> metaphysics <strong>of</strong> history and politics.<br />

Th e metaphysical essence <strong>of</strong> history, the metaphysical secret <strong>of</strong><br />

the speculative judgement—in so far as the logic <strong>of</strong> history is based<br />

upon the modality <strong>of</strong> speculative judgement—is none but death.<br />

Death is the secret <strong>of</strong> history. Death is that demonic site where history<br />

comes to pass as history, which unites in a terrible fashion what passes<br />

away and what abides, the transitory and the universal, the divine<br />

and the mortal. Th e supreme work and its supreme achievement<br />

<strong>of</strong> copula in the speculative judgement is the supreme achievement<br />

<strong>of</strong> death. It makes judgement possible, it makes history possible;<br />

it makes history itself into a speculative judgement, and makes<br />

speculative judgement into history. Th e logic <strong>of</strong> origin, according to<br />

this manner <strong>of</strong> thinking, would not be stranger to the phenomena<br />

<strong>of</strong> disappearance and dissolution, to this ‘non-actuality’ 3 called<br />

‘death’, which is <strong>of</strong> all names the most terrifying. Th e speculative<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> origin is what makes this ‘non-actuality’ into the actuality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the actual, into the possibility <strong>of</strong> the possible. Th e actuality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

actual out <strong>of</strong> the ‘non-actuality’ when it realizes itself without any<br />

remainder is called Absolute. As making possible <strong>of</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

actual, and possibility <strong>of</strong> the possible, this logic that feeds upon the<br />

labour <strong>of</strong> death, is judgement <strong>of</strong> history, not judgement upon history,<br />

but history as judgement. As such the judgement <strong>of</strong> history upon the<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> individuals is the sentence <strong>of</strong> death. Th is judgement is<br />

the speculative truth <strong>of</strong> history, truth that is told in the form <strong>of</strong> the<br />

speculative proposition, which says not the fi xed, inert, lifeless truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> substance, but truth as Subjectivity, what has come to be history,<br />

which has passed as history, and preserved itself, in the interior depth<br />

<strong>of</strong> memory, as a ‘gallery <strong>of</strong> images’ (Ibid., p. 492). Death will then


Judgement and History • 59<br />

appear, as the appearing <strong>of</strong> the unapparent, the phenomenality <strong>of</strong><br />

the non-phenomena, the power <strong>of</strong> non-power. As such it is supreme<br />

power, the power <strong>of</strong> judgement. It is the force <strong>of</strong> law, the eye <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement, the gaze <strong>of</strong> power, for it founds upon nothing given but<br />

upon the work <strong>of</strong> nothing itself.<br />

One wonders whether this logic <strong>of</strong> origin, the judgement <strong>of</strong> history<br />

that passes the sentence <strong>of</strong> death is the originary logic <strong>of</strong> origin, or<br />

whether beyond or outside <strong>of</strong> this logic <strong>of</strong> origin, outside the dream<br />

<strong>of</strong> an autochthonous ground, outside this reductive totalization<br />

<strong>of</strong> a thought <strong>of</strong> history that celebrates the feast <strong>of</strong> victory over the<br />

vanquished, there lies a more originary logic <strong>of</strong> origin, an origin<br />

which is the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> the time yet to come. It is this<br />

promise that is the more originary judgement than the judgement<br />

<strong>of</strong> history. To think this outside it is necessary, without abandoning<br />

the historical-speculative task <strong>of</strong> dialectical thought altogether, to<br />

introduce another movement than the sacrifi cial-tragic time <strong>of</strong><br />

history, another modality <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> mortality that is outside<br />

being the source <strong>of</strong> power and the force <strong>of</strong> law. Such a thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> origin is yet to come, not because this future will come<br />

one day to pass, but an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> future not yet that is given<br />

originarily as an origin. Such a logic <strong>of</strong> origin, because it in advance<br />

determines everything what is to come, therefore is more originary<br />

than any passed past; in so far as it would not come to pass but<br />

remain to come, it is more originary than any future. To introduce<br />

this thinking <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> origin is neither to think mortality on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the power and the force <strong>of</strong> death, nor to think temporality on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the tragic-sacrifi cial time <strong>of</strong> the dialectical.<br />

It will then be necessary to show that the predicative nature <strong>of</strong><br />

this speculative history forecloses, and therefore cannot think, by a<br />

necessary logic, the event-ness <strong>of</strong> history itself, whose advent is not<br />

mere relative ruptures belonging to the universal history but epochal<br />

ruptures whose sudden, momentary advent makes history itself unto<br />

stillness <strong>of</strong> time, when death does not sublate itself unto the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> law. Th is stillness <strong>of</strong> the advent, in its sudden appearing <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent, is not the speculative truth <strong>of</strong> history, for the singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> its coming lies outside the universal movement <strong>of</strong> predicative<br />

proposition. Th erefore it is necessary to think the temporality itself<br />

otherwise, no longer on the tragic-sacrifi cial modality <strong>of</strong> historical


60 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

time, no longer the time <strong>of</strong> the gaze <strong>of</strong> law and the time <strong>of</strong> the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> power, but temporality in its refusal to gather unto the unity <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept, presents itself in a discontinuous presentation, in a confi<br />

guration, as a kind <strong>of</strong> assemblage, when time <strong>of</strong> presentation and<br />

its radical exteriority come-together, simultaneously, in a ‘monstrous<br />

coupling’ (Hölderlin 1988, 96-100).<br />

Th is Moment when there happens this demonic, monstrous<br />

coupling <strong>of</strong> time and its radical outside, time and eternity, reason<br />

and its inassimilable other, ground and the abyss, it marks the<br />

tremor <strong>of</strong> the event, which is the advent <strong>of</strong> history itself. Th inking<br />

that has borne witness the unspeakable horrors <strong>of</strong> history and has<br />

felt in its bones and marrow the totalizing power <strong>of</strong> death, a life<br />

that is ‘damaged’ (Adorno 1984) by the disrobing power <strong>of</strong> death’s<br />

gaze, such a thinking is now weary <strong>of</strong> the historical-memorial task<br />

<strong>of</strong> dialectical thinking, that is, to preserve in its interior depth the<br />

‘victorious’ march its becoming. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking now, at the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> such a speculative-dialectical history, supposing such an end<br />

has arrived (when?), is to think the redemptive advent, without the<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> thetic-sacrifi cial closure. Such an opening <strong>of</strong> thought is<br />

possible only on the basis <strong>of</strong> an exposure to the excess <strong>of</strong> promise<br />

arising at the moment <strong>of</strong> the suspension <strong>of</strong> law, a promise without<br />

judgement and without violence.<br />

Th inking <strong>of</strong> the end is not the thinking the ‘end’ in the sense that<br />

the ‘end’ is the ‘end’ that manifests itself in a site topological, but<br />

it is the thinking <strong>of</strong> the advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent at the extremity<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, at the ecstatic limit <strong>of</strong> time. It is the Eschatos <strong>of</strong> time that<br />

opens, inaugurates, welcomes the wholly other arrival. Each time an<br />

essential thinker attempts to think essentially, that means historically,<br />

if such a historical task is not recoiled from the terror and violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the judgement <strong>of</strong> history, such thinking must feel in its innermost<br />

depth such violence, so that it must evoke another judgement, in<br />

the name <strong>of</strong> truth and in the name <strong>of</strong> justice, a judgement upon<br />

history. But thinking does not have to be that alone. Th e courage <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking needs to be evoked, once again, no longer in the old tragicheroic<br />

pathos <strong>of</strong> a totalizing thought, but as hopeful, affi rmation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a messianic, redemptive coming <strong>of</strong> justice. Perhaps the task <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking that must confront now, more than ever before, is to think<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> the violence <strong>of</strong> a totalizing history and to rethink the


Judgement and History • 61<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> event in relation to history. Th is advent or event must not<br />

be assimilable to totalizing history without remainder. What would<br />

remain as ‘remainder’ is nothing but a redemptive promise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial that comes from a future beyond calculations, <strong>of</strong> a birth<br />

to come. For that, thinking does not have to be satisfi ed with what<br />

has become <strong>of</strong> a historical process, but to welcome, in hope, what is<br />

otherwise, and what is the ‘not yet’, noch Nicht (Bloch 1995).<br />

Metaphysics and Violence<br />

In his Th e Unforgettable and the Unhoped For (2002) Jean-Louis<br />

Chrétien calls us to note the denial <strong>of</strong> the immemorial and radical<br />

forgetting, <strong>of</strong> that radical already always loss—which is neither to be<br />

lamented nor to be anguished over—by the dominant metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

Parousia that totalizes the promise <strong>of</strong> coming from the immemorial<br />

past within the immanence <strong>of</strong> a self-presence. According to one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dominant modalities <strong>of</strong> thinking that founds metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Parousia,<br />

forgetting founds memory as if, as it were, it is the abyssal condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> memory. Th ere is, according to this understanding,<br />

no immemorial as such. Th ere is no radical loss in forgetting, in<br />

the sense that there is no forgetting that would not open itself to<br />

memory, that would not serve the memorial recall: nothing essential<br />

is lost, for what is lost and forgotten is the inessential as the structural<br />

opening to the memorial grasp <strong>of</strong> the essential. Th is metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

immanence where the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the infi nity is either mere<br />

privation <strong>of</strong> an immanent totality in visible forms, or for which the<br />

unapparent promise from an immemorial merely serves the essential<br />

self-foundation <strong>of</strong> the memorial; this is the secret <strong>of</strong> the dominant<br />

metaphysical essence <strong>of</strong> history and politics which is founded upon,<br />

what Chrétien calls, ‘forgetting <strong>of</strong> forgetting’.<br />

Hegel’s Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit exhibits in its utmost pr<strong>of</strong>undity<br />

the impossibility <strong>of</strong> a radical loss in a forgetting beyond memory.<br />

Th ere is no advent that has not been interiorized, assimilated or<br />

subjectifi ed in the innermost subjectivity <strong>of</strong> the Subject which is<br />

already memorial, for its task is to recall the moment <strong>of</strong> its origin at<br />

its end. Th e speculative memory <strong>of</strong> the dialectical history, grounded<br />

by its apophansis, is the circular re-appropriation <strong>of</strong> the beginning in<br />

the end. Th ere is no outside beyond the plenitude <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s


62 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Parousia. Th ere is no immemorial loss that would not manifest itself<br />

in the visible forms <strong>of</strong> universal history. Th e logic <strong>of</strong> Aufhebung is<br />

the memorial logic <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject. It preserves<br />

the essential in the innermost depth <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s parousia, and<br />

making the mourning for the loss into the mere privation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Subject’s self-presence.<br />

In the chapter <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit called ‘Sense-Certainty’,<br />

Hegel expounding the meaning <strong>of</strong> Th is in a phenomenological<br />

manner—that means, as the movement <strong>of</strong> Th is taking place as such—<br />

shows how in this phenomenological movement <strong>of</strong> taking place <strong>of</strong> Th is,<br />

the Th is shows on its emphatic self-certainty to be its own impossibility<br />

to maintain itself its Th is-ness. Th is phenomenological movement <strong>of</strong><br />

the Th is—that is supposed to be this absolutely irreducible singular<br />

phenomenon—already, immediately (the moment it advents itself,<br />

erupts itself as Th is) is opened to a loss, not in an accidental manner,<br />

but precisely because the Th is is Th is. Th e moment—here and now—<br />

the Th is appears, it is already a passed past, it is immediately a Th is<br />

which is no longer Th is and therefore an other than Th is: a lapsed<br />

presence, a presencing that in its advent has annulled itself, and has<br />

become other than itself. What it shows in this phenomenological<br />

appearing <strong>of</strong> the Th is is that the phenomenological movement itself<br />

originates on the basis <strong>of</strong> a loss, a forgetting, a presence that can<br />

never be recounted, a void or emptying away. What it shows is that<br />

the movement <strong>of</strong> the Th is appearing is a movement that puts into<br />

its peril <strong>of</strong> this appearing itself so that Th is can never be same Th is<br />

that the phenomenological consciousness will later recall. Th e Th is is<br />

essentially a ‘perilous being’, that means, its essence is to perish that<br />

is simultaneous with its advent. Th e phenomenological movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> history opens itself to this abyss <strong>of</strong> disappearance and dissolution,<br />

to the night <strong>of</strong> annihilation which can never be recalled by memory<br />

to the day <strong>of</strong> history, for it immediately has fallen outside the<br />

phenomenological movement <strong>of</strong> history, precisely in order to open<br />

this movement to itself for the fi rst time, as an excess <strong>of</strong> presencing<br />

that must immediately absent itself, as a forever passed past, as an<br />

excess <strong>of</strong> loss that opens time and being on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone<br />

can there be history, community, politics etc. Hegel writes,<br />

To the question: what is Now? let us answer, e.g. ‘Now is Night.’<br />

In order to test the truth <strong>of</strong> this sense-certainty a simple experience


Judgement and History • 63<br />

will suffi ce. We write down this truth; a truth cannot lose anything<br />

by written down, anymore than it can lose anything through our<br />

preserving it. If now, this noon, we look again at the written truth we<br />

shall have to say that it has become stale (Hegel 1998, p. 60)<br />

History is based upon a foundational loss, a loss that founds by giving<br />

the gift <strong>of</strong> the day; but precisely for that very reason, for Hegel, this<br />

loss is not an essential loss, for this night founds the day and gifts us<br />

the speculative truth <strong>of</strong> history and memory. Th is day is outside any<br />

this day or that night, a day other than or indiff erent to any this or<br />

that. What is lost, though in an ineluctable manner, is only the inessential<br />

which must undergo dissolution so that the essential as such takes place,<br />

which is the realm <strong>of</strong> essence, the universality immanent which erupts on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the loss—<strong>of</strong> the sense-certainty <strong>of</strong> the Th is. Hegel continues,<br />

Th e Now that is Night is preserved, i.e. it is treated as what it pr<strong>of</strong>esses<br />

to be, as something that is; but it proves itself to be, on the contrary,<br />

something that is not. Th e Now does indeed preserve itself, but as<br />

something that is not Night; equally it preserves itself in the face <strong>of</strong><br />

the Day that it now is, as something that is also not Day, in other<br />

words, as a negative in general. Th is self-preserving Now is, therefore,<br />

not immediate but mediated; for it is determined as a permanent<br />

and self-preserving Now through the fact that something else, viz.,<br />

Day and Night is not…so it is in fact the universal that is the true<br />

[content] <strong>of</strong> sense-certainty. (Ibid.)<br />

Th e Aufhebung <strong>of</strong> the phenomenological-speculative history—the<br />

power and work <strong>of</strong> negativity, that ‘energy <strong>of</strong> thought’ and <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Subject ‘the pure ‘I’’ (Ibid., p. 19)—is the work <strong>of</strong> interiorization<br />

through memory that constitutes the Subjectivity <strong>of</strong> speculative<br />

history for which mourning for the loss is merely privation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

constitutive process, a process similar to Freudian work <strong>of</strong> mourning.<br />

Th is power and force <strong>of</strong> negativity, which constitutes history in its<br />

inner depth and interiority, lies in this power <strong>of</strong> pure positing that<br />

converts the loss <strong>of</strong> the already and immediacy into the pr<strong>of</strong>i t or<br />

gain <strong>of</strong> the mediated universal which alone is essence, for this essence<br />

alone is the essential. Th is work <strong>of</strong> mourning which is the work <strong>of</strong><br />

Aufhebung that drives the phenomenological movement <strong>of</strong> speculative<br />

history is a violent movement <strong>of</strong> pure positing that the ‘pure ‘I’’, the<br />

Subject posits. Th e Speculative concept begins with positing—not<br />

with ‘this’ or ‘that’, for that would already be a mediated beginning,


64 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and hence would not be a beginning without pre-supposition—but<br />

with the pure act <strong>of</strong> positing itself, presupposing nothing which<br />

is mediated ‘this’ or ‘that’. Th is is so, in so far as philosophy that<br />

must begin without any presupposition, and therefore must not<br />

begin with ‘this’ or ‘that’, but with a beginning without mediation.<br />

Fichte, at the beginning <strong>of</strong> German Idealism, calls this pure power<br />

<strong>of</strong> positing as ‘primordial act’—the power, the energy <strong>of</strong> the ‘pure<br />

‘I’’—which is primordial in so far as its abyssal beginning begins this<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> beginning itself. Its beginning does not begin with<br />

what has already began, but beginning with the act <strong>of</strong> positing this<br />

beginning itself. Hence, the beginning <strong>of</strong> the speculative-dialectical<br />

history is a thetic beginning. It is the pure power <strong>of</strong> positing its own<br />

coming out <strong>of</strong> its non-actuality, out <strong>of</strong> a foundational loss which is<br />

death if death be the name <strong>of</strong> this ‘non-actuality’, <strong>of</strong> this nothing, <strong>of</strong><br />

this void that arises as full presence only to pass away immediately<br />

into nothing. Th e speculative movement <strong>of</strong> history is the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Concept founds itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> loss, the movement <strong>of</strong><br />

actualizing the non-actual. From the beginning <strong>of</strong> the speculativedialectical<br />

history, concept is the name <strong>of</strong> the pure power <strong>of</strong> positing<br />

itself, an autochthonous power <strong>of</strong> negativity that excludes, and<br />

through this exclusion includes within its totality what is otherwise,<br />

the expelled and excrement outside, either as an immanent loss,<br />

or as an inessential loss that must be expelled so that the essential<br />

essence may take place. Since this positing power <strong>of</strong> thetic must also<br />

posit, by a necessary logic <strong>of</strong> dialectical, its own otherwise, it has to<br />

exclude its outside, by its power <strong>of</strong> negativity, only to include this<br />

outside within its interiority as an essential void <strong>of</strong> being where the<br />

pure ‘I’ throws itself to its peril only to recover itself as essential,<br />

universal Subject <strong>of</strong> history. As such it is the speculative Subject <strong>of</strong><br />

the speculative proposition that maintains its Parousia through its<br />

own dissolution on the basis <strong>of</strong> a foundational loss that passes away<br />

only on the condition that it opens itself to the resurrection <strong>of</strong> being.<br />

Th is process <strong>of</strong> the dialectical historical, whose logic <strong>of</strong> movement<br />

is grasped in the speculative-predicative proposition, is not without<br />

suff ering and violence, but must go through violent antagonisms, life<br />

and death struggle and countless useless deaths whose numberless<br />

cries are already always eff aced from the memorial speech <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

Th e immemorial lamentation from which the Owl <strong>of</strong> Minerva is


Judgement and History • 65<br />

forever in fl ight refuses ‘the work <strong>of</strong> mourning’. Is it not the secret<br />

<strong>of</strong> law and history that it derives its power and force from what<br />

is non-power par excellence; that it derives the foundation <strong>of</strong> its<br />

force upon the absence <strong>of</strong> any foundation? Such is the ‘magical’ or<br />

‘tremendous’ power which is more powerful than any power, in that<br />

precisely because it can convert even non-power and non-foundation<br />

into foundation and its force? Th e force and power <strong>of</strong> the speculative<br />

proposition that captures the truth <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical task<br />

<strong>of</strong> totalization is this power and force <strong>of</strong> death, <strong>of</strong> this non-power,<br />

<strong>of</strong> this non-actuality. Hegel the metaphysician, who discovered the<br />

cunning <strong>of</strong> reason that secretly governs history, gave us the truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> this history, the truth <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> non-power, foundational<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> non-foundation, totalizing possibility without totality.<br />

Th is truth begins with the notion <strong>of</strong> possible and capacity, even if it<br />

is possibility <strong>of</strong> the impossible. It begins with the power <strong>of</strong> positing,<br />

even if it is power <strong>of</strong> the non-power. It begins with the force <strong>of</strong> the<br />

negative, even if this negative does not have any given foundation <strong>of</strong><br />

its own.<br />

Is this truth originary, truth that begins with power and force,<br />

truth that founds law and its work? How the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> violence<br />

that adheres in the dialectical-historical task be atoned and redeemed<br />

if its truth has to begin and thereby end (for according to this logic<br />

the end must coincide with its beginning, so that the end is nothing<br />

but resulting truth <strong>of</strong> its beginning) with the power <strong>of</strong> positing, with<br />

the thetic force <strong>of</strong> the concept? Here comes the impasse, or dialectical<br />

aporia <strong>of</strong> speculative dialectics.<br />

Th e dialectical concept, with its pure power <strong>of</strong> positing, calls forth<br />

its dialectical opposite, it’s anti-thesis so that the violence <strong>of</strong> positing<br />

concept is dialectically counter- acted by its anti-thesis. But this<br />

anti-thetic concept, in so far it is concept, must proceed to counteract<br />

the thetic time with one more positing. Since this anti-thetic too<br />

proceeds by the power <strong>of</strong> positing, synthetic <strong>of</strong> this violence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

thetic and anti-thetic is called forth, which is turn itself is another<br />

thetic, positing power <strong>of</strong> the negative. As a result—and this is the<br />

irremediable aporia that cannot be resolved within the speculativedialectical<br />

totality—a remainder <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical violence <strong>of</strong><br />

the speculative concept haunts even at the End <strong>of</strong> history, even


66 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the Absolute concept. Th e metaphysical violence <strong>of</strong> the speculative<br />

proposition that begins with the pure power <strong>of</strong> positing is not<br />

redeemed even in the Absolute concept, for were this redemption<br />

possible, this possibility must already have been promised in the<br />

beginning before the speculative beginning <strong>of</strong> conceptual positing;<br />

in other words, this promise must be given in an immemorial past<br />

before all predication and before all positing so that the immanence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the self-consuming predications and positing be opened to the<br />

immemorial promise, to the unconditioned transcendence <strong>of</strong><br />

the unpredicative that arrives from a site <strong>of</strong> pure future. Th e<br />

redemption <strong>of</strong> this metaphysical violence <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical<br />

must already be promised at the beginning, which for that matter<br />

would not be the origin with the pure, autochthonous power <strong>of</strong><br />

positing, for it is the impasse, or aporia <strong>of</strong> dialectical-speculative<br />

history that it proceeds to the atonement <strong>of</strong> the violence <strong>of</strong> history<br />

from the beginning which itself is none but that feeds upon the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> negativity, upon the force <strong>of</strong> nothing, upon the pure power<br />

<strong>of</strong> non-foundation. At the very beginning <strong>of</strong> the thetic which the<br />

speculative concept carries to the end <strong>of</strong> the process, to the end <strong>of</strong><br />

history, the violence <strong>of</strong> the positing adheres itself, rendering the<br />

reconciliation at the end <strong>of</strong> history (which Hegel dramatizes upon<br />

the theatrical modality <strong>of</strong> tragic) insuffi cient and inadequate. Th at<br />

is why the dialectical-historical accomplishment <strong>of</strong> reconciliation<br />

at the end <strong>of</strong> history, with all its tragic-heroic pathos, remains for<br />

us un-redemptive and inconsolable, demanding an opening up<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dimension <strong>of</strong> an ‘unconditional forgiveness’ (Derrida 2001)<br />

beyond the immanent logic <strong>of</strong> reconciliation.<br />

What would remain, today, <strong>of</strong> the sense and signifi cation <strong>of</strong> this<br />

reconciliatory pathos <strong>of</strong> tragic-historical dialectics, when with the<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> its painful insuffi ciency there comes the necessity that<br />

thinking gives itself another task, that <strong>of</strong> welcoming the redemptive<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> an ‘unconditional forgiveness’ outside the pathos <strong>of</strong><br />

reconciliation? How to think <strong>of</strong> a non-foundation that would not<br />

have to be the origin as autochthonous, auto-engendering pure<br />

positing <strong>of</strong> ‘the pure ‘I’? Th is other origin, whose origin must begin<br />

before beginning and hence an immemorial beginning would<br />

therefore not be the dialectical-historical memorial task, but the


Judgement and History • 67<br />

immemorial task <strong>of</strong> the origin that must already always promise <strong>of</strong><br />

the redeeming advent that arrives from a site wholly otherwise. Th e<br />

beginning must already always bear this promise, for otherwise it<br />

would not be promise, for otherwise there would not be fulfi lment <strong>of</strong><br />

this promise. Th e failure <strong>of</strong> speculative historical to bring the melancholy<br />

<strong>of</strong> historical violence to the redemptive fulfi lment is that <strong>of</strong> the failure to<br />

think <strong>of</strong> origin in a more originary manner. Instead it mistook its own<br />

beginning, which is derivative, to be something else, by a necessary<br />

logic, which is not an accidental mistake <strong>of</strong> an eccentric, perishable<br />

thinker with a certain proper name, but the essential failure <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thought. Th e essential failure <strong>of</strong> this thought consists in that it has<br />

already always failed itself, by a necessary logic, even before it begun<br />

its movement, at its beginning or already before beginning. Because<br />

it has already always failed itself, and therefore failed essentially, it<br />

has to fail at its end that means, at its own result. Th e End <strong>of</strong> History<br />

does not redeem the violence to the immemorial loss, for it already<br />

always lacks justice to those who have not yet come. Th e success or<br />

failure <strong>of</strong> this thought cannot be measured by ordinary standards <strong>of</strong><br />

success and failure. Only on the basis <strong>of</strong> this non-measure <strong>of</strong> forgiveness,<br />

the essential failure or an essential success <strong>of</strong> a thought can be measured,<br />

for only according to the measure <strong>of</strong> this non-measure the pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>of</strong><br />

thought is done justice to.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> an essential failure <strong>of</strong> thought there comes a deep,<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound melancholy. It is the melancholy <strong>of</strong> a thought that cannot<br />

be understood according to psychological or psycho-analytical make<br />

up <strong>of</strong> a thinker. Th ere is a melancholy <strong>of</strong> thought in that thinking is<br />

essentially, in the innermost manner, is fi nite. But this melancholy,<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the deep recognition <strong>of</strong> a failure <strong>of</strong> thought, demands thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> redemption that opens itself to an excess <strong>of</strong> history, to an excess <strong>of</strong><br />

the world-historical ‘politics’. It is in this sense thinking has a future<br />

even when it is touched with an essential failure, even when there<br />

is an apparent success, even when thinking is damaged by violence<br />

and by pain. An essential failure touches us at the deepest depth <strong>of</strong><br />

our destinal existence, precisely at that moment thinking claims<br />

to attain the Absolute. It is only in this sense Hegel’s thought is a<br />

failure, but it is an essential failure, precisely because and precisely<br />

at that moment when thought realized itself as Absolute Concept, as<br />

System. Schelling who in his younger days was driven, like his friend


68 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Hegel, by this overwhelming desire to constitute a system, to render<br />

thinking itself attain itself to system, recognized an essential failure <strong>of</strong><br />

thought, and who out <strong>of</strong> this anguished recognition, then attempted<br />

another movement <strong>of</strong> thinking, one radically distinguished from<br />

Hegel’s. While Hegel’s success at being able to constitute his system<br />

brought him fame and name, the essential failure <strong>of</strong> Schelling who<br />

could never write system, was relegated to the mere transitory passage<br />

to Hegel. But this common place, ordinary standard <strong>of</strong> evaluating a<br />

thinker does not touch the essential, as if the depth, the originality and<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>of</strong> a thinker lies in constituting systems. From where and<br />

why so the standard <strong>of</strong> measuring the depth, originality, pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>of</strong><br />

a thought have to be the extent thinking attains to system or totality?<br />

Perhaps the courage <strong>of</strong> thinking rather lies in recognizing its essential<br />

failure to attain totality, in that it must fall short <strong>of</strong> totality at all and<br />

could never constitute, by its own eff ort and capacity, its system.<br />

But this essential failure is nothing negative, but a departure point<br />

<strong>of</strong> a new beginning. ‘It is a sign’, says Heidegger about Schelling and<br />

Nietzsche here, ‘<strong>of</strong> the advent <strong>of</strong> something completely diff erent, the<br />

heat lightning <strong>of</strong> a new beginning. Whoever really knew the reason<br />

for this breakdown and could conquer it intelligently would have to<br />

become the founder <strong>of</strong> the new beginning’ (1985, p.3).<br />

What is the new beginning that Schelling made? It is to initiate a<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> origin, a movement that opens itself to the immemorial past<br />

and to the unhoped for future which as such does not allow itself to<br />

be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> the speculative-predicative proposition; it<br />

is the movement <strong>of</strong> releasing the unconditional outside the closure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the speculative-apophantic history. Th is unconditional outside is<br />

the site where the event <strong>of</strong> presencing <strong>of</strong> presence arrives that opens to<br />

a time always to remain, a remnant <strong>of</strong> time that is after, and outside<br />

all closure. Th is advent is not mere historical event amongst others<br />

belonging to the homogenous unity <strong>of</strong> universal history, but the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming as such. Th e eruption <strong>of</strong> the advent has its condition the unconditional<br />

epochal rupture that renders history to an interval. Th is<br />

interval does not belong to the homogenous logic <strong>of</strong> the predicativespeculative<br />

proposition, for it does not function in the manner <strong>of</strong> a<br />

copula in a speculative proposition. Th is abyss <strong>of</strong> the interval is not<br />

death that serves the interests <strong>of</strong> the universal, for it is not the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> the negative that converts nothing into being, the non-actuality


Judgement and History • 69<br />

into actuality. Th is judgement would not be judgement <strong>of</strong> history,<br />

then, but a judgement upon history. Th e task <strong>of</strong> this judgement is<br />

no longer that <strong>of</strong> constituting historical totalities, or metaphysicalhistorical<br />

system-making, but to think radically epochal ruptures and<br />

the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming whose promise is given in a time preceding<br />

the tragic-sacrifi cial time <strong>of</strong> history, and remains, as a messianic<br />

remnant, as promise to come, here and now.<br />

The Passion <strong>of</strong> Potentiality<br />

Schelling in his later works, however already beginning with his<br />

Inquiries into the Essence <strong>of</strong> Human freedom, attempts to think the<br />

essence <strong>of</strong> human freedom no longer on the basis <strong>of</strong> the predicative<br />

proposition, that means, no longer on the basis <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> identity, but unity understood as confi guration. Hence is<br />

the origin <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> ‘Zusammenhang’ that Schelling later elaborates<br />

in Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World (2000): co-fi guration or constellation that<br />

infl uenced Heidegger’s (1969) notion <strong>of</strong> belonging-together, or<br />

constellation <strong>of</strong> the relation between Being and man. Th is thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> confi guration arises at the accomplishment <strong>of</strong> a certain, dominant<br />

metaphysical constitution <strong>of</strong> onto-theology. Constellation is, in this<br />

sense, a ‘non-identical thinking’ (Adorno 1973). Constellation is a<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> unity without identity, what belongs together without<br />

ontological ground <strong>of</strong> identity, an assemblage <strong>of</strong> the incommensurable<br />

disparates. Th is problematic <strong>of</strong> thinking as confi guration is inseparable<br />

from a radical re-thinking <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> event (Ereignis): the event<br />

as a free arising <strong>of</strong> history, each time anew, on the un-ground <strong>of</strong> an<br />

irreducible diff erence. Th e event pre-supposes freedom as a forever<br />

inappropriable, originary donation from a site or ground forever<br />

ungrounded. Th is freedom cannot be grounded on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

apophansis <strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition; it is rather the diff erence<br />

that opens the immanent self-grounding presence to the presencing<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence that alone makes history possible. Such is the task <strong>of</strong><br />

Schelling’s thinking in his Freedom essay.<br />

Here without renouncing the systematic task <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

freedom—and here rightly with Heidegger (1985) one can pose<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> the compatibility <strong>of</strong> the system and the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom—Schelling attempts to think again the notion <strong>of</strong> judgement


70 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and system that does not completely belong to the metaphysical<br />

constitution <strong>of</strong> an onto-theology, but that opens on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> (un)ground <strong>of</strong> freedom to the redemptive possibility <strong>of</strong> a pure<br />

futurity which no apophantic work <strong>of</strong> predicative proposition can<br />

anticipate. Freedom here works as the principle <strong>of</strong> pure potentiality<br />

that never ceases to inaugurate the event <strong>of</strong> history that is opened<br />

to the immemorial and to the excess <strong>of</strong> the not yet, to the excess<br />

that is always to remain, the eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> an excess <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

over the given. In so far as the question <strong>of</strong> judgement is inseparable<br />

from the question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> system, as Heidegger shows<br />

in his lectures on the Metaphysical Foundations <strong>of</strong> Logic, (1984) the<br />

task is to think in a more originary manner the logical notion <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement that founds itself upon the metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong><br />

identity and the notion <strong>of</strong> system as such. Th is originary manner <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking the notion <strong>of</strong> judgement is introduced with the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom. Th is question <strong>of</strong> freedom is no longer then understood<br />

as the possibility <strong>of</strong> free will in relation to the question neither <strong>of</strong><br />

determination, nor as property (or faculty) <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’, but as<br />

‘free space’ <strong>of</strong> the Open where the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming happens as<br />

fi nite opening. What at stake is not the task <strong>of</strong> thinking ‘identity <strong>of</strong><br />

the identity and diff erence as in Hegel, but the question <strong>of</strong> originary<br />

cision, or caesural opening as the abyssal ground <strong>of</strong> the de-cision<br />

<strong>of</strong> good and evil. Freedom here, in Schelling’s thought, is not the<br />

speculative-apophantic movement <strong>of</strong> the energy <strong>of</strong> the concept that<br />

founds history, but actuality that manifests itself in the de-cision<br />

between good and evil: the event <strong>of</strong> history arises out <strong>of</strong> this abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all must open the mortal existence to the advent<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming so that there be history. Th is advent <strong>of</strong> coming that is<br />

opened by abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom must already always happen even if there<br />

to be something like apophantic-speculative work <strong>of</strong> judgement,<br />

which is that <strong>of</strong> converting nothing into being. Th erefore, there is<br />

a potentiality <strong>of</strong> freedom that inaugurates history as such which is<br />

not, and which is irreducible to the potentiality <strong>of</strong> the concept that<br />

apophantically recuperates the passed past and converts the nothing<br />

into being. What the potentiality <strong>of</strong> freedom opens is not a passed<br />

past, but the immemorial past that opens time to truth and being.<br />

Th is immemorial is not grasped by the speculative proposition, for it<br />

is already always opened by this immemorial.


Judgement and History • 71<br />

In so far as the question <strong>of</strong> freedom is the question <strong>of</strong> the Open,<br />

the more originary ‘free space’ on the basis <strong>of</strong> which free will can at<br />

all be posed, and in so far as de-cision, not yet ontologically founded,<br />

is born <strong>of</strong> the cision, that means, at the limit <strong>of</strong> predication, the<br />

judgement and the system <strong>of</strong> freedom can no longer be based on<br />

the onto-theological-predicative principle <strong>of</strong> identity but can only<br />

be thought when the question <strong>of</strong> freedom is introduced into the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> constellation. Th is cision, the originary separation<br />

(Scheidung) 4 does not function in the manner <strong>of</strong> copula <strong>of</strong> the<br />

predicative- speculative judgement. In other words, it does not enable<br />

the subject and predicate to pass into each other in the manner <strong>of</strong><br />

speculum, in the manner <strong>of</strong> mirroring that renders this passing itself<br />

into the eternal truth <strong>of</strong> passing. Th is cision which while separating<br />

what is separated and disjoined render belong together (and not<br />

belong-together. We have learnt to distinguish between the two,<br />

after the manner <strong>of</strong> Heidegger (1969)) is rather the abyss whose<br />

temporality no metaphysics <strong>of</strong> self-presence based upon the logic <strong>of</strong><br />

predication can sublate into itself, in so far as the cision as the nonconditional<br />

void (which for that matter is not pure Nothing, nor the<br />

negativity that converts Nothing into being) is the originary interval<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> which judgement character <strong>of</strong> judgement arrives. Th is<br />

place <strong>of</strong> the cision is this non-place, this monstrous site where there<br />

takes place that demonic encounter with the wholly otherwise where<br />

history as such inaugurates itself. Th is judgement <strong>of</strong> freedom, if it<br />

can still be called ‘judgement’, is then a monstrous judgement whose<br />

copula is at once coupe and yet coupling, a cutting away and joining,<br />

a parting and calling what is parted to belong together, withdrawing<br />

and bringing together the withdrawn. Th e judgement is this<br />

monstrous coupling, which is at once coupe that is, between subject<br />

and predicate, a non-thetic judgement in that it does not begin itself<br />

by its power <strong>of</strong> pure positing, but with the non-appropriable logic <strong>of</strong><br />

origin, which as cision precedes all the logic <strong>of</strong> positing. Th e cision<br />

<strong>of</strong> this monstrous, demonic judgement is the non-place placing, the<br />

non-placed encountering on the basis <strong>of</strong> which—on the basis <strong>of</strong> this<br />

encounter—there takes places the exigency for the mortal, fi nite<br />

being to decide between the good and evil.<br />

Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> good and evil which alone must explain<br />

the enigmatic question <strong>of</strong> human freedom, therefore, belongs to


72 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

fi nitude, fi nitude that claims upon the mortal being called ‘man’, and<br />

throws him to his destiny. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this non-appropriable<br />

fi nitude this mortal being called ‘man’ assumes his freedom. It is on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> this more originary monstrosity, on the basis <strong>of</strong> a nonappropriable<br />

‘loan’ which must fi rst <strong>of</strong> all expropriate the mortal,<br />

that something like truth <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ manifests itself to ‘man’. It<br />

is this monstrosity <strong>of</strong> judgement alone explains the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil<br />

in man, and consequently the essence <strong>of</strong> human freedom. Th erefore,<br />

if Hegel attempts to address the question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil,<br />

and the question <strong>of</strong> freedom as such, he could only explain it away<br />

as mere diremptive moment, which is due to the fi nitude which is<br />

necessarily uplifted (Aufheben), resurrected unto Absolute Concept<br />

as infi nite negativity. Th is could only happen like this in so far as<br />

dialectical-speculative judgement cannot explain the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fi nitude <strong>of</strong> man whose ecstasy is the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> a de-cision (that is,<br />

opening to the possibility <strong>of</strong> good and evil in an equal measure). Th is<br />

ecstasy <strong>of</strong> decision cannot be explained away by the predicative nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> speculative judgement, in so far as the speculative judgement<br />

already always presupposes the logical principle <strong>of</strong> identity, as if<br />

ecstasy <strong>of</strong> decision can only be logical-speculative. What is missing<br />

in speculative judgement is this ecstatic dimension <strong>of</strong> decision that<br />

arises out <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> man, and that is granted to man by the<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom. As a result freedom is explained away without<br />

taking into account its ecstatic dimension, its infi nite transcendence,<br />

and its opening to what is otherwise than the mortal.<br />

Th ere is a monstrosity, or madness in all de-cisions, in so far as it<br />

carries in each <strong>of</strong> the mortal’s forehead the terror <strong>of</strong> the cision or abyss,<br />

forever non-appropriable to man. Th e speculative judgement <strong>of</strong> history<br />

presupposes the more originary monstrous judgement <strong>of</strong> freedom that fi rst<br />

<strong>of</strong> all must already always ecstatically place the mortals unto that placing,<br />

to the demonic encountering with the wholly otherwise, to the divine and<br />

the elemental forces <strong>of</strong> nature, to the immemorial past that forever exceeds<br />

any immanence <strong>of</strong> self--presence. As such, freedom exposes us, tears<br />

us open, and wounds us to the pure potentiality which is the name<br />

<strong>of</strong> a radical future. Th e predicative truth <strong>of</strong> history which Hegel’s<br />

speculative judgement apophantically seeks to recuperate belongs to<br />

this abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom, to the monstrous judgement <strong>of</strong> freedom, to<br />

the pre-predicative revelation on the basis <strong>of</strong> which ‘man’ decides,


Judgement and History • 73<br />

that man seeks conversion <strong>of</strong> the possibilities into actualities. But the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> this decision is always pre-predicative abyss (Abgrund) which<br />

is, born out <strong>of</strong> the undecidable, at the limit, is solicited both to the<br />

good and evil in an equal measure, since it cannot—because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fi nitude <strong>of</strong> man—persist eternally in the undecidable. Because <strong>of</strong> this<br />

fi nitude <strong>of</strong> man, because <strong>of</strong> the non-appropriable outside as ground,<br />

what this mortal actualizes is only a limitation <strong>of</strong> the possible, only<br />

a limitation <strong>of</strong> the undecidable. On account <strong>of</strong> our irreducible<br />

fi nitude, there remains an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> potentiality. In other<br />

words, the potentiality given as gift can never be exhausted in the<br />

acts <strong>of</strong> actualization which man undertakes on his own behalf, on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> his pure power <strong>of</strong> negativity.<br />

What man undertakes on behalf <strong>of</strong> his power <strong>of</strong> negativity, and<br />

seeks to constitute the foundation <strong>of</strong> his own historical existence,<br />

belongs to the passion <strong>of</strong> potentiality that is not exhausted in the<br />

dialectical-historical labour <strong>of</strong> historical man. What remains, then, as<br />

un-pre-thinkable remnant, but that must be given to man as promise<br />

and gift in the already always, is this pure potentiality itself that does<br />

not completely pass over into actuality. What remains as ‘irreducible<br />

remainder’ (Schelling 1936) is nothing but this potentiality itself,<br />

which may or may not pass over into being. Th e demonic essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom lies in its potentiality <strong>of</strong> it’s ‘perhaps’ and its ‘may be’. If<br />

the speculative judgement must presuppose what must have already<br />

actualized, then potentiality cannot even be a logical category. Th e<br />

ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the potentiality will forever overfl ow what is already<br />

actualized. Th is ‘forever’ is at once the promise <strong>of</strong> joy and the source<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unspeakable melancholy in fi nite life that is evoked by Schelling<br />

at the end <strong>of</strong> his Inquiry.<br />

In God, too, there would be a depth <strong>of</strong> darkness if he did not make<br />

the condition his own and unite it to him as one and as absolute<br />

personality. Man never gains control over the condition, even though<br />

in evil he strives to do so; it is only loaned to him independently<br />

<strong>of</strong> him; hence his personality and selfhood can never be raised to<br />

complete actuality. Th is is the sadness which adheres too all fi nite life,<br />

and in as much as there is even in God himself a condition at least<br />

relatively independent, there is in him, too, a source <strong>of</strong> sadness which,<br />

however, never attains actuality but rather serves for the eternal joy <strong>of</strong><br />

triumph. Th ence, the veil <strong>of</strong> sadness, which is spread over all nature,<br />

the deep unappeasable melancholy <strong>of</strong> all life. (1936, p. 79)


74 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

In not to be able to actualize oneself completely without remainder,<br />

in not to be able to appropriate the ground <strong>of</strong> one’s existence, in our<br />

never being able to attain actuality to make our condition our own,<br />

to own our condition, to make it our ‘proper’ <strong>of</strong> the ‘proper’, to make<br />

it our ‘present’ to ourselves: this is the ‘unappeasable melancholy’ <strong>of</strong><br />

our fi nite life. Th e event <strong>of</strong> existence does not begin with the pure,<br />

thetic power <strong>of</strong> positing. It rather begins immemorially with our<br />

non-power, our essential failure, and our non-possibility in relation<br />

to the ground whose eternal remnant can never be appropriated. If<br />

this is the occasion <strong>of</strong> joy for the fi nite existence, it is in so far as this<br />

eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> the never appropriated ground is also the ground<br />

with joyous affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a creative freedom, since this inscrutable<br />

ground is also the ground <strong>of</strong> the advent. Th is ‘irreducible remainder’<br />

is at once the promise <strong>of</strong> joy, and the source <strong>of</strong> the unspeakable<br />

melancholy <strong>of</strong> fi nite life. Th e Abgrund that eternally remains in the<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> a fi nite existence is not therefore negation <strong>of</strong> our freedom.<br />

Elsewhere I have written,<br />

In other words, Abgrund does not undermine, negate, or even minimize<br />

freedom; rather the other way, Abgrund is what calls for freedom, or rather<br />

calls itself forth in acts <strong>of</strong> revealing, that calls forth acts <strong>of</strong> actualizations,<br />

to the infi nite possibilities <strong>of</strong> freedom, to the labour <strong>of</strong> eff ective actions.<br />

If an ‘unappeased melancholy’ adheres to all our fi nite life, being<br />

fi nite and conditioned being that we are who cannot appropriate our<br />

own condition once and for all, it is this melancholy that calls forth,<br />

each moment and singularity, the joyous acts <strong>of</strong> creation as infi nite,<br />

inexhaustible, never-once-and-for-all actualizable acts <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

(Das 2008, pp. 167-180)<br />

What is then the occasion for joy? Th e fi nite freedom <strong>of</strong> the mortal<br />

which can never appropriate its own condition bears (precisely<br />

because <strong>of</strong> this fi nitude) the redemptive fulfi lment in this affi rmation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Not Yet, the passion <strong>of</strong> infi nite potentiality. Th is passion and<br />

ecstasy <strong>of</strong> potentiality is the occasion <strong>of</strong> joy for the fi nite, mortal existence.<br />

Melancholy and joy for the mortals are not mere opposites: they unite<br />

in man in a monstrous coupling when the dialectics <strong>of</strong> history comes to<br />

a sudden pause. It is at this sudden pause <strong>of</strong> the dialectics <strong>of</strong> history the<br />

monstrosity <strong>of</strong> freedom makes sudden appearance in lightning fl ash that<br />

strikes us the mortals. Th e monstrous logic <strong>of</strong> this freedom, then, does not<br />

begin, nor end with the pure, thetic power <strong>of</strong> positing. Th e meaning <strong>of</strong>


Judgement and History • 75<br />

this judgement is not the pure power <strong>of</strong> law <strong>of</strong> the Absolute, or the force<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dialectics <strong>of</strong> history. It is the logic <strong>of</strong> the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> coming into<br />

existence that opens with the passion <strong>of</strong> potentiality.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking history is no longer that <strong>of</strong> constituting<br />

historical, epochal totalities whose logic <strong>of</strong> origin would be to<br />

apophantically grasp its story <strong>of</strong> what is actualized, but that which,<br />

opening to the thought <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, opens to the outside, that means,<br />

to the passion <strong>of</strong> potentiality. Th is is to realize that this mortal called<br />

‘man’ is not primarily the power <strong>of</strong> the negative which he uses to<br />

constitute his own historical totalization, and encloses all that is to<br />

come in the logic <strong>of</strong> this negativity. To realize the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> ‘man’<br />

and to abandon the task <strong>of</strong> metaphysical-historical totalization—<br />

though appears a loss to man—is more salutary task <strong>of</strong> thinking.<br />

Th is retreat from, and renunciation from all possible metaphysicalhistorical<br />

totalizing process is an attempt to make anew the sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> the historicity <strong>of</strong> history for this mortal being called ‘man’. If a<br />

fundamental attunement <strong>of</strong> melancholy adheres to our fundamental<br />

being, essentially, in our retreating historical refl ections, this only<br />

attunes us to our damaged historical existence that bears witness the<br />

consequences <strong>of</strong> various totalizing attempts made in the name <strong>of</strong><br />

certain History. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking is no longer that <strong>of</strong> judgement<br />

<strong>of</strong> history on basis <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> negativity, but we must disclose<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> historical existence logic <strong>of</strong> judgement in relation to<br />

a non-appropriable fi nitude. Th is non-appropriable fi nitude is the<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> a freedom on the basis <strong>of</strong> which man creates his history.<br />

Th e transcendence <strong>of</strong> this other time, the wholly otherwise time,<br />

constitutes the ecstasy and passion <strong>of</strong> a fi nite existence. Th is ecstasy<br />

and passion is the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> a freedom and passion for potentiality<br />

that welcomes the ‘unhoped for’ that foils our expectations, that<br />

does not belong to the logic <strong>of</strong> accumulative, linear unfolding <strong>of</strong><br />

homogeneous instants. Th is arrival is welcomed on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

loosening the structure <strong>of</strong> dominant thinking; in other words,<br />

the judgement <strong>of</strong> history itself has to be rendered monstrous. Th e<br />

monstrosity <strong>of</strong> history bears witness the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> history itself. But<br />

above all, this bears witness and remembers, and in remembering<br />

prepares the advent <strong>of</strong> another coming. It is this redemptive fulfi lment,<br />

its necessity for mortal existence that pronounces judgement upon<br />

history.


§ Transfi guration, Interruption<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> coming calls forth two fold tasks: to interrupt what<br />

has acquired the solidity <strong>of</strong> foundation which is legitimized by the<br />

myth <strong>of</strong> a foundation (or founding <strong>of</strong> myth) and to transfi gure what<br />

is loosened in the given architecture <strong>of</strong> foundation into affi rmation<br />

<strong>of</strong> something ‘not yet’. Together they constitute the task <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

itself, for what affi rms the ‘not yet’ must also affi rm the unworking<br />

<strong>of</strong> foundation so that becoming and dissolution, joyfulness and<br />

mourning are brought together in this monstrous coupling <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

fold interruption and transfi guration. Placed at this site <strong>of</strong> encounter,<br />

the Open, which is the monstrous site <strong>of</strong> history itself, where the<br />

mortal ‘ man’ is placed as the copula, as the abyss <strong>of</strong> unity between<br />

interruption and transfi guration, man is thereby placed to welcome<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> coming itself.<br />

*<br />

Th e demonic site <strong>of</strong> the open does not belong to necessity but to<br />

the essence <strong>of</strong> freedom, which—in so far as it is freedom and not<br />

necessity—always carries in itself the possibility <strong>of</strong> In Vain. In other<br />

words, this freedom can never be completely actualized without a<br />

melancholic remnant because <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the mortal, which is<br />

to be distinguished from the melancholy <strong>of</strong> fulfi llment, for there is<br />

also a melancholy, albeit paradisiacal, in fulfi llment. Th e melancholy<br />

<strong>of</strong> In-Vain lies in the fact that the passion <strong>of</strong> potentiality that is<br />

given in freedom may not pass over into being without reserve, that<br />

there may always remain a remnant <strong>of</strong> un-fulfi llment. Th is reserve<br />

is the messianic reserve, the withdrawn in <strong>of</strong>f ering, the secret in


Transfi guration, Interruption • 77<br />

promise whose fulfi llment and communication demands another<br />

event <strong>of</strong> actualization outside man’s mastery on behalf <strong>of</strong> his power<br />

<strong>of</strong> negativity. Th is reserve is what exceeds the force <strong>of</strong> law and the<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> history. It introduces the Moment <strong>of</strong> transcendence<br />

in each hic et nunc, rendering each hic et nunc opaque to its own<br />

light, like the mirror that does not see its own light. Th is reserve<br />

adhering in the ‘darkness <strong>of</strong> lived presence’ (Bloch 2002) that renders<br />

each hic et nunc opaque to itself because <strong>of</strong> its excess, is the secret<br />

<strong>of</strong> time that carries a promise outside communication; or, rather it<br />

communicates itself in a communication that is pure communication,<br />

pure <strong>of</strong>f ering, and therefore does not appear itself as communicable<br />

in the given, already accomplished communicability. Th e pure<br />

actuality <strong>of</strong> communication is not the potentiality <strong>of</strong> negativity<br />

realized imperfectly in dialectical-historical world. In each historical<br />

realization or production <strong>of</strong> himself as dialectical ‘man’ in this<br />

historical world, there is always a reserve <strong>of</strong> the outside, which is the<br />

reserve <strong>of</strong> a pure actuality <strong>of</strong> coming, which is also—paradoxically—<br />

the pure reserve <strong>of</strong> actuality. Th e pure actuality cannot be thought<br />

in ontological terms, which is neither Being nor Nothing, but what<br />

Schelling (2000) develops in his later thought as Überseyn which is<br />

above or outside being, and therefore outside nothing. It is beyond<br />

and above being and nothing, and therefore is an excess <strong>of</strong> being<br />

that opens fi rst <strong>of</strong> all time to being and being to its time. What is<br />

reserved is neither potentiality <strong>of</strong> being nor potentiality <strong>of</strong> nothing<br />

but is the pure advent <strong>of</strong> actuality without remainder, which for that<br />

matter always remains a remainder in the dialectical-historical world<br />

<strong>of</strong> negativity. As the pure actuality <strong>of</strong> the unconditioned presencing,<br />

this presencing in its advent conceals itself, reserves itself in the world<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nite, conditioned presences, and thereby keeps itself open to its<br />

unconditionality that means, to its futurity which no conditioned<br />

presences ever exhaust in any immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence. Th is<br />

reserve is the reserve <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong> thought. While in respect<br />

to the relation to itself it is pure actuality without remainder, in<br />

respect to the relation to the historical world <strong>of</strong> negativity it is the<br />

passion <strong>of</strong> potentiality that is a reserve without force and without<br />

power. Pure giving and yet a reserve at once, simultaneously, each<br />

time and always: such is the thought <strong>of</strong> promise, and the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

thought.


78 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

What exists as this fi nite existence, whose condition for that<br />

matter is always only given, gifted, is never a saturated phenomenon.<br />

Each being, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it comes into existence at all, is un-saturated and<br />

in-excess. Hence is the possibility, not only <strong>of</strong> In-Vain, but <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unhoped for fulfi llment in the possibility <strong>of</strong> the eternal remnant <strong>of</strong><br />

the reserve (<strong>of</strong> future and time). If what exists is not saturated merely<br />

with its given form, with what has already arrived and become <strong>of</strong> it,<br />

but rather ‘ventures beyond’( Bloch1995, p. 5)says, because it loves<br />

the open sea and the blue sky above, then it must also assume the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> In-Vain. Th e ship that loves the red dawn must traverse<br />

many nights <strong>of</strong> perils so that the coming <strong>of</strong> the red dawn appears, and<br />

illumines all that is coming. Th e abyss <strong>of</strong> the night is not an objection<br />

that is to be eliminated, since the coming <strong>of</strong> the dawn must also<br />

know the suff ering <strong>of</strong> the brooding labour which existence undergoes.<br />

Th inking too, in its patient waiting for the coming, undergoes, and<br />

knows the pangs <strong>of</strong> the night out <strong>of</strong> which the dawn shines forth. It<br />

is not for nothing that Hegel speaks <strong>of</strong> philosophy as ‘way <strong>of</strong> despair’<br />

(1998, p.49). Yet philosophy, at least in its dominant form, also<br />

attempts mastery <strong>of</strong> this despair, to minimize its abyss, or give itself<br />

the vain consolation <strong>of</strong> an eternity which the concept represents. For<br />

Hegel, the metaphysician <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, absolute concept is eternal, an<br />

eternity which is not a stranger to the fi nitude, but an eternity that<br />

has traversed the suff erings <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, and has lifted up this fi nitude<br />

unto itself. Absolute concept is Calvary that has carried death to its<br />

own transfi guration, into eternity itself.<br />

It is not for nothing that the dominant metaphysics seeks to<br />

master this abyss, this non-condition, this ground called mortality;<br />

and it is possible to show that this desire <strong>of</strong> the mastery <strong>of</strong> mortality,<br />

this thanatology, is constitutive <strong>of</strong> the dominant metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the<br />

west. Th is ‘econo-onto-thanatology’ (Das 2010) constitutes itself<br />

on certain economic fi guration <strong>of</strong> death, and thereby forecloses<br />

the astonishment <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> the immemorial coming from a<br />

pure future. In such a way this metaphysics, this ‘econo-onto-thanaontology’<br />

comes to give itself the task to constitute a world- historical<br />

totality, produced by the labour <strong>of</strong> the negative through the violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the life and death struggle for recognition. Th is violence consists<br />

not merely life and death war between man against man, the ethos<br />

<strong>of</strong> war constituting and deconstituting historical epochs one after


Transfi guration, Interruption • 79<br />

another, but mortal being’s metaphysical desire to master his own<br />

ground, his own abyss, and his own mortality. Metaphysics, at least<br />

the dominant metaphysics, bears witness this violence, man’s thetic<br />

violence that seeks to sublate his ground, which is his non-condition,<br />

as if his non-condition is the objection to his own existence. In this<br />

desire for mastery, in this metaphysical violence lies the metaphysical<br />

origin <strong>of</strong> man’s evil. Th is evil is the self-abnegation <strong>of</strong> the fi nite<br />

creature’s own condition, that is, his fi nitude.<br />

Schelling’s treatise on the essence <strong>of</strong> human freedom, which is one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>oundest inquiry into the question <strong>of</strong> evil in the history <strong>of</strong><br />

modern philosophy, attempts to think <strong>of</strong> the mortal task <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

not the mastery or nihilation <strong>of</strong> abyssal ground, but transfi guration<br />

<strong>of</strong> this non-conditional gravity into the possibility <strong>of</strong> joy and grace.<br />

Th is transfi guration is the creative task <strong>of</strong> the mortal being that <strong>of</strong><br />

opening, or inaugurating on the basis <strong>of</strong> an inappropriable ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom ever new possibilities <strong>of</strong> future. Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fl ight <strong>of</strong> the Eagle: the Eagle’s fl ight is not elimination <strong>of</strong> the force<br />

<strong>of</strong> gravity, but rather a continuous elevation <strong>of</strong> it into the possibility<br />

or means to its fl ight. So it is with the many abysses <strong>of</strong> the night <strong>of</strong><br />

brooding thinking undergoes; so it is with our sorrows and our joys,<br />

our past and future, our memory and our promise, our history and<br />

its redemption. Th e task <strong>of</strong> the voyage is therefore not the self-abnegation<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nitude but a continuous elevation or an infi nite transfi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

our ground into existence, gravity into grace. Th e night <strong>of</strong> broodingthinking,<br />

groping for illumination which is beyond is only a point<br />

<strong>of</strong> departure—not even the origin, let alone the end—for the great<br />

voyage it undertakes that must, because <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the mortal,<br />

continuously ‘venture beyond’. Every arriving is always born out <strong>of</strong><br />

the night <strong>of</strong> brooding, groping, and foreboding, the dark night <strong>of</strong><br />

the eternal past before all presence which no light <strong>of</strong> the day ever<br />

completely illuminates without remainder. Th is night which in itself<br />

is no objection to existence is precisely the immemorial that opens<br />

existence to the time yet to come. Th e task here is <strong>of</strong> transfi guring the<br />

night <strong>of</strong> the immemorial into the light <strong>of</strong> the dawn, by interminably<br />

bringing to light <strong>of</strong> hope and into its affi rmation the promise that<br />

is given in the immemorial, in the already always, before any selfpresence<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence. Every coming into presence is born out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

non-condition that places us unto the Open, that releases us to the


80 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

welcoming <strong>of</strong> the gift that bears the mark <strong>of</strong> our death, a death that<br />

cannot be reduced to the ‘econo-onto-thanatology’ <strong>of</strong> the dominant<br />

onto-theological totalization, but opens us to the pure potentiality <strong>of</strong><br />

presencing <strong>of</strong> presence.<br />

In order to welcome the shining <strong>of</strong> the arriving, it is necessary to<br />

confront the abyss <strong>of</strong> the past, to enter into the concentrated form<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence that has become (existence thick with ‘the darkness<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence’), not in order to tarry with it, but rather so that all<br />

that has solidifi ed into the concentrated form <strong>of</strong> present existence<br />

is melted anew, given away, given to its own worklessness, and is<br />

opened thereby to welcome the coming, to welcome what has not<br />

yet solidifi ed into presence and that has not acquired the darkness <strong>of</strong><br />

the past. Th is mortality is not Calvary <strong>of</strong> the concept, but the tragic<br />

task <strong>of</strong> existence itself: every now and then existence is to be given<br />

over to that ‘monstrous coupling’ where becoming and dissolution<br />

are united, where joy is at once touched with that unspeakable<br />

melancholy that spreads over our whole existence. All coming <strong>of</strong><br />

the new is essentially an act <strong>of</strong> transfi guration: what has become <strong>of</strong><br />

existence and has acquired the solidity <strong>of</strong> a foundation through our<br />

objective-historical institutions (this historico-discursive foundation<br />

<strong>of</strong> our existence that has become <strong>of</strong> us) and through which we have<br />

known ourselves to have become, through which we have given<br />

ourselves to ourselves as historical being, all that is to be transfi gured<br />

into what is not yet, into an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a ‘becoming through<br />

perishing’, <strong>of</strong> an opening that at once keeps itself in reserve through<br />

which the promise is kept in secret. But this transfi guration <strong>of</strong> despair<br />

into hope, <strong>of</strong> sorrows into joy, <strong>of</strong> our melancholic existence into the<br />

joyous affi rmation <strong>of</strong> redemption in coming, <strong>of</strong> what is into what is<br />

not yet is not without interruption. It is rather that transfi guration<br />

demands interruption, as a light requires an already opening and<br />

clearing where it may then shine forth. As mere interruption <strong>of</strong><br />

the given without transfi guration—interruption <strong>of</strong> that which has<br />

become a foundation for us—is nihilism; so transfi guration without<br />

interruption is mere continuity <strong>of</strong> the what has become <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

as mere extension: it does not then affi rm the eternal ‘Yes’ that<br />

welcomes, in unconditioned hospitality, the unapparent presencing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise.


Transfi guration, Interruption • 81<br />

Th is task <strong>of</strong> transfi guration through interruption <strong>of</strong> solidifi ed<br />

past, and reifi ed, this undoing <strong>of</strong> a sedimented foundation: this is<br />

what fi nite politics means, not the politics which is performed by<br />

the economic fi guration <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> death, but an opening <strong>of</strong><br />

being to the advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent that is marked by the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

death. It is this that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all gives us the mortals any sense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

political and presence ethical at all: that is, as an open existence,<br />

we are thrown, exposed unto the Open by mortality, unto the pure<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> the advent <strong>of</strong> history.. As the Night to be transfi gured<br />

into the Dawn, the abyss <strong>of</strong> the Night is to be interrupted, so<br />

redemptive affi rming <strong>of</strong> the coming time demands that what has<br />

become and has become dead, or those whose death has rendered<br />

our melancholy unredeemed, our sorrows and mourning for the lost<br />

that has pervaded our existence, this mourning and unredeemed<br />

melancholy is to be transfi gured into an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the coming<br />

time, towards a redemption in future always in reserve, for it is<br />

already always in the Open.<br />

So it is with individual existence. Th e ground <strong>of</strong> his existence lies in<br />

the irrecuperable abyss <strong>of</strong> the past where he was not yet there—or, he<br />

was there as not yet, as a kind <strong>of</strong> possible actual. Each present moment<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence for the existent is thick with this dark light. Th erefore<br />

existence comes too late to us as awareness and when we are aware<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence, we already are ‘thrown’ to the world, or we have already<br />

arrived to presence, as if something has already passed us—that<br />

opening that is already there in the coming into the light—and has<br />

now become the abyss, has receded into the past, an inscrutable<br />

and unfathomable ground. Th is belatedness <strong>of</strong> our arriving makes<br />

us non-contemporary in relation to the ground <strong>of</strong> our existence.<br />

An irreducible separation, an originary disjunction, a chasm marks<br />

our existence, exposing us for the fi rst time to what is outside all<br />

presence: to the immemorial and to the un-anticipatable. It is on this<br />

space <strong>of</strong> exposure that spaces us to time, it is in this ‘the-there’ (‘Da’<br />

<strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s Dasein) that history arrives for us from the destination<br />

<strong>of</strong> pure futurity.<br />

Th e being-there <strong>of</strong> the opening, or clearing that has become the abyss,<br />

is not an objection, nor is it anyway blocking <strong>of</strong> existence coming to


82 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

presence. Th ere lies the interminable, the infi nite task for the mortals:<br />

not the mastery, nor appropriation <strong>of</strong> this non-conditional ground<br />

unto the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence, but continually to elevate,<br />

transfi gure the abyss into affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the coming, <strong>of</strong> darkness<br />

into the light, so as to keep open the possibility <strong>of</strong> originary opening<br />

once more, that means, infi nitely. To transfi gure the abyss into an<br />

affi rmation <strong>of</strong> coming is not thereby a negation or a mastery <strong>of</strong> the<br />

abyss; it is rather to carry, within existence, its own abyss as abyss, and<br />

to render at each moment, our individual and historical existence<br />

un-predicative and incalculable, releasing the unconditioned in us<br />

from what Jean Luc Nancy calls ‘the immanent self-consumption’<br />

(Nancy 1993, p.13). To render our existence un-predicative, and to<br />

release that transcendence from any given totalization is to be, at<br />

each moment, fi nite and mortal, but it is an unenclosed mortality<br />

and an unenclosed fi nitude, open to the fear and trembling, to the<br />

astonishment <strong>of</strong> the event, or even to the madness <strong>of</strong> the moment<br />

that seizes us, dispropriates us, and opens our given form <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

into the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the future. It is in relation to this futurity<br />

that a kind <strong>of</strong> transcendence is possible for the mortals, an eternity is<br />

granted as a gift from freedom with which history inaugurates itself,<br />

not in relation to its immanent ground, but bearing the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

transcendence given in the immemorial. Th e thought <strong>of</strong> future <strong>of</strong><br />

history is the thought <strong>of</strong> its redemption itself. Redemption means here<br />

none other than the coming to presence that is kept open in the opening.<br />

Its task is the infi nite transfi guration and keeping open <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

unto the future, unto the possible, unto the coming to presence. Th is<br />

‘facticity’ <strong>of</strong> the coming to presence <strong>of</strong> existence, the ‘that is’ irreducible<br />

to the empirical facts <strong>of</strong> every particularity <strong>of</strong> this and that, the beingthere<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Open is intimated in non-predicative disclosure <strong>of</strong><br />

language that arrives as lightning fl ash, exposes us to the astonishing<br />

event <strong>of</strong> language.<br />

Each time someone arrives, it arrives as this singular presentation<br />

that is non-contemporaneous with itself: it is already always opened<br />

up in the abyss, in that caesural yawning gap where there occurs the<br />

coupling between the immemorial past and the coming. Existence<br />

is always singular each time, belonging never to the logic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

system, irreducible to the universality <strong>of</strong> categories, already always<br />

falling away from the order <strong>of</strong> generality that tends to constitute a


Transfi guration, Interruption • 83<br />

form <strong>of</strong> totality. It is as if a never grounded interval inscribes itself<br />

between itself and itself. Hence existence can only present itself<br />

to itself as a relation to a never grounded past, as if as it were it is<br />

born out <strong>of</strong> the disjunction between its ground and its coming into<br />

existence, the non-conditional ground that has now fallen outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence. Schelling calls this originary fall which falls outside<br />

in the immemorial, eternal past as a result <strong>of</strong> the disjunction or<br />

cision, as Abfall. Th is character <strong>of</strong> belatedness <strong>of</strong> existence, this noncontemporaneous<br />

character carries the latency <strong>of</strong> its own coming<br />

into future and hence the necessity, in creative freedom, to affi rm a<br />

future yet to come. Because <strong>of</strong> this non-contemporaneous character<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence, it still has at each moment <strong>of</strong> arriving, the something <strong>of</strong><br />

the not yet <strong>of</strong> come in itself that has remained as surplus, as excess,<br />

<strong>of</strong> an un-saturated remnant. To affi rm the coming in the not yet, it is<br />

necessary for it to interrupt and transfi gure what has come into an<br />

affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future, which demands that the phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the<br />

visible to open to the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the unapparent that cannot be<br />

grasped by the categorical, eidetic acts <strong>of</strong> consciousness.<br />

If a certain thanatology has governed the dominant metaphysics,<br />

it is thereby unable to open itself, or rather is insuffi ciently open<br />

towards any affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a coming time. Th erefore it is necessary to<br />

expose this thanatology, which is nothing sort <strong>of</strong> ontology, to open to<br />

the passivity <strong>of</strong> the inception and the non-predicative redemption <strong>of</strong><br />

the coming. Th is is one way to conceive <strong>of</strong> a new critique <strong>of</strong> violence,<br />

not merely <strong>of</strong> the violence that manifests every now and then as ‘this’<br />

or ‘that’ violent act, but <strong>of</strong> this metaphysical violence on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

which alone the violence <strong>of</strong> man can be understood.<br />

Transfi guration demands that something <strong>of</strong> what has become<br />

be posited as ‘that it has become so’, or ‘it was so’—that means<br />

interrupting the concentrated presence, or solidifi ed past—so that<br />

an opening to ‘that is not yet so’, or ‘that it was not yet so’ is possible.<br />

Th is opening <strong>of</strong> the space, between ‘that it has become so’ and ‘that it<br />

is not yet so’, is the space <strong>of</strong> interruption, the interval <strong>of</strong> the caesura,<br />

the epochal rupture <strong>of</strong> history, <strong>of</strong> which Hölderlin speaks <strong>of</strong> as the<br />

site <strong>of</strong> becoming as perishing, where the transfi guration also takes<br />

place as corollary <strong>of</strong> interruption. One who affi rms the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own becoming, that is, what is not yet become <strong>of</strong> him, must<br />

interrupt himself, and interrupt all that has become <strong>of</strong> him, as if he


84 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

has thereby made himself a monster, or rendered himself the play<br />

space where infi nite and fi nitude, joyous mourning and becoming<br />

one, perishing and coming to be are yoked together. As if what has<br />

served hitherto the ground and foundation <strong>of</strong> his own existing, all<br />

that is now dissolved; as if confronting his own mortality—to which<br />

he is exposed in the opening—he enters there and then into the<br />

darkness <strong>of</strong> his being and confronts his solidifi ed past, giving over<br />

his solidifi ed foundation to its unworking. He interrupts himself by<br />

rendering himself a past; what seemed to him as clear as the day and<br />

what he is confi dent about the solidity and substantiality <strong>of</strong> being<br />

now evaporates. Th e abyss <strong>of</strong> the night is transfi gured into light<br />

through this interruption, as future transfi gures the past, and thereby<br />

redeems it. Th e entering into the night is also the entering into the<br />

light that shines in the distance, as point <strong>of</strong> departure into the new<br />

sea—towards the distance more future than any future present—<br />

towards the future, which is not already given.<br />

Since the coming light is not a given truth, it belongs to the<br />

undecidable and the unpredicative. It is the possible which also<br />

includes the possibility <strong>of</strong> the not coming <strong>of</strong> the light at all. Each<br />

affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the possible is simultaneously an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

non-condition; it at once an impossible where the vertigo <strong>of</strong> the<br />

undecidable watches over us, where the madness <strong>of</strong> the non-thought<br />

keeps vigil, where the anguish and despair <strong>of</strong> the unnamable tempers<br />

with the possible. To the possible belongs not only realizable and<br />

realized, but also the unrealized and the unrealizable. It is on the<br />

non-condition <strong>of</strong> the possible that possibility and impossibility<br />

makes themselves manifest. To exist is to be tempered with the<br />

non-condition. To render existence open to its non-condition is the<br />

highest eff ort <strong>of</strong> thinking. Its logic is not provided by the speculativedialectical<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition.<br />

Th e demonic essence <strong>of</strong> possibility is essentially the excess <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. Here the possibility holds that the possible may not pass<br />

into, or pass over to being, since it does not have the self-foundational<br />

character <strong>of</strong> a logical necessity and identity, so that a releasing, a<br />

freeing and opening remains for the possibility <strong>of</strong> the otherwise. Th is<br />

is what we call, in the highest sense, contingency, the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

otherwise to come, which is also the possibility <strong>of</strong> the non-arrival. Th e<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> the possible is not the dialectical-speculative logic <strong>of</strong> negativity.


Transfi guration, Interruption • 85<br />

It does not convert the nothingness into being without a remainder.<br />

Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> the non-possible does not belong to the traditional<br />

logic, because it defi es the logical principle <strong>of</strong> non-contradiction<br />

and identity. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> the non-possible, instead, belongs<br />

to what call the Open: in the Open the otherwise may come, the<br />

impossibility may arrive, and the possibility may not pass over into<br />

being. Each time the voyage begins and the ship sails, it is inserted<br />

into the undecidable and the incalculable: the incalculability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

demonic weather, a madness and a certain monstrosity takes its vigil.<br />

Th is monstrosity, not enough <strong>of</strong> being human, claims the mortal,<br />

and delivers him to his mortality, for man is the mortal who never<br />

becomes completely ‘human’ enough. Sometimes the monstrosity <strong>of</strong><br />

history leads one to stray into the wrong paths, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as decisions<br />

are always taken at the limit, ins<strong>of</strong>ar man belongs to freedom and not<br />

freedom to man. Hence the voyage into the coming is incalculable<br />

par excellence: the voyage <strong>of</strong> the possible, since it is in love with the<br />

open sea and blue sky above, with the horizon without horizontality,<br />

it does not yet know its own destination and destiny, whose only<br />

destiny is to be without destination, an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the incalculable<br />

and arriving <strong>of</strong> the light without certitude <strong>of</strong> knowledge. Th e light<br />

may fall, or the moment arrives without thunders and lightning, but<br />

in a faint murmur <strong>of</strong> the dawn, or in ‘doves’ feet’ that guides the<br />

world: ‘it is the stillest words which bring the storm, thoughts that<br />

come on doves’ feet guide the world’ (Nietzsche 1992,p. 35). Th e<br />

destiny <strong>of</strong> a voyage without destination is in love with the freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

the unknown, for the unknown arrives with a freedom whose ground<br />

is not yet given, but that has claimed man and in claiming man,<br />

releases man to the open. Heidegger could write,<br />

Freedom governs the open in the sense <strong>of</strong> the cleared and lighted up,<br />

i.e., <strong>of</strong> the revealed. It is to the happening <strong>of</strong> revealing, i.e., <strong>of</strong> truth,<br />

that freedom stands in the closest and must intimate kinship... All<br />

revealing comes out <strong>of</strong> the open, goes into the open, and brings into<br />

the open.<br />

He goes on to say,<br />

Freedom is that which conceals in a way that opens to light, in whose<br />

clearing there simmers that veil that covers what comes to presence <strong>of</strong><br />

all truth and lets the veil appear as what veils. Freedom is the realm


86 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> the destining that at any given time starts a revealing upon its way.<br />

(Heidegger 1977, p. 25).<br />

Kant had something like an intimation <strong>of</strong> this abyssal, inscrutable<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> freedom that claims the mortals, on the basis <strong>of</strong> which<br />

mortals are what they come to be. Th erefore existence remains for<br />

Kant something un-predicable, which remains as remnant outside all<br />

predication, not as a result <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> predication, but what is<br />

already always presupposed even the process <strong>of</strong> predication to begin.<br />

What Kant wanted to think, through freedom as what is inscrutable,<br />

is the dark abyss, which is also the pure <strong>of</strong>f ering, the sublime <strong>of</strong>f ering,<br />

the gift from a destination wholly otherwise. Th is un-predicable is<br />

not what would be one day predicated in absolute knowledge, and<br />

therefore existence, because it is the pure gift, sublime <strong>of</strong>f ering from<br />

other destination, cannot be included in any system <strong>of</strong> knowledge,<br />

even if it is absolute knowledge. Th ere can only be pure presentation<br />

(Darstellung) as distinguished from representation <strong>of</strong> a dialectically<br />

mediated knowledge, which is in appearing as unapparent, elicits<br />

from us respect (Achtung). It is this fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the mortals that is<br />

truly tragic, and not the tragic <strong>of</strong> the dialectical mediation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

infi nite and fi nitude uplifted (Aufheben) unto unity through which<br />

there occurs atonement <strong>of</strong> gilt. Life being essentially mortal and<br />

ineluctably fi nite is a synthesis <strong>of</strong> the infi nite and fi nitude. But this<br />

synthesis is never a unity for man. It lies outside <strong>of</strong> mortals as a kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> abyss, a kind <strong>of</strong> inscrutable, dark ground. It is the separation from<br />

this synthesis the coming arrives as unknown, out <strong>of</strong> an unground,<br />

since the foundation <strong>of</strong> the solidifi ed presence is infi nitely interrupted<br />

and given over to the opening.<br />

Should we name this opening as ‘beginning’?


§ Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin<br />

We are too late for the gods<br />

And too early for Being.<br />

Being’s poem,<br />

Just began, is man.<br />

Of Beginning<br />

Martin Heidegger (2001, p.4)<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> beginning is not merely the beginning <strong>of</strong> questioning<br />

for philosophy; it is also the most diffi cult one. Does philosophy begin<br />

with something, or someone, with ‘that’ <strong>of</strong> a beginning or with ‘what’<br />

<strong>of</strong> a beginning? Where and when is the beginning a ‘beginning’? Is<br />

it that with each beginning, at each single instance opening towards<br />

the coming, must there remain open an already always so that<br />

beginning—multiple and singular each moment—is already to come<br />

in advance, a future that arrives from the past or that is given as<br />

promise in the immemorial past? Th is will be to think beginning itself<br />

as promise, which is each time the promise <strong>of</strong> the coming which is always<br />

to come. In that sense Heidegger’s notion <strong>of</strong> the phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

the unapparent is a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> promise, the thought <strong>of</strong> an<br />

originary promise that fi rst opens time to the being that is essentially<br />

fi nite and ineluctably mortal. Th ere must already have began a<br />

beginning which is inappropriable, inscrutable and the groundless<br />

opening, therefore an eternal beginning, in relation to which alone<br />

existence comes to presence, and wherein alone lies the creatureliness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortal being: on this account the creature called ‘man’ is who


88 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

happens to arrive as this being. In the beginning an opening holds<br />

sway as the possibility <strong>of</strong> beginning, as the promise <strong>of</strong> arriving, an<br />

opening with which every voyaging begins, the ship ventures forth,<br />

sallies beyond and welcomes the open sea in its infi nite ebb and fl ows<br />

and the blue sky opening above with the play <strong>of</strong> lights and darkness<br />

unknown. Th e beginning is the spacing where there occurs the play,<br />

the play <strong>of</strong> not yet seen thousand morning rays and thousand not yet<br />

known evening twilight . It is that the beginning, at the same time,<br />

that is yet to come, at each instance, beginning that is never given<br />

in advance so that each beginning is a beginning wholly otherwise,<br />

wholly anew, wholly dawning. Such a past is always to come in future,<br />

a past to come, for which it is necessary that beginning will also always<br />

begin in future, that in the future there may remain the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the ever new beginning. Th is ever new possibility <strong>of</strong> beginning which<br />

is also always to come is the messianic notion <strong>of</strong> promise par excellence.<br />

Here neither the past is seen as a mere passed past, nor is the future<br />

seen as a future that will come to pass.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> beginning is that <strong>of</strong> opening, <strong>of</strong> inception that<br />

is to come, an inception that is to be renewed each instance, at each<br />

presentation <strong>of</strong> presence, so that at each instance that there be an<br />

inception <strong>of</strong> renewal. Such a thinking <strong>of</strong> beginning, in order to<br />

distinguish from another notion <strong>of</strong> beginning—dialectical-speculative<br />

beginning, for example, that follows the logic <strong>of</strong> generation—shall be<br />

called here as ‘inception’. Heidegger in his lectures on Parmenides<br />

calls such a beginning ‘in-ception’ (An-fang) that is distinguished<br />

from beginning as ‘outset’. Th e latter is the thinking <strong>of</strong> beginning at<br />

a defi nite time, or historical epoch, while inception is the thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

beginning itself, where thinking is no more mastering <strong>of</strong> beings, but<br />

thinking outside a given, dominant metaphysics, thinking that steps<br />

back, or retreats from such a metaphysics. Heidegger says:<br />

In distinction from the mastering from beings, the thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

thinkers is the thinking <strong>of</strong> Being. Th eir thinking is a retreating in face<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being… Th e beginning is not something dependent on the favor<br />

<strong>of</strong> these thinkers, where they are active in such and such a way, but,<br />

rather, the reverse: the beginning is that which begins something with<br />

these thinkers—by laying a claim on them in such a way that from<br />

them is demanded an extreme retreating in the face <strong>of</strong> Being. Th e<br />

thinkers are begun by the beginning: ‘in-cepted’ [An-gefangenen] by


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 89<br />

the in-ception [An-fang]; they are taken up by it and are gathered into<br />

it. (Heidegger 1992, pp. 7-8).<br />

Th is promise <strong>of</strong> such inception, which is also the promise <strong>of</strong> coming, is a gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking that must retreat from the techno-thana-ontological mastery<br />

<strong>of</strong> entities presently given. Th e gift <strong>of</strong> time is that <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

its renewal in each hic et nunc: such is here the thought <strong>of</strong> inception<br />

with which the voyage <strong>of</strong> thinking begins, always anew and always<br />

otherwise, always with a repetition that never repeats as the same.<br />

With the inception the wholly otherwise, and wholly coming is given<br />

as a gift that incalculably arrives from future that endows time with<br />

eternity, since this gift has already always opened the mortal being to<br />

a never passed immemorial past and to the incalculable future, and<br />

thereby redeeming time itself, as if for the fi rst time and each time,<br />

opening time to its transcendence. Th is eternity is not the eternal<br />

immobility <strong>of</strong> the empty time, nor the mobility <strong>of</strong> the monotonous<br />

conceptual generation (for concept to generate, none otherwise than<br />

concepts are necessary) but the eternity <strong>of</strong> actual beginning to arrive.<br />

Th is eternity is a fi nite eternity which presents itself in the lightning<br />

fl ash <strong>of</strong> its advent where becoming and perishing strikes the mortals,<br />

seizes them and opens them to the inauguration <strong>of</strong> a new history.<br />

Th is is what will be spoken here <strong>of</strong> as the logic <strong>of</strong> origin. Th e logic <strong>of</strong><br />

the origin, the scene <strong>of</strong> the origin, is the originary not yet 1 . It is the<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> the future <strong>of</strong> the past and the past <strong>of</strong> the not yet. Th e originary<br />

not yet is the originary gift <strong>of</strong> time that endows upon the mortals the<br />

task—for all gift brings along with it a task—to renew this gift <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality, and thereby delivering this gift to its own transcendence,<br />

in so far as renewal transcends each time what is given and brings<br />

to it what is always and each time new. Such transcendence will be<br />

each moment a fi nite transcendence that befi ts this fi nite being called<br />

‘man’. Th is fi nite transcendence opens the fi nite being to the divine<br />

excess, to the advent <strong>of</strong> the holy in the separation that holds together<br />

the divine and the mortal.<br />

Man is this openness to its beginning that transcends itself. With<br />

this is given the hope that redeems and rewards the travail which the<br />

voyage undergoes, goes itself under, ex-periences itself (that also means<br />

ex-periences ahead <strong>of</strong> itself, going beyond <strong>of</strong> itself, outside <strong>of</strong> itself,<br />

becoming other <strong>of</strong> oneself) as undergoing perils <strong>of</strong> the tempestuous


90 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

sea, yet frolicking forth with energy and passion for the unknown,<br />

living at the edge or limit <strong>of</strong> the world so that the light <strong>of</strong> the eye meets<br />

the light <strong>of</strong> the Sun. Th inking is always, as Ernst Bloch says, ‘venturing<br />

beyond’. In this sense the thought <strong>of</strong> an immemorial promise is not<br />

alien to ‘perilous being’ that the mortal essentially is. Th e notion <strong>of</strong><br />

experience here is not constitutive <strong>of</strong> an eidetic consciousness, or <strong>of</strong><br />

a transcendental subject’s Parousia. Th e notion <strong>of</strong> ‘experience’ here is<br />

to be thought outside <strong>of</strong> any eidetic phenomenology. It is rather to<br />

name what is unnamable, that <strong>of</strong> the essential ‘peril <strong>of</strong> being’ who<br />

is exposed to what arrives from ‘beyond’. Th e undergoing itself is<br />

thereby going beyond, venturing beyond <strong>of</strong> itself: these two meanings<br />

are interwoven in the word ‘experience’. What sinks us also elevates us.<br />

Or in Hölderlin’s words: ‘Where the danger grows, there too grows<br />

the saving grace’. Th e German word for ‘experience’, Er-fahrung,<br />

evokes this experience <strong>of</strong> traversal or voyaging with the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> perils to be undergone. What is undergone falls upon him who<br />

undergoes and as Heidegger (1982, p. 57) says, transfi gures him. Th e<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> time with which the possibility <strong>of</strong> the eternity <strong>of</strong> ever renewed<br />

and wholly otherwise inceptions are given, transfi gures the one who<br />

undergoes the voyage <strong>of</strong> experiencing and thinking that seeks the<br />

beyond, the furthest and the more distant than any others that are<br />

known in advance, beyond all that is programmable and calculable.<br />

Were there not given this gift <strong>of</strong> time, nothing new would arrive and<br />

come; the melancholy <strong>of</strong> the unredeemed presence and past would<br />

lose the meaning <strong>of</strong> eternity for us, and nothing would remain as<br />

promise for us, for with the gift <strong>of</strong> time there is also given the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

remaining time beyond that has become, beyond that has grown old<br />

and stale and decayed, beyond all entities <strong>of</strong> the given presence that<br />

make up the world in its given-ness.<br />

Th e gift <strong>of</strong> ever new beginning yet to come is always a gift <strong>of</strong><br />

eternity <strong>of</strong> future, a gift <strong>of</strong> remaining and redemption. Th e gift <strong>of</strong><br />

time must keep—how to keep the gift <strong>of</strong> time—the remembrance<br />

<strong>of</strong> this gift and the remembrance <strong>of</strong> its task, that <strong>of</strong> the task <strong>of</strong><br />

remembering the immemorial. But this remembrance through<br />

which ever new beginning is renewed in thinking, in acting, in our<br />

historical labour and through our historical-discursive formation, is<br />

a remembrance that is not <strong>of</strong> mere past, therefore not a recollection,<br />

but renewal in presence unto the eternity <strong>of</strong> future. Th is means: there


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 91<br />

must be a remembrance <strong>of</strong> which is not yet remembered and has not yet<br />

passed through ‘the gallery <strong>of</strong> images’, a remembrance that arrives only<br />

at the cost <strong>of</strong> an essential ‘peril <strong>of</strong> being’ to which beings are exposed<br />

and which releases these being from the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence.<br />

We forget this future in our absorption in ‘the darkness <strong>of</strong> the lived<br />

moment’ (Bloch 2000, p. 276), or in the illusion <strong>of</strong> false eternity,<br />

or in our distraction and drowning in the rumbling monotony <strong>of</strong><br />

presents that pass away unredeemed. Th erefore the task <strong>of</strong> remembrance<br />

claims from this historical mortal being an almost insomniac vigilance<br />

and attention. For the eternity <strong>of</strong> coming to redeem the not yet<br />

redeemed, it is necessary that each single instance <strong>of</strong> the beginning<br />

is wholly otherwise beginning, wholly opening towards outside,<br />

hollowing inside out, voiding the being <strong>of</strong> our being so that in the<br />

pure nakedness <strong>of</strong> exposure, the other may burst forth. Th ere alone,<br />

melancholic time thickened with the unredeemed past, sees the light<br />

coming from wholly other destination and is endowed with eternity.<br />

Th is wholly otherwise destination cannot be subordinated to any ideology<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nalism in the form <strong>of</strong> teleology or eschatology. Th is eternity, this<br />

transcendence comes from the incalculable, non-teleological future<br />

which is not the future as one <strong>of</strong> the modes <strong>of</strong> temporality, but<br />

the Moment that illuminates the entirety <strong>of</strong> existence and redeems<br />

time endowing it with the stamp <strong>of</strong> eternity. Th e Moment is the<br />

incalculable advent <strong>of</strong> the future, <strong>of</strong> transcendence bursting into that<br />

seizes the mortal, historical existence. Th en ‘all that is solid melts<br />

into air’ (Marx & Engels 2002, p. 70) . Th e Moment is the moment<br />

<strong>of</strong> fear and trembling, when mortality claims upon our solidifi ed<br />

foundation. Such a moment can be called ‘revolution’, which is the<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> coming and perishing united in a ‘monstrous coupling’.<br />

It is the possible, the category <strong>of</strong> which is pr<strong>of</strong>ounder, vaster than<br />

anything that is presently given, is a form <strong>of</strong> eternity. ‘Th us understood’,<br />

writes Kierkegaard, ‘the moment is not properly an atom <strong>of</strong> time,<br />

but an atom <strong>of</strong> eternity. It is the fi rst refl ection <strong>of</strong> eternity in time,<br />

its fi rst attempt, as it were, at the stopping time’ (Kierkegaard 1980,<br />

p. 88). At the time <strong>of</strong> revolution, which is the time without time,<br />

because it is the demonic coupling <strong>of</strong> the beginning <strong>of</strong> time and end<br />

<strong>of</strong> time simultaneously, time itself, as if, stops dead, and assumes the<br />

stillness <strong>of</strong> an eternity. Th e future from wholly otherwise destination<br />

bursts forth, and bursts into the concentrated thickness <strong>of</strong> presence,


92 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and tears apart any closure <strong>of</strong> immanent self-presence. Th e mortals<br />

experience this form <strong>of</strong> eternity as death, as an excess that strikes<br />

with violence without violence, when the moment becomes the site<br />

<strong>of</strong> monstrosity. Th e entirety <strong>of</strong> time is then experienced at this single<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> revolution when the whole <strong>of</strong> history presents itself in<br />

a Darstellung where the unapparent advents. Such a moment is the<br />

moment <strong>of</strong>, what Hölderlin speaks as ‘becoming in dissolution’ when<br />

the disappearing <strong>of</strong> the fugitive gods and the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming<br />

Holy is experienced with a joyous mourning. Th is becomes possible<br />

because interruption has opened it, prepared it to the coming <strong>of</strong><br />

the otherwise, and to the arriving <strong>of</strong> transcendence in astonishment<br />

that transfi gures and redeems all that has been into the coming by<br />

delivering all that is solid into the peril <strong>of</strong> its being. Mortals receive<br />

this guest <strong>of</strong> eternity in a hospitality attuned to a pure seizure, to a<br />

fear and trembling.<br />

Th e bursting <strong>of</strong> eternity <strong>of</strong> future into presence, because it is<br />

experienced as a kind <strong>of</strong> violence (without violence), it is the peril<br />

<strong>of</strong> the voyage, more perilous than any others, but there also lies<br />

its saving grace, its redemption. Th e faint murmur <strong>of</strong> the coming<br />

redemption is not alien to the tearing apart <strong>of</strong> the present; likewise<br />

the becoming is not alien to perishing. In the opening voyage lies<br />

an opening to the unpredictability and the incalculability <strong>of</strong> the<br />

inception. Inception incepts, not the lifeless and harmless pure<br />

Being <strong>of</strong> empty generation which Hegelian logic dramatizes, but a<br />

coming in astonishment and wonder, in ecstasy and tearing apart,<br />

a sundering inside out. Inception is an exposure to the thunders<br />

and lightning that also bring coming murmurs <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th is<br />

tearing apart and exposing to the coming is also an interruption,<br />

but an interruption that requires ever new beginning, ever renewed<br />

voyage on the open sea. Interruption is not blockade <strong>of</strong> the ever-new<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> inception and <strong>of</strong> ever renewed voyage, but that delivers<br />

and exposes the ship to the demonic weather <strong>of</strong> the beyond. Th ere<br />

lies the gift <strong>of</strong> time that rendering the origin into a remnant to come,<br />

endows the voyage with the gift <strong>of</strong> eternity.<br />

With it, as if, time itself begins anew. Th is beginning <strong>of</strong> time<br />

is caesural. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> this beginning <strong>of</strong> time is inseparable<br />

from the anguish <strong>of</strong> disjunction and suff erings <strong>of</strong> waiting. With the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> ever new inception <strong>of</strong> time through cision and caesura,


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 93<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> eternity is itself inseparable. In these moments fi nite<br />

beings partake <strong>of</strong> the eternity <strong>of</strong> time, and shares in the divine excess.<br />

Th e future arrives, eternity bursts into, and there comes redemption<br />

in lightning fl ashes. Th is promise is granted to man only on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> his perilous exposure to his mortality, only when man opens his<br />

soul to eternity in anguish <strong>of</strong> his mortal condition.<br />

One, who learns to wait, also learns to hope.<br />

Madness<br />

If the energy <strong>of</strong> thinking is not saturated and exhausted in mere<br />

clarifi cation <strong>of</strong> the given world, or phenomenon that are presently<br />

come, cognized and grasped, but to expose to the event <strong>of</strong> coming to<br />

the presence <strong>of</strong> the world and thereby venturing beyond the already<br />

given, then this venturing must be irreducible to the immobile,<br />

vacant, theoretical gaze <strong>of</strong> the philosopher and <strong>of</strong> the sober, sterile<br />

scholar who petrifi es the event <strong>of</strong> truth unto mediated determinations<br />

or categorical cognition. Such a theoretical thinker and sober scholar,<br />

who are never touched by the divine madness and creative ecstasy,<br />

can only see what has been presently given state <strong>of</strong> the aff airs <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. Aristotle speaks <strong>of</strong> certain people whose greatness is constantly<br />

touched by certain madness, albeit regulated, for such a joyous, divine<br />

look sees what is not yet given but that constantly lies as the light<br />

and warmth <strong>of</strong> future within the womb <strong>of</strong> the dark presence that is<br />

opaque to itself, not because <strong>of</strong> its lack <strong>of</strong> presence, but precisely due<br />

to the excess <strong>of</strong> presencing in it. It is the light that the present does<br />

not contain within itself as the self-contained form, but that threatens<br />

to burst forth from within as the light <strong>of</strong> grace that escapes the force<br />

<strong>of</strong> gravity. Th e seeing that sees the future in matter, the infi nity in the<br />

fi nite and the eternity <strong>of</strong> the Moment in each his et nunc is touched<br />

by the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> existence coming to presencing, because in such a<br />

look there appears the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong> coming, the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> future, the infi nite appearing in the fi nite as a kind <strong>of</strong> excess, as<br />

a kind <strong>of</strong> non-economic <strong>of</strong>f ering or as a sublime gift, immeasurable<br />

in itself precisely because it gives the measure its ‘measure-ness’.<br />

Th e phenomenology <strong>of</strong> excess which such a seeing calls forth is a<br />

phenomenology <strong>of</strong> pure donation where the excess <strong>of</strong> the invisible<br />

incessantly exposes the domain <strong>of</strong> the visible from the immanence


94 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-presence to what is incomprehensible and unfathomable yet<br />

which alone grants us the gleam <strong>of</strong> life. For such a phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

excess language is not an expression <strong>of</strong> conceptual thought, nor mere<br />

exteriorization <strong>of</strong> the interior, nor is it a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> spirit<br />

coming to the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness. It is rather exposure<br />

to the excess <strong>of</strong> the gift which the incomprehensible generously and<br />

exuberantly grants us so that the invisible and unapparent may comes<br />

to presence here and now.<br />

Schelling works towards such an unheard phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

excess that while opening us to being and truth conceals itself. ‘<br />

whoever has to some extent’ says Schelling, ‘exercised their eye for the<br />

spiritual contemplation <strong>of</strong> natural things knows that a spiritual image<br />

whose mere vessel is the coarse and ponderable, is actually what is<br />

living within the coarse and ponderable. Th e purer the image is, the<br />

healthier the whole is. Th is incomprehensible but not imperceptible<br />

being, always ready to overfl ow and yet always held again, and which<br />

alone grants to all things the full charm, glint and gleam <strong>of</strong> life, is<br />

that which is at the same time most manifest and most concealed.<br />

Because it only shows itself amidst a constant mutability, it draws<br />

all the more as the glimpse <strong>of</strong> the actual being that lies concealed<br />

within all things <strong>of</strong> the world and which simply awaits its liberation’<br />

(Schelling 2000, pp. 61-2) . Th e world for such an ecstatic, poetic<br />

look is not yet a fi nished world, for the promise <strong>of</strong> its coming is not<br />

yet over, the world has not yet completely become. Th e world appears<br />

rather as pure donation wherein the enigma <strong>of</strong> manifestation is not<br />

yet saturated. Th is phenomenon <strong>of</strong> manifestation is not the manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a phenomenon that can be measured by cognitive categories, for what<br />

manifests is the excess itself, the excess <strong>of</strong> manifestation as such. Such<br />

a look can be called an utopian look, in the sense <strong>of</strong> ‘utopia’ that<br />

is without ‘topia’, without ‘topos’, a topos that has not yet been<br />

determined as ‘this’ historical place, as ‘this’ geographical territory, as<br />

‘this’ epochal community that is known to us, cognized by us, that<br />

has become the world-historical ‘lived experience’ for us.<br />

For that matter utopian thinking is neither vain thinking, nor<br />

mere fantasizing about a wonderland where everything is beautiful<br />

and harmonious, where being coincides without remainder with its<br />

own time. What is happiness if not being’s unity to its own time? If<br />

one still retains the notion <strong>of</strong> utopia, it is in the sense <strong>of</strong> a messianic


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 95<br />

promise where the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the coming is in-dissociably<br />

bound up with the intensity <strong>of</strong> the here and now, where the plenitude<br />

and the bursting <strong>of</strong> here and now is not yet fi nished, cognized, grasped<br />

at any given present instant. Th e Moment <strong>of</strong> here and now would<br />

appear then not as presently appearing instant that is destined to pass<br />

away in a successive manner, but as a non-saturated excess which brings<br />

into its gift a donation <strong>of</strong> its own inexhaustive infi nity, its own future.<br />

Th is is a future in each here and now: a kind <strong>of</strong> excess <strong>of</strong> the world, a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> ecstasy <strong>of</strong> time, a kind <strong>of</strong> vertigo <strong>of</strong> phenomenon, a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

‘dream <strong>of</strong> the matter’ as Marx says, or a sort <strong>of</strong> a madness <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

Th is madness is not annihilation <strong>of</strong> reason but what sustains and<br />

nourishes reason. Th is future is not an annulment <strong>of</strong> here and now,<br />

but what bestows upon each here and now the poetry <strong>of</strong> plenitude, the<br />

darkness <strong>of</strong> the Moment, the excess <strong>of</strong> presencing over each and every<br />

given presence. It is ebullience <strong>of</strong> future, an emblem <strong>of</strong> eternity, a kiss<br />

<strong>of</strong> joy. Th e poet-thinker’s task, which is not dissociable from certain<br />

ecstasy (because it is constantly solicited to a certain madness, unlike<br />

the imbecile theoretician and the sterile scholar), is to see the future<br />

in each here and now, to see the eternity <strong>of</strong> the Moment that suddenly<br />

arrives, to dream ‘the dream <strong>of</strong> the matter’, to release the writhing<br />

soul animating the form <strong>of</strong> things. Th erefore a kind <strong>of</strong> vertigo or even<br />

madness adheres to the poet thinker’s very existence, seizing his soul<br />

to its innermost depth that fi rst dispossessing him, depriving him <strong>of</strong><br />

himself, bestows upon him the creative word, his poetic saying. It is<br />

the ‘divine madness’ that enraptures the poet, because this ‘divine<br />

madness’ releases him unto the open where the eternity appears to<br />

him with a mark <strong>of</strong> happiness.<br />

In all essential thinking that does not seek to annihilate the<br />

phenomenality <strong>of</strong> phenomenon or to damage phenomenon with<br />

its death like cognition is constantly solicited to a certain madness,<br />

which is a solicitation to the unthought, to a radical exteriority, to an<br />

essential solitude that mortality bestows upon thinking. Th e solitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> such a dream, utopian, is not a self-enclosed consciousness shut<br />

within its self-consuming immanence. Solitude, in that sense, is that<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> being exposed to the not yet, as an essential moment <strong>of</strong><br />

peril <strong>of</strong> the given state <strong>of</strong> consciousness and which is not yet shared<br />

within the given world <strong>of</strong> generality. Such a thinking will be called<br />

fi nite thinking, a fi nite thinking where fi nitude and thinking are not


96 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

in accidental relationship, but rather a thinking that is, essentially,<br />

inextricably fi nite. Th inking that is not touched by a certain solicitation<br />

to madness, to its radical exteriority and to the unthinkable is<br />

satisfi ed with the mere sterile cognition <strong>of</strong> the presently given world,<br />

or phenomenon. It does not know the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the exuberant<br />

future latent in phenomena and existence, the writhing reason in<br />

existence that seeks its coming into existence out <strong>of</strong> a non-reason, the<br />

unapparent in all that is apparent, ‘the invisible remainder’ in all that<br />

is visible. Like poets, Schelling says, ‘also the philosophers have their<br />

ecstasy. Th ey need this in order to be safe, through the feeling <strong>of</strong> the<br />

indescribable reality <strong>of</strong> that higher representation, against the coerced<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> an empty dialectic that lacks enthusiasm’ (Schelling<br />

2000, p. xxxviii). Unlike the theoretical and sterile cognition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

scholar untouched by madness, a poet-thinker is like a pregnant<br />

woman who bears the future in her womb, the exuberant future<br />

whose transcendence is not fi xed in the monotonous, immobile gaze<br />

<strong>of</strong> the theoretician. Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> this sterile intellectual as the<br />

one in which:<br />

[T]here is no madness whatsoever. Th ese would be the uncreative<br />

people incapable <strong>of</strong> procreation, the ones that call themselves sober<br />

spirits. Th ese are the so called intellectuals whose works and deeds<br />

are nothing but cold intellectuals works and intellectual deeds…<br />

but where there is no madness, there is certainly no proper, active,<br />

living intellect (and consequently there is just the dead intellect, dead<br />

intellectuals). (Ibid., p.103)<br />

Th e moment here and now is like this pregnant woman. Each<br />

apparition carries its invisible, dark source that renders the remote<br />

future nearer to nearness, and its nearness to itself distant than any<br />

distance. Not only the poet but even a thinker has a relation to<br />

certain joyous madness, for an essential thinker sees not only what<br />

has arrived, but the arrived that is pregnant with the unborn, the light<br />

that is dark now—not with lack <strong>of</strong> presence, but due to the excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> presencing over the present. But a sterile scholar and an imbecile<br />

theoretician who is not solicited to vertigo <strong>of</strong> the unthought, to the<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> madness, or to pregnancy <strong>of</strong> exteriority, can only produce<br />

logical categories that can grasp in a reductive totalizing manner<br />

only what is amenable to logical thought, namely, the entities that


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 97<br />

has become. Th erefore logic gives the theoretical philosopher certain<br />

pretension to totality, or system <strong>of</strong> visible forms. Since such totality,<br />

or system seeks to include all that has become and presently given,<br />

such totality can only be the most banal, most sterile totality without<br />

ecstasy, without transcendence. It must not know, for that matter,<br />

the exuberant future <strong>of</strong> each here and now, the bursting Moment<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity that overfl ows the cup <strong>of</strong> time, the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the leap<br />

that steps outside the totality <strong>of</strong> visible forms, that ‘the dream <strong>of</strong> the<br />

matter’ which is not mere inert material malleable to the concept.<br />

Th e invisible poesy <strong>of</strong> the future which each here and now bears in<br />

its dream has a diff erent logic <strong>of</strong> origin, a logic that is touched by a<br />

constant solicitation to its inscrutable ground, to the madness <strong>of</strong> an<br />

unthinkable, to the exuberant future, to the unapparent apparition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming that is promised in it at the inception.<br />

Th is logic <strong>of</strong> origin has a diff erent logic than the logical origin<br />

<strong>of</strong> concepts that generate their own end and beginning. Each here<br />

and now carries the dream <strong>of</strong> its messianic completion that is outside<br />

time, in a certain sense, in that it does not belong to the time that<br />

is presently given. Th erefore a fi nite thinking is a contemplation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the timeless promise, not in the sense <strong>of</strong> the endlessness <strong>of</strong> time<br />

that is the infi nite lengthening <strong>of</strong> a homogenous instant, nor in the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> the pure void <strong>of</strong> time, but the coming <strong>of</strong> time itself and its<br />

completion, which for that matter, strikes the mortals as eternity.<br />

Such an eternity that attunes us with a beatifi c joy is not a dialectical<br />

time <strong>of</strong> history, nor the mythic time <strong>of</strong> the a-historical, nor is it selfpositing<br />

thetic time <strong>of</strong> the logical. Neither dialectical time <strong>of</strong> history<br />

nor mythic-tragic time without time, nor self-positing thetic time <strong>of</strong><br />

logic brings us joy and happiness and give us hope, for each <strong>of</strong> them<br />

is only cognition <strong>of</strong> presently given entities. As Schelling (Ibid., p.42)<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> joy that only future brings, the pure future without any<br />

reduction to self-presence, so only a time that in a messianic hope<br />

anticipates at each here and now and renews the promise <strong>of</strong> inception<br />

and completion can make us joyous, because such an eternity alone<br />

is an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future at each hic et nunc, at each presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence, at each appearing <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. At each hic et nunc<br />

there must arrive a future, at each presentation <strong>of</strong> presence there must<br />

arrive an arrival. Each here and now is eternal and at once radically<br />

fi nite. Its apparition is sudden advent, like a lightning fl ash, in the


98 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

most immediately ordinary here and now that illumines our existence,<br />

because therein eternity itself presents itself in its arrival. We are then<br />

open to eternity, mortal and fi nite that we are. Such an eternity can<br />

only be a fi nite eternity, and so its illumination: it disrupts itself,<br />

interrupts itself, suspends itself in its advent so that its recalcitrant<br />

apparition escapes the vacant gaze <strong>of</strong> the logical-dialectical thinker,<br />

his logical categories, and his predicative concepts, however their<br />

claim for mobility may be.<br />

Th e apparition <strong>of</strong> fi nitude that strikes the mortals with a silence, and<br />

escapes the categories <strong>of</strong> the logical thinker, is the interest <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

according to Constantine Constantius. Th e fi nitude is the interest<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence, if not the interest <strong>of</strong> a logic (even if it is for Hegelian<br />

speculative version <strong>of</strong> it), for this logical movement is only an<br />

immanent movement, and therefore does not suff er fi nitude, for<br />

what at stake in suff ering is this not-being-able-to-remain immanent,<br />

this not-being-able-to-be, this outside <strong>of</strong> itself that writhes in agony<br />

and cannot contain within itself its own movement. All actual<br />

movement begins with pain and suff ering, and not with the lifeless,<br />

dull logical category <strong>of</strong> beginning that begins with the immediate.<br />

It is in this sense one can say that logic does not know suff ering<br />

which is the interest <strong>of</strong> existence, in the sense that Franz Rosenzweig<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> philosophy that philosophy does not know mortality. Th e<br />

logical movement is a false movement; it does not begin with the<br />

actual, real beginning—that is, with suff erings <strong>of</strong> mortality, with<br />

the transcendence <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, with the agony <strong>of</strong> a beginning. Th e<br />

agony <strong>of</strong> the beginning is the agony <strong>of</strong> thought’s inability to begin<br />

with itself, its inability to retrieve its own condition and ground, its<br />

inability to master its own abyss. Th is radical fi nitude <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

renders thinking short <strong>of</strong> any totalization and completion, for this<br />

fi nitude does not exhaustively acquire the visible forms that constitute<br />

totality. It thereby, ineluctably, falls short <strong>of</strong> its absolute and systemic<br />

completion. Suff ering does not have system; only logic can have<br />

systemic completion. Th e vertigo that founders and falters thinking,<br />

this impossibility called madness that watches over thinking, this<br />

ecstasy and agony <strong>of</strong> the beginning shows the fragility <strong>of</strong> thinking,<br />

as if thinking in order to prosper, must constantly negotiate with its<br />

radical impossibility and a madness, which is not a negotiable other<br />

but the non-negotiable itself. Th is eff ort <strong>of</strong> thinking that thinking


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 99<br />

invests its energy in order to begin and to prosper makes all beginning<br />

painful, even despairing. Th is logic <strong>of</strong> origin is <strong>of</strong> a diff erent origin<br />

than the beginning <strong>of</strong> the logical process that simply, harmlessly and<br />

without agony, begins with the immediate which smoothly passes<br />

into the mediation. Th is logic that begins with agony is the logic <strong>of</strong><br />

existence itself to which existence is thrown and is an agonal being.<br />

For the thinking to begin actually and really, that is, fi nitely and<br />

mortally, this fi nitude and mortality must not be the result <strong>of</strong> a logical<br />

process. Th e beginning <strong>of</strong> this movement is the movement that<br />

existence itself makes, <strong>of</strong> its coming into presence. For existence pain<br />

is the interest, the innermost and pr<strong>of</strong>oundest interest <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

for it is in suff ering that existence makes the fi rst, the beginning<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> its coming into presence, and it’s disappearance in death.<br />

Th erefore, in so far as suff ering is concerned, logic founders as soon<br />

as suff ering manifests itself in the existent. Th e apparition <strong>of</strong> suff ering<br />

in existence is not the moment <strong>of</strong> negativity that is again uplifted<br />

(Aufheben) in the universality <strong>of</strong> reconciliation. What manifests as<br />

suff ering in existence is the element that escapes the reconciliatory<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> the speculative-dialectical tragedy.<br />

Th e suff ering one, then, makes another movement <strong>of</strong> beginning<br />

which is irreducible to the movement <strong>of</strong> the speculative. It is the<br />

movement that opens itself to the divine order where cry <strong>of</strong> the<br />

singular being is heard, and where the anguish <strong>of</strong> death is not<br />

vainly consoled in the universal order <strong>of</strong> generality. Referring to<br />

what Constantine Constantius speaks <strong>of</strong> repetition as the interest <strong>of</strong><br />

metaphysics, Vigilius Haufniensis says:<br />

[Th is] sentence contains an allusion to the thesis that metaphysics is<br />

disinterested, as Kant affi rmed <strong>of</strong> aesthetics. As soon as the interest<br />

emerges, metaphysics steps to one side. For this reason the word<br />

interest is italicized. Th e whole interest <strong>of</strong> subjectivity emerges in real<br />

life, and then metaphysics founders. (Kierkegaard 1957, p.16)<br />

When Constantine Constantius and Vigilius Haufniensis (two <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pseudonyms <strong>of</strong> Kierkegaard) refer to the foundering <strong>of</strong> metaphysics<br />

when repetition becomes the interest <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, they allude to<br />

the element <strong>of</strong> suff ering in existence. Th e manifestation <strong>of</strong> suff ering<br />

mocks at the vain arrogance <strong>of</strong> logic, even if it is the speculative logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hegel that claims to include existence within the visible forms <strong>of</strong> its


100 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

system as a category amongst others. Th e speculative logic founders<br />

and steps outside <strong>of</strong> its vain arrogance when suff ering itself makes<br />

manifest, and when it manifests itself to be completely other than<br />

‘the agony <strong>of</strong> the concept’ 2 . Th e principle <strong>of</strong> logic and the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> metaphysics is the same, which is to say, that the metaphysical<br />

foundation <strong>of</strong> logic is nothing but the principle <strong>of</strong> immanence that<br />

begins itself immanently, that engenders its own beginning and its<br />

own end which Hegel gave the name <strong>of</strong> negativity. It is therefore,<br />

as Franz Rosenzweig complains that nothing really dies in this<br />

system, for the system does not have a place for death, for death<br />

can only be a presupposition for that system, death that is outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic. Th e language <strong>of</strong> death is not the language <strong>of</strong> logic: the tremor<br />

<strong>of</strong> mortality, its trembling and its cry, its anguish and its abyss is<br />

excluded by the language <strong>of</strong> logic, that <strong>of</strong> predication and negativity<br />

in a necessary gesture, for otherwise it would not be able to engender<br />

its own beginning and its own end, it would not be immanent. It<br />

is the interest for the system, for the necessity <strong>of</strong> its possibility and<br />

constitution, necessity for its own genesis and raison d’art, that it can<br />

only be interested in disinterest, that is, ‘ in the agony <strong>of</strong> the concept’.<br />

For this matter Hegel’s Science <strong>of</strong> Logic does not have to begin with<br />

suff ering and mortality. It does not have to be shaken in its innermost<br />

depth by the tremor <strong>of</strong> mortality. It does not have to founder in<br />

the yawning abyss. Th erefore Hegel’s Science <strong>of</strong> Logic has to begin its<br />

movement, conceptually, with pure Being and pure Nothing and not<br />

with its presupposition which is the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> suff ering before<br />

death. Here it is claimed that nothing is presupposed at this instant<br />

<strong>of</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> the system—neither mortality nor birth—which<br />

what Hegel calls ‘Immediate’ that immediately annuls itself into its<br />

opposite. In the beginning <strong>of</strong> his Science <strong>of</strong> Logic, Hegel says,<br />

Pure Being and pure Nothing are, therefore, the same. What is the truth<br />

is neither being nor nothing, but that being does not pass over—but<br />

has passed over into nothing, and nothing into being. (Hegel 1969,<br />

p 82)<br />

It is this appearing and pure passing away into the anonymity <strong>of</strong><br />

the eternally homogenous Now, the eternally immobile mobility,<br />

eternally restless rest that is without ecstatic transcendence and<br />

without future that Hegelian logic calls movement which begins with


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 101<br />

nothing, for it begins only with itself, and ends with nothing, for<br />

it ends only with itself. In this way the presuppositional element <strong>of</strong><br />

existence, i.e., its anguish before death is already here foreclosed in<br />

this dialectical logic <strong>of</strong> visible forms.<br />

Th e actual beginning begins with something else, and therefore<br />

has its presupposition, its ground and condition outside <strong>of</strong> it. Such<br />

a reason presupposes the agony <strong>of</strong> a non-reason out <strong>of</strong> which it<br />

emerges. Reason is essentially fi nite; it belongs to a fi nitude which<br />

it presupposes. Such a beginning is actual beginning, for coming<br />

into existence implies its fi nitude and its transcendence, its relation<br />

to an outside which is outside <strong>of</strong> the totality <strong>of</strong> visible forms and<br />

outside any system <strong>of</strong> relations. Such an actual beginning is a nonconceptual<br />

beginning which cannot be included within any logical<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> presupposition-less totality.<br />

Th is beginning, which Schelling calls ‘actuality’ as distinguished<br />

from Hegelian beginning as mere logical, immanent and potential<br />

beginning, bears the peculiar fate, i.e., the fate <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, which is<br />

this: this beginning has a relation to that which is without relation,<br />

a beginning that has already begun before this beginning, a condition<br />

which is without condition, a ground which is without ground and<br />

without foundation. Th e time <strong>of</strong> this beginning is in relation to a<br />

time that is outside time, which is to say, an immemorial past which<br />

can only be presupposed, and cannot be thought within the logical<br />

system <strong>of</strong> visible forms. Th is abyss <strong>of</strong> mortality that adheres into each<br />

coming into existence bears the trace <strong>of</strong> its tremor, as a kind <strong>of</strong> eternal<br />

remnant, or as ‘irreducible remainder’, in the existence itself. Each<br />

here and now, then, carries the remnant <strong>of</strong> the eternal, immemorial<br />

past that has already always become an abyss, irreducible to any<br />

concept or name.<br />

Th e agony <strong>of</strong> fi nitude is the very interest <strong>of</strong> existence and not<br />

mere logical category. Th is trace <strong>of</strong> mortality, this eternal remnant<br />

<strong>of</strong> a beginning before beginning, this anguish and suff ering <strong>of</strong> a<br />

coming, this irreducible remainder <strong>of</strong> cision is what exceeds the<br />

language <strong>of</strong> predication, which is that <strong>of</strong> logic and metaphysics.<br />

Since this ‘irreducible remainder’ carries the immemorial beginning<br />

in each presentation <strong>of</strong> presence as what is outside <strong>of</strong> it, as what<br />

is transcendent to it, as what is past <strong>of</strong> presence, there remains an


102 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> beginning, which is in a sense eternal, because it<br />

does not come to pass. It is this possibility <strong>of</strong> an outside <strong>of</strong> presence,<br />

<strong>of</strong> a transcendence to each presentation <strong>of</strong> presence, but in a certain<br />

way, heterogeneously co-existing with presence, that makes possible<br />

something like time to manifest itself. Th e apparition <strong>of</strong> time timing<br />

itself cannot be thought within the phenomenological ontology <strong>of</strong><br />

visible forms. Th is heterogeneous remnant and eternal remainder is<br />

not a mere passed past, because it does not immediately pass into<br />

becoming. As the eternal beginning, it is also ahead <strong>of</strong> itself and as<br />

such it is the eternally coming to be beginning in future, a beginning<br />

yet to come, a past yet to come. Th is beginning is not the pure,<br />

indeterminate being which is equal to nothing, but a principle <strong>of</strong><br />

possibility that has the potentiality to inaugurate itself anew. Each<br />

moment, each presenting <strong>of</strong> presence is a coming that is irreducible<br />

to this or that coming. It is rather a coming as inauguration which<br />

opens the world and time for the fi rst time, and as such it is a<br />

beginning before beginning and future after the last future. We call<br />

them ‘eternal’ beginning and ‘eternal future’.<br />

Th erefore past, presence, future are not particular modalities, points<br />

and successive instants belonging to the homogenous scale <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Now <strong>of</strong> eternity, where each instance <strong>of</strong> now generates automatically<br />

and successively, progressively its own successor in such a logical<br />

manner that they need nothing <strong>of</strong> the transcendence <strong>of</strong> coming. Th ese<br />

successive, auto-generating instants that presuppose nothing would<br />

then form a logical system, because these homogenous nows would<br />

belong to the universality and generality <strong>of</strong> One, Same Now. But the<br />

ecstatic coming <strong>of</strong> the eternal future, past and presence, in so far as<br />

each is coming to presence (that overfl ows each instants <strong>of</strong> presence),<br />

is the constellation <strong>of</strong> ‘the ecstasies <strong>of</strong> temporalities’. Each coming is<br />

ecstatic in its ahead-ness <strong>of</strong> itself, since each coming carries its ecstatic<br />

transcendence that does not belong to the universality <strong>of</strong> cognition<br />

and predication, for they do not form totality <strong>of</strong> visible, categorical<br />

forms. Th ey rather move in a confi guration, or constellation <strong>of</strong><br />

ecstasies, that in their sudden apparition as co-fi guring, announces,<br />

heralds the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming. Th e Moment is the fi gure (which is<br />

also a dis-fi guring) <strong>of</strong> this eternity when the eternity <strong>of</strong> past, presence,<br />

future come together, co-fi gures that can happen suddenly in any<br />

here and now, which momentarily make history pause. In this silence


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 103<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pause the beginning is remembered as a remembrance yet to<br />

begin. Th e moment is not the fi gure called ‘instant’, therefore not<br />

a fi gure <strong>of</strong> time, but ‘an atom <strong>of</strong> eternity’, as Kierkegaard says <strong>of</strong> it:<br />

Th e moment is not properly an atom <strong>of</strong> time, but an atom <strong>of</strong> eternity.<br />

It is the fi rst refl ection <strong>of</strong> eternity in time, its fi rst attempt, as it were,<br />

at stopping time. (Kierkegaard 1980, p. 88)<br />

A fi nite thinking begins with a beginning that is always a fi nite<br />

opening, but that opens unto the infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the immemorial<br />

and the incalculable pure future. A logical thinking that constitutes<br />

the dominant metaphysics also claims to begin with the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> beginning, but it is a false beginning. It is what Schelling speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hegel as, only a potential beginning, and not- actual, real<br />

beginning, for the actual beginning to come, this beginning has to<br />

be thought outside immanence, which logic does not permit us to<br />

think, by a necessary reason internal to the logic <strong>of</strong> this logic itself.<br />

Th erefore it is necessary to put into question the sovereign claims <strong>of</strong><br />

the logic whose metaphysical foundation presupposes, in advance,<br />

as its necessary condition, an abyss which is none but mortality<br />

itself that grants in advance to mortals a time to come. Because<br />

this mortality is not the interest <strong>of</strong> this metaphysics, metaphysics is<br />

therefore not interested in redemption, for redemption is the interest<br />

only for the mortal existence which is singular (therefore cannot<br />

be included into the system <strong>of</strong> visible forms), and not for a logical<br />

concept. Logical concept does not need redemption or promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming time, because it claims to have already mastered death.<br />

But a mortal existence whose existence lies in the non-mastery <strong>of</strong><br />

death, this question <strong>of</strong> redemption is <strong>of</strong> utmost interest, for such a<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption alone makes sense <strong>of</strong> out politics and our<br />

ethics.<br />

Astonishment<br />

Where and when a beginning is beginning? With what beginning<br />

begins? Hegel’s Science <strong>of</strong> Logic begins with this question <strong>of</strong> beginning,<br />

since Speculative Logic must not presuppose the given-ness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

object <strong>of</strong> thought, and therefore must not presuppose the given-ness<br />

<strong>of</strong> its beginning either. Th e beginning, in so far as it is beginning,


104 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

must not yet be the mediated one—a ‘this’, or a ‘that’—and therefore<br />

is not a determinate one. A non-determinate and non-mediated<br />

beginning can only be ‘Being Pure and Simple’, since with it nothing<br />

is (supposedly) presupposed yet, since Pure Being, irreducible to<br />

any ‘this’ or ‘that’, rather empty <strong>of</strong> any ‘this’ or ‘that’, is equal to<br />

Nothing. With this Hegelian speculative logic claims to begin with<br />

the beginning, presupposing nothing else, for it begins with Nothing<br />

equal to ‘Being Pure and Simple’.<br />

Hegelian speculative logic then begins with Concept—with the<br />

most universal, because emptiest <strong>of</strong> all concepts—the Concept <strong>of</strong><br />

Being pure. Yet Hegelian Speculative Logic does not end there, for<br />

it must move out <strong>of</strong> the beginning <strong>of</strong> the empty Concept <strong>of</strong> Being,<br />

it must give this emptiness itself a movement—<strong>of</strong> negativity—a<br />

generative potentiality. Hence there must emerge out <strong>of</strong> the emptiest<br />

<strong>of</strong> all Concepts the movement, not <strong>of</strong> ‘this’ or ‘that’ coming into<br />

existence, but the movement <strong>of</strong> the movement itself, out <strong>of</strong> the empty<br />

Concept, as if out <strong>of</strong> nothing. With this not only the entirety <strong>of</strong> the<br />

movement character <strong>of</strong> speculative logic is deduced subsequently, but<br />

the coming <strong>of</strong> coming, existence coming to presence is claimed to be<br />

included in the logical system <strong>of</strong> categories and predicates: be-coming<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence becomes predicative by being included as a category <strong>of</strong><br />

categories. Th e whole organic character <strong>of</strong> categories automatically,<br />

in a monotonous manner, generate themselves one after another<br />

in smooth succession—without interruption or cision—leading to<br />

the Absolute Concept, beginning with Nothing and ending with<br />

everything. 3<br />

Were there not already a halt, a cision, a disjunction marks this<br />

beginning if there has to come something into existence at all? In<br />

the Hegelian logical system <strong>of</strong> categories beginning with pure Being<br />

the coming, however, appears only as ineluctably that has to come,<br />

so that in the beginning with the ‘Pure Being and Simple’, nothing<br />

really begins, though according to Hegel’s claim there really comes<br />

something into existence. Would the concept <strong>of</strong> Being itself come<br />

into existence if Being itself is not already a coming? Th erefore<br />

existence is not a concept, but something else entirely which the<br />

concept presupposes? Being here is not really, actually existence in<br />

its existentiality but purely a conceptual construct, a speculative<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> beginning which must be pure, indeterminate being.


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 105<br />

Already then in the beginning with the Concept—for Hegelian logic<br />

can only speak <strong>of</strong> transition, or generation from concept to concept,<br />

and not existence to concept—the beginning itself, a more originary<br />

beginning is missed or is diverted (what Schelling calls ‘Abfall’: falling<br />

away, diverting away) from. Th is unapparent presencing <strong>of</strong> presence,<br />

which is the beginning more originary, is not included within the<br />

speculative system <strong>of</strong> visible forms, for the speculative logic can<br />

only recount that phenomenon that exhaustively presents itself<br />

to the categories. For the speculative system is to be possible, this<br />

unapparent phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the presencing must not be there. Since<br />

in this necessary logic <strong>of</strong> foreclosure nothing coming must come,<br />

nothing really arrives in the logical system <strong>of</strong> movement subsequently<br />

either. Everything comes in this system remains a mere conceptual<br />

coming, only a representation <strong>of</strong> coming.<br />

If the task is to think, not the representation <strong>of</strong> coming, but the<br />

unconditional coming that cannot be predicated, and then thought<br />

itself must be open to the coming, it must already be exposed to<br />

the open region that lies before any predication, or categorical<br />

grasp. Th ere then precedes a coming in the opening that is always<br />

to come (in the infi nitive sense). Th is event <strong>of</strong> coming whose coming<br />

is not yet predicated and grasped in the Concept—for ‘Being Pure<br />

and Simple’ is then appears, what Nietzsche calls the ‘last fume <strong>of</strong><br />

evaporating reality’—is therefore a non-ontological opening, <strong>of</strong> what<br />

Schelling is his Berlin Lectures on Positive Philosophy calls ‘Überseyn’,<br />

over or beyond being. Th e over or beyond being is not an autogenerative<br />

potentiality <strong>of</strong> the Concept as in Hegel, but an actuality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming as the-there-<strong>of</strong>-coming, irreducible to the predicative<br />

proposition, a time to come that began already before the immanent<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> the logical categories. Th e actuality <strong>of</strong> the coming, each<br />

time singular, is irreducible to the subsequent predication <strong>of</strong> it as<br />

essence (for essence only belongs to the order <strong>of</strong> potentiality, and not<br />

the actuality; it belongs to the order <strong>of</strong>: if X exists, then it is so and<br />

so), and is the extra-logical, pre-predicative, pre-categorical leap <strong>of</strong><br />

the event into presence. It is with the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the leap that<br />

marks the cision or disjunction that something actually begins and<br />

not in thought. Th erefore thinking cannot represent this coming into<br />

existence, because a wholly otherwise, a heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> the ‘un-prethinkable’<br />

begins here, as an ecstatic leap <strong>of</strong> the event.


106 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

In his Ages <strong>of</strong> the World (2000), Schelling calls even God’s coming<br />

to presence, or coming to existence as un-pre-thinkable de-cision,<br />

which also means cision, or interruption, event as leap. Th e coming to<br />

presence is an event. Th e event <strong>of</strong> coming is welcomed, received in the<br />

opening that is disclosed, manifested in the eternity <strong>of</strong> the sudden<br />

fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning, in the holding sway <strong>of</strong> the open. It is eternity—not<br />

in the sense <strong>of</strong> pure nothing, or pure void <strong>of</strong> time—but an ecstatic<br />

transcendence <strong>of</strong> time, the condition <strong>of</strong> time as the beginning <strong>of</strong><br />

time, the timing <strong>of</strong> temporalities. Th is beginning is before beginning,<br />

an immemorial passivity genesis where there occurs bestowal, a pure<br />

giving, and a gift <strong>of</strong> time upon the mortals, the gift <strong>of</strong> existing itself<br />

as mortals. Th is beginning is always an eternal beginning, in a certain<br />

sense, without which there begins nothing and there nothing arrives;<br />

in other words, the beginning is already always disjunctive and<br />

caesural where the beginning falls outside as ground or condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> what comes to be this historical world, this mortal existence, this<br />

fi nite presence. Th ere is beginning in the sense that the beginning<br />

that opens the historical world itself does not wholly belong to that<br />

historical world only because it is the beginning <strong>of</strong> the world. Th is<br />

‘un-pre-thinkable’ beginning which is stronger than the world elicits<br />

from us astonishment or wonder. Plato calls this experience <strong>of</strong> the<br />

origin as ‘Wonder’ in Th eatetus with which thinking itself is opened<br />

in the opening, welcoming the event <strong>of</strong> arrival.<br />

If philosophical thinking gives itself the task <strong>of</strong> thinking its own<br />

beginning, then it is with the question fi nitude, the un-conditional<br />

opening—and not beginning with ‘Being pure and Simple’—that<br />

thinking must begin if thinking is not to be mere logical-speculative<br />

thought but actual existential opening to the coming. Such an<br />

existence-thinking begins as this ecstatic astonishment at the origin,<br />

which is less because it is a logical generation out <strong>of</strong> the barren womb<br />

<strong>of</strong> Concept, but because it is exposure <strong>of</strong> thought to the-there-<strong>of</strong>the-coming<br />

that is stronger than the concept or language. It is rather<br />

the astonishment at the enigma <strong>of</strong> coming and existence arriving to<br />

presence. Th e-there-<strong>of</strong>-the-coming is not already accomplished form<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence, but an already that is yet to come and yet to-be-visible.<br />

As such existence, each time occurring, is an event. Th is event marks<br />

the wound <strong>of</strong> mortality, and bears an originary tremor that precedes<br />

either Being or its opposite, the negativity <strong>of</strong> Nothing. Th en there


Th e Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin • 107<br />

comes necessity <strong>of</strong> thinking neither the event which is neither Being,<br />

nor its negativity, but a coming into existence which is otherwise than<br />

Being, and otherwise than Negativity.<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> coming is not grasped in the dialectical-historical<br />

memorial task, for it refuses the gathering unity <strong>of</strong> the innermost<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> memory. Th e event does not have the logical principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> identity as the ground <strong>of</strong> recollection. Th erefore the dialecticalhistorical<br />

memory cannot discover its own inscrutable, unfathomable<br />

ground. Such an inscrutable, unfathomable ground attunes us with<br />

astonishment at the ‘un-pre-thinkable’ coming to presence out <strong>of</strong><br />

unground. In that inscrutable opening, darkness and light play together<br />

as agonal elements in an eternal strife. It is in that open space the<br />

withdrawal <strong>of</strong> the ground and pure <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> time upon mortals play<br />

their originary polemos. Th is co-fi guration, in so far as it is indissociable<br />

from dis-fi guration at the momentary presentation <strong>of</strong> itself, like the<br />

lightning fl ash, it therefore refuses to form a system, or totality. Martin<br />

Heidegger attempts to think this originary confi guration—which is<br />

non-dialectical, diff erential play <strong>of</strong> oblivion and remembrance—as<br />

a polemos <strong>of</strong> unconcealment and concealment. Th is originary play,<br />

this originary polemos that Heraclitus alludes to is withdrawal <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ground and pure giving (through this very withdrawal) that keeps<br />

open history towards its own outside, towards its own epochal<br />

ruptures. Th ese epochal ruptures refuse to be incorporated into the<br />

logical-speculative principle <strong>of</strong> identity and therefore they do not<br />

belong to the universal history. Th e event is to be thought as a far<br />

more originary eruption <strong>of</strong> history into presence, as keeping open<br />

to the Possible, keeping open to the transcendence <strong>of</strong> mortality. An<br />

anticipative thinking <strong>of</strong> redemption is not therefore a-historical but<br />

precisely more historical than any history or historicism, for it alone<br />

anticipates—in hope or in astonishment—the event <strong>of</strong> coming that<br />

alone opens history to itself to come and opens history itself to the<br />

happiness <strong>of</strong> its fulfi llment.


§ Repetition<br />

Repetition and Recollection<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> repetition is as old as philosophy itself. One<br />

remembers Plato’s notion <strong>of</strong> anamnesis, recollection that the<br />

mortal is endowed with as a gift. Extending beyond any time <strong>of</strong><br />

self-presence and even before birth, anamnesis opens the mortal<br />

existence to the immemorial, to the already always there. As if<br />

there is in man something essential, according to this conception,<br />

something primordial given in an originary manner which he is not<br />

the originator nor the ground <strong>of</strong> its subsistence, as if, as it were, the<br />

beginning <strong>of</strong> his beginning is not his beginning, that it has a destinal<br />

inauguration, or destiny <strong>of</strong> inauguration elsewhere whose past and<br />

futurity lies beyond recuperation in self-presence. Here the mortal<br />

appears to be a passage <strong>of</strong> traversal where the invisible infi nitely passes<br />

through the visible, eternity infi nitely crosses through the fi nitude,<br />

and unapparent infi nitely touches the apparent. Man is the spacing <strong>of</strong><br />

the undecidable between the visible and the invisible, the play space<br />

where the visible strives itself with the invisible interminably, where<br />

the eternity never ceases wounding the fi nite existence in its fl esh<br />

like a thorn. Recollection will then appear like repetition. It is the<br />

repetition <strong>of</strong> the unapparent in the apparent, invisible in the visible,<br />

an already always in each hic et nunc as an excess, as an unsaturated<br />

apparition which no eidetic phenomenology ever can thematize in<br />

categorical cognition. It is this that makes repetition an inexhaustible<br />

movement, for it bears away in its advent its own transcendence, and


Repetition • 109<br />

makes, each time there happens repetition, unsaturated, excessive,<br />

overfl owing the cup <strong>of</strong> self-presence.<br />

Man is then not the phenomenon that is saturated in relation to<br />

his own destinal inauguration and telos. He is only the passage <strong>of</strong> hic<br />

et nunc, the movement in-between where the immemorial something<br />

manifests itself, the unapparent appears, the invisible thickens the<br />

visible. To recollect, then, would not mean anything like ‘learning’,<br />

or ‘acquiring knowledge’. It is rather the movement that welcomes<br />

the transcendence in immanence, the outside in each hic et nunc, the<br />

unapparent in the apparent, and the unnamable in the name. To exist<br />

in this fi nite manner doesn’t mean to be enclosed and to be saturated<br />

in the fi nitude. It is rather to repeat, at each hic et nunc what befalls<br />

as transcendence, the unapparent and the destinal occlusion. It is to<br />

bear the immemorial given in our past in each present moment as<br />

promise. It is to welcome the coming what has already always come<br />

immemorially without having passed by, and would never ceasing<br />

coming to us from the extremity <strong>of</strong> a radical futurity. Th e movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> this welcoming is the movement <strong>of</strong> anamnesis, <strong>of</strong> recollection.<br />

Søren Kierkegaard in his work called Repetition distinguishes the<br />

Platonic anamnesis which is oriented to the immemorial past from<br />

repetition in future, determining anamnesis and repetition as two fold<br />

symmetrical tasks: one extending to the already always, and the other<br />

extending to the not yet. Yet it is the Moment, where the truth occurs,<br />

happens, is the monstrous site <strong>of</strong> encounter <strong>of</strong> the unapparent<br />

apparition, invisible visible, occluded revelation, transcendent<br />

immanence. It is that encounter, bursting out <strong>of</strong> any totalization,<br />

that bears itself this infi nite lengthening <strong>of</strong> time towards the already<br />

always and the not yet. As such the Moment, but not instant that is<br />

what Kierkegaard calls ‘atom <strong>of</strong> eternity’, a momentary unsaturated<br />

presentation (as distinguished from representation) <strong>of</strong> eternity. It is at<br />

this moment which repeats the transcendence in immanence, eternity<br />

in time, infi nite in fi nitude, at this moment history pauses and brings<br />

into itself epochal ruptures where something else, an entirely new<br />

and wholly otherwise inaugurates, something else becomes together,<br />

simultaneously with this dissolution. Th is Moment as simultaneity,<br />

for repetition is a simultaneity—as distinguished from ‘succession’<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘homogenous empty instants’ (Benjamin 1977, pp. 251-61)—is


110 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the truth <strong>of</strong> the event when language falls silent not because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

lack <strong>of</strong> speech but with its completed beatitude, in a kind <strong>of</strong> what<br />

Rosenzweig calls ‘completed understanding’. Redemptive fulfi llment<br />

demands the movement <strong>of</strong> repetition, which is to bring together, to<br />

bring into simul which the mortals in the historical unfulfi lled time<br />

<strong>of</strong> negativity only experience as succession <strong>of</strong> instants. Repetition<br />

cannot be thought within the successive representation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

temporal negativity that constitutes dialectical-historical totality.<br />

Repetition is the non-totalized presentation (Darstellung) <strong>of</strong> eternity<br />

as Moment in a kind <strong>of</strong> discontinuous, disjunctive movement <strong>of</strong><br />

confi guration, and is irreducible to the dialectical-historical totality<br />

constituted by the act <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>of</strong> succession <strong>of</strong> continuous,<br />

homogenous instants.<br />

Only the Moment repeats, instants do not repeat themselves.<br />

Th erefore there is no encounter within dialectical-historical<br />

immanent time. It fl ows itself away and arrives as self-same<br />

diff erentiation without redemptive fulfi llment, but never as<br />

discontinuous, disjunctive simultaneity in confi guration. Repetition<br />

is only possible in confi guration, in a non-systematic presentation <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> arrival where there takes place radical encounter with<br />

the wholly otherwise.<br />

Moment<br />

A fi nite thinking that begins with the thinking <strong>of</strong> beginning—the<br />

beginning or inception which is singular and in a certain sense,<br />

eternal—must be able to come again must be able to begin again. Th e<br />

beginning is not the inert, lifeless beginning, lying as never moving<br />

substance, but—since it is fi nite—it must move out <strong>of</strong> itself, out <strong>of</strong> its<br />

self-presence and yet remain as a beginning. Only then the beginning<br />

would be what it is: an ever begun beginning, an always beginning,<br />

and an eternal remainder <strong>of</strong> the beginning. Th erefore, beginning<br />

thought essentially and not in the logical manner <strong>of</strong> beginning,<br />

is a beginning that is at once an ever lasting, always remaining a<br />

beginning, and a beginning that is fi nite. As fi nite, the beginning<br />

disrupts itself, ecstatically suspends itself, and discontinues itself. As<br />

such it presents itself only by perishing itself in this presentation. It


Repetition • 111<br />

is ‘becoming in perishing’ (Hölderlin 1988), arriving in dissolution<br />

that does not persist, and yet persist as remainder <strong>of</strong> the beginning.<br />

It is this aporia <strong>of</strong> beginning that is not lifted up, in Hegel’s word,<br />

sublated into the logical movement, this aporia <strong>of</strong> the fi nite beginning<br />

that is at once infi nite so that mourning and joy present themselves<br />

in simultaneous poetic tone. Repetition demands this eternity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

beginning, which is a fi nite infi nity, be repeated in time, in ever new<br />

presentation <strong>of</strong> presence. As a result, there remains always already an<br />

ever new excess at ever new presentation <strong>of</strong> presence, an ever new<br />

renewal <strong>of</strong> the immemorially old promise, the most ancient <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ancient gift <strong>of</strong> time. Th e gift given in the already always immemorial<br />

past must pass through time. It must pass through each presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence. In this manner it renews itself in this passing from<br />

ever new presence to ever new presence, and through this renewal,<br />

remains eternally old and eternally new at the same time, eternal and<br />

fi nite at the same moment. It has a Janus-like face looking forward<br />

and backward at the same time so that it does not weave only the<br />

recollection’s sad moments. Unlike recollection, repetition is no mere<br />

‘gallery <strong>of</strong> images’ (Hegel 1998, P.492) <strong>of</strong> the shapes that the Spirit<br />

has passed through history, nor is it ever new instants that pass away<br />

in a monotonous succession. In such a monotonous succession <strong>of</strong> ever<br />

new instants there is no face-to-face encounter <strong>of</strong> past, presence and<br />

future with each other apart from monotony <strong>of</strong> the logical principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> unity that is continuous with each passing instant, rendering each<br />

instant only a relative realization <strong>of</strong> the same.<br />

Th erefore there is no repetition in Hegelian universal order <strong>of</strong><br />

history, but only recollection that weaves into song the memory <strong>of</strong><br />

its own shapes that came into being. Repetition, on the other hand,<br />

is ecstatic repetition <strong>of</strong> eternity into presence, <strong>of</strong> the immemorial<br />

promise into future, without gathering unity <strong>of</strong> the monotonous,<br />

homogenous logical principle underlying it. Neither recollection <strong>of</strong><br />

what has already become and neither dead, nor ever new anticipation<br />

<strong>of</strong> monotonous instants passing away in banal succession knows that<br />

ecstasy <strong>of</strong> repetition that co-joins, co-fi gures and thereby makes<br />

possible ecstatic encounter <strong>of</strong> past, presence, and future with each<br />

other. It is only on the basis <strong>of</strong> the ecstatic encounter there appears<br />

something like the event <strong>of</strong> history. Th e ecstatic co-fi guration <strong>of</strong> past,<br />

presence and future—without underlying any speculative-logical


112 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> unity—is a monstrous, disjunctive confi guration, or<br />

assemblage <strong>of</strong> temporality as fi nite eternity that seizes the mortals and<br />

delivers him to his fateful, monstrous destiny which is the event <strong>of</strong><br />

history that determines in advance what is to come. Th is in-advance<br />

is that we shall call ‘inception’.<br />

Th e originary inception before any inceptions, this originary<br />

opening before anything that is open, must repeat itself in time to<br />

come, each time singular and irreducible, because there lays alone<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> future. Any philosophical thinking that is thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> future is a thinking <strong>of</strong> repetition. Repetition <strong>of</strong> the inception alone<br />

opens time beyond death, towards a future remaining after death. With<br />

this is the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption is also given the gift <strong>of</strong> time. Repetition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the inception is never a repetition <strong>of</strong> the given, for repetition<br />

singularly distinguishes itself from recollection, because the inception<br />

to be repeated is the inception yet to come. Th erefore repetition is<br />

always an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a yet to come. Repetition is always repetition<br />

as remembrance, and not repetition as memory. With each repetition,<br />

a yet to come announces itself as possibility <strong>of</strong> the beginning anew,<br />

a promise <strong>of</strong> a time <strong>of</strong> redemption, which will not come so as to<br />

pass, but remains as an eternal remnant. Th is announcing is not<br />

the categorical cognition <strong>of</strong> given entities but a phenomenology <strong>of</strong><br />

‘thinking-saying’ that is not distinguished from said, but itself is the<br />

said whose event character cannot be thought within the dominant<br />

metaphysics. Th is event-character <strong>of</strong> ‘thinking-saying’ consists <strong>of</strong><br />

its welcoming the other beginning by (re)calling together (or better<br />

by repeating), in the manner <strong>of</strong> what Heidegger calls ‘conversation’<br />

(Gesprach) or dialogue the fi rst decisive beginning with the other<br />

beginning. In a certain important text Heidegger writes <strong>of</strong> this event<br />

character <strong>of</strong> ‘thinking-saying’:<br />

[W]e must attempt the thinking-saying <strong>of</strong> philosophy which comes<br />

from another beginning. Th is saying does not describe or explain,<br />

does not proclaim or teach. Th is saying does not stand over against<br />

what is said. Rather, the saying itself is the ‘to be said’ as the essential<br />

swaying <strong>of</strong> be-ing. (Heidegger 1999a, p. 4).<br />

Th e repetition <strong>of</strong> the beginning is not mere recapturing it in relation<br />

to the other beginning. Th e dialogue which repetition brings is not the<br />

dialogue <strong>of</strong> the self-same entities. It is rather that the other beginning


Repetition • 113<br />

even demands a ‘relentless turning away’ from the fi rst beginning so<br />

as to inaugurate or welcome the ones to come. Repetition is a leap<br />

in the ‘midpoint’ which is the abyss between these two beginnings<br />

where the event announces itself, not in categorical cognition <strong>of</strong><br />

‘presently given entities’ but as the thinking-saying <strong>of</strong> Da-sein who is<br />

the play space <strong>of</strong> strife between announcing and concealing.<br />

Th inking in the crossing brings into dialogue what has fi rst been <strong>of</strong><br />

be-ing’s truth and that which in the truth <strong>of</strong> be-ing is futural in the<br />

extreme—and in that dialogue brings to word the essential sway <strong>of</strong><br />

be-ing, which has remained unquestioned until now. In the knowing<br />

awareness <strong>of</strong> thinking in the crossing, the fi rst beginning remains<br />

decisively the fi rst—and yet is overcome as beginning. For this<br />

thinking, reverence for the fi rst beginning, which most clearly and<br />

initially discloses the uniqueness <strong>of</strong> this beginning must coincide with<br />

the relentlessness <strong>of</strong> turning away from this beginning to an other<br />

questioning and saying. (Ibid., p. 5)<br />

What Heidegger speaks here <strong>of</strong> the extremity <strong>of</strong> future, the Eschatos<br />

<strong>of</strong> the other beginning should not be understood archè-teleologically,<br />

for the arrival <strong>of</strong> the other beginning is radically incalculable and<br />

un-programmable. Th is eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> future is diff erent from<br />

the every new banal instants that come to pass away, unredeemed,<br />

because it is continuous with the given. Only repetition, because it<br />

occurs on the condition <strong>of</strong> the non-condition, because it is possible<br />

on the condition <strong>of</strong> the impossible, only this repetition brings us<br />

redemption, because it faces the abyss <strong>of</strong> death, that ‘midpoint’ <strong>of</strong><br />

an interval that cannot be bridged over by human eff orts or human<br />

mastery alone. Th is radical fi nitude does not arrive in the categorical<br />

language <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, but that must already attune the thinkingsaying<br />

that welcomes it in being seized by the ‘distress <strong>of</strong> the<br />

abandonment <strong>of</strong> being’ (Heidegger 1999a).<br />

Th e pure event <strong>of</strong> the future in its radical incalculability is also<br />

announced in Nietzsche’s idea <strong>of</strong> the Eternal Return <strong>of</strong> the Same.<br />

Th e promise <strong>of</strong> this return is not the promise <strong>of</strong> the return to the<br />

same in recollection, but redemption <strong>of</strong> the recollection into<br />

promise, redemption <strong>of</strong> time into the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the eternity <strong>of</strong><br />

the future, into the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> eternity <strong>of</strong> the beginning yet to<br />

come. Nietzsche’s thought <strong>of</strong> the eternal return is the paradoxical


114 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

con-junction between the thinking <strong>of</strong> death, and yet the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> a redemptive future. Th erefore a redemptive joy always announces<br />

itself in repetition, for repetition alone—if that is possible—redeems<br />

the melancholy <strong>of</strong> time that has remained unredeemed. Repetition<br />

and its possibility makes one cheerful and joyous, for on account<br />

<strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> future alone existence can be redeeming. ‘To<br />

redeem those who lived in the past and to recreate all ‘it was’ into<br />

‘I willed it’—that alone should I call redemption’ (Nietzsche 1995,<br />

p.139): Zarathustra promises. Repetition is the bringer <strong>of</strong> joy, were it<br />

be possible, for it loves eternity, by liberating the melancholy <strong>of</strong> past<br />

into a time yet to arrive. For that it must face death that means, it<br />

must enter or undergo the abysses <strong>of</strong> nihilism, for only the thought<br />

that faces death in its unavowable tremor transfi gures the past into<br />

future and brings redemptive fulfi llment. Th e way down to the abyss is<br />

the same as the way to the summit. Th is is the secret joy in Zarathustra’s<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> eternal Return <strong>of</strong> eternity itself which is also a thought <strong>of</strong><br />

death: ‘ All anew, all eternally, all entangled, ensnared, enamored—<br />

oh, then you loved the world. Eternal ones love it eternally and<br />

evermore; and to woe too, you say: go, but return! For all joy wants—<br />

eternity’ (Ibid., p.323).<br />

‘All joy wants eternity’, all joy wants repetition. Kierkegaard too,<br />

in his work on Repetition, sees repetition as an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future<br />

whose existential mood is joy: ‘Recollection makes us unhappy, but<br />

repetition, if it is possible, will make us happy, provided we give<br />

ourselves time to live and do not immediately, at birth, try to fi nd<br />

some lame excuse (that we have forgotten something, for example)<br />

for creeping out <strong>of</strong> life again’ (Kierkegaard 2001, p. 116). Th e gift <strong>of</strong><br />

repetition comes with being able to ‘give ourselves time to live’ that<br />

‘will make us happy’. To be able to repeat is to have time beyond death.<br />

To give oneself time to repeat, to give oneself the gift <strong>of</strong> time, and<br />

to have time to remain after death, or beyond death, which alone<br />

will make us happy in a time yet to come. Repetition is a promise <strong>of</strong><br />

happiness, because it is redemptive, because it is the promise <strong>of</strong> time<br />

that there will always be time. Hence the task in Kierkegaard: to<br />

make inwardness itself into repetition, or to make repetition itself into<br />

the inwardness <strong>of</strong> freedom. Repetition promises happiness because it<br />

re-casts the remainder <strong>of</strong> the beginning into the future, and thereby


Repetition • 115<br />

repeats eternity in presence. Th is possibility <strong>of</strong> eternity in each fi nite<br />

presence is the secret <strong>of</strong> a joyous existence, for what is life if life only<br />

has to repeat what has already become and exhausted its possibility?<br />

What is life if life has only to bring ever new, yet ever banal, ever<br />

monotonous succession <strong>of</strong> instants? For if it is the Possible—not the<br />

exhausted and sterile—that makes us happy, and joyous, then neither<br />

recollection <strong>of</strong> what is already exhausted, nor banal, monotonous<br />

succession <strong>of</strong> instants will make us joyous.<br />

Th e Possible lies neither in recollection, nor in banal anticipation<br />

<strong>of</strong> ever new, homogenous, empty instants. It is the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

repetition alone that brings the eternity <strong>of</strong> the Possible as Moment to<br />

us, and makes us divinely joyful. It is in this sense the Possible is greater<br />

than the actual. While the universal Now <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical is<br />

only the contraction or re-collection <strong>of</strong> the plurality <strong>of</strong> homogenous,<br />

vacant instants, repetition occurs on the other hand as the Moment<br />

that strikes us with its lightning, for it is none other than the fullness<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity itself. Th is fullness <strong>of</strong> eternity is the messianic intensity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘here and now’ that presents itself like what Hölderlin calls<br />

‘heavenly fi re’. Th is heavenly violence (which is without violence)<br />

<strong>of</strong> the divine fi re bursts open, tears open any immanence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

universal order, and delivers it to its own mortality and disappearing.<br />

Th e person who wills repetition is not the adult who sings at the<br />

dusk, neither is he the boy who ‘chases butterfl ies or stand on tiptoe<br />

to look for the glories <strong>of</strong> the world’, nor ‘an old woman turning the<br />

spinning wheel <strong>of</strong> recollection’ (Kierkegaard 1983, p. 132), but the<br />

one who rejoices in his existence, because at each moment, singularly,<br />

eternity presents to himself. Eternity alone makes one joyous. But<br />

this joyousness <strong>of</strong> repetition is inseparable from the highest suff ering,<br />

which is nothing but the suff ering <strong>of</strong> fi nitude that does not have<br />

Hegelian consolation <strong>of</strong> the concept. Th erefore repetition alone, were<br />

it possible, is ‘actuality and earnestness <strong>of</strong> existence’:<br />

If God had not willed repetition, the world would not have come<br />

into existence. Either he would have followed the superfi cial plans<br />

<strong>of</strong> hope or he would have retracted everything and preserved in<br />

recollection. Th is he did not do. Th erefore the world continues, and<br />

it continuous because it is a repetition, repetition that is actuality and<br />

the earnestness <strong>of</strong> existence. (Ibid., pp. 132-33)


116 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Repetition, if it were possible, alone would make us joyous, for it gives<br />

us back what is taken from us: it gives us the possibility <strong>of</strong> inception<br />

again. Th is repetition is possible only outside the given universal<br />

order, outside the immanent order constituted by recollection, for<br />

recollection is merely the spinning wheel <strong>of</strong> the old woman that<br />

weaves what has already happened, the given past that is worn out<br />

and has become stale and dead. Only outside the universal order <strong>of</strong><br />

the ethical can there be repetition. Repetition is the Archimedean<br />

point, outside the universal. It is the singular Moment, and not the<br />

particular instants <strong>of</strong> the universal. Th is repetition is the repetition <strong>of</strong><br />

the eternity in the heart <strong>of</strong> presence that bestows upon the beginning<br />

a meaning, because this beginning has the meaning <strong>of</strong> a future, a not<br />

yet, a promise <strong>of</strong> yet to come.<br />

Th erefore in Kierkegaard’s text, both the young lover poet and<br />

his adviser Constantius despair <strong>of</strong> repetition. Repetition is neither<br />

possible in ethical order, nor in the aesthetic sphere. Hence the<br />

need <strong>of</strong> the third type <strong>of</strong> repetition that alone enables eternity to<br />

arrive in presence, so that the singular being whose existence is not<br />

completely exhausted in the universal claims <strong>of</strong> history, confronts,<br />

encounters each moment, ecstatically, what is not yet, the eternity,<br />

and the coming time. Th e singular existence that wills repetition and<br />

one that is not satisfi ed by virtue <strong>of</strong> being enclosed to the immanent,<br />

universal, ethical order, it seeks redemption in an Archimedean point:<br />

a point that is no point, where the ground <strong>of</strong> the aesthetic and the<br />

ethical disappears, and all that appears solid in that universal order<br />

trembles and melts away. It is the ‘midpoint’ where there must occur<br />

the leap, that ‘quantum leap’ (Kierkegaard 1983) to the order <strong>of</strong> faith<br />

which singularity affi rms and wherein singularity is affi rmed. Th is<br />

is the moment <strong>of</strong> the epochal ruptures that tears apart history, and<br />

opens itself to the advent to come. Repetition is neither grounded<br />

upon a speculative-logical principle <strong>of</strong> unity, nor is it supported by<br />

the universal, immanent order <strong>of</strong> the ethical. Repetition, in the face<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Absurd, is experience <strong>of</strong> mortality as mortality that enables<br />

an arriving in perishing, in a monstrous coupling <strong>of</strong> infi nitude and<br />

fi nitude that does not know Aufhebung. It is the Moment when the<br />

immanent, universal, ethical order comes to a halt and opens itself to<br />

the Abgrund where the Other holds sway, and gives us the direction<br />

<strong>of</strong> history. If for Kierkegaard repetition is a task <strong>of</strong> transforming it


Repetition • 117<br />

into the inwardness <strong>of</strong> freedom, this task then is none but the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> mortality itself which is to repeat the immemorial that enables the<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> the coming.<br />

If for Kierkegaard repetition is a task <strong>of</strong> transforming it into the<br />

inwardness <strong>of</strong> freedom, Heidegger envisages the task <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

at the end <strong>of</strong> certain metaphysics—a metaphysics wherein Being is<br />

grasped as presence—as the task <strong>of</strong> repetition <strong>of</strong> the inception to<br />

come in order to think the coming to presence itself, not <strong>of</strong> this and<br />

that, nor the totality <strong>of</strong> beings as history <strong>of</strong> beings, but to affi rm<br />

the coming itself, which is not told in the predicative language <strong>of</strong><br />

categories, but as Wink, in poetic Saying as hint that at once shows<br />

. To think inception itself, which is concealed by unconcealment<br />

itself (this is the originary polemos that Heraclitus alludes to), because<br />

it alone enables the coming to come. Th e task <strong>of</strong> repetition is to<br />

repeat what has never been present and therefore repetition is beyond<br />

metaphysics that thinks Being as presence whose presence is told in<br />

predicative propositions, for the predicative proposition grasps Being<br />

only as constantly given presence, as what is ‘presently given’. Instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> the categorical, leading back the apophansis—the ontological<br />

task <strong>of</strong> the traditional ontology that understands Being as entities<br />

‘presently given’ (Vorhandenheit), hence in terms <strong>of</strong> a presently<br />

presence (Anwesenheit)—Heidegger’s Being and <strong>Time</strong> attempts to<br />

think Being in its verbal resonance, its event <strong>of</strong> coming (Anwesung)<br />

to presence in a hermeneutic <strong>of</strong> existential disclosure. Da-sein is<br />

not ‘human’ in the sense <strong>of</strong> ‘animal rational’ but the open-ness <strong>of</strong><br />

space where timing times, where this timing manifests itself as strife<br />

between preserving the truth <strong>of</strong> being and yet opening itself to arrive.<br />

Th erefore the task <strong>of</strong> repetition is to be distinguished from categorical<br />

apprehension and comprehension. To repeat the inception is rather<br />

to welcome the coming to presence itself in the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> poetic<br />

Saying, or in the thinking-saying <strong>of</strong> the philosopher who shelter the<br />

truth <strong>of</strong> being from oblivion. Th is remembrance has to do with the<br />

other history that Heidegger calls Geschichte which he distinguished<br />

from the memorial <strong>of</strong> Historische.<br />

Th e inception, however, can only be experienced as an inception<br />

when we ourselves think inceptively and essentially. Th is inception is<br />

not the past, but rather, because it has decided in advance everything<br />

to come, it is constantly <strong>of</strong> the future. (Heidegger 1993, p.13)


118 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

To repeat the inception is to open towards the coming that comes,<br />

to welcome the past in the future to come, in the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

beginning again the beginning that in advance enables ‘everything<br />

to come’. Only with this thinking <strong>of</strong> inception, essential thinking<br />

begins. Th is beginning has a diff erent history (Geschichte) than<br />

being historical (Historische). It is the astonishment, or wonder, or<br />

marvel <strong>of</strong> thinking. With the astonishment the coming <strong>of</strong> thought<br />

itself is welcomed, for ‘we never come to thoughts. Th ey come to us’<br />

(Heidegger 2001, p. 6).


§ Language and Death<br />

Mortals are they who can experience death as death. Animals cannot<br />

do so. But animals cannot speak either. Th e essential relation between<br />

death and language fl ashes up before us, but remains still unthought.<br />

—Martin Heidegger (1982, p. 107)<br />

The States <strong>of</strong> Exception<br />

Arthur Schopenhauer is said to have revealed, as Franz Rosenzweig<br />

(2005, p. 11) reports us, the secret that philosophy has kept for two<br />

and a half thousand years, that death is philosophy’s Musaget. Th at<br />

this secret <strong>of</strong> philosophy is revealed to us only at the accomplishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the philosophical discourse is signifi cant, as if the secret <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy which is death, may have to do with philosophy’s own<br />

accomplishment (Vollendung); in other words, with philosophy’s<br />

own death, philosophy’s own undoing. In this sense the secret <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy may have to do with the failure <strong>of</strong> philosophy. Philosophy<br />

has failed, and has not been stopped failing because <strong>of</strong> its secret,<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the force and power which this secret gives to it.<br />

Th is failure is consequence <strong>of</strong> the discovery that philosophy has<br />

made long time ago about which Hegel tells us a story. It is the<br />

discovery that this strange animal called ‘man’ who alone speaks a<br />

language, who is the only one to be capable <strong>of</strong> death, is also the<br />

animal who out <strong>of</strong> a non-foundation, out <strong>of</strong> an abyss metaphysically<br />

founds all foundation. Th e one who can discover this secret and<br />

recounts the history <strong>of</strong> this discovery—namely, the philosopher—


120 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

thereby has at his credibility to recount the metaphysical foundation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the historicity <strong>of</strong> the historical existence <strong>of</strong> this historical being<br />

called ‘man’, which is expressed in the history <strong>of</strong> the political-socialcultural<br />

institutions, all <strong>of</strong> them being the expression <strong>of</strong> this peculiar,<br />

this terrible metaphysical secret <strong>of</strong> man’s power. Such knowledge<br />

will not be the knowledge <strong>of</strong> this particular thing, but an essential<br />

knowledge, knowledge that knows the foundation <strong>of</strong> its knowing and<br />

is united with it. Hegel calls it, according to the language <strong>of</strong> Idealism,<br />

‘Absolute Knowledge’. Language is then man’s metaphysical power,<br />

not this or that power, but the very essence <strong>of</strong> the power, the powerness<br />

<strong>of</strong> power, this power <strong>of</strong> non-power, what constitutes power’s<br />

secret <strong>of</strong> being power, the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> power. As metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

power, language is capable <strong>of</strong> death. It is a terrible secret, one whose<br />

sense and value is only now becoming clearer to us—and Nietzsche<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> the fi rst to reveal and investigate into this metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

power—so that out <strong>of</strong> an investigation into the metaphysical essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, at least language <strong>of</strong> philosophy, an essence <strong>of</strong> power can<br />

be reached.<br />

In his famous Politics Aristotle says:<br />

Nature, as we <strong>of</strong>ten say, makes nothing in vain, and man is the only<br />

animal whom she has endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong> speech. And whereas<br />

mere voice is but an indication <strong>of</strong> pleasure and pain and is therefore<br />

found in other animals (for their nature attains to the perception <strong>of</strong><br />

pleasure and pain and the intimation <strong>of</strong> them to another, and no<br />

further), the power <strong>of</strong> speech is intended to set forth the expedient,<br />

and therefore likewise the just and unjust. And it is characteristics <strong>of</strong><br />

man that he alone has any sense <strong>of</strong> good and evil, <strong>of</strong> just and unjust,<br />

and the like, and the association <strong>of</strong> living beings who have this sense<br />

makes a family and a state.(Aristotle 2001, p. 1129).<br />

Th e power <strong>of</strong> speech, as distinguished from the cries <strong>of</strong> animals’ is<br />

not that <strong>of</strong> the distinction between pleasure and pain, but that <strong>of</strong><br />

the distinction <strong>of</strong> between just and unjust, <strong>of</strong> the good and evil. As<br />

speaking animal, man is the capacity to transform the pure animalistic<br />

possibility to cry into speech. Language is a negative capacity or,<br />

a capacity <strong>of</strong> negativity that, being able to negate the cries <strong>of</strong> the<br />

animal and yet preserving it, posits the possibility <strong>of</strong> the distinction<br />

between just and unjust, which is the pure possibility <strong>of</strong> law. As pure


Language and Death • 121<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> law, language is the metaphysical power <strong>of</strong> man, the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> negation and preservation, power <strong>of</strong> positing and the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> preserving. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this possibility given to man who<br />

speaks, which is his metaphysical condition, that man founds his<br />

foundation and expresses this foundation through visible forms, that<br />

is, the historico-political institutions, and becoming truly ‘man’ as<br />

distinguished from animals. It is only then man is a political-historical<br />

animal, only then an animal who has something like history, and who<br />

has something like politics, only then the man who not merely cries<br />

and screams but also speaks. Th at man has something like history, and<br />

something like politics has its metaphysical condition in this power <strong>of</strong><br />

death or negation. Th is power <strong>of</strong> positing and preserving law occurs<br />

with language that is distinguished from cries from pleasure and<br />

pain. In language man is exposed to death. In this exposure to death,<br />

man learns to speak ‘I’. Th is ‘I’ is then born out <strong>of</strong> anguish, which<br />

however even animals feel, when for example—and this is Hegel’s<br />

famous example <strong>of</strong> the anguish <strong>of</strong> the animals—when the beast <strong>of</strong><br />

prey sees the utter destructible character <strong>of</strong> the animal before him.<br />

He then does not wait, but jumps unto the animal and destroys it.<br />

Hegel’s Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit brings this discovery <strong>of</strong><br />

metaphysics to a dramatic force, and thereby bringing this story to<br />

its accomplishment at its utmost limit when what philosophy has to<br />

do is none but to reveal its own essence to itself, that is, its own secret,<br />

that death is its Musaget. Th e metaphysical essence <strong>of</strong> world-history<br />

where ‘man’ for the fi rst time emerges as ‘man’, this metaphysical<br />

occurring <strong>of</strong> man as man is his history, which is the history <strong>of</strong> this<br />

occurring. But the metaphysical essence <strong>of</strong> the historicity <strong>of</strong> this<br />

history is this death, that is, in being able to say ‘I’, man summons<br />

his own death unto language, looks death in its face and ‘tarries with<br />

it’(Hegel 1998,p. 19). To say ‘I’ is not to recognize the face that cries<br />

in pleasure and pain, but it is to recognize one’s own dissolution,<br />

one’s utter dismemberment, to see death’s face, as if, as it were, in<br />

saying ‘I’ it is death that speaks in its name, that is, in the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

a name, in the name <strong>of</strong> a name that has already perished, and sunk<br />

into nothing. Th e truth that man rescues from this utter shipwreck,<br />

the utter sinking <strong>of</strong> his pure being unto nothing is this ability, this<br />

metaphysical capacity to posit one’s own death, and to preserve<br />

one’s own death as pure power. It is through this capacity for death,


122 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

power for the fi rst time manifests itself this really real power. It is<br />

from this history acquires for itself the power <strong>of</strong> a law, a gaze and a<br />

force, a constituting gaze that founds itself, out <strong>of</strong> this death, out <strong>of</strong><br />

the absence <strong>of</strong> a foundation. As such man, instead <strong>of</strong> belonging to<br />

sovereignty, himself is this state <strong>of</strong> exception, that means, ex-ception<br />

in relation to his own state: he ex-cludes himself from himself—in<br />

speaking ‘I’—and through this essential exclusion in-cludes himself,<br />

inserts himself, posits himself and preserves himself. He empowers<br />

himself with law, which is the law <strong>of</strong> history, and the law <strong>of</strong> his<br />

politics. As empowerment <strong>of</strong> oneself, man is this occurring, this<br />

excluding-including state <strong>of</strong> exception, this logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty.<br />

What is happening here? Th e question that concerns us at this<br />

moment is simply this. What if death is man’s metaphysical power<br />

par excellence, the very essence <strong>of</strong> power, the power <strong>of</strong> the nonpower,<br />

then what is the relation between language and death, apart<br />

from that both language and death have certain relation to power, or<br />

rather, are the secrets <strong>of</strong> power, that constitute power as power, as if<br />

power in its positing, in its assertion and negations (and the language<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic and grammar is, as we know, primarily takes its point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure, that means, its analysis <strong>of</strong> statement, proposition from<br />

this) summons, each time, a death and a language, one and at the same<br />

time. Th erefore Nietzsche’s attempt at deconstruction <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

at it metaphysical constitution accompanies a deconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

grammar, for grammar replaces God, even after the death <strong>of</strong> God. As<br />

the power <strong>of</strong> positing, or positing <strong>of</strong> power, grammar and God posit<br />

law as law. Th is law which is none but the law-ness <strong>of</strong> law, which<br />

constitutes law as law, is a law for death and law against death in the<br />

enunciation <strong>of</strong> itself as law, as if each enunciation whose truth and<br />

validity begins with this occurring, there also occurs the enunciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> death itself. It is not a vain death but is invested in sight <strong>of</strong> law.<br />

As law for death, law is positing law and as law against death it is<br />

preserving law as ban. Th ey are tw<strong>of</strong>old sides <strong>of</strong> the same law, for<br />

each time law posits itself as law, it calls forth both assertion and<br />

negation as simultaneous moments <strong>of</strong> occurring. Law as such is power<br />

<strong>of</strong> negation and power <strong>of</strong> assertion which comes to be at the moment <strong>of</strong><br />

enunciation. It means that law as such is not a (given) state, nor is it<br />

a presently given entity. It is this occurring, this advent <strong>of</strong> law as law


Language and Death • 123<br />

that is not amenable to the classical ontological understanding <strong>of</strong> law<br />

that is, as substance or a categorically graspable entity.<br />

What we are trying to understand here is the connection <strong>of</strong><br />

simultaneity <strong>of</strong> the occurring <strong>of</strong> law that demands its coming to<br />

presence in a language, <strong>of</strong> its own enunciation. As a state <strong>of</strong> exception,<br />

this structurally transcendental condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> law,<br />

this moment <strong>of</strong> enunciation unites at this demonic moment death<br />

and birth, negation and assertion. It annihilates the given nexus <strong>of</strong><br />

forces to bring into force new law. As such, law is to be understood<br />

here as partitioning <strong>of</strong> forces in its verbal resonance. It is, as we have<br />

learnt from Carl Schmitt (2006), the logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty. As logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> sovereignty, language carries death to the power <strong>of</strong> negation and<br />

assertion, as if out <strong>of</strong> an abyss, outside the world <strong>of</strong> general validity and<br />

norms. Or, should we say, as state <strong>of</strong> exception, death carries language<br />

to the point <strong>of</strong> its power <strong>of</strong> negativity, which, precisely because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

power <strong>of</strong> negativity is what posits something as something, which<br />

means, it negates something else.<br />

Is there not another state <strong>of</strong> exception, another exceptional<br />

exception, an immemorial exclusion which must be outside the above<br />

mentioned logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty, outside the moment <strong>of</strong> enunciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the positing-negating language <strong>of</strong> law and power? Th is true state<br />

<strong>of</strong> exception which is neither a consequence nor a mere result <strong>of</strong><br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty but precedes it, in an immemorial manner,<br />

is the redemptive arrival <strong>of</strong> the messianic future, only because it is<br />

exceptionally prior, and exceptionally ancient, immemorial that<br />

arrives from the extremity <strong>of</strong> time, from an Eschatos <strong>of</strong> the pure future<br />

. Th is messianic arrival strikes the mortals with lightning fl ash, a<br />

sudden suspension <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty, which therefore appears<br />

to mortals to be coming from a radical future, only because time here<br />

is reversed, or experienced as reversed, not as mere instant-in-between<br />

<strong>of</strong> an irreversible succession <strong>of</strong> nows, but moment <strong>of</strong> simultaneity <strong>of</strong><br />

the past, present and future where the unhoped arrives, foiling all our<br />

expectations, calculations and predications. In so far as mortal lives,<br />

according to the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> his existence, as this time-in-between <strong>of</strong><br />

irreversible succession <strong>of</strong> nows, the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> the reversed temporality<br />

arrives as that whose excess falls on us like mortality’s lightning fl ash.<br />

Th is state <strong>of</strong> exception does not found the law-positing and law-


124 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

preserving violence. What Walter Benjamin (1986, p. 277-300) calls<br />

as ‘divine violence’ which he distinguishes from the law positing and<br />

law preserving violence is a state <strong>of</strong> exception that does not serve the<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty. Th is divine violence is the mortal’s immemorial<br />

exposure to the state <strong>of</strong> exception to which he already always belongs,<br />

which owns him in advance and opens him to the truth and time on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> this belonging. Th is owning is far more originary and<br />

prior to the capacity <strong>of</strong> man being able to say ‘I’, that is, prior to<br />

this capacity <strong>of</strong> man to ex-clude himself from himself and in-clude<br />

himself as this exclusion. It is prior to his non-foundation that by the<br />

energy <strong>of</strong> thinking he converts it into the foundation <strong>of</strong> his history;<br />

it is prior to his exposure to this death which gives him back the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> being. Th e originary exception is the open where there takes<br />

place encounter with the wholly other, and where Love utters the<br />

redemptive, creative Word.<br />

Th is Word, which is the word <strong>of</strong> Love, is already always given to<br />

him as an immemorial promise or gift. Th is gift <strong>of</strong> the Word must<br />

fi rst open the tongue <strong>of</strong> the human so the human must partake the<br />

creative joyousness <strong>of</strong> the divine, which for that matter precedes<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> judgement, which is the judgement based upon the<br />

distinction not so much between pleasure and pain, but between just<br />

and unjust, good and evil. Th erefore Love is more originary than<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> good and evil and is truly the state <strong>of</strong> exception. It is<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> belonging to this exception which is Love that there<br />

manifests for mortals something like politics and history, i.e., the<br />

realm <strong>of</strong> judgement, which is the language <strong>of</strong> distinction between<br />

just and unjust that founds those visible forms: the cultural-political<br />

institutions, the state, the nation etc. Following Aristotle if we can<br />

say that man is essentially a political and historical animal, one who<br />

essentially has something like history, and something like politics, it<br />

already always belongs to Love that is more ancient than judgement,<br />

before politics and before history. Th is does not mean being a-historical<br />

but only this much: that it is the opening <strong>of</strong> history itself; it is that what<br />

inaugurates history itself. Love in its pure arriving to man is happiness.<br />

Th is happiness is in being before God, and in being refl ected in the<br />

light <strong>of</strong> the creative Word <strong>of</strong> the divine which it partakes, shares,<br />

speaks.


Language and Death • 125<br />

The Facticity <strong>of</strong> Love and the Facticity <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

As state <strong>of</strong> exception the creative word <strong>of</strong> love is prior to evil and<br />

good. Th e language <strong>of</strong> this love, this word <strong>of</strong> love that mortal has its<br />

glimpses in relation to the divine revelation is not the language <strong>of</strong><br />

sovereignty. Th e law <strong>of</strong> love is not the law <strong>of</strong> law. It does not posit<br />

and preserve itself. It is what precedes the gaze and force <strong>of</strong> a decision<br />

<strong>of</strong> law. Yet there is a de-cision in love, an according discord, a bringing<br />

together in holding-apart where the separation <strong>of</strong> principles are hold,<br />

as in a constellation. Th e decision <strong>of</strong> love is not the decision between<br />

good and evil. It is rather the language that fi rst opens the world,<br />

reveals the world, as a kind <strong>of</strong> facticity, ‘that there is’. ‘Th at there is’<br />

love, and ‘that there is language’ is its facticity or actuality before any<br />

potentiality. Since this facticity is not posited (because it is granted<br />

to man beforehand) but can only be affi rmed (this Yes saying), this<br />

language is a non-positing affi rmation, before assertion and before<br />

negation: that there is love. Th at there is love: it is not an assertion, but<br />

a Yes before assertion and negation that begins as longing-in-loving.<br />

At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the world, as the world’s coming to presence,<br />

as the revelation <strong>of</strong> the world, there is an affi rmation before assertion<br />

and before negation, which is ‘that there is’. It is an actuality which<br />

thought cannot reach, where language falls silent, not because it<br />

negates language, but it is language in its pure state <strong>of</strong> exception,<br />

that is, in its completion, in its actuality without potentiality and<br />

without predicates. Th e language <strong>of</strong> love is the language <strong>of</strong> actuality,<br />

because it is itself actuality, from where thought begins, from<br />

where thought lovingly, exuberantly—like the bellowing Sea with<br />

its pregnant waves—goes forth, longs for its own futurity. Where<br />

the beginning is the beginning with actuality, with the facticity <strong>of</strong><br />

love, there language is an affi rmation as pure state <strong>of</strong> exception. It<br />

is precisely this point, the point not <strong>of</strong> the end but <strong>of</strong> the beginning<br />

which Hegel’s philosophy <strong>of</strong> Absolute knowledge fails to reach.<br />

Th at Schelling affi rms love to be the beginning and end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

very movement <strong>of</strong> his essential thinking, shows that an essential<br />

thinking has a movement outside system. Unlike Hegel’s assertion <strong>of</strong><br />

the completion <strong>of</strong> his system to be Absolute Knowledge, or Absolute<br />

Concept as Infi nite negativity, it rather shows why Schelling makes<br />

the creative Word-language (whose ‘un-pre-thinkable’ actuality,


126 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

this exuberant beyond and outside being (Überseyn) precedes mere<br />

conditioned potentiality <strong>of</strong> the conceptual negativity) into love as<br />

the originary revelation <strong>of</strong> existence. Hegel’s system <strong>of</strong> Absolute<br />

Knowledge appears to be bereft <strong>of</strong> language, because it begins with<br />

the mere negativity and mere potentiality <strong>of</strong> the concept that means,<br />

with the language <strong>of</strong> mere assertion and negation, with apophantic<br />

predication. Th is reductive language <strong>of</strong> speculative logic is at<br />

complete disposal <strong>of</strong> the categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> events already occurred,<br />

or <strong>of</strong> entities presently given. In this manner the facticity <strong>of</strong> language<br />

in its movement <strong>of</strong> longing-loving and in its movement <strong>of</strong> creative,<br />

exuberant affi rmation is sought to be reduced to the categorical<br />

movement, or movement <strong>of</strong> categories <strong>of</strong> a speculative logic.<br />

Language that opens with and goes towards love, whose beginning<br />

lies in the ‘un-pre-thinkable’ beginning before beginning, and whose<br />

completion lies in the extremity <strong>of</strong> future, as Eschatos always to arrive,<br />

this language <strong>of</strong> promise opens itself to the pure caress <strong>of</strong> longing<br />

for what is still remained to be attained. It thereby transcends itself<br />

and opens itself to a time yet to come. Th e language <strong>of</strong> promise that<br />

is given in love is the language that overfl ows itself beyond what is<br />

already said. It appears as if in this overfl owing <strong>of</strong> caress, time itself<br />

can no longer be individuated into particularized, atomic instants<br />

that are homogeneous and successive. <strong>Time</strong> here fl ows. But it is not<br />

an incessant un-diff erential murmuring or interminable humming<br />

<strong>of</strong> waves which Bergson calls ‘duration’. Th e caress <strong>of</strong> this time<br />

rather brings into encounter what are past, present and future in<br />

their respective ecstatic character. In this bringing together time<br />

itself is intensifi ed, and yet is extended to the immemorial past<br />

and incalculable future, beyond the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence.<br />

Th is is the moment <strong>of</strong> revelation when time spaces open and space<br />

temporalizes itself: a trans-immanent, a trans-fi nite movement where<br />

language becomes caress, and utters unto the space <strong>of</strong> revelation the<br />

redemptive word that is to arrive.<br />

Th e creative word <strong>of</strong> beginning, at the opening <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

and creation is like the bellowing Sea, pregnant with infi nity that<br />

surges forth, bursts forth, sallies itself beyond. Th e originary promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the word that structurally opens each discourse or conversation<br />

is not ‘pure being passing into nothing’ without language, but the<br />

exuberant unfulfi lling fulfi lment, the movement <strong>of</strong> longing-loving


Language and Death • 127<br />

towards the Other, the caress that in its plenitude leaves to itself a<br />

‘not yet’. Th e remainder <strong>of</strong> the ‘not yet’ that opens with the promise<br />

is the condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> the future yet to arrive that is<br />

latent in each moment <strong>of</strong> discourse or conversation. Th is latency is<br />

the driving force which drives each discourse beyond its saturation<br />

with its self-enjoyment and opens itself to the radical otherness<br />

<strong>of</strong> futurity. Th erefore at the heart <strong>of</strong> loving, the Word carries an<br />

irreducible remnant or a reserve that shelters or preserves a promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> happiness in a time to come, <strong>of</strong> bliss that will be renewed in future.<br />

Th is beatitude <strong>of</strong> the future is not one particularized mode <strong>of</strong> time<br />

that will come to pass but an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> time. What the<br />

mortal seeks, one for whom death is a facticity before all facticity, is<br />

a beatitude that is truly the pure state <strong>of</strong> exception. Th is exception<br />

arrives from beyond the gaze <strong>of</strong> Law, and outside positing-preserving<br />

violence; it advents from a Yes saying, from an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

facticity that can equal to the facticity <strong>of</strong> death. Th at is why it is said<br />

that ‘love is equal to death’.<br />

As an immemorial promise love precedes and follows the language<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement. Th is occurring <strong>of</strong> loving attunes us in our fundamental<br />

attunements to truth and time that aff ects us in a fundamental<br />

manner. Outside the categorical apparatus <strong>of</strong> predicative truth<br />

at cognitive disposal and outside the En-framing <strong>of</strong> calculable,<br />

technological mastery, love is pure aff ection <strong>of</strong> time from beyond:<br />

the immemorial and the incalculable. Even before the language <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement comes to constitute itself as positing law and preserving<br />

law, love already always opens us to the promise <strong>of</strong> the other beginning<br />

which love places us by displacing our given mode <strong>of</strong> existence. It<br />

is the attunements <strong>of</strong> love whose various modes are understood by<br />

Hölderlin as various poetic tonalities that make the creative word<br />

<strong>of</strong> love attain that paradisiacal fulfi lment which is not that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> judgement, but the caesural constellation, like the music<br />

<strong>of</strong> the spheres. Th e constellation-music <strong>of</strong> love where love seeks its<br />

messianic fulfi lment, in so far language appears here pure movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> presentation (Darstellung) <strong>of</strong>f ers meaning itself in its character <strong>of</strong><br />

pure <strong>of</strong>f ering. Th ere is a character <strong>of</strong> giving in the presentation <strong>of</strong> love,<br />

which is, renouncing <strong>of</strong> mastery and appropriation, dispropriates<br />

ecstatically the one who gives. In this pure giving in love and in<br />

love’s grateful receiving, which is inseparable from renunciation <strong>of</strong>


128 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

mastery—in so far as there is sadness in any renunciation—there is in<br />

love something like joyous mournfulness. But this melancholy is not<br />

the melancholy as a consequence <strong>of</strong> law’s violence or as a consequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> death that one who is subjugated to the sovereign<br />

power <strong>of</strong> law feels in his veins with fear and trembling. It is rather the<br />

blissful melancholy <strong>of</strong> a beatifi c fulfi lment which Adam felt when he<br />

named the animals, and they bowed in front <strong>of</strong> him out <strong>of</strong> gratitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> being named. Th e mournfulness in love’s plenitude, as a condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> loving, lies in a non-economic giving, a giving <strong>of</strong> a self to a blissful<br />

knowing, is a condition immanent to God, and transcendent to the<br />

mortals.<br />

In his pr<strong>of</strong>ound refl ection on human freedom, Schelling speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> an originary melancholy even in God’s creative Word <strong>of</strong> love, a<br />

melancholy however to be distinguished from melancholy from evil<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> human freedom. Th is originary melancholy<br />

that must have adhered in the creative Word <strong>of</strong> love precedes the<br />

melancholy that arises from evil, which means love is more ancient<br />

than the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil. Th is means that which begins as revelation<br />

as creative Word <strong>of</strong> love, precisely lays therein the seeds <strong>of</strong> redemption.<br />

Love is this messianic language <strong>of</strong> redemption. While the melancholy<br />

<strong>of</strong> God is immanent to God’s condition and therefore it never<br />

becomes actual in God but remains as mere possibility, in the mortal<br />

on the other hand—who is essentially this linguistic being, whose<br />

essence consists in being able to present to himself—language—<br />

this melancholy becomes actual, which means transcendent. Man is a<br />

creature <strong>of</strong> an originary melancholy, for unto him alone redemption<br />

becomes the utmost necessity. Th is redemption arrives only when<br />

man prepares himself to abandon evil, to abandon this particular will’s<br />

all consuming lust for mastery <strong>of</strong> its own fi nitude and conditionedness,<br />

and thereby, through this abandonment, gives himself over to<br />

love’s creative language, opening himself to the gift <strong>of</strong> language itself.<br />

The Gift <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

What, then, is the relationship between mortality and fi nitude with<br />

language, a mortality that is not reducible to the death’s power <strong>of</strong><br />

positing-preserving, to the language <strong>of</strong> judgement which constitutes<br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> sovereignty? Is it that with mortality the gift <strong>of</strong> language


Language and Death • 129<br />

is also given thereby, the gift <strong>of</strong> the originary revelation that bursts us<br />

open to the entirety <strong>of</strong> the world, our relation to the others, to the<br />

divine, to the elemental forces <strong>of</strong> nature and the solitude <strong>of</strong> the earth?<br />

Who are those mortals who are exposed to the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coming and opened to the open where light and darkness, presence<br />

and absence play their strife? What language would be without<br />

the gift <strong>of</strong> time, intimated by fi nitude, and by a coming time that<br />

endows time with eternity and thereby redeeming time itself? Would<br />

language, then, be conceptual apparatus to grasp through cognition<br />

the ‘entities presently given’ (Vorhandenheit), <strong>of</strong> things and objects<br />

that have acquired the signifi cation <strong>of</strong> categories for us, predicative<br />

and predictable, which the business <strong>of</strong> logic busies itself with? Or<br />

language would rather reveal in an originary manner the not-yetpredicated<br />

and not-yet categorical? Mortal would then be the one<br />

who is revealed to himself in language even before cognizing the<br />

world through his cognitive power and through his rational capacity<br />

for calculation and en-framing predication. Language then reveals<br />

man to himself and endows man with the gift to be present to himself,<br />

gives man the possibility to reveal himself to himself, and makes him:<br />

an open existence, exposed to the presencing that presences and arrival <strong>of</strong><br />

a time that remains. Th e gift <strong>of</strong> language renders the mortal open to<br />

the claims <strong>of</strong> the earth and also to the claim <strong>of</strong> elevation to light, <strong>of</strong><br />

gravity into grace, ground into existence. He then hears, in language<br />

that is given to him, the cries <strong>of</strong> fi nite creatures waiting in distress for<br />

redemption. In that naming- language loaned to him, he hears the<br />

mortal cries <strong>of</strong> the vanquished.<br />

Man knows <strong>of</strong> death from language, from the possibility <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

which ties him to his mortality. In language, man is exposed<br />

to the temporality <strong>of</strong> the advent. Th is is what Heidegger meant when<br />

he says <strong>of</strong> man as the one who ‘knows death as death’. Only then man<br />

speaks as created ones, and he encounters in this opening <strong>of</strong> language<br />

his future, his fi nitude whose strangeness astonishes him, ungrounds<br />

him, tears him apart from himself, and opens him towards the<br />

entirety <strong>of</strong> the created existence, to the elemental manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

nature and to his own historical task, which is to create out <strong>of</strong> his<br />

creative freedom his historical world. It is out <strong>of</strong> this creative freedom<br />

there comes to be something like politics and history, ethics and logics.<br />

Th erefore a philosophical thinking <strong>of</strong> existence, or an existence-


130 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, which is not mere categorical and predicative, is<br />

also, with the same gesture a language-thinking (Sprachdenken).With<br />

this, the existence-philosophy <strong>of</strong> Franz Rosenzweig’s philosophical epic<br />

Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption begins. Th e task here is to extract from this<br />

book a fundamental thought, which is this: a philosophical thinking<br />

that claims, through the predicative power <strong>of</strong> its categories where<br />

language serves the conceptual apparatus <strong>of</strong> cognition, to make death<br />

itself a work <strong>of</strong> negativity, and thereby claims to have been able to<br />

redeem death itself into thought, to have been to include existence itself<br />

into predicative categories—this is a thinking without language.<br />

Th is is also the thinking without confrontation with the temporality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming time, for it forgets the originary gift <strong>of</strong> language intimated<br />

with fi nitude and time. Th erefore it knows neither the mortal<br />

fear nor the claim <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th e lightning fl ash that reveals the<br />

leap <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> existing is not intimated in a thinking for which<br />

event and existence are conceptual categories in the function <strong>of</strong> predication<br />

<strong>of</strong> what has only been, as the end result <strong>of</strong> a logical process. Event<br />

leaping into the coming is fl ashed through the lightning <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

for language alone opens man to the event. A thinking for which<br />

language itself is none but conceptual apparatus for cognition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

already available world misses the event and gives itself the illusion<br />

that event. What then is the gift <strong>of</strong> language given to the mortals?<br />

Th e gift <strong>of</strong> language keeps man open to the event and thereby promises<br />

redemption. A philosophical thinking that makes vain <strong>of</strong> death, for it<br />

gives the illusion <strong>of</strong> an eternity in the Concept beyond death 1 , would<br />

render the hope for redemption a mere embellishing necessity. For<br />

there to be hope in the event to come, man must remain open, in the<br />

lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> language, for language alone reveals man his death,<br />

to a time to come. Th is is the pr<strong>of</strong>oundest connection <strong>of</strong> language<br />

and death. Man knows death in language alone; for language reveals<br />

to man that his existence is existence unto death. But that is not<br />

alone. Language, revealing the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> his existence to him, calls<br />

forth creation that is to remain beyond death, calls forth the creative<br />

task to give himself ever new beginning <strong>of</strong> himself.<br />

It is here the question <strong>of</strong> origin is posed along with the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

event. Event, the possibility <strong>of</strong> the coming, is a confrontation with<br />

death, but also an encounter to future beyond death. A thinking <strong>of</strong>


Language and Death • 131<br />

event must take death, and also time seriously, and not to include<br />

it as a mere category in the system <strong>of</strong> a logical thinking. A nonpredicative<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> the event is called forth here, along with<br />

a non-generative modality <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> a time yet to come, and<br />

also language itself, irreducible to the cognitive system <strong>of</strong> concepts,<br />

as fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning where the opening reigns for the event to come<br />

forth, to leap into presence. No recollection, but repetition: there<br />

lies the joyous participation in the future as revealed in the opening<br />

shining forth. Th is joyous repetition <strong>of</strong> the event in the time to come<br />

which is multiple- singular, does not wholly belong to the order <strong>of</strong><br />

generality and essentiality <strong>of</strong> the Concepts and categories. A wholly<br />

otherwise must begin here with the event that is not yet recollected<br />

in the spinning wheel <strong>of</strong> categories, for with each beginning there<br />

comes a coming, not this and that, but a coming itself.<br />

Th e coming comes and the presencing presences: this is already a<br />

venturing, reaching, opening to the beyond. It does not begin with<br />

the logical propositional thought <strong>of</strong> beginning with empty nothing<br />

equal to Being, for there is a thinking <strong>of</strong> coming that is neither equal<br />

to Being nor equal to nothing <strong>of</strong> the negative. It is at once an excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> being and nothing, but also a lack <strong>of</strong> their fullness <strong>of</strong> presence,<br />

either <strong>of</strong> being or <strong>of</strong> nothing. Th e coming comes and presencing<br />

presences: this is the existential facticity <strong>of</strong> the event, that each time<br />

repeating itself is transfi gured into the wholly new beginning, but<br />

whose origination is not with the abstract concept <strong>of</strong> pure Being, but<br />

with a longing that is itself a moving and becoming without positing<br />

an act <strong>of</strong> consciousness or a logical concept outside. Th e facticity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coming belongs to the question <strong>of</strong> existence and not to predication. Th e<br />

coming into existence is not one category among others. It is intimated<br />

in prophesy that is announced in the open. A wholly new apparatus,<br />

or even otherwise than the notion <strong>of</strong> apparatus, but a confi guration<br />

or constellation <strong>of</strong> thoughts—seized in the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> the<br />

open—alone constitutes, or de-constitutes the event <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

or the existential facticity <strong>of</strong> the event. An existential thinking is<br />

always thinking <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> the future <strong>of</strong> the arriving, not in<br />

the monotonous generation <strong>of</strong> the same but as ex-tatic diff erence <strong>of</strong><br />

‘perdurance’ (Heidegger 1969) wherein transcendence bursts into,<br />

and tears open existent to the arrival.


§ Confi guration<br />

What we are attempting to think with the notion <strong>of</strong> confi guration,<br />

or constellation is a whole without totality, an assemblage without<br />

system. A conceptually and logically generative principle running<br />

through them does not unite them, nor are they inserted into the<br />

cognitive apparatus <strong>of</strong> categories where the question is asked about<br />

the essence <strong>of</strong> them (in its ‘what is’), for it is presupposed there to have<br />

a shared essence, unitary, identical and absolute. Th e confi guration<br />

movement, in so far as this movement inaugurates the singular<br />

coming into existence and not what has already been predicated in<br />

the generalized economy <strong>of</strong> system, has to be thought outside such<br />

a system. Th e generalized economy <strong>of</strong> the categories miss the event-<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> coming—it is because it subordinates the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

confi guration to the system and to totality, the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong><br />

language to concepts, repetition to recollection, transcendence to<br />

the immanent generation, eternity into presence, illumination to<br />

methodological cognition belonging to the universality <strong>of</strong> essence,<br />

existential constellation to categorical thought, the Naming language<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortals to the apophantic, the coming to the overwhelming <strong>of</strong><br />

what has been, prophetic intimation to regressive memory into the<br />

Archaic, fi nitude and mortality to the negativity <strong>of</strong> death, redemption<br />

and revelation to the categories <strong>of</strong> future and presence that brings<br />

nothing new and reveals nothing new, ecstatic freedom to ground <strong>of</strong><br />

necessity, astonishment <strong>of</strong> the event to the dialectical march <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept, remembrance to memory, possible to the realized.<br />

*


Caesura<br />

Confi guration • 133<br />

Confi guration is a co-fi guration, a kind <strong>of</strong> caesural whole without<br />

totality, a co-fi guring communication where each is hold apart and is<br />

hold towards each other. Th eir communication lies in the explosive<br />

opening to transcendence without transcendent that ecstatically opens<br />

to the outside. Such a spacing <strong>of</strong> temporality can neither be represented<br />

as continuum <strong>of</strong> the underlying Subjectum beneath ruptures, nor as<br />

a generative-immanent principle grasped by the speculative logic.<br />

Confi guration is the (dis)fi gure <strong>of</strong> bursting out <strong>of</strong> totality represented by<br />

the econo-geometric fi gure <strong>of</strong> the circle that re-appropriates in its selfsame<br />

ground what is its other. Transcendence without transcendent is<br />

therefore not circular, but bursting <strong>of</strong> a non-convergent opening—<br />

let’s say ‘perdurance’ (following Heidegger. See Heidegger 1969)—<br />

where the leap occurs to what is arriving. It is the spacing, the abyss<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘midpoint’ that calls the extremity <strong>of</strong> distance to nearness and<br />

nearness to distantiate itself. Th is calling calls forth to conversation<br />

between the ecstatic extremities <strong>of</strong> time <strong>of</strong> the immemorial past and<br />

the incalculable future where time is no longer merely passing away<br />

<strong>of</strong> now after now, but their encounter in a momentary event that<br />

strikes the mortals. It is the encounter when time occurs as time<br />

and space occurs as spacing. Th is is how communication takes place<br />

in a confi guration: communication in this sense is a confi guration at<br />

each moment temporal and fi nite. Confi guration itself is a fi gure <strong>of</strong><br />

communication as con-fi guring without return to pre-conceived<br />

plane. Th is notion <strong>of</strong> confi guration as a whole is without totality,<br />

for the notion <strong>of</strong> totality does not have place for the intermittent<br />

interval—the abyss <strong>of</strong> the ‘midpoint’—where repetition opens any<br />

recollected closure to transcendence outside. In the open, repetition<br />

baths renewed voyages with new sky and the new sea.<br />

Th e notion <strong>of</strong> confi guration is therefore intimately bound up<br />

with the question <strong>of</strong> repetition and the radical epochal break that<br />

inaugurates the other history or otherwise than history that does<br />

not belong to the logic <strong>of</strong> continuum, i.e., Subjectum underlying<br />

beneath the ruptures <strong>of</strong> history. Not only that repetition is not<br />

possible without confi guration, but without repetition confi guration<br />

is reduced to totality or system. Confi guration is co-fi guration<br />

made possible by repetition multiple and singular, where its caesura


134 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

enables fi guration a ‘co’—a belonging together without totality—a<br />

hyphenated opening, enabling notes <strong>of</strong> a musical piece hold-together,<br />

also separating from each other. As it is possible to think <strong>of</strong> repetition<br />

belonging as con-fi guration, perhaps it is also possible to think a<br />

repetition <strong>of</strong> confi guration. Th rough repetition the advent to come is<br />

always renewed in the future <strong>of</strong> the past and in the past <strong>of</strong> the future,<br />

for repetition calls forth, summons the extremities <strong>of</strong> time to the<br />

destinal conversation that opens history to its essential historicity.<br />

Th is is, then, the relation between the advent <strong>of</strong> the event and<br />

language. Th ey occur as confi guration, a whole that holds together<br />

the singular multiplicity <strong>of</strong> repetitive origin or beginning, without<br />

forming a system or totality. As caesura interrupting each note, opens<br />

to the other by inserting a time without present so in the open there<br />

takes place the movement <strong>of</strong>, or towards transcendence, a coming<br />

to come. Th at the coming comes in the open: this is to be grasped in the<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> caesura.<br />

Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption<br />

Th e thought <strong>of</strong> confi guration or constellation is not the formal<br />

method, but the movement <strong>of</strong> thinking that being irreducible<br />

to representation is the pure movement <strong>of</strong> presentation where<br />

the unapparent arrives in a ‘thinking-saying’ which is in a sense<br />

‘tautological’. As such it is not a representational process <strong>of</strong> arriving<br />

at categorical cognition, even if it is Absolute Knowledge, for this<br />

unapparent arriving does not acquire completely those visible forms<br />

that tend to form totality or system. As such it does not belong to<br />

the philosophy <strong>of</strong> immanence or philosophy <strong>of</strong> All that moves ‘the<br />

whole venerable brotherhood <strong>of</strong> philosophers from Iona to Jena’<br />

(Rosenzweig 2005, p. 18).<br />

It is with this question <strong>of</strong> confi guration or constellation that<br />

Franz Rosenzweig’s Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption begins. Th is book asks<br />

the questions <strong>of</strong> existence and language, <strong>of</strong> creation and revelation<br />

and redemption, not from the basis <strong>of</strong> a representational cognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> visible forms that form system but from the hither side, from<br />

the point which is denied, excluded, expelled as illegitimate,<br />

indigestible from the philosophical discourse <strong>of</strong> All. Th e result comes<br />

to be peculiar. We are introduced into the movement <strong>of</strong> thinking


Confi guration • 135<br />

that speaks to us because <strong>of</strong> an excluded All—not just the All that<br />

excludes—as if from an Archimedean point <strong>of</strong> view, from outside the<br />

system <strong>of</strong> visible forms, to welcome the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong> a<br />

presence from a radical future. Th e movement <strong>of</strong> constellation begins<br />

from this point where a movement begins outside the All, where the<br />

All is not All yet all. Such constellation thinking must discover at<br />

the heart <strong>of</strong> All which is not All, at the heart <strong>of</strong> an identity a nonidentity,<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> a pre-supposition-less-ness <strong>of</strong> a structure <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thinking ‘ from Iona to Jena’ a presupposition. What emerges out <strong>of</strong><br />

this discovery is irreducibly singular-multiplicity that does not form<br />

a system <strong>of</strong> visible forms, since it does not originate and end with<br />

the presupposition-less self-identity <strong>of</strong> the All, but that begins with a<br />

presuppositional diff erential multiplicity, singular in relation to each<br />

other, which is a constellation.<br />

Th erefore for Rosenzweig constellation is not system, for it does<br />

not have its ground in the thinkability <strong>of</strong> the All, which is thinkability<br />

<strong>of</strong> an identity. Th e constellation is rather the non-identical<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> relation, the movement <strong>of</strong> a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> singulars<br />

as a movement <strong>of</strong> discontinuous simultaneity. Such is the relation<br />

among God, man and World that tempers the temporal relations<br />

among creation, revelation and redemption—the eternal past, the<br />

eternal presence and the eternally arriving messianic Kingdom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world—as a discontinuous simultaneity which is distinguished from the<br />

dialectical-speculative System that accounts only the successiveness<br />

<strong>of</strong> homogeneous, empty instants. As such the constellation or<br />

confi guration is not mere conglomeration or aggregate unity <strong>of</strong><br />

‘given’ fi gures, and the confi gurational composition <strong>of</strong> the elements<br />

does not take place according to mathematical rules. Th ey are the real<br />

happening whose eventiveness cannot be reduced to the geometrical<br />

or mathematical fi guration. Rosenzweig writes,<br />

For confi guration is diff erentiated from fi gure by the fact that certainly<br />

the confi guration could be composed <strong>of</strong> mathematical fi gures.<br />

Yet that in truth its composition did not take place according to a<br />

mathematical rule, but according to a supra-mathematical principle;<br />

here the thought furnished the principle <strong>of</strong> characterizing the<br />

connections <strong>of</strong> the elementary points as symbols <strong>of</strong> a real happening<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> any realizations <strong>of</strong> a mathematic idea.( Rosenzweig 2005,<br />

p. 275).


136 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

God, man and the world, each is not ‘presently given entity’. Th ey<br />

cannot be incorporated into the categorical, cognitive apparatus <strong>of</strong><br />

the All. Rosenzweig envisages the ecstatic movement <strong>of</strong> their arising<br />

as simultaneously discontinuous, therefore singular each in relation the<br />

others, arising and becoming out <strong>of</strong> an abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom that begins<br />

outside the categorical apparatus <strong>of</strong> the Universal One and All.<br />

Th e messianic movement <strong>of</strong> constellation is therefore a noncategorical,<br />

non-ontological movement whose movement is not<br />

grounded, gathered in the unity <strong>of</strong> the logical principle <strong>of</strong> identity,<br />

for the constellation does not begin nor end with the entities that<br />

are predicated, or that can be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> pure being<br />

and pure Universal nothing. God, man and the world are not<br />

therefore predicated entities but each is a discontinuous movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming to presence, <strong>of</strong> coming into existence, simultaneously and<br />

yet singularly relating to the other in this coming into presence.<br />

Rosenzweig calls this coming into presence ‘existence’.<br />

Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption begins with the deconstruction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

philosophy’s claim <strong>of</strong> its pre-supposition-less beginning, and its<br />

denial <strong>of</strong> death. Th at philosophy has to be thinkable, and that this<br />

thinkability has to have its ground in the unity <strong>of</strong> Logos—which<br />

defi nes the character <strong>of</strong> the ‘whole brotherhood <strong>of</strong> philosophers from<br />

Ionia to Jena’—therefore this philosophy has to deny, by a necessary<br />

reason, the multiplicity and singularity <strong>of</strong> the mortal cries in the face<br />

<strong>of</strong> death. For mortals for whom the ‘poisonous sting’ <strong>of</strong> death, its<br />

‘pestilential breath’ (Rosenzweig 2005, p.9) is not taken away in the<br />

vain consolation <strong>of</strong> the concept, in the empty promise <strong>of</strong> categories,<br />

has then to make another movement, another inauguration outside<br />

the cognition <strong>of</strong> the All, outside the system <strong>of</strong> One and Universal<br />

Being that has subsumed its nothing within itself. Such a mortal<br />

thinking which is seized in its veins with such fear and trembling,<br />

which is seized by death’s ‘poisonous sting’ and its ‘pestilential breath’,<br />

begins with presupposition, that is with nothing that is death, with a<br />

nothing which is not pure universal One and which is not a nothing<br />

equal to pure Universal One being, but rather with nothing that is<br />

something, a seizure, a trembling and a cry. Such a thinking—if does<br />

not have to dupe us with empty universals and empty One-ness—has<br />

to be a thinking non-identical, that means, multiple and singular,


Confi guration • 137<br />

for the categorical system <strong>of</strong> One and All there is no place for the<br />

multiplicity and singularity. Th at philosophy has to exclude death in<br />

order to be presupposition-less is also the very reason that thereby it<br />

also has to deny multiplicity and singularity, because only singulars<br />

and only multiple die, because for the One and Universal death does<br />

not exist, because for the One and Universal death has been deprived<br />

<strong>of</strong> its ‘poisonous sting’. If system or the totality <strong>of</strong> visible forms is<br />

based upon a death that has been rendered sterile and harmless, a<br />

constellation movement, on the other hand, is a fi nite, discontinuous<br />

movement which, since its begins with the presupposition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

undeniable ‘facticity’ <strong>of</strong> death—a ‘facticity’ that cannot be thought<br />

within concept, within System—calls forth the anguish and cries<br />

<strong>of</strong> the multiple and singulars that have rebelled against the unity <strong>of</strong><br />

Logos, and have thereby loosened themselves from the totality <strong>of</strong> One<br />

and Universal Nothing equal to One and Universal Being.<br />

In other words, the logical principle <strong>of</strong> unity no longer guarantees<br />

their cohesion. In being loosened from the oppressive unity <strong>of</strong> Logos,<br />

God and man and world are not entities present already, but events<br />

in their discontinuous simultaneity coming into presence, coming<br />

into existence, in so far as this coming constitutes the event character<br />

<strong>of</strong> these events, multiple and singular events holding-together -by-<br />

holding-apart so that they can breath besides each other in their<br />

relative autonomy. Instead <strong>of</strong> One and Universal Nothing <strong>of</strong> totality<br />

that Hegel conceives <strong>of</strong> as harmless (by taking away its ‘poisonous<br />

sting’), here there are nothings (in the plural) that are something (that<br />

is, as potentiality for something which is not mere the potentiality <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept, but potentiality <strong>of</strong> existence). What is introduced in and<br />

as constellation is constellation <strong>of</strong> Nothings, multiple and singulars,<br />

irreducible to the Universal and the One, irreducible to the unity <strong>of</strong><br />

Logos. Its logic <strong>of</strong> origin is not the sterile and harmless nothing but<br />

‘a perpetual derivation from a ‘something’—and never more than a<br />

something, an anything—from the nothing, and not from the empty<br />

nothing in general, but always from ‘its’ nothing, belonging precisely<br />

to this something’ (Ibid., p.27).<br />

What, then, the movement <strong>of</strong> constellation introduces is a logic <strong>of</strong><br />

origin, which is neither a logical deduction <strong>of</strong> categories nor derivation<br />

<strong>of</strong> an event from the One and Universal Nothing, but an origin which<br />

is nothing yet pregnant with something, a diff erential logic <strong>of</strong> origin


138 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

(or a logic <strong>of</strong> the diff erential). Rosenzweig attempts to think this logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> origin that he introduces with its constellation movement with<br />

the help <strong>of</strong> Hermann Cohen’s use <strong>of</strong> the mathematical notion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

diff erential and the infi nitesimal. Rosenzweig writes,<br />

Mathematics does not produce its elements out <strong>of</strong> the empty nothing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the one and universal zero, but out <strong>of</strong> the nothing <strong>of</strong> the diff erential,<br />

a defi nite nothing in each case related to the element it was seeking.<br />

Th e diff erential combines in itself the properties <strong>of</strong> the nothing and<br />

<strong>of</strong> the something; it is a nothing that refers to a something, to its<br />

something, and at the same time a something that still slumbers in the<br />

womb <strong>of</strong> the nothing. (Ibid., pp. 27-28).<br />

And little below about Hermann Cohen,<br />

In the place <strong>of</strong> the one and universal nothing, which, like the zero,<br />

could really be nothing more than ‘nothing’, that genuine ‘nonthing’,<br />

he sets the particular nothing whose fruitfulness refracted<br />

into realities. It was precisely Hegel’s foundation <strong>of</strong> logic upon the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> being that he most critically opposed; and consequently<br />

the entire philosophy that Hegel inherited. For here, for the fi rst time,<br />

a philosopher who still regarded himself as an ‘idealist’—a further<br />

sign <strong>of</strong> the force <strong>of</strong> this event in him—knew and acknowledged that<br />

when thinking sets out ‘to beget purely’, it encounters not being—but<br />

nothing. (Ibid., p.28).<br />

Th e logic <strong>of</strong> the origin is not a logical deduction from an empty, one<br />

and universal nothing but it is the logic <strong>of</strong> nothing <strong>of</strong> the diff erential,<br />

which is a simultaneously discontinuous, diff erential coming into<br />

presence, on the one hand as a powerful negation <strong>of</strong> the nothing and<br />

on the hand, as infi nitesimal, a calm affi rmation ‘<strong>of</strong> that which is<br />

not nothing’ (Ibid., p. 28). Th is is the real existential logic <strong>of</strong> origin,<br />

and not begetting purely conceptually, where something bursts<br />

forth, erupts, and comes into existence in its strife with nothing.<br />

Th is diff erential logic <strong>of</strong> origin is the play-space <strong>of</strong> strife between the<br />

potentiality that is latent in nothing and an actuality that bursts forth<br />

as singular. Constellation is a movement <strong>of</strong> the diff erential, a holdingtogether-by-holding-apart.<br />

In other words, it has to begin with the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> existence, as it has to begin with the question <strong>of</strong> death,<br />

but not with ‘being pure and simple’. Rosenzweig here, like Kant and<br />

Schelling before, makes the distinction between existence and being,


Confi guration • 139<br />

with the priority given to existence, which is each time coming into<br />

presence, an event, and not a predicate or category. Th e constellation<br />

thinking is, therefore, an existential-thinking, which means, thinking<br />

existence as event in its coming into presence.<br />

Discontinuous Finitude<br />

In the beginning <strong>of</strong> his Th e Origin <strong>of</strong> German Tragic Drama Walter<br />

Benjamin introduces the idea <strong>of</strong> constellation as philosophical<br />

contemplation which is distinguished from the categorical cognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> phenomena. Benjamin calls this philosophical contemplation<br />

‘timeless constellations’, not <strong>of</strong> concepts at cognitive disposal but<br />

<strong>of</strong> Ideas, whose concern is not knowledge as it is with concepts,<br />

but with truth. Philosophical contemplation is distinguished<br />

from cognitive possession, as Idea is distinguished from concepts.<br />

Philosophical thinking as constellation or confi guration is not concerned<br />

with the cognitive possession <strong>of</strong> phenomena, but their redemption. Th is<br />

redemption is the freeing, clearing, releasing <strong>of</strong> phenomena from the<br />

positing power <strong>of</strong> the concepts to its originary Idea. It is releasing the<br />

phenomena from the concepts’ gaze <strong>of</strong> law and from the violence <strong>of</strong><br />

cognition unto the dignity <strong>of</strong> the naming ‘unimpaired by violence’.<br />

As if philosophical contemplation in so far as it is concerned with<br />

truth and not knowledge, rescues phenomena from a categorical<br />

apparatus, from a regime <strong>of</strong> cognitive mastery, and releases it<br />

from the melancholy <strong>of</strong> the damaged condition. Th is melancholy<br />

is not that blissful melancholy <strong>of</strong> the philosophical contemplation<br />

that bears the beatitude and dignity <strong>of</strong> the creative naming, but a<br />

melancholy that suff ers being at cognitive disposal, damaged and<br />

impaired by the violence <strong>of</strong> cognitive mastery and the overnaming<br />

language <strong>of</strong> judgement. Philosophical contemplation therefore is<br />

not conceptual knowledge <strong>of</strong> objects but redemptive Naming-loving<br />

where the creative gift <strong>of</strong> language that is given in Adam’s naming—<br />

melancholic because it is paradisiacal—adheres itself. Philosophical<br />

contemplation is more originary and more primordial promise than<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> judgement, more originary than overnaming that<br />

precedes the evil that arises in overnaming the name. Th is redemptive<br />

naming, because the world is also revealed to us in the name, arrives in<br />

this blissful philosophical contemplation that shares with the source


140 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> the creative life <strong>of</strong> the divine. Th is arrival occurs outside totality,<br />

outside the categorical apparatus, but in a movement <strong>of</strong> constellation<br />

that brings together the extremities <strong>of</strong> time—the immemorial past<br />

and incalculable arrival <strong>of</strong> the other origin.<br />

Without an underlying continuum <strong>of</strong> Subjectum rendering a<br />

system <strong>of</strong> phenomena in their visible forms, confi guration is rather<br />

like a mosaic where singularity <strong>of</strong> Idea has a relative independence,<br />

whose relation is dependent less upon a common logical selfgrounding<br />

foundation than as ‘the harmony <strong>of</strong> the stars’. Benjamin<br />

says in his Th e Origin <strong>of</strong> the German Tragic Drama:<br />

All essences exist in complete and immaculate independence, not<br />

only from phenomena, but especially, from each other. Just as the<br />

harmony <strong>of</strong> the spheres depends on the orbit <strong>of</strong> the stars which<br />

do not come into contact with each other, so the existence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mundus intelligibilis depends on the unbridgeable distance between<br />

pure essences... Th e harmonious relationship between such essences is<br />

what constitutes truth. (Benjamin 1998, p. 38)<br />

As it is with Rosenzweig, confi guration does not here form a system,<br />

for it is not a coherence <strong>of</strong> concepts at the cognitive disposal unifi ed<br />

by a logical self-foundational principle <strong>of</strong> identity. A confi guration is<br />

rather an assemblage <strong>of</strong> discontinuous, disparate, multiple, repeated<br />

attempts to think anew the same, which is renewed in thinking with<br />

what Benjamin calls ‘a continual pose for breath’.<br />

A confi guration thinking is a mosaic <strong>of</strong> multiple seizure <strong>of</strong><br />

thoughts, or experiences through singular repetitions <strong>of</strong> what in itself<br />

is singular and is in relative independence—like God, man and world<br />

in Rosenzweig—and therefore is discontinuous, interruptive <strong>of</strong> itself,<br />

caesural and ecstatic. Each singular thought or Idea in relation to the<br />

other forms a new confi guration <strong>of</strong> truth, as each remains thereby<br />

singular, irreducible to the generative principle <strong>of</strong> particularized<br />

universality <strong>of</strong> the Concept; each is in multiple relations, as singular<br />

multiple repetition <strong>of</strong> the origin. It is as if the beginning begins itself<br />

anew each time, ecstatic and in astonishment at the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the ever anew repetition <strong>of</strong> itself by interrupting itself, discontinuing<br />

itself. Communication occurs as ‘perdurance’ <strong>of</strong> the discontinuous.<br />

Th is discontinuity occurs with the ‘breath’ <strong>of</strong> a pause. With each<br />

repetition the origin is opened to the coming, or rather, thinking


Confi guration • 141<br />

itself is opened to the ‘origin’ (and not ‘genesis) and is exposed to the<br />

lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> the sudden illumination, which without forming<br />

an underlying continuum, separates itself from the apparatus <strong>of</strong><br />

rested cognition <strong>of</strong> ‘presently given entities’ (Vorhandenheit). With<br />

each repetition in a confi guration there arrives, in a discontinuous<br />

seizure, in sudden lightning fl ash, in ecstatic astonishment, the<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise. In this sense each repetition is<br />

wholly new, wholly singular existing (that is, it transcends itself)<br />

that transcends each time from the generalized, immanent economy<br />

<strong>of</strong> the self-consuming predicates. Th is intermittent, discontinuous<br />

seizure <strong>of</strong> experiences, thought as ‘confi guration’ here, we also call<br />

‘caesural thinking’ in order to emphasize the interval, intermittent<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the confi guration. Benjamin calls such a constellation<br />

or confi guration as ‘discontinuous fi nitude’ (Benjamin 1998, p. 38).<br />

Th e advent <strong>of</strong> the arrival can only be told in a pre-predicative<br />

confi guration, for confi guration is less concerned with cognition<br />

and predication than with its task <strong>of</strong> redeeming phenomenon from<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition. Benjamin calls this arrival as ‘pr<strong>of</strong>ane<br />

illumination’ when ‘dialectics stands still’ and history comes to a halt.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> philosophical contemplation is not cognitive mastery <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomena but a linguistic task, that <strong>of</strong> renewing the act <strong>of</strong> Naming:<br />

‘Ideas are displayed, without intention, in the act <strong>of</strong> naming, and<br />

they have to be renewed in philosophical contemplation. In this<br />

renewal as the primordial mode <strong>of</strong> apprehending words is restored’<br />

(Ibid., p. 37). Th is renewal is the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary not<br />

yet impaired by the cognitive violence, and is irreducible to historical<br />

memory <strong>of</strong> the speculative-dialectical.<br />

EN-FRAMING, REVELATION<br />

A thinking that gives itself the task <strong>of</strong> ‘destruction <strong>of</strong> ontology’ at<br />

the completion <strong>of</strong> a certain metaphysics does not ask the question <strong>of</strong><br />

Being as ‘constant presence’ but Being understood in the infi nitive<br />

<strong>of</strong> the verbal resonance, as the event <strong>of</strong> Being, as Being’s coming into<br />

presence. Th erefore the existential analytic <strong>of</strong> Dasein in Sein und<br />

Zeit distinguishes the existential analytic from categorical grasp <strong>of</strong><br />

‘entities presently given’ (Vorhandenheit), ins<strong>of</strong>ar as the existential<br />

Dasein for whom—who is a ‘who’, and not a ‘what’—its own being


142 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

is at stake does not have the character <strong>of</strong> the ‘entities presently given’,<br />

for in itself existential is each time singular occurring, each time its<br />

coming into presence that distinguishes this existential analytic from<br />

the average-ness <strong>of</strong> the ‘Das Man’, ‘the Th ey’. As such Being as event<br />

cannot be thought within the categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> the everyday ‘what’<br />

presently given but as the temporalized constellation <strong>of</strong> ecstasies <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalities, each is each time its own mode <strong>of</strong> coming to presence.<br />

Th is thinking <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> Being—which is also the thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> diff erence as diff erence (<strong>of</strong> what Heidegger calls ‘ontological<br />

diff erence’)—is the task in Being and <strong>Time</strong>.<br />

In his later writings Heidegger no longer thinks this coming into<br />

presence, this event <strong>of</strong> Being as the task <strong>of</strong> constituting a fundamental<br />

ontology anymore but as the advent <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> Being presencing<br />

to presence that transforms the history <strong>of</strong> Being as Metaphysics to<br />

the ‘thinking-saying’ <strong>of</strong> the other beginning. It is here Heidegger<br />

introduces the two-fold notions <strong>of</strong> constellation, on the one hand<br />

constellation as En-Framing (das Gestell) where there holds sway<br />

the danger <strong>of</strong> the oblivion <strong>of</strong> the disclosing coming into presence <strong>of</strong><br />

the truth <strong>of</strong> Being, wherein this coming into presence is ‘entrapped’<br />

and on the other hand, constellation as disclosing coming into<br />

presence, when there occurs the epochal transformation <strong>of</strong> man’s<br />

relation to Being, when as a result <strong>of</strong> danger coming to pass as danger<br />

transforms itself into the coming into presence <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> Being.<br />

Th is constellation <strong>of</strong> the epochal transformation <strong>of</strong> man’s relation to<br />

Being which welcomes the coming into presence in its coming, the<br />

coming as such is what Heidegger calls ‘the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’ or<br />

‘enowning’ (Ereignis). Th erefore constellation as En-framing which<br />

is the danger and the constellation as saving power are not simply<br />

opposites; they are <strong>of</strong> the diff erential modes <strong>of</strong> the coming into presence<br />

as Being’s oblivion and as unconcealment <strong>of</strong> Being. Th is diff erential<br />

modes <strong>of</strong> coming into presence is thought as belonging together and<br />

belonging together <strong>of</strong> man and Being where neither man nor Being<br />

is thought as constant presence <strong>of</strong> ‘entities presently given’ but each<br />

time as coming into presence, and therefore outside the categorical<br />

appropriation into system.<br />

Confi guration or constellation in Heidegger’s later thinking is<br />

man’s transformative relation to Being where the confi guration is<br />

thought not constituting a system but as belonging-together <strong>of</strong> man


Confi guration • 143<br />

and Being, open to the advent <strong>of</strong> the other beginning. Th e event<br />

itself occurs as confi guration or constellation, as a constellation <strong>of</strong><br />

man’s relation <strong>of</strong> ‘belonging-together’ to Being, and not <strong>of</strong> belongingtogether<br />

(as it is reductively understood in the onto-theological<br />

constitution <strong>of</strong> metaphysics). Th e latter is the thinking <strong>of</strong> metaphysics<br />

as what Heidegger calls ‘En-Framing’ where there holds sway the<br />

oblivion <strong>of</strong> the danger as danger. En-Framing is the appearing <strong>of</strong><br />

the confi guration, or constellation <strong>of</strong> man and Being in the world<br />

<strong>of</strong> technological calculability, and therefore it is only a prelude to<br />

the far more originary confi guration or constellation as the ‘event<br />

<strong>of</strong> appropriation’, that means, event <strong>of</strong> the arrival and the coming.<br />

Heidegger says:<br />

What we experience in the frame as the constellation <strong>of</strong> Being and man<br />

through the modern world <strong>of</strong> technology is a prelude to what is called<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation. Th is event, however, does not necessarily<br />

persist in its prelude. For in the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation the possibility<br />

arises that it may overcome the mere dominance <strong>of</strong> the frame to turn<br />

into a more original appropriating. Such a transformation <strong>of</strong> the frame<br />

into the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation, by virtue <strong>of</strong> that event, would bring<br />

the appropriate recovery—appropriate, hence never to be produced<br />

by man alone—<strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> technology from its dominance back<br />

to servitude in the realm by which men reaches truly into the event <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation. (Heidegger 1969, p. 37)<br />

Th e belonging-together, but not belonging-together <strong>of</strong> the constellation,<br />

as the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation, is an exposure <strong>of</strong> man to what ‘man<br />

alone cannot produce’, what is otherwise than man, an exposure <strong>of</strong><br />

man himself to the ‘event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’. Man is, then, no longer<br />

understood as ‘animal rational’ but Dasein, who is the open space<br />

<strong>of</strong> strife, ‘the midpoint’ between overwhelming and arriving. In his<br />

Contributions to Philosophy, Heidegger writes <strong>of</strong> this Dasein:<br />

Dasein: Th e ‘between’ which has the character <strong>of</strong> a mid-point that is<br />

open and sheltering between the arrival and fl ight <strong>of</strong> gods and man,<br />

who is rooted in that ‘between’ Heidegger 1999a, 23).<br />

Dasein belongs to event or enowning (Ereignis) and only ins<strong>of</strong>ar as<br />

Dasein belongs to enowning, or event, it is also the creative being<br />

that leaps into be-ing. In this leap or spring, event is an essential<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> thinking beyond the given En-Framing towards


144 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the arrival <strong>of</strong> the beginning: ‘looking towards the present, beyond<br />

the situation <strong>of</strong> man, thinking sees the constellation <strong>of</strong> Being and<br />

man in terms <strong>of</strong> that which joins the two—by virtue <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation’ (Heidegger 1969, p. 40).<br />

Th inking as constellation, or confi guration as holding-together, or<br />

belonging-together <strong>of</strong> Being and man that man encounters, confronts<br />

the strangeness <strong>of</strong> the coming <strong>of</strong> Being to man, only in so far as Being<br />

is here near to the nearness <strong>of</strong> man’s essence. In other words, man<br />

confronts his future, the incalculable coming, only when the event <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation as leap, spring into the arrival is thought as the retreat<br />

from the reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> a certain dominant metaphysics, the<br />

metaphysics where the truth <strong>of</strong> Being—which Being is its disclosing<br />

coming-into-presence—is entrapped in oblivion, as if it were, Being<br />

abandons man. What is thought with the constellation as En-<br />

Framing is the experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment. Th e constellation where<br />

there Being comes to pass in its disclosing coming into presence is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation <strong>of</strong> this abandonment, and not at all man’s<br />

mastery <strong>of</strong> this abandonment, nor it is at all calculative technological<br />

totalization. But for that it becomes necessary for man to undergo<br />

the essential distress <strong>of</strong> the abandonment <strong>of</strong> man by being. Th e event<br />

<strong>of</strong> appropriation is rather dispropriation, displacement <strong>of</strong> man and<br />

Being’s place in En-framing, that are turned (Kehre) into their placing<br />

in what is its own. Th is undergoing the distress <strong>of</strong> the abandonment<br />

<strong>of</strong> being is the displacement <strong>of</strong> man into Dasein, into the abyss<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘midpoint’ that un-grounds man where Dasein is enowned (or<br />

appropriated) by being itself. In his Contributions to Philosophy,<br />

Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> this displacement as such:<br />

Th e awakening <strong>of</strong> this distress is the fi rst displacing <strong>of</strong> man into that<br />

between where chaos drives forth at the same time as god remains in<br />

fl ight. Th is ‘between’ is, however, not a ‘transcendence’ with reference<br />

to man. Rather, it is the opposite: that open to which man belongs<br />

as founder and preserver wherein as Da-sein he is en-owned by being<br />

itself—be-ing that holds sway as nothing other than enowning.<br />

(Heidegger 1999a, p. 19)<br />

Th e relation between the constellation as En-Framing and<br />

constellation as epochal transformation <strong>of</strong> man’s relation to Being


Confi guration • 145<br />

into the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation is that <strong>of</strong> turning (Kehre), or displacing<br />

man from established determination into the abyss <strong>of</strong> the midpoint<br />

which is Da-sein. Th is turning is not appropriation <strong>of</strong> Being nor is it<br />

the reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> Being through technological mastery at<br />

man’s disposal. Th e event <strong>of</strong> appropriation, that arrives with the turn,<br />

rather demands that man renounces his claim <strong>of</strong> mastery and that<br />

man opens himself, placing himself in the Open where the lightning<br />

fl ash <strong>of</strong> Being arrives, to the claim <strong>of</strong> the disclosing truth <strong>of</strong> Being.<br />

Th is truth claims man rather than man claiming the lighting fl ash<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth so that passing through man, man is placed in its proper<br />

place in the transformative constellation. It is this claim that occurs<br />

as event <strong>of</strong> appropriation, and not as what man appropriates the<br />

coming <strong>of</strong> Being as event.<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> appropriation is diff erential manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

the coming into presence <strong>of</strong> Being’s truth, and therefore is a<br />

welcoming <strong>of</strong> a non-totalized advent, <strong>of</strong> what is to come only in so<br />

far dispropriation <strong>of</strong> man’s placing in the En-Framing remembers<br />

man’s originary placing in the Open, in the originary constellation<br />

<strong>of</strong> man and Being where man is already always dispropriated from<br />

the mastery <strong>of</strong> Being. In other words, it is where man is originarily<br />

en-owned by being. Th e event <strong>of</strong> appropriation is appropriation <strong>of</strong><br />

Being’s abandonment <strong>of</strong> man in En-Framing to place man in the<br />

originary abandonment (by undergoing its distress) in the originary<br />

constellation <strong>of</strong> the Open. Th is remembrance occurs only at the end,<br />

at a certain accomplishment <strong>of</strong> the coming into presence <strong>of</strong> Being<br />

at its utmost realization when this realization comes to pass as Enframing,<br />

and when the danger <strong>of</strong> this En-framing passes as danger<br />

which turns this danger <strong>of</strong> En-Framing into the saving power <strong>of</strong> a new<br />

destinal beginning, an inauguration <strong>of</strong> a new constellation, which is<br />

yet to come, whose future suddenly arrives as lighting fl ash outside<br />

man’s calculation and projection. Th e En-framing and the saving<br />

power are like the two stars in a constellation whose paths cross each<br />

other which belong, as diff erential manifestation to the constellation<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this constellation <strong>of</strong> truth alone that the<br />

question concerning the essence <strong>of</strong> technology, its danger and saving<br />

power can be asked in so far as the essence <strong>of</strong> technology is nothing<br />

technological or technical, but revelation <strong>of</strong> Being whose coming to


146 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

pass is concealed, forgotten as this coming. Th e constellation <strong>of</strong> truth<br />

will occur only when the coming into presence—the event—will<br />

come to pass as coming, outside the totalizing En-framing.<br />

Heidegger writes,<br />

Th e irresistibility <strong>of</strong> ordering and the restraint <strong>of</strong> the saving power<br />

draw past each other like the paths <strong>of</strong> two stars in the course <strong>of</strong> the<br />

heavens. But precisely this, their passing by, is the hidden side <strong>of</strong> their<br />

nearness.<br />

When we look into the ambiguous essence <strong>of</strong> technology, we behold<br />

the constellation, the stellar course <strong>of</strong> the mystery.<br />

Th e question concerning technology is the question concerning the<br />

constellation in which revealing and concealing, in which the coming<br />

to presence <strong>of</strong> truth comes to pass. (Heidegger 1977, p.33)<br />

Confi guration is this diff erential and non-identical, non-totalized<br />

revealing which sends (Schicken) destiny (Geschick) which must<br />

already always holds sway outside man’s mastery. Because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

‘already always’ character, understood more essentially, it does not<br />

come to pass as mere past but in its arriving, or as fore-shining. Th is<br />

fore-shining is to be understood in the constellation <strong>of</strong> a temporality<br />

<strong>of</strong> an immemorial past (be-fore) and its arriving (in-advance).<br />

Confi guration enables the coming to be intimated as fore-shining,<br />

making visible <strong>of</strong> the distant light, for it is already permeated by the<br />

fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning, by the revelation <strong>of</strong> the beginning. Confi guration is<br />

not the fl ight <strong>of</strong> Minerva’s owl when the historical labour <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

is fi nished, but that which enables the coming to be said in poetic<br />

Saying, and in artistic creation, in the philosophical contemplation<br />

as confi guration <strong>of</strong> ideas.<br />

Confi guration is the diff erentiating perdurance between the<br />

overwhelming and arrival. Or rather, should we say, the diff erentiating<br />

perdurance, as happening <strong>of</strong> the event itself occurs as constellation,<br />

or confi guration where thinking undergoes transformation unto the<br />

beginning, unto that originary abandonment. In the confi guration<br />

therefore there is always a repetition <strong>of</strong> beginning. Th e repetitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the beginning are hold together as it were in a constellation, c<strong>of</strong>i<br />

guration, where each experience or thought is seized anew in their<br />

relative freeing from the other, and thereby relating to each other


Confi guration • 147<br />

as singular relations <strong>of</strong> non-mastery. As a disjunctive assemblage that<br />

never constitutes a system or totality, each singular interrupts itself<br />

and others at the same time in its coming into existence, and thereby<br />

opens and exposes itself to others. Heidegger attempts to think<br />

this holding-together in confi guration as ‘being apart and the being<br />

towards each other’ (Heidegger 1969, p. 65). Confi guration sends<br />

man and being away from each other while holding them towards<br />

each other so that man is placed in its proper place in relation to<br />

Being, that means, placing man as properly non-propriating being,<br />

whose propriety and property consists in being non-property and<br />

non-propriety. Only then is he open to the incalculable arrival <strong>of</strong> the<br />

lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> truth. Confi guration is welcoming this incalculable<br />

arrival which man experiences in the stillness <strong>of</strong> completed language,<br />

in the stillness <strong>of</strong> an eternity appearing as standing still, when the<br />

unapparent becomes apparent as the dis-fi guring fi gure <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

that strikes the mortal, abandoning him to the originary experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> his abandonment, to the originary strife <strong>of</strong> darkness and lightning,<br />

<strong>of</strong> sheltering and exposing <strong>of</strong> man to the event <strong>of</strong> being.<br />

Lightning, Clearing<br />

Th e turning from the danger <strong>of</strong> En-Framing (das Gestell) to the<br />

constellation where the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation arrives, this turning<br />

may occur momentarily, suddenly that in it’s like the lightning strikes<br />

the mortals, like what Hölderlin speaks <strong>of</strong> Apollo striking him. Th e<br />

mortals then experience this suddenness <strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash in a<br />

‘glance’ <strong>of</strong> the moment, in a sudden clearing and opening where<br />

language falls silent, because <strong>of</strong> its fulfi llment where saying and said<br />

comes together to welcome the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. Th e<br />

stillness <strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash ‘stills Being into the coming to presence<br />

<strong>of</strong> world’ (Heidegger 1977, p. 49). Heidegger here plays with the<br />

words: blitzen (to fl ash), blicken (to glance), Einblick (in-sight), and<br />

Augenblick (moment, suddenness). Heidegger writes,<br />

Th e turning <strong>of</strong> the danger comes to pass suddenly. In this turning,<br />

the clearing belonging to the essence <strong>of</strong> Being suddenly clears itself<br />

and lights up. Th is sudden self-lighting is the lightning fl ash. It brings<br />

itself into its own brightness, which it itself both brings along and<br />

brings in. When, in the turning <strong>of</strong> the danger, the truth <strong>of</strong> Being


148 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

fl ashes, the essence <strong>of</strong> Being clears and lights itself up. Th en the truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> the essence, the coming to presence, <strong>of</strong> Being turns and enters in.<br />

(Ibid., p. 44).<br />

Th is disclosing coming to presence <strong>of</strong> Being (Ereignis), this event <strong>of</strong><br />

Being arrives in a sudden, momentary (Augenblick) lightning fl ash<br />

(Blitzen). In this fl ashing glance (Blicken) the truth <strong>of</strong> coming into<br />

presence <strong>of</strong> Being enters (Einblick) into the new constellation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relation between man and Being. Th e lightning fl ash arrives as the<br />

stillness <strong>of</strong> the still, as if the entirety <strong>of</strong> the ecstatic temporalities—the<br />

ecstatic past, the ecstatic presence and the ecstatic future—arrives as<br />

simultaneous disjunction, as a simultaneous discontinuity, which is<br />

the eternity <strong>of</strong> the glance, <strong>of</strong> the moment.<br />

In German language the word Lichtung means both clearing and<br />

lightening, both opening and lighting. Heidegger in his later writing<br />

no longer understands Aletheia as truth but this lighting-lightening,<br />

clearing-opening where darkness and light, presence and absence<br />

comes into pass. In colloquial German the word Lichtung means<br />

forest clearing, to lighten open, to clear open a site and to open to<br />

the opening—as in the forest clearing and opening—where light<br />

and darkness, appearing and vanishing, and also coming takes place,<br />

happens, occurs. In Th e End <strong>of</strong> Philosophy and the Task <strong>of</strong> Th inking<br />

Heidegger attempts to translate Aletheia into Lichtung. Th is opening<br />

precedes any presence and absence, for it alone enables presencing to<br />

take place, for the arriving to arrive. It is the open sea where the sea<br />

opens the voyage to the coming. But this opening is to be far more<br />

primordially thought than beings that have arrived and presented<br />

themselves—as beings, as totality <strong>of</strong> beings—in a system. Th e<br />

task <strong>of</strong> thinking at, what Heidegger calls ‘the end <strong>of</strong> philosophy’,<br />

philosophy for whose matter <strong>of</strong> thinking is the question <strong>of</strong> Being<br />

as presence, is to open the present itself to a coming, to the unapparent<br />

presencing that presences. If the beings as such in their totality whose<br />

Being is grasped as ground <strong>of</strong> beings, enables Being to be thought<br />

as presencing itself—whose movement Hegelian speculative logic<br />

includes in the system—it has come to itself only in so far as an<br />

originary opening to presence is already hold sway. A confi guration<br />

thinking is not a confi guration <strong>of</strong> categories, whose truth is told in<br />

predicative propositions—in other words, it is not the thinking <strong>of</strong> beings


Confi guration • 149<br />

as totality, or Being as presence—but an astonished exposure, a lightning<br />

opening to the coming, a clearing freeing for the arrival. Only then the<br />

arrival arrives, Being comes to presence in this enabling appearing: ‘Th e<br />

opening’, says Heidegger, ‘grants fi rst <strong>of</strong> all the possibility <strong>of</strong> the path<br />

to presence, and grants the possible presencing <strong>of</strong> that presence itself’<br />

(Heidegger 1978, p. 387). Heidegger says,<br />

Th e beam <strong>of</strong> light does not fi rst create the opening, openness, it only<br />

traverses it. It is only such openness that grants to giving and receiving<br />

and to any evidence at all what is free, in which they can remain and<br />

must move’. (Ibid., p. 385)<br />

Th e constellation emits the light <strong>of</strong> its own, and therefore it does not<br />

have its destiny, for it itself as event <strong>of</strong> appropriation sends destinal<br />

inauguration to man. But this destinal inauguration arrives from<br />

a site wholly otherwise, from a future incalculable. Th e experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking according to Heidegger, like Benjamin’s philosophical<br />

contemplation, is not categorical, cognitive mastery <strong>of</strong> phenomena<br />

or objects but to enter into the constellation <strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash<br />

where the mortal remembers the immemorial promise, as if it comes<br />

into presence from the site <strong>of</strong> the yet to come. It arrives as momentary<br />

illumination when all <strong>of</strong> time as if stands still, and the mortal<br />

experiences this stillness—mortal whose fate is his fi nitude—as an<br />

eternity. Th ere in that lightning fl ash man has momentary glance<br />

into the truth and essence <strong>of</strong> his own origin where the primordial<br />

creative, the divine word is uttered. In this time without time there<br />

is no before absolutely before and no after absolutely after, which<br />

for that matter does not collapse into One indiff erent, Universal,<br />

homogenous empty Now, but as a constellation <strong>of</strong> ecstasies coming<br />

together without totality, without system. Th e contemplation <strong>of</strong> this<br />

eternity in philosophical thinking, and the renewal <strong>of</strong> this eternity in<br />

our primordial remembrance give philosophical thinking a dignity<br />

and nobility that refl ects the paradisiacal, blissful creative naming <strong>of</strong><br />

Adam who in naming inherited God’s creative Word. Constellation<br />

then has to enter into language where revealing coming to presence is<br />

not impaired by the categorical En-framing in its cognitive mastery<br />

and ordering, in its challenging forth. Heidegger attempts to think<br />

the constellation <strong>of</strong> the diff erential revealing by renewing the old idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> techne: the bringing into radiance, bringing forth unto beautiful,


150 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

unto the splendor <strong>of</strong> the open. Understood, techne <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> art<br />

is neither technological nor aesthetic enjoyment. As beautiful, it is<br />

rather the letting the grant <strong>of</strong> revelation to hold sway, which is outside<br />

mastery or calculability but that precisely calls forth man to renounce<br />

the calculability and mastery and to abandon oneself to the ‘distress<br />

<strong>of</strong> the abandonment <strong>of</strong> being’.<br />

Before Heidegger, both Schelling and Nietzsche, who already<br />

understood the essence <strong>of</strong> the apparatus, <strong>of</strong> En-framing in their own<br />

singular ways, thought <strong>of</strong> love and beautiful as what radiate forth in<br />

the work <strong>of</strong> arts, as what lighten up, what shine forth in the works <strong>of</strong><br />

art. What shines forth in works <strong>of</strong> art as fore-shining is the advent, is<br />

the arrival that transfi gures man’s existence unto a new future. In the<br />

works <strong>of</strong> art, in a more originary manner than philosophy, love and<br />

beauty utter their creative breath which arrives to mortals as sudden<br />

apparition. Th is arrival may not accompany great noises and may<br />

not come in the thunders <strong>of</strong> great events but in a language faintly<br />

audible, barely a murmur, in the stillness <strong>of</strong> a breath.<br />

Schelling in his Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World writes <strong>of</strong> this event,<br />

In the nocturnal vision where the Lord passed by the prophet, a<br />

mighty storm fi rst came which rent the mountains and shattered the<br />

rocks. After this came an earthquake, and then fi nally a fi re. But the<br />

Lord himself was in none <strong>of</strong> these, but rather was in a s<strong>of</strong>t murmur<br />

that followed. Likewise, Power, Violence, and Stringency must come<br />

fi rst in the revelation <strong>of</strong> the eternal so that the eternal itself can fi rst<br />

appear as the Eternal Itself in the s<strong>of</strong>t wafting <strong>of</strong> Love. (Schelling<br />

2000, p. 83)<br />

CONSTELLATION OF TEMPORALITIES<br />

Confi guration, not <strong>of</strong> categories, but singular multiple opening to<br />

come is essentially a thinking <strong>of</strong> time, <strong>of</strong> coming into presence, the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> arriving, for time-space is the open site where the strife occurs<br />

between the reserve and exposure <strong>of</strong> man to its futurity. Confi guration<br />

is con-fi guring <strong>of</strong> temporalities—multiple and singular—in their<br />

ecstasies and astonishment, hope and anticipation as their existential<br />

fundamental moods, or attunements. As there are attunements <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalities, and they are existential, so there are temporalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> attunements: they are thought as and in confi guration, or


Confi guration • 151<br />

constellation, or as caesural perduring. Hence confi guration thinking<br />

is to be distinguished from the task <strong>of</strong> system making. For the<br />

system, or thinking in totality, multiplicity is merely an attenuated<br />

modulation or variation <strong>of</strong> the logical principle <strong>of</strong> generation. In<br />

Hegelian system, temporalities are the multiplicity as particulars,<br />

and they hold together only so far as what Hegel calls ‘Presence’ or<br />

‘ Eternity’ traverses them and unites them in the innermost ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> the One Subjectum. Here then, as Heidegger reminds, the<br />

belonging-together is not thought in an originary manner, that is, as<br />

confi guration <strong>of</strong> belonging-together, but as En-framing <strong>of</strong> belongingtogether<br />

at the accomplishment or end <strong>of</strong> metaphysics in its ontotheo-logical<br />

constitution (Heidegger 1969).<br />

In the Hegelian system temporalities are not seen as confi guration<br />

<strong>of</strong> ecstatic singularities, but mere particulars that are mastered and<br />

elevated, uplifted unto the Universal. As mere particulars, instances<br />

are only the attenuated modifi cation <strong>of</strong> the Same universal. Th e<br />

System, or Totality has place neither for the multiple, nor for the<br />

singulars, since the notion <strong>of</strong> diff erence is grasped here on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the generative principle <strong>of</strong> variation—that means, the side by sideness<br />

<strong>of</strong> indiff erent particulars—where ‘each’ (<strong>of</strong> ecstatic temporalities)<br />

is subordinated to ‘every’ (<strong>of</strong> a monotonous homogeneity), ecstatic<br />

diff erentiation to an attenuated particularities. Later is the modality<br />

<strong>of</strong> time from where certain notion <strong>of</strong> ‘emanation’ has come as<br />

generative principle, a thinking that is provided by Aristotle’s treatise<br />

on Physics, and whose sovereignty is to be found in the Hegelian<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> temporality itself as generation.<br />

Th is notion <strong>of</strong> generation always presupposes the Universal One<br />

which uplifts (Aufheben) the multiplicities <strong>of</strong> the singulars in so far<br />

as multiple only there appears as variation <strong>of</strong> the Same, the Parousia<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Subjectum. As ‘each’ is only thought as ‘every’—where ‘every’<br />

is understood as every ‘instant’ on the spatial scale <strong>of</strong> succession,<br />

as a succession <strong>of</strong> nows, for that alone enables the system to be<br />

accomplished—the thought <strong>of</strong> totality misses the thinking <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ecstatic singularities <strong>of</strong> temporalities and therefore seeks to exclude the<br />

opening to the outside, to the arrival <strong>of</strong> the event. Th e event arrives in<br />

the sudden fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning that tears open man to transcendence,<br />

bursting open the ‘every’-ness <strong>of</strong> the instants into the Moment when<br />

the ecstatic temporalities belong together as an assemblage <strong>of</strong> eternity.


152 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th e sudden fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning to tear open and the transcendence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming to burst into, there must be an ecstatic ‘each’ stepping<br />

out, leaping forth, springing outside the given present instants. Such<br />

lightning fl ash that appears as momentary illumination must not<br />

be gathered in the re-collected totality <strong>of</strong> the Universal One. Th e<br />

moment—and not the instant—is this stepping out <strong>of</strong> the totality,<br />

in ecstasy and astonishment, but not in an indiff erent monotony<br />

and the banality <strong>of</strong> the same recollected instants in succession. Th e<br />

moment does not allow itself to be recollected, precisely because it is<br />

stepping out <strong>of</strong> recollection and collection: each moment, each time,<br />

singular and irreducible, ecstatic and eternal, leaps into the open.<br />

Th e eternity <strong>of</strong> the singular is the moment <strong>of</strong> its irreducibility to the<br />

recollected unity <strong>of</strong> the instants. It is rather the surplus, the excess,<br />

the transcendence without there being any transcendent waiting<br />

fi xed and immobile.<br />

What makes Both Heidegger and Rosenzweig in their critique<br />

and overcoming <strong>of</strong> Hegelian determination <strong>of</strong> temporality is their<br />

singular relation to later Schelling’s attempt to think the ecstatic<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> temporalities itself as confi guration, where the ecstatic<br />

potentialities <strong>of</strong> the eternal past, the eternal presence and eternal<br />

future are not determined as auto-generative and homogenous<br />

instances <strong>of</strong> the Universal One, but as irreducible multiplicity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

singulars, each in relative independence from the other and yet is<br />

an inseparable holding-together as Zusammenhang, as confi guration.<br />

not only Heidegger’s three ecstasies <strong>of</strong> temporalities which are not<br />

grasped as entities ‘presently given’ (Vorhandenheit), and therefore<br />

irreducible to their leveling <strong>of</strong>f to the homogenous succession,<br />

but also Rosenzweig’s Star itself is nothing but a confi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalities <strong>of</strong> eternal past, eternal presence and eternal future in<br />

their respective relation to Creation, Revelation, and Redemption,<br />

with God, Man and World as their co-fi gures that are irreducible to<br />

each other as singular multiple. As such, confi guration thinking does<br />

not have sublation (Aufhebung) as the negative speculative principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> unity. As confi guration, each is its stepping out <strong>of</strong> closure, stepping<br />

towards transcendence, towards the coming and the arriving. Each is,<br />

in this sense, a relation to a coming, to a future.<br />

In this manner the question <strong>of</strong> the future and its relation to eternity is<br />

thought in the confi guration and not in the system. In this sense future


Confi guration • 153<br />

alone is eternal, for each ecstatic temporality is stepping towards the<br />

incalculable, infi nite coming, towards transcendence; or, should we<br />

say, each is its transcendence, each affi rming the coming and future. In<br />

other words, this ecstatic future alone is truly eternal, and not a mere<br />

modality <strong>of</strong> <strong>Time</strong>, for it alone enables each stepping out <strong>of</strong> itself into<br />

the open, and opens each to the coming. Th is is what later Heidegger<br />

repeatedly speaks <strong>of</strong> as ‘time times’: timing <strong>of</strong> time is that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

simultaneity as holding-together <strong>of</strong> the irreducible singular multiple<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ecstatic temporalities, which alone enables an encounter, in the<br />

disclosure <strong>of</strong> the opening, with the future:<br />

<strong>Time</strong> times—which means, time makes ripe, makes rise up and grow.<br />

<strong>Time</strong>ly is what has come up in the rising. What is it that time times?<br />

Th at which is simultaneous rises up together with its time. And what<br />

is that? We have long known it, only we do not think <strong>of</strong> it in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> timing. <strong>Time</strong> times simultaneously: that which has been, and the<br />

present that is waiting for our encounter is normally called the future.<br />

(Heidegger 1982, p.106)<br />

While for Heidegger the simultaneity <strong>of</strong> ecstatically singular<br />

temporalities in the confi guration is experienced as stillness <strong>of</strong> silence,<br />

in Rosenzweig’s constellation <strong>of</strong> temporalities silence constitutes the<br />

beatitude <strong>of</strong> completed understanding. Silence is the attunement<br />

<strong>of</strong> completed understanding to the coming redemption which is<br />

promised, in the already always, in the immemorial gift <strong>of</strong> language.<br />

But this is so only in so far as constellation, or confi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalities is always already attuned to the coming so that what<br />

Heidegger calls ‘stillness’, or Rosenzweig’s silence—instead <strong>of</strong> being<br />

denial <strong>of</strong> language—brings language, as if for the fi rst time, to its<br />

fullness <strong>of</strong> completion when language, irreducible to any cognitive<br />

disposal and instrumentality, appears in its unapparent apparition as<br />

language <strong>of</strong> the name, Adamic, blissful, paradisiacal.<br />

Language is not here the categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> ‘the presently given<br />

entities’ (Vorhandenheit) which is the mere result <strong>of</strong> a process,<br />

a predicative proposition about the result <strong>of</strong> the process, but is<br />

redemptive remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary promise, which is<br />

understood in the silence <strong>of</strong> completed understanding. Language<br />

happens together with the coming as lightning fl ash, as the ‘time


154 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

times simultaneously’, belonging-together, as confi gured harmony.<br />

Th at will be the redemption <strong>of</strong> language itself that is renewed in<br />

what Benjamin calls ‘the act <strong>of</strong> Naming’. Th e beatitude <strong>of</strong> the<br />

completed understanding in silence, rescued and redeemed from<br />

its cognitive instrumentality and serviceability, from reduction <strong>of</strong><br />

language to the entities ‘presently given’, is experienced as eternity.<br />

Here alone man, as mortal and fi nite creature, is endowed with<br />

an eternity beyond transience, and beyond death. Here alone man,<br />

open to mortality is endowed with the beatitude <strong>of</strong> redemption by<br />

being intimated with the entirety <strong>of</strong> time coming together, which<br />

manifests itself—a phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the unapparent—as an ‘atom<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity’. It is in the eternity <strong>of</strong> the holding together <strong>of</strong> time—<br />

as constellation—that man has a time beyond death, that he is<br />

given the gift <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th e eternity <strong>of</strong> the moment is not<br />

present as Ousia or Parousia <strong>of</strong> the Subjectum that is present as<br />

permanent enduring, but as coming into presence, as event <strong>of</strong> time<br />

that simultaneously spaces itself as temporalization.<br />

It is in relation to the question <strong>of</strong> temporality alone, as confi guration,<br />

that the questions <strong>of</strong> revelation and redemption occur, for the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> transcendence is posed only when time itself is released<br />

beyond the thetic time <strong>of</strong> negativity, beyond the predicative grasp <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalities. <strong>Time</strong> does not time itself as positing. Th erefore the<br />

questions <strong>of</strong> revelation and redemption do not have a place in Hegelian<br />

system, for the beginning and the end <strong>of</strong> Hegelian system is none but<br />

a positing, thetic, predicative one. Th e unapparent phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

the extreme future is not to be understood as particular instant <strong>of</strong><br />

now that is coming to pass. Th at there is a past, and presence only in<br />

so far as each is to come that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens to each advent <strong>of</strong> this or<br />

that coming. Elsewhere I wrote,<br />

…this future is not the future <strong>of</strong> the specifi c temporality: there are<br />

singular ecstatic temporalities only to the extent that each one, in its<br />

singular way, is attuned to coming, each one is ahead <strong>of</strong> itself, and<br />

there lies the ecstases <strong>of</strong> each one <strong>of</strong> them. Here it is necessary to<br />

elaborate the notion <strong>of</strong> attunement <strong>of</strong> coming as transcendence, which<br />

can be understood as follows: there is no ecstatic past, ecstatic present<br />

or ecstatic future without each one being attuned to the transcendence<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself. Th is aheadness, this forward dimension, this opening to the


Confi guration • 155<br />

coming, is the originary <strong>of</strong> fi nite existence: ‘this’ futurity, which is not<br />

a future as one <strong>of</strong> the three dimensions <strong>of</strong> time, is messianic future, a<br />

futurity and coming other than ‘future’. Th is futurity therefore does<br />

not arrive, or come in time, let alone some future time: what comes<br />

as coming, this messianic coming, is not this or that coming, but<br />

coming itself. (Das 2008, p.173)<br />

Th is radical futurity, this extremity <strong>of</strong> time cannot be included within<br />

the immanent system <strong>of</strong> visible forms. Th e system does not have place<br />

for redemption and revelation, for it can only think <strong>of</strong> temporalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the singular multiple as a collection <strong>of</strong> banal, unredeemed, sterile,<br />

successive instants as nows and is therefore deaf to the anguished cry<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortal one, praying for redemption which is to arrive from<br />

beyond the closure <strong>of</strong> immanent historical time that is lived out in<br />

every self-consuming nows.<br />

What remains to come, the remnant <strong>of</strong> time is future, the coming<br />

time. It is that which steps out <strong>of</strong> the given, and ventures beyond<br />

and embarks into the new voyage <strong>of</strong> hope—hope that there may<br />

remain time after death, so that the remaining time may redeem all<br />

that has been missed fulfi llment and happiness. Here the lesson is<br />

drawn from the fundamental task <strong>of</strong> Levinasian philosophy: that <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking, not time on the basis <strong>of</strong> death, not <strong>of</strong> thinking death on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> time (Levinas 2000), that means, ‘to have time beyond death,<br />

time to remain after all ends <strong>of</strong> time, time to remain after every last<br />

time, after all last time’ (Das 2008, p. 173). Each singular-ecstatic<br />

temporality in the confi guration by itself is a venturing beyond into<br />

the open that inaugurates a new beginning to come that ‘remaining<br />

ever, redeems death’ (Ibid.). In the confi guration <strong>of</strong> each ecstaticsingular<br />

temporality—in their freeing and opening—a coming is<br />

permeated to arrive, a hope is intimated, a redemption promised, a<br />

future anticipated, a possibility fore-shines in the distant sky, and a<br />

new voyage begins.<br />

With this the notion <strong>of</strong> a coming time is attempted here to be<br />

elaborated, the coming that is not told in predicative proposition<br />

or in the categories <strong>of</strong> conceptual apparatus, the coming that is not<br />

grasped in the logical-immanent principle <strong>of</strong> generation, nor in the<br />

totality <strong>of</strong> recollected instants as multiple variations <strong>of</strong> the Same, but<br />

in the explosive confi guration, ablaze by the fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning and<br />

hold open in the opening, a confi guration where singular multiplicity


156 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> each ecstatic temporalities are hold together in the open, in the<br />

freeing, in the clearing <strong>of</strong> the open. Th e holding together, in or<br />

as confi guration is essentially a fi nite relation, which we shall call<br />

henceforth a relation <strong>of</strong> fi nitude. Confi guration thinking therefore<br />

replaces generation with relation, totality with a new notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

fi nite whole.<br />

Transfinitude<br />

As it is shown above, confi guration thinking is not an enclosed<br />

infi nitude within the immanence <strong>of</strong> its self-consuming predicates,<br />

but a fi nitude that bears the wound <strong>of</strong> the infi nite, that is exposed<br />

to the infi nite that aff ects it from a destination wholly immemorial<br />

past and wholly incalculable future. What is at stake in thinking the<br />

coming time as confi guration is this infi nite fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the coming<br />

time which is always to remain? We shall also call this ‘infi nite fi nitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming’ as transfi nite. Th e transfi nitude <strong>of</strong> the coming time: the<br />

infi nite-fi nitude <strong>of</strong> that which is to come and which is to remain to<br />

come. What not here to be missed is the infi nitive <strong>of</strong> the verbal resonance:<br />

‘to’.<br />

Schelling, Heidegger and Rosenzweig: with each <strong>of</strong> these three<br />

thinkers <strong>of</strong> the coming, this promise <strong>of</strong> the advent is sought to be<br />

released from the reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> the dominant metaphysics.<br />

Since this thought <strong>of</strong> the promise is inseparable from the problematic<br />

<strong>of</strong> time and gift, each <strong>of</strong> these thinkers is also thinker <strong>of</strong> gift which is<br />

pure donation from a time immemorial. Schelling, Heidegger, and<br />

Rosenzweig: they themselves form a confi guration <strong>of</strong> thinkers here.<br />

Th rough them and with their help a logic <strong>of</strong> origin—an inception to<br />

come—and therefore a notion <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong> time is elaborated<br />

in a constellation, or confi guration <strong>of</strong> repeated seizure <strong>of</strong> thoughts,<br />

and in a confi guration <strong>of</strong> questions. Th e intermittent, marked by<br />

interval and discontinuity, coming back again repetitively, but always<br />

singularly and diff erently to the question <strong>of</strong> the coming time and<br />

its logic <strong>of</strong> origin: this is the ‘gesture’ or ‘style’ <strong>of</strong> thinking here, the<br />

rhythm <strong>of</strong> the wandering poetizing. What follow are only exercises<br />

<strong>of</strong> repetition where sobriety <strong>of</strong> philosophical refl ection is not alien to<br />

the phosphorous poetic seizure in lightning fl ash.


Confi guration • 157<br />

Th inking that knows not, is never touched by the lightning<br />

fl ash <strong>of</strong> the coming is never intimated by the bursting open<br />

towards transcendence, or never exploded from within in ecstasy<br />

and astonishment. Such sober thinking is capable <strong>of</strong> nothing like<br />

venturing beyond. Without venturing beyond, thinking is a sterile<br />

absolute, mere humming monotony <strong>of</strong> the empty indiff erence, an<br />

infi nite boredom that busies itself with recollection <strong>of</strong> what has<br />

already happened, like the old woman on the spinning wheel that<br />

Kierkegaard speaks <strong>of</strong>. Such a sober thinking has long since become<br />

dead like, capable <strong>of</strong> nothing creative, but busies itself with singing<br />

the song <strong>of</strong> Minerva’s owl. Such a sterile thinking privileges boredom<br />

over ecstatic, creative transformation <strong>of</strong> the old into new. It is the<br />

eternal return <strong>of</strong> boredom: nothing happens, nothing comes anew,<br />

nothing repeats, nothing redeems, but only concept generating<br />

another concept, one category generating other categories—as<br />

Schelling mockingly refers to Hegel here—in a predictable, precalculable,<br />

mechanical manner, an auto-engendering and autoproducing<br />

logical generation <strong>of</strong> the Same. Th e creative thinking,<br />

on the other hand, must not shy away from the contingencies <strong>of</strong> a<br />

fi nite life, the ecstasy and the incalculability <strong>of</strong> the extremity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

future that foils our anticipation and our hope, the exuberance <strong>of</strong><br />

the unpredictable that can also bring the distress and melancholy<br />

<strong>of</strong> In-Vain. Instead <strong>of</strong> returning to the archaic past so that history<br />

can preserve in its ‘the gallery <strong>of</strong> images’ (Hegel 1998, p. 492) those<br />

shapes which the Spirit has passed through, and preserving the<br />

triumphal march <strong>of</strong> the victorious, the creative reading must be able<br />

to read—to speak with Walter Benjamin—what is not yet read, and<br />

through this reading, to cipher and to trace the messianic, redemptive<br />

element that were possible but never actualized. Meanwhile countless<br />

deaths <strong>of</strong> those whose hopes were destroyed and unredeemed in<br />

that dialectical march <strong>of</strong> history, have remained buried, forgotten<br />

and lost. Th erefore it is necessary that thinking may not be content<br />

with the historical memorial task, but gives itself to the demand <strong>of</strong><br />

redemption, the requirement <strong>of</strong> a coming, <strong>of</strong> a future outside the<br />

historical memory <strong>of</strong> the past is to be opened up. Th inking itself must<br />

be redeeming, otherwise it is not worthwhile. It must be able to begin<br />

again, venture itself again, forwards, in the front, in the open sea and<br />

under the blue sky.


158 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th inking must have future. Such a thinking that takes seriously the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> redemption and the requirement <strong>of</strong> a coming time is not<br />

content with claiming to sublate death into the concept, and thereby<br />

making death as mere vanity <strong>of</strong> the mortals. Instead, thinking must<br />

take the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> existence seriously: later is thinking that both<br />

Rosenzweig and Schelling pursue. Th ere must arrive a time that is<br />

promised, or intimated that remains beyond the works <strong>of</strong> death<br />

which universal history undertakes on the behalf <strong>of</strong> negativity. Th is<br />

time beyond negativity alone redeems all that has become, all that is<br />

unredeemed, this melancholy <strong>of</strong> existence. Even God, so Schelling says<br />

towards the end <strong>of</strong> his Philosophical Inquiry into the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

Freedom, would have been sunk into the abyss <strong>of</strong> melancholy, for he<br />

too had a source <strong>of</strong> melancholy within him, had he not transfi gured<br />

his sadness unto his creation out <strong>of</strong> his freedom. Creation transfi gures<br />

and thereby redeems our melancholic existence. Man partakes this<br />

task <strong>of</strong> transfi guration with the divine, for he too shares with God<br />

an essential freedom whose ground, however, is unfathomable. Man<br />

partakes <strong>of</strong> the divine task <strong>of</strong> transfi guration—<strong>of</strong> sorrows into joy,<br />

melancholy into hope—out <strong>of</strong> the freedom that is gifted to him,<br />

loaned to him, endowed upon him as created ones. But this freedom<br />

is ungrounded, or whose ground is inscrutable and unfathomable.<br />

To seek to master this ground constitutes man’s attempt at the selfabnegation<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own fi nitude. Th ere lies the mortal’s capacity for<br />

evil. Th erefore the task <strong>of</strong> thinking lays in-letting hold swaying <strong>of</strong> the<br />

open, and not seeking to master it by the violence <strong>of</strong> our power <strong>of</strong><br />

negativity. In this open region <strong>of</strong> freedom we are owned to the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> en-owning.<br />

Man is someone who asks the question <strong>of</strong> his own existence. Th is<br />

question is inextricably bound up with the question <strong>of</strong> his mortality<br />

and his fi nitude. As a mortal being, he asks what he can do out <strong>of</strong> his<br />

creative freedom. But what he can do—because he is mortal, fi nite<br />

being—only on the basis <strong>of</strong> an inappropriable grant, a non-economic<br />

gift, a non-masterable promise granted to him in advance. It is on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> what is not his capacity, mastery, or possession that mortality<br />

grants the mortals the gift <strong>of</strong> future. Only on the basis <strong>of</strong> this nonpower<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> coming time is gifted to the mortals. While<br />

this makes mortals melancholic, this is also an occasion <strong>of</strong> his joy. To<br />

remember this gift can be the highest thanking task <strong>of</strong> the mortals.


Part II<br />

The Lightning Flash


§ Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals<br />

Th is chapter attempts to think the relation <strong>of</strong> mortality to language<br />

anew. If language is not to be understood merely in its cognitive<br />

disposal—language as categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> ‘entities presently given’—<br />

then language in relation to mortality can no longer be determined<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> (Hegelian notion <strong>of</strong>) negativity alone. In so far as<br />

Hegel’s dialectical-speculative notion <strong>of</strong> language subsumes language<br />

in the service <strong>of</strong> a speculative universal, language here is reduced to its<br />

cognitive disposal. Th e attempt is made here to think language in a<br />

more originary manner, as non-negative fi nitude that affi rms what is<br />

outside dialectical-speculative closure, what is to come. What arrives,<br />

arrives in its lightning fl ash. Language is an originary exposure to the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> language in its lightning fl ash. Th is essay reads Heidegger,<br />

Schelling and Walter Benjamin to think language in its non-negative<br />

fi nitude, as an originary exposure to the messianic arrival <strong>of</strong> the ‘not<br />

yet’ (Bloch 1995). What at stake is the question <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

language, the messianic promise <strong>of</strong> what is ‘to come’, understood in<br />

the infi nitude <strong>of</strong> its verbal resonance: ‘to come’.<br />

THE PRESUPPOSITION<br />

*<br />

Th ere is more than one reason that a philosophical thinking begins<br />

with mortality as its presupposition. A philosophical thinking that<br />

does not make mortality the end result <strong>of</strong> a dialectical-historical<br />

process begins with mortality as presupposition or as the starting


162 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

point. Only that way philosophical thinking keeps open the way <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking to the coming time, time that survives death, remains after<br />

death. Th e way opens itself to time that is to arrive. Th e way is not<br />

‘way’ if it is to end with death, or if it makes death its end. Th e way,<br />

then, if does not have to end its ‘way’ character, has to make death as<br />

the point <strong>of</strong> departure rather than as the end point. Th at is why the<br />

way <strong>of</strong> thinking makes death itself as the starting point, not an end. It<br />

addresses death as question, or better, death addresses us as question,<br />

question that seizes us with the tremor <strong>of</strong> mortality, fascinates and<br />

astonishes us and touches us as destiny.<br />

Th e question why mortality seizes us as the question <strong>of</strong> destiny<br />

is the destinal question <strong>of</strong> language. Language does not make death<br />

the end result <strong>of</strong> a speculative process and that is why language holds<br />

us essentially in its promise, the promise <strong>of</strong> language that is at once<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> time yet to come. Only he who hears this promise, to<br />

whom this promise is granted fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, one who is fi nite and mortal,<br />

is open thereby what the way opens towards, that is—to the coming<br />

time, to the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the pure future. It will be illuminating<br />

here to discuss the later Heidegger’s thinking <strong>of</strong> language. Heidegger<br />

here attempts to think the promise <strong>of</strong> language which is essentially<br />

that <strong>of</strong> thinking the way, thinking on the way, thinking underway<br />

which is going under, thinking on the way to thinking, for the way<br />

grants to mortals in advance, it gives (es gibt) already—the advent,<br />

the coming to presence but not what has presently come as this or<br />

that coming amenable to the categorical, intelligible gaze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

knower. Th inking on the way is the promise <strong>of</strong> thinking that arrives<br />

in advance, before anything else, as immemorial and that is why it<br />

also appears as destinal. What gives in advance is called ‘inception’<br />

(Anfang), which is distinguished by Heidegger from ‘beginning’<br />

(Beginn). In his 1934-35 lectures on Hölderlin’s hymns ‘Germanien’<br />

and ‘Der Rhein’, Heidegger says,<br />

‘Beginn’—das ist etwas anderes als ‘Anfang’. Eine neue Wetterlage, z.<br />

B. beginnt mit einem Sturm, ihr anfang aber ist die vorauswirkende,<br />

völlige Umwandlung der Luftverhältnisse. Beginn ist jenes, womit<br />

etwas anhebt, Anfang das, woraus etwas enspringt. Der Weltkrieg<br />

fi ng an vor Jahrhunderten in der geistig-politishen Geschichte<br />

des Abenlandes. Der Weltkrieg begann Vorpostengefechten. Der


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 163<br />

Beginn wird alsbald zurückgelassen, er verschwindet im Fortgang<br />

des Geschehens. Der Anfang, der Ursprung, kommt dagagen im<br />

Geschehen allererst zum Vorschein und ist voll da erst an seinem<br />

Ende 1 (Heidegger 1980, p.3).<br />

In another lecture on language that is collected as On the Way to<br />

Language, Heidegger says <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong> this advent, <strong>of</strong> this<br />

inception: ‘For man is man only because he is granted the promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, because he is needful to language, that he may speak it’<br />

(Heidegger 1982, p.90).<br />

Th is ‘already’ the-there <strong>of</strong> promise that is granted to man in advance<br />

so that he may speak a language: how to think this ‘in advance’,<br />

which is not a being among beings, an entity among entities and<br />

that is given to man in a more originary manner than anything<br />

‘presently given’? It is not anything (‘presently given’) nor pure and<br />

simple nothingness <strong>of</strong> negativity with which Hegel’s Logic begins.<br />

How to think this the-there <strong>of</strong> the promise, or the gift <strong>of</strong> language<br />

if not as an essential, originary fi nitude, which already in advance<br />

grants the mortals the promise <strong>of</strong> language? Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

that seeks to hearken, listen to this promise <strong>of</strong> language begins with<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude and mortality, which is to be understood<br />

here in its non-negative fi nitude. Th e pain <strong>of</strong> this fi nitude that adheres<br />

to language is not the pain <strong>of</strong> the labour <strong>of</strong> the negative. We are here<br />

trying to think <strong>of</strong> a fi nitude and mortality that has another modality,<br />

another dimension than the dimension <strong>of</strong> negativity. To begin with<br />

death is not to make death a cognitive entity so as to ground the<br />

speculative historical process <strong>of</strong> a philosophical thinking. It is rather<br />

otherwise. If it is from language alone that we experience death as death,<br />

and that this language <strong>of</strong> man is already always seized by the tremor <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality, then mortality is precisely the non-condition, the unground<br />

that keeps the historical world open, like an open wound, to what is<br />

forever outside <strong>of</strong> what has come as unground, or as the-there . Th e event<br />

<strong>of</strong> language arrives as un-grounded clearing, or, as the un-ground <strong>of</strong><br />

a clearing, whose occurring is singular each time and irreducible to<br />

the universality and general order <strong>of</strong> the conceptual cognition. Th e<br />

ecstatic occurrence <strong>of</strong> this event <strong>of</strong> language is not one being among<br />

beings, not one category among categories, but is the originary<br />

opening, is the more primordial disclosure to what is not yet given.


164 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

In the beginning <strong>of</strong> his Being and <strong>Time</strong> (1962) Heidegger<br />

distinguishes existential in its originary apophantic dimension <strong>of</strong><br />

language from the categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> ‘presently given’ (Vorhandenheit)<br />

entities. What Heidegger there refers to as ‘Da’ <strong>of</strong> Dasein, as the there,<br />

the facticity <strong>of</strong> Dasein—Dasein whose being is being-towards-death—<br />

is also thereby essentially, in the innermost manner, a linguistic<br />

existence whose existentiality is this being-towards-death. Dasein is<br />

that existence whose ‘Da’ lies in the originary apophansis <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

even before language comes to be categorical and predicative <strong>of</strong><br />

‘presently given entities’. In section B <strong>of</strong> 7 that belongs to the<br />

Introduction II <strong>of</strong> Being and <strong>Time</strong>, Heidegger attempts to understand<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> Logos in a more originary manner than as mere locus<br />

<strong>of</strong> logical truth. Logos is understood here as originary disclosure <strong>of</strong><br />

this existentiality <strong>of</strong> existence called Dasein whose existentiality is this<br />

‘being-towards-death’. It is this intimate connection between the logos<br />

<strong>of</strong> language with the logos <strong>of</strong> mortality that precisely makes fi rst <strong>of</strong> all<br />

Dasein as existence irreducible to the entities ‘presently given’, this<br />

event <strong>of</strong> language irreducible to the truth <strong>of</strong> logic in its propositional,<br />

predicative structure. Th erefore the task <strong>of</strong> Destruktion der Ontologie<br />

(as one <strong>of</strong> the two fold tasks <strong>of</strong> Being and <strong>Time</strong>) accompanies the<br />

‘destruction’ <strong>of</strong> traditional logic in its propositional-predicative<br />

structure in order to reveal, in retrogressive manner, the buried,<br />

originary pre-supposition, which is, the existentiality <strong>of</strong> a linguistic<br />

existence as being-towards-death. Th e existence whose existentiality<br />

is this ‘toward-ness’, this ahead-ness (understood in the infi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

the verbal resonance <strong>of</strong> ‘to’) towards its own impossibility, to its own<br />

nothingness and abyss—and in so far as this toward-ness to death<br />

fi rst <strong>of</strong> all discloses itself in the originary existential-apophansis <strong>of</strong><br />

language—existence is therefore already always attuned to language,<br />

essentially, and in the innermost manner. What Heidegger here<br />

attempts to think in the name ‘logos’ to which mortals in their beingtowards-death<br />

are attuned to, and yet which cannot be appropriated<br />

by these mortals, is not ‘reason’ <strong>of</strong> ‘human’ as against the sheer brutal,<br />

instinctive assertion <strong>of</strong> brute being-among-beings, but the originary<br />

apophansis before the categorical grasp, that lies even before what<br />

Edmund Husserl refers to as ‘categorical intuition’ 2 .<br />

Taking this point from Heidegger as point <strong>of</strong> departure, we<br />

venture forward to say that language is not primarily predicative


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 165<br />

locus <strong>of</strong> ‘truth’ as the truth <strong>of</strong> what has appeared, but enablingclearing,<br />

disclosing-appearing <strong>of</strong> the unapparent, which is without<br />

name and without concept, which in the midst <strong>of</strong> existing opens<br />

from the heart <strong>of</strong> existence like an yawning abyss, which seizes those<br />

mortals who speak with fear and trembling. Language then, if I am<br />

allowed to say this, is the site <strong>of</strong> this unapparent apparition, which is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> existence that is prior to the entities ‘presently given’. It is<br />

as if the event <strong>of</strong> language is each time born out <strong>of</strong> an abyss that<br />

remains outside us like an eternal remainder <strong>of</strong> non-knowledge,<br />

the abyss where language ruins itself while incessantly, interminably<br />

moving towards it as if towards its own essence, that means, towards<br />

its outside. Language <strong>of</strong> this linguistic existence is this being-towards<br />

its own ruination on the basis <strong>of</strong> which the unapparent apparition<br />

takes places, erupts in the midst <strong>of</strong> existing.<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> language is this event <strong>of</strong> existence itself whose<br />

existentiality lies in its toward-ness to its un-working-ruination where<br />

the intensity <strong>of</strong> the moment <strong>of</strong> ripeness is at once its dissolution<br />

and sinking unto nothing without being converted into being, as<br />

if language in its ripeness and plenitude coincides with its own<br />

dissolution. Th e simultaneity <strong>of</strong> the ripeness and its ruination,<br />

fullness and dissolution, arises like lightning which language in its<br />

inability to contain itself, at once points to, indicates to what is<br />

outside all representation, rendering the outside as wholly otherwise<br />

manifestation, the unapparent, the bluish evaporating <strong>of</strong> death.<br />

Death at once makes manifestation possible, while ruining the works<br />

<strong>of</strong> any fi guration. Th e intensity <strong>of</strong> the moment is this dis-fi guring<br />

expropriation <strong>of</strong> language from its own gathering, rendering language<br />

to say the unsayable and to unsay the sayable, to point towards at<br />

once, simultaneously, what language is and what language is not.<br />

Language is this strange monstrous site whereas Kierkegaard says 3 ,<br />

opposing Epicurus—where death is, I am as this linguistic being is<br />

there; in other words, which is to say, ‘ I am there where I am not<br />

there’, where this simultaneity <strong>of</strong> ‘ where I am’ and ‘where I am not’<br />

is without reconciliation, without synthesis . Language presents this<br />

simultaneity <strong>of</strong> the disjoining—‘<strong>of</strong> ‘where I am’ and ‘I am not’—<br />

this discontinuous continuity, or continuous discontinuity as dieresis<br />

where non-being intensifi es itself more being insists in itself, like an<br />

infi nite debt where the debt increases itself more we pay <strong>of</strong>f , as a


166 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

result there never occurs the instant when the debt and pay <strong>of</strong>f is<br />

leveled <strong>of</strong>f , when ‘being and nothing is the same’.<br />

Unlike Hegel’s speculative-logical determination <strong>of</strong> beginning,<br />

language neither begins with the identity <strong>of</strong> being and nothing, nor<br />

ends there. Th is instant when the being and nothing is the same can<br />

happen only in logical system where nothing really happens at all<br />

in so far as all happening here is merely a logical movement but not<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> existence. Th e event <strong>of</strong> existence begins, because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

inextricable fi nitude and mortality, as indebted, as—what Schelling<br />

(1936) call—‘loan’. Th is infi nite loan is the presupposition <strong>of</strong> an<br />

‘already there’, ‘the-there’ as facticity <strong>of</strong> existence, an immemorial,<br />

infi nite past. Th is facticity and presupposition <strong>of</strong> language with<br />

which the event <strong>of</strong> existence begins is unlike Hegel’s system <strong>of</strong> logic,<br />

for Hegel’s logical system does not need presupposition in order to<br />

constitute itself as system. Th is presupposition <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

which is also the event <strong>of</strong> existence, is nothing but this mortality itself<br />

which Hegel’s system has to exclude in order to be an all inclusive<br />

system, as All. It is because <strong>of</strong> this exclusion Hegel’s all inclusive<br />

system remains outside language, and outside existence, for the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> language is essentially pre-suppositional, i.e., it presupposes not<br />

what is ‘presently given’, but the unapparent that strikes language<br />

with its lighting fl ash. It presupposes, indebted to what it is not in<br />

order to be language, which is its structural condition <strong>of</strong> possibility,<br />

its opening moment, it’s coming into existence as language.<br />

Th e structural opening <strong>of</strong> each discourse—in so far as each<br />

discourse is fi nite inextricably—begins as gratitude, as thankfulness<br />

for its coming into existence, for the gift <strong>of</strong> its existence which is never<br />

paid <strong>of</strong>f . Th e infi nitude <strong>of</strong> this gratitude in so far as this gratitude is<br />

never leveled <strong>of</strong>f with the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> this existence, in so far as more<br />

the infi nitude increases more fi nitude <strong>of</strong> existence expands itself,<br />

transcends itself, ecstatically goes beyond itself—<strong>of</strong> what Schelling<br />

calls this ‘exuberant being’—the moment in existence itself is never<br />

reached when existence is equal to what it is indebted to, to what is<br />

its presupposition, to what is the condition <strong>of</strong> its possibility. So it<br />

is with language. Language is never equal to its own presupposition,<br />

never equal to itself, is never equal to—how to say this?—its own<br />

nothing, its own fi nitude, its own limit and its own mortality that<br />

in a manner <strong>of</strong> un-apparition, gives to language its open-ness to its


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 167<br />

own arrival. Th e event <strong>of</strong> language whose existentiality is this beingtowards-its-own-nothing<br />

never can appropriate this ‘toward-ness’<br />

simply because this ‘toward-ness’ is its presupposition to which it<br />

never attains, from which it already always falls <strong>of</strong>f , more exuberantly<br />

it moves towards this ‘toward-ness’, more ecstatic is this movement,<br />

more and more it affi rms itself. Language in this eventive character<br />

is, paradoxically, an infi nite impoverishment and infi nite plenitude at<br />

once that forever draws it out <strong>of</strong> its limit and exposes it to the pure<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. Th e movement <strong>of</strong> language is this moving<br />

towards its own essence, its fulfi llment as language, its happiness<br />

and its plenitude that is also its ruination. Th is aporia <strong>of</strong> language—<br />

its dieresis—is never sublated into speculative reconciliation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

synthesis; rather, synthesis here is excluded as excluded synthesis,<br />

<strong>of</strong> what Rosenzweig calls ‘an excluding All’ (Rosenzweig 2005, 19).<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> thinking that begins with language, therefore, begins<br />

with presupposition, which is this radical fi nitude, this mortality <strong>of</strong><br />

language, and its indebt-ness to what is outside thinkable and outside<br />

system, namely, the unapparent advent <strong>of</strong> language itself coming into<br />

presence, beyond all the visible, apparent forms <strong>of</strong> ‘the presently given<br />

entities’.<br />

Franz Rosenzweig’s Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption begins with this question<br />

<strong>of</strong> presupposition. It begins with the interrogation <strong>of</strong> that claim which<br />

the system as philosophy <strong>of</strong> All makes on behalf <strong>of</strong> thinkable that it<br />

does not presuppose anything. Th is claim—that it is presuppositionless—is<br />

the presuppositional condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

system at all, the presupposition that death is nothing, or rather that<br />

death must be thinkable, if at all there be anything like thinkable.<br />

What makes thinkable alone ‘thinkable’ is the presupposition that it<br />

is presupposition-less. Th is alone makes, by reducing the unapparent<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the pure arrival <strong>of</strong> the language into apparent, visible<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> the ‘categorical intuition’, the system <strong>of</strong> knowledge, <strong>of</strong> light<br />

and <strong>of</strong> its ontological intelligibility. Th erefore death is nothing in the<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> All. It has to cast aside death’s ‘poisonous sting’ and<br />

‘its pestilential breath’, the fear and trembling which is heard in each<br />

mortal cry in the face <strong>of</strong> death. Th at this philosophy <strong>of</strong> All has to<br />

deny the presupposition <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> existence—existential facticity<br />

that the ‘nothing <strong>of</strong> death is something’—this philosophy also has<br />

to be thereby bereft <strong>of</strong> language. Th e presupposition <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong>


168 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

language is the unthinkability <strong>of</strong> death, but an unthinkability which<br />

is for that matter not pure nothing but something, a mortal ‘pitiless<br />

cry’, from where thinking begins, from where language erupts—with<br />

a nothing that is something. Rosenzweig then says:<br />

But when philosophy denies the dark presupposition <strong>of</strong> all life, when<br />

it does not value death as something, but makes it into nothing, it<br />

gives itself that appearance <strong>of</strong> having no presupposition. In fact, all<br />

cognition <strong>of</strong> the All has for its presupposition—nothing. For the one<br />

and universal cognition <strong>of</strong> the All, only the one and universal nothing<br />

is valid. If philosophy did not want to stop its ears before the cry<br />

<strong>of</strong> frightened humanity, it would have to take the following as its<br />

point <strong>of</strong> departure—and consciously as its point <strong>of</strong> departure—the<br />

nothing <strong>of</strong> death is a something, each renewed nothing <strong>of</strong> death is a<br />

new something that frightens anew, and that cannot be passed over in<br />

silence, nor be silenced. (Ibid., p.11).<br />

What cannot be included therefore within the universal representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy as the cognition <strong>of</strong> the All is this facticity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

nothing that is something, this unthinkable presupposition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> existence, this presuppositional opening that each time<br />

enables language to erupt and ruin itself. It is with this presupposition<br />

that, like Rosenzweig’s text, that we shall begin here. It is this<br />

presuppositional opening that discloses existence its own fi nitude, its<br />

inextricable, indescribable, unthinkable mortality that ties existence<br />

to its own condition <strong>of</strong> possibility and impossibility at the same time,<br />

so that one who exists has to say—if he is not duping himself in<br />

the deception <strong>of</strong> a philosophical promise—that when one is, one is<br />

not. When one says, each time one says, as Kierkegaard—‘when I<br />

am, I am not’—this saying occurs, erupts each time with such fear<br />

and trembling, with such stammering, with such anguish and tremor<br />

chocking one’s throat, which must be the throat <strong>of</strong> language. Th e<br />

anguish <strong>of</strong> language lies in its presuppositional structure in the face<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unthinkable advent <strong>of</strong> the un-apparition, which is outside the<br />

presupposition-less, harmless, sterile cognition <strong>of</strong> the thinkable. Th e<br />

real event <strong>of</strong> thinking begins here, with its dark presupposition, with<br />

the anguish and terror <strong>of</strong> language that means, with the un-thinkable,<br />

with—what Schelling calls—the ‘un-pre-thinkable’ (Unvordenkliche),<br />

with the actuality before mere potentiality <strong>of</strong> concepts, with the<br />

facticity <strong>of</strong> the ungrund which precedes all grounding. It is this event


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 169<br />

<strong>of</strong> language from which alone we know death as death, where the<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> the unapparent arrives in lighting fl ash, opening<br />

this abyss at the heart <strong>of</strong> all thinkability, <strong>of</strong> all explication, <strong>of</strong> all<br />

interpretation, <strong>of</strong> all grounding acts <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

A mortal thinking that begins with its dark presupposition, with<br />

the anguish and terror in the face <strong>of</strong> pitiless death, has therefore<br />

to be a language-thinking, not language as mere medium <strong>of</strong> spirit,<br />

as mere means <strong>of</strong> communication at the cognitive disposal <strong>of</strong> the<br />

categorical apparatus, but a thinking that is essentially linguistic in<br />

its inextricable presupposition. As death is sought to be domesticated<br />

in the system <strong>of</strong> visible forms, so language is reduced to its categorical<br />

function <strong>of</strong> grasping apparent, visible entities ‘presently given’ at its<br />

cognitive disposal 4 . Th is language does not primarily belong, without<br />

remainder, to the world <strong>of</strong> negativity constituted by the work <strong>of</strong><br />

synthesis, nor is language primordially in the cognitive function <strong>of</strong><br />

the speculative-historical judgement. By not completely belonging<br />

to the dialectical-historical closure, language opens itself to the nonconditional<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the inception that is outside synthesis, outside<br />

the reconciliatory pathos <strong>of</strong> dialectical history. What is bestowed by<br />

language upon man as gift opens in this abyss, which is the Open,<br />

not the ontological or topological site, but the monstrous site<br />

where the unapparent event arrives incalculably. It is in this sense<br />

the early Heidegger too attempted to understand the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

‘hermeneutic’ in conjunction with language beyond its predicative,<br />

categorical function (Heidegger 1999b): the inextricably linguistic<br />

mortal being is that who is abandoned to the open space where<br />

Being itself advents. Th is advent <strong>of</strong> Being strikes the language that<br />

welcomes, announces—because it is already always disclosed open<br />

to the event, is enowned (appropriated) to the event—its unapparent<br />

presencing to presence. Only in so far as the gift originates as if from<br />

an abyss that there can be something like gift, that there is gift for<br />

the one who himself is marked by death, has his ground like an abyss<br />

that is outside his mastery, outside his power. Th is gift is the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

language.<br />

Walter Benjamin in his beautiful text called Language as Such<br />

and Language <strong>of</strong> Man recognizes a touch <strong>of</strong> melancholy in the acts<br />

<strong>of</strong> overnaming that forgets this gift <strong>of</strong> language, when language<br />

becomes for him mere medium <strong>of</strong> communication, mere medium


170 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> man’s assertion <strong>of</strong> his power to name, in other words, when<br />

name becomes overnaming, namely, the language <strong>of</strong> judgement.<br />

As if language itself suff ers here by being reduced to inscription, to<br />

that draft at the cognitive disposal, where death, instead <strong>of</strong> being<br />

that originary fi nitude which is gift <strong>of</strong> the creaturely existence,<br />

becomes—in being overnamed—prattle. Benjamin calls the ceaseless<br />

overnaming that has already lost the gift-character <strong>of</strong> language given<br />

with the paradisiacal Naming <strong>of</strong> proper names, as prattle. Th erefore<br />

the categorical language is bereft <strong>of</strong> the character <strong>of</strong> proper name,<br />

for the proper name appears as gift from the wholly other to the<br />

one who is singular, irreducible and who as the irreducible one, is<br />

summoned forth by the gift <strong>of</strong> this name to face the sign <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

that language, in its irreducibility to propositions and predications,<br />

points towards, in the hint <strong>of</strong> its showing.<br />

Taking this clue from Benjamin, we can go forth to say that<br />

the proper name, therefore, is borne out <strong>of</strong> the encounter with<br />

the singular, inescapable, inextricable death as death, and out <strong>of</strong><br />

this encounter with this death, to be responsible to the others who<br />

are mortals. Th e proper name is far from property or propriety <strong>of</strong><br />

the one who bears the proper name; he can neither appropriate<br />

his own name nor can he bear it like property <strong>of</strong> his self-identity.<br />

He is already always dispropriated from anything like self-identity<br />

by virtue <strong>of</strong> being endowed with a proper name, for he is already<br />

always responsible to the other (from where language immemorially<br />

arrives to him as gift) —who is yet to come—a responsibility that has<br />

already always occurred to him, a responsibility that is presupposed<br />

in being endowed with a proper name. To be endowed with a proper<br />

name is not being able to be oneself, a solitary and self-enclosed,<br />

autochthonous entity. It is rather to encounter, on the basis <strong>of</strong> an<br />

originary dispropriation, the other mortals to whom one is responsible<br />

and to other time, when the time <strong>of</strong> the meaning <strong>of</strong> the address is<br />

the not yet. It is to introduce temporality into discourse, the time <strong>of</strong><br />

an infi nite future at the heart <strong>of</strong> fi nitude so that the address to the<br />

others appears as infi nite transcendence in relation to the one who<br />

confronts death as death.<br />

Th is transcendence is the presupposition outside <strong>of</strong> language<br />

by virtue <strong>of</strong> which language appears as language, language that<br />

encounters death as death. Since this death appears to mortals in


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 171<br />

its imminent uncertainty as advent <strong>of</strong> futurity, language therefore<br />

can never become self-enclosed autochthonous entity, but constantly<br />

points itself towards, goes ahead to the undecidability <strong>of</strong> the unknown<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent. Th is transcendence which does not have a<br />

topos <strong>of</strong> its own cannot be named, precisely because it is the event <strong>of</strong><br />

naming itself.<br />

Kierkegaard’s Indirect Communication<br />

Th erefore the gift <strong>of</strong> language always bears the mark <strong>of</strong> death. Søren<br />

Kierkegaard knew something <strong>of</strong> this: that the gift, which is the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> death, is also thereby a singular experience <strong>of</strong> transcendence, an<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> the-there, which is ‘death’s decision’, a trembling and<br />

a cry. Th is ‘death’s decision’ (Kierkegaard 1993, pp. 71-102) which<br />

gives ‘earnestness’ to existence, which is the utmost existential<br />

interest <strong>of</strong> the singular being with a proper name, refuses to serve<br />

the interests <strong>of</strong> the universal Spirit; it is what does not belong to<br />

the ethical order <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> visible forms. Its claim is then to<br />

be sought elsewhere, in that Archimedean point where language<br />

presents the un-presentable as discontinuous presentation, as<br />

dis-fi guring, momentary advent, whose singularity <strong>of</strong> occurrence<br />

suspends the universal order <strong>of</strong> generality. Kierkegaard does not<br />

abandon language as insuffi cient to express the arrival <strong>of</strong> the divine,<br />

or, as merely expression <strong>of</strong> the universal ethical Spirit that dialectically<br />

constitutes the historical-speculative world. What is more interesting<br />

is Kierkegaard’s recognition <strong>of</strong> language’s insuffi ciency in relation<br />

to itself, the incommensurability between the singular eruption <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> its coming and the universal claims <strong>of</strong> the Speculative<br />

history in its categorical claims to grasp the result <strong>of</strong> a becoming,<br />

which is the process <strong>of</strong> a universal history. Language that is marked<br />

by ‘death’s decision’ (because death is what is unpresentable in the<br />

negative labour <strong>of</strong> a conceptual language) opens the fi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

language to the un-presentable apparition <strong>of</strong> the unapparent, tearing<br />

language from itself in fear and trembling and giving over to its<br />

ruination. Neither this ‘death’s decision’ nor this language at the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> cognition is communicable in the generality <strong>of</strong> the concept,<br />

or within the ethical realm <strong>of</strong> the universal where each particular<br />

is homogenous with others, exchangeable with others. As such, this


172 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

language can only be indirect communication that bears—or cannot<br />

bear—the mark <strong>of</strong> ‘death’s decision’ which refuses to belong to the<br />

universal ethical realm which is produced by the labour <strong>of</strong> negativity.<br />

Language neither presents itself as the self-presentation <strong>of</strong> the spirit <strong>of</strong><br />

negativity nor presents its absence. Language rather marks, remarks,<br />

demarks ‘death’s decision’ which renders language irreducible,<br />

incommensurable, non-contemporaneous to the ethical claims <strong>of</strong> a<br />

universal history. Th is language is not readable and decipherable in<br />

the universal Book, or in the system <strong>of</strong> the ethical without remainder.<br />

Th is remainder is what Kierkegaard calls secret.<br />

If the indirect communication is marked by ‘death’s decision’, it<br />

is because its incommensurable diff erential places, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, the one<br />

who speaks outside <strong>of</strong> all communication. As Kierkegaard knew, this<br />

alone enables transcendence to arrive, bursting out <strong>of</strong> closure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence, i.e., from the ethical realm <strong>of</strong> generality.<br />

Th is advent <strong>of</strong> transcendence is neither the plenitude <strong>of</strong> pure presence<br />

(Parousia <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject) nor impoverishment that<br />

arises out <strong>of</strong> the need <strong>of</strong> the subject that needs to be nourished. It<br />

is rather the arrival as the fullness <strong>of</strong> time that at once darkens the<br />

presencing <strong>of</strong> presence with the excess <strong>of</strong> its brilliance. Th is darkness<br />

<strong>of</strong> light that suddenly makes its appearance is not the fusion unto<br />

transcendence but a diff erentiating transcendence, a holding-togetheras-holding-apart.<br />

Th erefore it does not work like Hegelian speculative<br />

judgement that bears its own dissolution within it, converting its own<br />

dissolution unto the unity <strong>of</strong> the concept or the Subject. Th erefore<br />

unlike the speculative judgement <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical, this<br />

‘death’s decision’ does not form historical-dialectical totalities, but<br />

mark this demonic, monstrous disjunctive co-fi guration, which is the<br />

site <strong>of</strong> more originary historicity than speculative universal history.<br />

It bears the anguishing face <strong>of</strong> that originary melancholy that is<br />

touched by ‘death’s decision’. It is the melancholic face <strong>of</strong> the singular<br />

this being who bears a proper name called Søren Kierkegaard, who<br />

bears ‘thorn in the fl esh’, because—in so far he is—bears the decision<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘is not’, which is ‘death’s decision’.<br />

Indirect communication is nothing negative, but rather it affi rms<br />

what is outside the communicable entities <strong>of</strong> the given world.<br />

What, then, indirect communication affi rms is the event <strong>of</strong>


Th e Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals • 173<br />

communication, that moment <strong>of</strong> eruption <strong>of</strong> pure communication,<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone the singular individual, being fi rst placed<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> all given modes <strong>of</strong> communication—that means being<br />

abandoned in the open—communicates with the transcendent<br />

arrival. Th at means, the mortal existent communicates and makes<br />

communication the essential <strong>of</strong> his existence by fi rst <strong>of</strong> all being<br />

placed outside all communication, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all being deprived or<br />

being excess <strong>of</strong> all communication. He names—for man is someone<br />

who is essentially name-giver—by fi rst <strong>of</strong> all being placed outside<br />

the name, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all being deprived <strong>of</strong> the name, or being excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> the name. One, whose essential being lies in communication,<br />

communicates by being placed outside all communication. One<br />

whose essential being lies in naming, names by being placed<br />

outside all the given names. He then derives communication from<br />

an essential non-communication and naming from an essential<br />

namelessness.<br />

Th is essential solitude <strong>of</strong> language renders language irreducible to<br />

any cognitive function <strong>of</strong> a categorial-logical thinking. Th is noncommunication<br />

<strong>of</strong> communication, this ecstatic solitude, which for<br />

Kierkegaard is also an intimation <strong>of</strong> transcendence, is the secret <strong>of</strong><br />

language. Secret is not the interiority <strong>of</strong> an individual consciousness<br />

shut within itself, nor is it the treasure which the isolated self keeps<br />

it for itself as kernel <strong>of</strong> consciousness, shut from the divine and other<br />

mortals. It is rather the ecstatic solitude <strong>of</strong> language, bursting out <strong>of</strong> any<br />

self-enclosure unto an ecstatic transcendence, a non-communicating<br />

communication with the outside, an ecstatic relation to the event <strong>of</strong><br />

coming which is not ‘the presently given entities’, which does not<br />

yet exist in the already existing manner <strong>of</strong> communication. Th e<br />

language <strong>of</strong> naming, unlike the categorical language <strong>of</strong> judgement at<br />

its cognitive instrumentality is ecstatic because it ex-tatically ex-sists<br />

the nameable.<br />

Secret is the name <strong>of</strong> transcendence, the event that is not yet <strong>of</strong><br />

communication, which in order to affi rm the arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly<br />

otherwise, must step outside communication in ethical terms.<br />

Th erefore Abraham keeps silent. He does not speak in ethical terms,<br />

for he has to <strong>of</strong>f er, what is commanded him to <strong>of</strong>f er, is the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

death. Th e secret is the event <strong>of</strong> language itself that opens and yet


174 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

withdraws from any self-presentation, and announcing the advent <strong>of</strong><br />

the outside, which is the name <strong>of</strong> the pure future that belongs to the<br />

entirely heterogeneous order, completely incommensurable to the<br />

order <strong>of</strong> generality represented by the ethical, universal signifi cation.<br />

If language itself is tied to an originary fi nitude, to its own ruination,<br />

it is in so far as this originary fi nitude is the opening <strong>of</strong> language<br />

from any self-enclosure and self-presence, not at the same time in the<br />

name <strong>of</strong> an absence opposed to presence, but as oblique coming, as<br />

what Derrida (1995) calls ‘oblique <strong>of</strong>f ering’.<br />

Th is demands that the question <strong>of</strong> pain is needed to be renewed<br />

here. Th e completely heterogeneous order where the singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mortal, with his irreducible suff ering and anguish in the face <strong>of</strong> death<br />

is not evaded in the name <strong>of</strong> the generality <strong>of</strong> the ethical signifi cation<br />

is the order where language which the singular mortal speaks must<br />

assume entirety diff erent modality than the modality <strong>of</strong> signifi cation.<br />

For Kierkegaard such an essential language, more originary than the<br />

language <strong>of</strong> signifi cation, assumes a form <strong>of</strong> address, which is prayer<br />

addressed to the unapparent advent <strong>of</strong> the completely other, the<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly Other that seizes us by its gaze and transfi xes us.<br />

In the language <strong>of</strong> prayer alone the suff ering mortal is open to the<br />

redemptive happiness arriving from a wholly otherwise destination,<br />

from an immemorial past and from an incalculable, pure future<br />

beyond the immanence <strong>of</strong> self-present now instants.


§ Pain<br />

Work and Pain<br />

Let us say, to begin with, and provisionally, naively, that it is possible<br />

to think <strong>of</strong> pain in two diff erent manners, entirely heterogeneous,<br />

irreducible <strong>of</strong> the one to the other. And we will see how this question<br />

<strong>of</strong> pain in its diff erential relation to the universal is also the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> language and communication, and above all, it is the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the gift, the gift where language itself is given to the mortals whose<br />

essence is essentially that <strong>of</strong> being linguistic, i.e., as being-in-language,<br />

being-belonging-to language. Such a being is essentially linguistic in<br />

the sense that he is the being (in his absolute singularity) who is fi rst<br />

<strong>of</strong> all open to himself and to others—the divine, the elemental forces<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature and those created beings—on the basis <strong>of</strong> this language that<br />

he speaks and in speaking, never being able to appropriate it and by<br />

belonging to language already always, immemorially which has never<br />

been his present.<br />

If man is the one who communicates, and speaks language, whose<br />

being is essentially, in the innermost manner, is this linguistic being<br />

(whose linguistic being consists in his being in communication, being<br />

as communicative, being as this opening to itself in communication),<br />

then does this communication, this being able to communicate<br />

enable him to bring to language that the-there (Da), this facticity<br />

<strong>of</strong> language itself, which fi rst <strong>of</strong> all already places him outside <strong>of</strong><br />

himself, that already tears him apart from himself and dispropriates<br />

him in advance? In other words, can he give to language that what<br />

language itself already gives him, promises him so that he may speak


176 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

language itself as such? If language alone enables him to experience<br />

death as death by tearing him, distantiating him, holding him apart<br />

from himself so that he can be near to himself (in language), does<br />

he thereby bring to language <strong>of</strong> signifi cation this experience <strong>of</strong> death<br />

itself, this tearing, this trembling and the seizure? If language is this<br />

tearing apart <strong>of</strong> being from himself, this distantiating <strong>of</strong> being from<br />

oneself in an originary manner so that there be nearness <strong>of</strong> being to<br />

oneself and to the other, so that in speaking man addresses to the<br />

other and to himself, so that man prays for the other on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> this language, does he thereby bring to language this distance and<br />

nearness on the basis <strong>of</strong> his power and capacity to speak? Or rather,<br />

on the other hand, that man speaks on the basis <strong>of</strong> an originary<br />

given-ness and a donation, a gift outside all conditions and outside<br />

all predicates, which is the very donation <strong>of</strong> language itself? In what<br />

language <strong>of</strong> the mortals, language itself is given? If the gift and the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> language is marked by death, the gift which fi rst <strong>of</strong> all<br />

bestows him the possibility to speak at all, is he thereby able to speak<br />

<strong>of</strong> death, to know death and even to make death the origin <strong>of</strong> a<br />

process whereby he comes to himself, becomes himself, becomes the<br />

origin and end <strong>of</strong> his own becoming? Is he able thereby to make this<br />

gift immanent to the process <strong>of</strong> his own initiation, making death as<br />

his own, his very own possibility and capacity?<br />

If language were the site <strong>of</strong> mortal’s power to bring to language<br />

his own mortality—and this is our fi rst step, out fi rst consideration<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking pain in relation to language—death would then be the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> the negative that yields the results <strong>of</strong> his own becoming.<br />

Man would then be, primordially and essentially, that being whose<br />

task, whose work—in so far as it is his possibility, capacity, his<br />

power—is to make the beginning <strong>of</strong> his becoming his own. Man<br />

would then be that being—in relation to his non-power, which is his<br />

dissolution, his death—he is the only one to discover, at the heart <strong>of</strong><br />

his non-power, his power to be that maintains, confronting the horror<br />

<strong>of</strong> one’s dissolution, his ground so that he can bring to language<br />

that he speaks, this nothingness itself. If man is the one who names,<br />

whose essential being is that he is the name-giver, the descendent <strong>of</strong><br />

Adam, then he also must be the one who names fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, before<br />

all names, what must be the unnamable itself, from which it will<br />

then be confi rmed his pure power to name not only the namable but


Pain • 177<br />

the unnamable itself. Only on the basis <strong>of</strong> this ability to name the<br />

unnamable, the capacity (or the possibility or the power) to name<br />

at all can be derived. In other words, man is the one who names—<br />

death. Man is this one being, the central being who, confronting with<br />

horror his own dissolution, names his own absence, and through this<br />

naming power, bringing near this absence as his very proper to his<br />

presence. Language is then not that which shrinks from horror; rather<br />

the horror <strong>of</strong> language consists in its being able to bring to man who<br />

speaks this absence into presence, in this being to recount for man<br />

the story <strong>of</strong> his own birth as an experience <strong>of</strong> death. Language is here<br />

assumes a terrible, magical power <strong>of</strong> conjuration that conjures the<br />

absence into presence, death into birth, and through this magical<br />

power, inaugurates another beginning which is man’s destinal history.<br />

Th is power <strong>of</strong> language, therefore, neither in itself is the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence, nor that <strong>of</strong> pure absence, but the movement <strong>of</strong> absence<br />

becoming presence in signifi cation. In the word ‘Cat’, the cat has<br />

neither (empirical) presence nor its absence, but the absence (<strong>of</strong> the<br />

empirical) becoming presence (as Idea). It is this movement—<strong>of</strong><br />

absence into presence—which Hegel captured with the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

Aufhebung. It is the movement <strong>of</strong> power that has felt in its vein the<br />

pain and horror <strong>of</strong> dissolution and disappearance, ‘the way <strong>of</strong> despair’<br />

that Hegel speaks (Hegel 1998, p. 49) <strong>of</strong>, but it is this pain and<br />

horror does not go in vain since it simultaneously heralds the birth <strong>of</strong><br />

man and the beginning <strong>of</strong> man’s destinal history.<br />

Here Hegel brings out this peculiar connection that language has<br />

in relation to power and death: language’s power to inaugurate and<br />

accomplish history, because it is the power <strong>of</strong> death, <strong>of</strong> what Hegel<br />

calls as ‘the work <strong>of</strong> death’ (Ibid., p. 270). Language is that ‘work<br />

<strong>of</strong> death’ that conjures even absence into presence, and this process<br />

which inaugurates history is that ‘way <strong>of</strong> despair’. Hegel’s speculative<br />

dialectical process, shows how this power <strong>of</strong> the negative constitutes<br />

for man his universal history out <strong>of</strong> the labour man himself initiates<br />

without any transcendental ground given to him independently.<br />

According to this metaphysics <strong>of</strong> man’s destinal history, man is the one<br />

who suff ers the pain for his own result—the result <strong>of</strong> his becoming—and<br />

his result redeems his suff erings. Who more than Hegel has provided the<br />

tragic drama <strong>of</strong> this suff ering <strong>of</strong> fi nitude and its atonement? Ultimately<br />

for Hegel this redemption or atonement consists <strong>of</strong> man being able


178 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

to assume the origin <strong>of</strong> his history at the end <strong>of</strong> history, so that he<br />

appropriates, through the pain and horror <strong>of</strong> the negativity, his own<br />

beginning at his end; he arrives at the end, because he is already always<br />

there at the moment <strong>of</strong> inauguration, as the one confronting with<br />

horror his own death as other’s death. As the coinciding <strong>of</strong> beginning<br />

with end, the atoned consciousness <strong>of</strong> man is Spirit. Language is seen<br />

here as the manifestation <strong>of</strong> this metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Spirit, which is an<br />

externalized interiority, or an internalized exteriority, in so far as it is<br />

a presentation <strong>of</strong> Sense, the Sense <strong>of</strong> absence itself. As a presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Sense, language itself work <strong>of</strong> the negative that is attuned to pain,<br />

but as accomplishment <strong>of</strong> Sense, language is also atonement <strong>of</strong> that<br />

grief, <strong>of</strong> that fi nitude, since it has subsumed within itself and never<br />

given away to that ‘way <strong>of</strong> despair’. As an accomplishment <strong>of</strong> Sense,<br />

language is also accomplishment <strong>of</strong> time—as the eternity <strong>of</strong> Absolute<br />

Idea, as ‘the infi nite negativity’ that has time within itself—for sense<br />

always appears as time. As absolute presentation <strong>of</strong> Sense, language is<br />

now co-incident with Spirit, as it is co-incident with eternity. It has<br />

now appropriated its own origin and end as circular reappropriation<br />

<strong>of</strong> its self-same diff erence.<br />

Hence Hegelian metaphysics is metaphysics <strong>of</strong> immanence. It is<br />

the immanent metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the presentation <strong>of</strong> Sense that seeks to<br />

bring into its sense its own origin and end, so that there is nothing<br />

originarily given as gift that is given on the basis <strong>of</strong> an ungrounded<br />

foundation. In other words, language does not appear here as gift,<br />

in its given-ness, out <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, out <strong>of</strong> non-appropriable origin and<br />

non-appropriable end. Instead language is the pain <strong>of</strong> bringing the<br />

origin into signifi cation that weights upon the laboring Subject; or,<br />

rather, pain here is the metaphysical manifestation <strong>of</strong> the Subject<br />

that undergoes suff ering <strong>of</strong> its own dissolution so as to appropriate<br />

its own origin and its end unto the unity <strong>of</strong> its self-presence. Pain<br />

would, then, be thought as a mode <strong>of</strong> the manifestation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Metaphysical Subject in its pathway to this manifestation, in so<br />

far the essence <strong>of</strong> manifestation has something to do with pain, as<br />

if manifestation already always is attuned to pain. In so far as this<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject manifests itself as laboring, and as being<br />

empowered as appropriating, propriating Subject, pain here is the<br />

pain <strong>of</strong> the violence that Subject infl icts upon itself, in the othering,<br />

dirempting, sundering itself from itself. What Hegel sought to speak


Pain • 179<br />

<strong>of</strong> pain here is the pain <strong>of</strong> the labour and the pain <strong>of</strong> the violence<br />

in the pathway <strong>of</strong> manifestation <strong>of</strong> the Subject, which is also the<br />

pathway <strong>of</strong> powering, appropriating metaphysical Subject. Pain here<br />

is bound up with work and power in its gathering <strong>of</strong> Subject <strong>of</strong> itself<br />

to itself, in its nearing <strong>of</strong> distance, in its presentation <strong>of</strong> sense, in<br />

its appropriating its own origin and end as eigentlich, its proper, its<br />

own origin. If for Hegel the phenomenological essence <strong>of</strong> Spirit is<br />

this manifestation where sense presents itself without remainder,<br />

then pain is the pain <strong>of</strong> this manifestation <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

the Subject, <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s gathering into its self-presence, which<br />

is grasped by Hegel on the basis <strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition, i.e.,<br />

that <strong>of</strong> its speculative judgement.<br />

In his Th e Question <strong>of</strong> Being, Heidegger brings out this innermost<br />

connection between work and pain as the motor force <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dominant metaphysics whose accomplishment arrives in Hegelian<br />

onto-theological dialectics. Heidegger writes:<br />

To be able to trace more clearly the relations that sustain the connection<br />

between ‘work’ and ‘pain’, nothing less would be necessary than to<br />

think through the fundamental trait <strong>of</strong> Hegel’s metaphysics, the<br />

unifying unity <strong>of</strong> the Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit and the Science <strong>of</strong> Logic.<br />

Th e fundamental trait is ‘absolute negativity’ as the ‘infi nite force’ <strong>of</strong><br />

actuality i.e. <strong>of</strong> the ‘existing concept’. In the same (not the identical)<br />

belonging to the negation <strong>of</strong> negation, work and pain manifest their<br />

innermost metaphysical relatedness...And if one ventured to think<br />

through the relations between ‘work’ as the fundamental trait <strong>of</strong><br />

beings and ‘pain’ by moving back via Hegel’s Logic, then the Greek<br />

word for pain, namely, άλγος would fi rst come to speak for us.<br />

Presumably άλγος is related to άλξγω, which is the intensivum <strong>of</strong><br />

λξγω means intimate gathering. In that case, pain would be that which<br />

gathers most intimately. Hegel’s concept <strong>of</strong> the ‘concept’ and when<br />

correctly understood, the ‘strenuous eff ort’, it entails say the Same<br />

on the transformed soil <strong>of</strong> the absolute metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity.<br />

(Heidegger 1998, pp. 305-6)<br />

Perhaps it is possible to think <strong>of</strong> pain another way, one that man does<br />

not suff er for the end result <strong>of</strong> a process which his own negativity<br />

initiates. It is not the pain <strong>of</strong> his labour that seeks atonement <strong>of</strong><br />

its violence by means <strong>of</strong> violence, the violence <strong>of</strong> positing with<br />

which the movement <strong>of</strong> the (Hegelian) concept begins. To think


180 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the redemption <strong>of</strong> this violence which is the violence <strong>of</strong> the pure<br />

positing <strong>of</strong> the speculative concept, an outside <strong>of</strong> the concept must<br />

be thought, for it is not within the capacity <strong>of</strong> the concept to redeem<br />

itself on behalf <strong>of</strong> its own possibility and resources. If the way opens<br />

with the abyss and not as the end result, then it must be to open time<br />

itself to come beyond violence. Th e question <strong>of</strong> the gift <strong>of</strong> language<br />

must be inseparable from the critique <strong>of</strong> violence.<br />

Th erefore what comes to come or the unapparent presencing to<br />

presence does not end with death but makes death as the beginning<br />

point for the possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th is redemption is redemption<br />

<strong>of</strong> violence. If here the question arises as to the possibility <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> time that is not annihilated, or made impossible by<br />

negativity, but that is opened up with mortality as its presupposition,<br />

then the question <strong>of</strong> mortality itself is to be thought anew, no longer<br />

as negativity but in relation to what we are calling the question <strong>of</strong><br />

‘origin’—the immemorial past that fi rst <strong>of</strong> opens time to come. Th is<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> origin is not what has become sublated unto concept, and<br />

thereby is mere past, but that arrives from a pure future that bears the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> a time to come beyond violence. An origin to come is to<br />

be thought here that is beyond violence only in so far as it is outside<br />

even the opposition between the violence and non-violence, in so far<br />

as the non-violence <strong>of</strong> the origin cannot even be posited, in concept<br />

or in signifi cation, as non-violent. Language is the site <strong>of</strong> this origin<br />

to come, outside any power <strong>of</strong> positing, and outside the pain <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept, as if there is a more originary pain <strong>of</strong> language there which<br />

is outside the labour and power <strong>of</strong> the concept, which does not allow<br />

the Subject to gather into itself in its metaphysical ground.<br />

The Melancholic Gift<br />

If it is from language alone that we experience death as death, know<br />

death as death, what kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge is it that language gives,<br />

knowledge that is so originary as to be the origin <strong>of</strong> knowledge,<br />

the origin <strong>of</strong> the knowledge <strong>of</strong> ourselves as such, <strong>of</strong> our essential<br />

mortality, our intrinsic fi nitude? As if in an essential manner, one that<br />

is enigmatic, the relationship <strong>of</strong> the mortal existent to its intrinsic<br />

mortality is at once tied intimately to language. Th erefore at the<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> a linguistic existence a lament, unappeased, resonates in an


Pain • 181<br />

originary manner, in the opening <strong>of</strong> existence to itself. It is the pain<br />

that inscribes itself at the heart <strong>of</strong> an origin to come, and renders this<br />

existence a tear and an open wound, exposed to the outside as an unenclosed<br />

immanence.<br />

To speak is to be attuned to a fundamental mournfulness, given<br />

in speaking itself. Pain is the originary opening <strong>of</strong> a linguistic<br />

existence beyond closure, beyond immanence. Th is originary pain<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, before the pain <strong>of</strong> the concept, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all tears open the<br />

naming man to the nameless, to the absence <strong>of</strong> ground and bestows<br />

upon man the gift <strong>of</strong> language itself. To name is to mourn.<br />

Mortality, instead <strong>of</strong> closing mortal existence into an immanence<br />

whose limits would then be predicated and drawn out by the labour<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, rather exposes the mortal existence to its outside, to<br />

the transcendence <strong>of</strong> what is not yet arrived, to the future beyond<br />

the linguistic power <strong>of</strong> predication. It is to this transcendence that<br />

language, at the limit <strong>of</strong> predication and at the limit <strong>of</strong> the conceptual<br />

cognition <strong>of</strong> representative thinking, interminably points towards,<br />

pushes itself as if towards the speech where speech itself falters, trembles<br />

and ruins itself. Language, instead <strong>of</strong> progressively realizing its own<br />

identity to its own limit—unlike the dialectical march <strong>of</strong> the concept<br />

as in Hegelian metaphysical Subject—falters into the dissonance in<br />

relation to itself, unto where language as if in an unspeakable lament<br />

abandons itself, delivers itself again and again to the abyss <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unspeakable and unnamable, from where language itself originates,<br />

as if there occurs, at the origin <strong>of</strong> language, an abandonment that has<br />

already ruined language to constitute itself as Subject or Spirit. In<br />

other words, and this is the essential anachrony <strong>of</strong> language, language<br />

keeps open a relation to its own origin by interminably distantiating<br />

from itself, by standing apart from itself, by incessantly exiling itself<br />

from itself, deviating and falling outside <strong>of</strong> itself, so that this essential<br />

dissonance, this ecstatic solitude <strong>of</strong> language bears the marks <strong>of</strong> a<br />

cision that separates language from itself, language from the one who<br />

speaks.<br />

One who speaks is not, is never a master <strong>of</strong> language, nor language<br />

originates in him as a power, or a law. It is rather a fundamental<br />

mourning that attunes the speaking mortals to his non-power and


182 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

non-mastery, outside the power <strong>of</strong> the concept, outside the labour<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement.<br />

Language, then, instead <strong>of</strong> being predicative power <strong>of</strong> representing<br />

our fi nitude for us and giving us the cognition <strong>of</strong> death, itself is<br />

fi nite in an essential sense. Th is is why a touch <strong>of</strong> melancholy always<br />

resonates at the heart <strong>of</strong> a linguistic being, even where there is a joy<br />

to be expressed, even when a plenitude <strong>of</strong> being present to oneself is<br />

affi rmed and even when the being- with all <strong>of</strong> existence is experienced.<br />

Th is coming together <strong>of</strong> joy and mournfulness is the moment <strong>of</strong><br />

‘becoming in perishing’ that Hölderlin speaks <strong>of</strong> (Hölderlin 1988,<br />

p. 96-100), the moment <strong>of</strong> epochal rupture, which is the monstrous<br />

site where history inaugurates itself. It is not because the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> sadness is always there for a fi nite existence which at any occasion<br />

at any instant <strong>of</strong> one’s life presents itself. It is rather that a more<br />

originary melancholy lies at the source <strong>of</strong> a fi nite existence, because<br />

it belongs to the originary opening, or originary transcendence, the<br />

immemorial past that has lapsed without return, that fi rst opens us<br />

to time, and enables the experience <strong>of</strong> mortality as mortality, death as<br />

death, and existence as existence.<br />

It is in this essential sense Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> a source <strong>of</strong> melancholy<br />

even in God. For created existence to be possible—where alone there<br />

be revelation to himself—there has to be an opening, or transcendence,<br />

that means an opening <strong>of</strong> an outside <strong>of</strong> himself . Th ere must be in God<br />

himself an outside <strong>of</strong> himself, a transcendence <strong>of</strong> himself, a rendering<br />

<strong>of</strong> himself into a past immemorial—which means at the same time<br />

an opening <strong>of</strong> a future through an originary cut (Scheidung) or a<br />

primordial separation, a tearing disjunction, an anachronic tune—<br />

which is an essential fi nitude <strong>of</strong> God’s relation to the created existence<br />

and to himself. But this veil <strong>of</strong> sadness, while remaining as mere<br />

possibility in God, becomes actual in mortal existence, since for the<br />

mortal the condition <strong>of</strong> his being remains his outside as the ground<br />

excludes itself as a non-appropriable abyss, a being-there that remains<br />

an outside, since for the mortal his being-present-to-himself is a loan<br />

gifted to him as non-appropriable gift, an <strong>of</strong>f ering which he never<br />

gains control over and never masters (Das 2007, pp.111-123). Th is<br />

is the ‘unappeasable melancholy <strong>of</strong> all life’, not being able to actualize<br />

oneself completely, for possibility marks his limit, and thereby, at the


Pain • 183<br />

same instance, limitlessly exposes him to infi nite possibilities, frees<br />

and releases him to his unnamable possibilities, the possibilities <strong>of</strong><br />

the joyous acts <strong>of</strong> creation, out <strong>of</strong> this essential freedom that is given<br />

to him ‘independently <strong>of</strong> himself’:<br />

In God, too, there would be a depth <strong>of</strong> darkness if he did not make<br />

the condition his own and unite it to him as one and as absolute<br />

personality. Man never gains control over the condition even though<br />

in evil he strives to do so; it is only loaned to him independent <strong>of</strong> him;<br />

hence his personality and selfhood can never be raised to complete<br />

actuality. Th is is the sadness which adheres too all fi nite life, and<br />

inasmuch as there is even in God himself a condition at least relatively<br />

independent, there is in him, too, a source <strong>of</strong> sadness which, however,<br />

never attains actuality but rather serves for the eternal joy <strong>of</strong> triumph.<br />

Th ence the veil <strong>of</strong> sadness, which is spread over all nature, the deep<br />

unappeasable melancholy <strong>of</strong> all life. (Schelling 1936, p. 79)<br />

Th is originary melancholy inscribes itself in this gift that forever<br />

remains outside <strong>of</strong> his mastery and appropriation. Th erefore in this<br />

sense both sadness and joy belong in its own way to an originary<br />

melancholy 1 . Man, in speaking and being endowed with language, is<br />

also endowed with this ‘unappeasable melancholy’ that adheres itself<br />

in the gift, gift that bears the mark <strong>of</strong> death, gift that bears the traces<br />

the suff erings <strong>of</strong> unmasterable diff erence and the pain <strong>of</strong> separation.<br />

Schelling calls this pain as the pain <strong>of</strong> ‘cision’ (Scheidung), the cut<br />

that while separating calls the separated to be together. Language<br />

enabling, gifting man to speak, endowing him to present to himself,<br />

to reveal himself to himself, forever and fi rst <strong>of</strong> all excludes him from<br />

the mastery <strong>of</strong> this gift. Henceforth he can only speak in a language<br />

that is borrowed, loaned to him, gifted to him from elsewhere, from<br />

another time, from another destination which precedes him, and in<br />

preceding him follows him. What precedes him and what follows<br />

him—that means what remains outside <strong>of</strong> him—this alone, this<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> an outside <strong>of</strong> an immemorial past and the incalculable<br />

future places man to be in the open space, that opening where man<br />

is exposed to his outside, that free opening where darkness and light<br />

play the originary co-belonging, where he fi nds himself exposed and<br />

open in relation to the entirety <strong>of</strong> created existence. It is in this sense<br />

one says that language reveals man to his own mortality. Th is revelation<br />

precedes all logical categories, and is inaccessible to his cognition.


184 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th at man is the one to whom mortality reveals itself in language,<br />

it is this man who is thrown to be, what Schelling calls as ‘central<br />

existence’ (Schelling 1936, p. 79).<br />

If man alone speaks language, it is not because language is the<br />

accomplishment <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical Subject at the service <strong>of</strong> its<br />

cognitive disposal; nor because language is the gathering <strong>of</strong> being to<br />

itself. Language rather throws being in the midst <strong>of</strong>, at the center <strong>of</strong><br />

created existence. Th is means: he is placed at the limit, at the line that<br />

disjoins him from the others and disjoining, calls the others to his<br />

nearness. Th e line, as the undecidable diff erence, as tearing disjunction,<br />

as the chasm <strong>of</strong> a cision, belongs to the experience <strong>of</strong> abyss as abyss.<br />

If man is central existence, it means none but that he is the one who<br />

experiences abyss as abyss, to whom mortality reveals itself and places<br />

him in relation to what is outside his power and capacity. Mortality,<br />

revealing itself to man, must already have seized him with a tremor<br />

and an awe, with what Kierkegaard (1980) calls ‘anxiety’. Schelling<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> man as constantly fl eeing from this center, withdrawing<br />

from this central fi re (the fi re that both Heraclitus and Hölderlin<br />

(1988) speak <strong>of</strong>) only because he is called forth towards it—how to<br />

say this?—by the attraction <strong>of</strong> a ‘divine violence’, that is, the attraction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the centre. Th is experiencing his death as death in this opening<br />

in a lightning fl ash, man also experiences eternity as eternity—the<br />

entirety <strong>of</strong> created existence—as that what is outside <strong>of</strong> him, precedes<br />

him and remains after him. Th is eternity is non-appropriable gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> experience which is fi rst <strong>of</strong> all be there in order for man to speak<br />

language. Th is originary non-appropriability <strong>of</strong> his condition, since<br />

it is given to him as an originary gift, makes language resonate with<br />

that ‘unappeasable melancholy’, or an unspeakable anguish.<br />

Th e melancholy <strong>of</strong> language is the originary transcendence, or<br />

originary opening <strong>of</strong> existence, fi nite and mortal, as that which exsists;<br />

which means, language in its essential melancholy, for the fi rst<br />

time, opens existence to its coming to presence, to the transcendence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming. If human existence is essentially transcendence that<br />

is in so far as existence is originary opening up in language to the<br />

coming time that is yet to arrive. Th is constitutes the messianic<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> language, intimated with fi nitude, and holding towards<br />

transcendence, incalculable and infi nite beyond any closure.


Pain • 185<br />

It is here the question <strong>of</strong> history and its ground (or, rather ‘origin’)<br />

in relation to language is to be thought. Th e ‘origin’ <strong>of</strong> history holds<br />

itself open in the poetics <strong>of</strong> the messianic promise <strong>of</strong> language, which<br />

for that matter, does not itself completely belong to the dialecticalhistorical<br />

immanence. It is this originary exposure <strong>of</strong> existence in a<br />

lightning fl ash to the opening—where history itself comes to presence—<br />

that makes the mortal existence and its historicity an un-saturated<br />

phenomenon, a hetero-aff ected phenomenon, wholly torn from<br />

within, exposed to the outside. Language in its sudden lightning<br />

advent originarily places the human outside <strong>of</strong> himself and exposes<br />

him to the otherwise <strong>of</strong> history. Is this not the experience <strong>of</strong> death<br />

as death, the originary phenomenon <strong>of</strong> disclosing the entirety <strong>of</strong><br />

existence to himself, which can only be experienced by mortals<br />

as mortality? Language is not simply the property <strong>of</strong> the one who<br />

speaks, nor is primarily language the source from where he derives<br />

the power <strong>of</strong> domination to the rest akin to himself and others.<br />

Language is neither the medium through which he grasps his own<br />

existence and existence as such, as if man is the origin and the end<br />

result <strong>of</strong> his own existence, nor language enables him to be the one<br />

who is saturated by and in speech. Language, rather, already always<br />

placing the mortal outside <strong>of</strong> himself (or rather displacing him,<br />

tearing him, exposing him to the opening), endows him with the<br />

intimation <strong>of</strong> his mortality and thereby renders him open to the<br />

historical character <strong>of</strong> his existence, or, makes his existence historical<br />

the fi rst time, that means before the fi rst, the fi rst before any fi rst his<br />

existence as essentially fi nite and mortal. Th is intimation <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

or death is not cognition like any other, nor can it be possession <strong>of</strong><br />

the human like any entities that he henceforth produces and endows<br />

them with the mark <strong>of</strong> the ‘human production’. It can only be an<br />

originary revelation to which man is opened—as both Heidegger and<br />

Kierkegaard in entirely diff erent manners and with entirely diff erent<br />

purposes, show—in anguish or in anxiety. Man neither possesses<br />

his death like any other possession, nor possesses the ground on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> which he possesses his historical world, for the ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> his possession lies in the promise that grants him, beforehand,<br />

his history, his being able to present to himself as the one who is<br />

essentially fi nite and mortal. Th e human knows, whatever he knows<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world and his self-knowledge on the basis <strong>of</strong> a lightning


186 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

fl ash that already places him outside <strong>of</strong> himself, outside <strong>of</strong> all his<br />

possession, outside the claim that henceforth he makes as the maker<br />

or creator <strong>of</strong> the ‘world’, this historical-discursive world which in<br />

being produced is also posits the producer. Th at this is his fi nitude<br />

attunes him to the lament <strong>of</strong> language that holds him open, like an<br />

open wound, to his historical existence that comes to presence, to the<br />

incalculable event <strong>of</strong> arriving that wounds him, aff ects him, touches<br />

him. Henceforth, that means in a time before and after time, history<br />

bears traces <strong>of</strong> this melancholy <strong>of</strong> language, rendering his historical<br />

existence as unfi nished, incomplete, unaccomplished, and at the same<br />

existence-in-excess, forever unsaturated, welcoming and bearing the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> its redemption in the coming time. Th is promise given in<br />

language arises in an originary dis-possession <strong>of</strong> the human, on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> which alone something like the origin <strong>of</strong> history happens<br />

to the mortal, arises up to him, and erupts towards him. Th e poetics<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin traces itself as the un-fulfi llment <strong>of</strong> history, which thereby<br />

points towards a fulfi llment outside any dialectical-historical closure, in<br />

the messianic—what Ernst Bloch (1995) calls—‘not yet’.<br />

Th erefore language does not completely belong to the world <strong>of</strong> works<br />

and to the works <strong>of</strong> the world. At the limit <strong>of</strong> the world, unsaturated<br />

and in infi nite excess, or at the limit <strong>of</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> the aff airs <strong>of</strong><br />

the world, language is the vanishing point <strong>of</strong> the indiscernible where<br />

language turns the prose <strong>of</strong> the world into the lament <strong>of</strong> music. Th ere<br />

language unsays itself in a lament, in the melancholy turned to music.<br />

Th e one who speaks is not master <strong>of</strong> the world thereby, nor the possessor<br />

<strong>of</strong> his existence as the sovereign master <strong>of</strong> the earth. Language rather<br />

de-territorializes the one who speaks. Or, rather, the one who speaks is<br />

touched by the essential melancholy to which language is thoroughly<br />

attuned at the limit <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> objects and possessions. In<br />

being touched by this unspeakable lament <strong>of</strong> language, the one who<br />

speaks is intimated by the intrinsic non-appropriability <strong>of</strong> language.<br />

Th e non-appropriable ground <strong>of</strong> existence itself, as if, precedes the<br />

speaking mortal something like an immemorial past and follows him<br />

something like a future as unfi nished, unaccomplished not yet. What<br />

is this experience if not the experience <strong>of</strong> fi nitude? Th e ‘experience’ <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude is the essential non-appropriation or non-conditional limit,<br />

the outside that ecstatically calls the power <strong>of</strong> the negative to the nonpower,<br />

the originary experience <strong>of</strong> non-power on the basis <strong>of</strong> which


Pain • 187<br />

we make claim <strong>of</strong> our historical existence, the non-power outside<br />

the dialectical-historical violence. What is the relationship between<br />

this essential non-power <strong>of</strong> language, and its essential melancholy<br />

that permeates what comes to presence, the essential fragility <strong>of</strong><br />

language that starts lamenting at the touch <strong>of</strong> appropriation precisely<br />

because it has began before any appropriation? Is it not therefore the<br />

poetic language that seeks renunciation <strong>of</strong> any mastery is thoroughly<br />

attuned with this unspeakable melancholy?<br />

Language appears, for that matter, enigmatic to us, at once<br />

originating in our non-power in relation to it and which for that<br />

matter keeps the historical existence open to redemption without<br />

violence, which is its promise and at the same time it is the ground<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> which the power <strong>of</strong> the world originates, where<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> language may turn into the violence <strong>of</strong> judgement,<br />

and the originary non-appropriation may turn into the evil <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation. Language appears <strong>of</strong>ten to us in its utter poverty and<br />

fragility, whenever it is a matter <strong>of</strong> speaking the extremes and yet all<br />

too excessive in relation to any presently given world so that language<br />

itself does not appear within it as ‘presently given’ (Vorhandenheit),<br />

for it is itself the more originary <strong>of</strong>f ering on the basis <strong>of</strong> which any<br />

given-ness presently arises, on the basis <strong>of</strong> which historicity makes<br />

manifest to us, reveals to us in its already holding sway <strong>of</strong> the lightning<br />

fl ash. Language itself is not saturated or exhausted in being spoken,<br />

or in our being able to speak. We neither exhaust the world in<br />

speaking about it, nor do we exhaust language in being able to speak<br />

a language. Rather, being able to speak is the trace <strong>of</strong> the future which<br />

is the inexhaustible <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language <strong>of</strong> itself, already open in its<br />

poetics <strong>of</strong> the origin. Th is <strong>of</strong>f ering is experienced by the mortals in<br />

that lightning fl ash that precedes our predication and our cognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world and <strong>of</strong> existence. Unimpaired by the cognitive function,<br />

it is the originary opening, attuned to us in a lament <strong>of</strong> language,<br />

because it is intimated with our essential fi nitude that holds us open<br />

to history coming to presence.<br />

Th erefore it is necessary to think <strong>of</strong> an originary language as promise,<br />

as donation beyond any presently given existence, in its relation to a<br />

past to arrive, instead <strong>of</strong> representing the presently given world in<br />

the conceptual system <strong>of</strong> cognition and predication. Th is originary<br />

language as the poetic origin <strong>of</strong> history, this pre-predicative language


188 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> opening, excess <strong>of</strong> any cognitive and predicative function, traces<br />

future in the past, because it carries the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th ere<br />

is no redemption if it is not already always given in the originary<br />

lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> the opening, which is already always given as an<br />

<strong>of</strong>f ering or as gift. Th is however does not mean that it is presently<br />

given.<br />

What is given in advance as the originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language may<br />

not be for that reason be presently given. Th e coming into presence<br />

rather than presently given is the eternal renewal <strong>of</strong> this <strong>of</strong>f ering and<br />

endowing language itself with the gift <strong>of</strong> time, a time <strong>of</strong> future. Such<br />

gift or <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language must already be given in the already always<br />

<strong>of</strong> the originary opening. Th is is the meaning to say that language<br />

traces the future in the past, which means that future is already given<br />

in the originary opening as an opening to the coming future as notyet-presently-given.<br />

To speak is never merely to speak the ‘presently<br />

given entities’ <strong>of</strong> the world, nor to make the world as the system <strong>of</strong><br />

predicated objects and cognitive relations, but to keep the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

time that is given with the <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language itself by the incessant<br />

renewal <strong>of</strong> the promise in presence, that is experienced by the<br />

mortals as an originary experience <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, disclosed to him in<br />

the lightning fl ash and which is attuned in him with an unspeakable<br />

lament turning to music. To speak is to keep the promise <strong>of</strong> time<br />

given in language that welcomes the event <strong>of</strong> time, which is future.<br />

Th is <strong>of</strong>f ering lies at the origin <strong>of</strong> history as ungrounded and unfounded<br />

poetic ground; or; this is to say that history begins with the <strong>of</strong>f ering<br />

<strong>of</strong> language. Th e question <strong>of</strong> history in relation to language is to be<br />

connected with the question <strong>of</strong> origin and <strong>of</strong>f ering that <strong>of</strong>f ers the<br />

time to come. Each time one opens her lips, each time history begins,<br />

it is time itself that is opened up, each time a time to come and each<br />

time she keeps this original promise <strong>of</strong> language by transferring its<br />

past into future. Th is transference that happens is itself nothing but the<br />

passage <strong>of</strong> time that defi nes the temporality <strong>of</strong> time as presencing, the<br />

transference <strong>of</strong> past unto future through renewal <strong>of</strong> time, for the passage<br />

renews what it transfers. What is renewed is the hope that makes the<br />

transference grow in strength and intensity. Th is hope is the messianic<br />

hope for the coming time. 2<br />

Th is is so because there is an essential element <strong>of</strong> hope in the <strong>of</strong>f ering<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, already given in advance in an originary manner. Th e


Pain • 189<br />

gift that is given is not to be responded by returning to the (giving)<br />

other with the same gift or with another gift. Th e gift is responded<br />

only by passing this gift itself to still other, the third, who is yet to<br />

come or coming and in this way renewing this gift, strengthening<br />

it with hope, and rendering the gift eternal. Th e relation <strong>of</strong> parents<br />

to children or teachers to students is exemplary here. Th e gift <strong>of</strong><br />

learning given by the teacher to the student is not to be returned to<br />

the teacher by remaining a student or by becoming oneself teacher to<br />

the teacher himself, who meanwhile must already have passed away<br />

or is gone. It is rather that the student himself becoming a teacher to<br />

the student yet to come, and passing the gift given to him by other<br />

to the still other yet to come that the gift becomes eternal. Is this not<br />

precisely the meaning <strong>of</strong> transference that marks the passage <strong>of</strong> time<br />

as presencing, a threshold each time to be transferred into yet another<br />

time, another destination, another place to traverse and being open<br />

to the still another beyond? Neither the child becomes parent to<br />

her parent, nor the student becomes teacher to her teacher, but she<br />

becomes a parent only to her child, or teacher to her student yet to<br />

come, or coming. Th is gift passing onto the future alone enables the<br />

gift to be eternal, and keeps alive the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption given<br />

in the past. Th e gift does not return to the same destination again<br />

either in progressively regressive manner, or regressively progressive<br />

manner to the originary giver <strong>of</strong> the gift, for it is the character <strong>of</strong> the<br />

gift, unlike the investment <strong>of</strong> the capital that it never has to return<br />

to the same. It keeps the originary promise in the gift by still passing<br />

onto the other still to come, through eternal renewal in presence,<br />

which must be the historical task <strong>of</strong> existence, that <strong>of</strong> keeping alive<br />

the promise <strong>of</strong> its redemption. But is not it that this passing the<br />

gift from past to the future for that matter an originary experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nitude or mortality itself, for only he who experiences death as<br />

death passes the gift <strong>of</strong> time, makes his past into the possibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

future by passing on the gift given by the other to still another who<br />

is not yet?<br />

Th e gift belongs to nobody, which is only to be passed to the other<br />

who in turn will still pass to another. We belong to the gift, the gift<br />

does itself belong to none. Rather the gift belongs to the eternity that<br />

is renewed in each historical presencing, and through this renewal<br />

it exceeds the logic <strong>of</strong> a ‘restricted economy’. Th is keeping alive


190 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the originary promise <strong>of</strong> redemption is on the basis <strong>of</strong> an essential<br />

fi nitude, <strong>of</strong> an essential non-appropriation: as one who does not<br />

own one’s death, does not own thereby the gift. Th e gift is itself<br />

annulled when it is made into a possession, when it is amenable to<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> use and exchange value, when on the basis <strong>of</strong> a<br />

possession it is opened to dis-possession, or to another possession<br />

(Derrida 1992). In the economy <strong>of</strong> possession the gift is never<br />

opened to the originary dis-possession, nor is dis-possession there<br />

only for the sake <strong>of</strong>, or in the name <strong>of</strong> the possession still to arrive<br />

in the circular re-appropriation or circular re-possession <strong>of</strong> it. Th e<br />

task <strong>of</strong> receiving the gift is rather to eternalize it, through infi nite<br />

renewal in time, and pass it onto the other still to arrive; in other<br />

words, to make this essential non-appropriation, the non-possession,<br />

the essential fi nitude itself an eternal task <strong>of</strong> the gift. Th e thankful<br />

task <strong>of</strong> the mortal who is endowed with the gift is to be eternally nonappropriated<br />

and non-possessed, to make this mortality itself a task.<br />

Th is is the meaning <strong>of</strong> saying that from language alone we<br />

experience death as death. Th is fi nitude is not the annihilation or<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> time but the possibility <strong>of</strong> time to come, the beginning<br />

or the origin <strong>of</strong> time that is opened up in an originary being placed<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> totality, outside the system <strong>of</strong> relations. To be placed outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> totality, outside the system <strong>of</strong> relation is an experience <strong>of</strong> death as<br />

death. It is also, for that matter experience <strong>of</strong> eternity as eternity, infi nity<br />

as infi nity. One who seeks the beginning must fi rst <strong>of</strong> all be placed<br />

outside totality, outside <strong>of</strong> all appropriation; in other words, he must<br />

take the great ‘step <strong>of</strong> death’.<br />

Schelling somewhere speaks,<br />

He who wishes to place himself in the beginning <strong>of</strong> a truly free<br />

philosophy must abandon even God. Here we say: who wishes to<br />

maintain it, he will lose it; and who gives up, he will fi nd it. Only he<br />

has come to the ground <strong>of</strong> himself and has known the whole depth<br />

<strong>of</strong> life who has once abandoned everything, and has himself been<br />

abandoned by everything. He for whom everything disappeared and<br />

who saw himself alone with the infi nite: a great step which Plato<br />

compared to death. (Quoted in Heidegger 1985, pp. 6-7)<br />

We will call this experience <strong>of</strong> infi nite ‘transcendence’, which is the<br />

unground on the ground <strong>of</strong> which time is existential, which means


Pain • 191<br />

time that is coming to presence. Th at the thinking <strong>of</strong> coming is a question<br />

<strong>of</strong> experiencing death as death is something that calls for thinking<br />

that would take language seriously. A philosophical thinking that,<br />

therefore, takes seriously the question <strong>of</strong> existence and death is also<br />

thereby the language-thinking (Sprachdenken). Th is term (language-<br />

thinking) we take it from Franz Rosenzweig, the philosopher who<br />

takes the question <strong>of</strong> death neither as mere ‘Naught’ nor time as<br />

the monotonous succession <strong>of</strong> empty presents. Th e philosophical<br />

thinking that takes language as mere cognitive apparatus to grasp the<br />

entities that has become, claims that death itself as mere ‘Naught’,<br />

and this philosophical thinking precisely thereby lacks the thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming time, the messianic event <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise.<br />

Only as existential the coming time is ecstatic, that means opening<br />

in fi nitude, exposed to mortality. Th erefore Schelling, Heidegger and<br />

Rosenzweig—with the help <strong>of</strong> whom the question <strong>of</strong> existence is<br />

renewed here—each on his singular manner begins his philosophical<br />

questioning with the question <strong>of</strong> mortality; with each <strong>of</strong> them<br />

existence-philosophy is at once language-philosophy, and with each<br />

one <strong>of</strong> them the philosophical task is to open the philosophical<br />

discourse itself to the thinking <strong>of</strong> the coming time beyond predicative<br />

closure <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-speculative thinking.<br />

If the task <strong>of</strong> thinking pursued here is to think the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

time, it must keep the promise <strong>of</strong> time given in language itself.<br />

Language neither predicates death, nor enables us to cognize it. But<br />

rather language attunes us to our mortality, to our essential fi nitude,<br />

in the pre-predicative lightning fl ash, in the poetic Saying, as the<br />

‘fundamental attunement’ <strong>of</strong> mournfulness. Th is mournfulness is not<br />

sadness due to a lack <strong>of</strong> a particular thing or object in the world,<br />

but this mournfulness, touching us at the limit, alone enables our<br />

mortality be experienced as mortality, as an un-appropriable limit, at<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> our mastery and at the limit <strong>of</strong> violence that the world<br />

<strong>of</strong> cognition posits. By delineating the limit <strong>of</strong> violence and the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> our mastery, touching us at the limit <strong>of</strong> power, the melancholy <strong>of</strong><br />

language keeps alive the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption, the promise <strong>of</strong> a time<br />

to come beyond and without violence, where the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world is redeemed from the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition. Th en melancholy<br />

will not be melancholic anymore. It will, then, be transfi gured<br />

into the redemptive joy when the eternity <strong>of</strong> time presents itself


192 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

as simultaneity <strong>of</strong> past, presence and future. Th is is what binds the<br />

attunement <strong>of</strong> joy, as the experience <strong>of</strong> beatitude, with future: future<br />

makes one joyful, for the sake which the mortal exists as an open<br />

existence, open to the time to come, open to redemption. Th e joy<br />

is the beatitude which the melancholy <strong>of</strong> language points towards<br />

as the fulfi llment <strong>of</strong> language in the completed understanding <strong>of</strong> a<br />

silence, not the silence that mythically posits the law <strong>of</strong> history and<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> appropriation, but a redemptive silence that fulfi lls<br />

the originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language itself, the stillness <strong>of</strong> the event<br />

which is divinely experienced in a joyous mourning.<br />

Naming and Overnaming<br />

At the limit <strong>of</strong> the world, language delineates, traces the limit <strong>of</strong> our<br />

appropriation and the limit <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical violence. Th e<br />

intimate, which is <strong>of</strong>ten diffi cult to reveal, connection between the<br />

speculative nature <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-predicative concept in its thetic<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> positing and the violence <strong>of</strong> the historical is painfully,<br />

melancholically communicated in the lament <strong>of</strong> language, for the<br />

thetic nature <strong>of</strong> positing seeks to erase the originary non-appropriation<br />

which is the immemorial donation <strong>of</strong> language itself. In the lament<br />

<strong>of</strong> language resonates the damaged nature <strong>of</strong> our historical existence<br />

that cries for redemption outside the dialectical-historical closure.<br />

Is not this unredeemed melancholic cry <strong>of</strong> numberless mortal<br />

beings—a melancholy that is not consoled and redeemed in the<br />

catharsis <strong>of</strong> the dialectical- historical concept—the faint murmuring<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the world that murmurs faintly the limit <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong><br />

the negative? Th e speculative-positing nature <strong>of</strong> the historical world<br />

itself, then, would not be the originary act, or the primordial act<br />

that posits itself as an act <strong>of</strong> nothingness. From Fichte’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

the primordial act <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness to Hegel’s speculative notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> negativity as the positing act <strong>of</strong> the concept, the thetic act <strong>of</strong><br />

Subject underlies the grounding assumption <strong>of</strong> German Idealistic<br />

thought. It is in this sense Rosenzweig’s (Rosenzweig 2005) saying<br />

that German Idealism is without language becomes meaningful, for<br />

any philosophy that begins with the positing act <strong>of</strong> nothingness,<br />

makes death the originary power <strong>of</strong> a mythic-positing violence, and<br />

therefore forgets the originary non-power <strong>of</strong> language outside the


Pain • 193<br />

dialectic between thetic and antithetic. If certain metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

violence underlies in the assumption <strong>of</strong> an act <strong>of</strong> positing, it turns<br />

deaf ear to the true mourning <strong>of</strong> language, the fragile lament <strong>of</strong><br />

language that accompanies any act <strong>of</strong> thetic positing. If that were<br />

so, then the primordial pain <strong>of</strong> language would not then be to<br />

constitute the innermost unity <strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> categories. It will not<br />

have its atonement in the catharsis <strong>of</strong> the speculative tragedy. Th is<br />

mourning adheres in the originary donation <strong>of</strong> the name, which the<br />

predicative-thetic concept apophantically cannot retrieve. Th erefore<br />

the originary donation <strong>of</strong> the name is never completely inscribed<br />

into the circulation <strong>of</strong> the predications. Th e originary donation <strong>of</strong><br />

language, since it arrives beforehand, with the inception that begins<br />

before any beginning, is not the song <strong>of</strong> the owl <strong>of</strong> Minerva but a<br />

herald that announces in the lightning fl ash the advent <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

to presence. Such a language that welcomes the coming to presence is<br />

poetic Saying.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> the positing power <strong>of</strong> the negative, it is non-power that<br />

opens the historical world to the coming to presence to itself, and<br />

that traces the limit <strong>of</strong> appropriation. What is it if not otherwise<br />

than the originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language itself? Th e critique <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

violence that demands redemption is therefore inextricably intimated<br />

with a radical re-thinking <strong>of</strong> mortality and language anew, to think<br />

anew how this mortality as non-appropriable is inscribed in the<br />

originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language that attunes us with its indescribable<br />

melancholy. Th is originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language must, then, precede<br />

the speculative-positing nature <strong>of</strong> predicative concept. Th e worldhistorical<br />

destiny is opened up in that originary revelation; language<br />

is exposed to this ‘heavenly fi re’ that fi rst tearing man unto the open,<br />

endows the historical world with the gift <strong>of</strong> time, with the gift <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event. Now this event is more originary than any event that occurs in<br />

time, or in history, precisely because it the event <strong>of</strong> history itself.<br />

To keep this event in attention is also the attention given to the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> redemption, that is, to keep open the originary opening <strong>of</strong><br />

history beyond history. To keep open this opening to which we must<br />

be attentive is the form <strong>of</strong> remembrance which language carries as<br />

promise. Th is remembrance is to be distinguished from dialecticalhistorical<br />

recollection, or speculative memory <strong>of</strong> the concept that


194 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

regressively traces back, at the dusk <strong>of</strong> the completion <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

labour, to the past that the speculative concept itself must have<br />

posited. Th e remembrance unimpaired by positing cognition is<br />

what we have been calling the event.<br />

Th e relationship between the event and origin, the event and fi nitude<br />

on the one hand, and with it melancholy and language is to be<br />

articulated: here is an attempt to think the event as the thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin and opening <strong>of</strong> history which is otherwise than the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> negativity that posits itself. In the dominant metaphysical<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> language and history, this originary opening is<br />

forgotten and language comes to be at the cognitive disposal <strong>of</strong><br />

predication constitutive <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-historical closure. Th e<br />

event <strong>of</strong> history but not historical event, on the otherhand, keeps<br />

remembrance (but not the historical recollection that the Owl <strong>of</strong><br />

Minerva sings at the dusk) <strong>of</strong> the originary opening renewed in<br />

language, by transfi guring the past unto the future event to arrive. Th is<br />

remembrance is thereby intimated by the melancholy <strong>of</strong> language, by<br />

the originary non-appropriation beyond violence. Th is melancholy is<br />

redeemed when there wholly transfi guration <strong>of</strong> this past into future<br />

happens. Th e beatitude <strong>of</strong> redemption then is experienced by mortals<br />

as silence—not the resolute silence <strong>of</strong> the mythic-tragic hero, nor the<br />

Pure, Absolute Concept <strong>of</strong> the historically accomplished existence,<br />

bereft <strong>of</strong> language—but silence <strong>of</strong>, what Rosenzweig calls, ‘completed<br />

understanding’, silence that arrives with redemptive fulfi llment <strong>of</strong><br />

language, recognized in its nobility and dignity. It is language in its<br />

messianic happiness.<br />

In his Language as Such and on the Language <strong>of</strong> Man (1996) Walter<br />

Benjamin thinks <strong>of</strong> a melancholy at the very paradisiacal, originary<br />

naming language <strong>of</strong> Adam which is the divine gift from God himself:<br />

a blissful melancholy, for it holds itself to the promise that comes<br />

with the gift <strong>of</strong> naming, for it promises redemption beyond and<br />

without violence. ‘To be named’, writes Benjamin, ‘even when the<br />

name is godlike and blissful—perhaps always remains an intimation<br />

<strong>of</strong> mourning’ (Ibid., p. 73). Th ere is a mourning which is blissful<br />

and even divine. Th e joyous life <strong>of</strong> free creation, the experience <strong>of</strong><br />

beatitude is not alien to this divine mourning, but partakes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

divine excess. In a letter written after the death <strong>of</strong> Caroline, Schelling


Pain • 195<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> a divine mourning where ‘all earthly pain is immersed’: ‘ I<br />

now need friends who are not strangers to the real seriousness <strong>of</strong> pain<br />

and who feel that the single right and happy state <strong>of</strong> the soul is the<br />

divine mourning in which all earthly pain in immersed’ (Schelling<br />

1975). Th is is the mourning that is blissful and paradisiacal, because<br />

it does not yet know the thetic violence <strong>of</strong> the concept, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dialectical-historical; it is not yet impaired by violence <strong>of</strong> cognition,<br />

by the violence <strong>of</strong> the overnaming.<br />

Th ere is, however, other mourning otherwise than the mourning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mute lament and otherwise even than the mourning in being<br />

named, the name that redeems the speechlessness <strong>of</strong> the nameless. It<br />

is not the divine blissful mourning at the heart <strong>of</strong> a fi nite existence.<br />

Th e other mourning is in relation to what Benjamin calls overnaming,<br />

when the name itself withers away, when the name becomes a mere<br />

means <strong>of</strong> communication which reduces the blissful pure naming into<br />

signifi cance at the service <strong>of</strong> cognitive disposal, when the immediacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> the communication is lost in the mediacy <strong>of</strong> the signifi cance, in<br />

the magic <strong>of</strong> judgement. Th ere arises the mythic violence <strong>of</strong> the law:<br />

Th ere is, in the relation <strong>of</strong> human languages to that <strong>of</strong> things,<br />

something that can be approximately described as ‘overnaming’—the<br />

deepest linguistic reason for all melancholy and [from the point <strong>of</strong><br />

view <strong>of</strong> thing] for all deliberate muteness.(Benjamin 1996, p.73)<br />

Benjamin speaks <strong>of</strong> it as fall: the loss <strong>of</strong> the name in the language <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement, in signifi cance when the name occurs as mere instrument,<br />

as mere cognitive means, as mere medium <strong>of</strong> communication.<br />

Language then becomes mediated in the language <strong>of</strong> judgement, and<br />

the name is hollowed inside out, becomes hollow and empty in the<br />

bubbling and prattling. Here also takes the mythic birth <strong>of</strong> law and<br />

force <strong>of</strong> it, the power <strong>of</strong> the positing act: the nameless is sought to<br />

be appropriated in overnaming that now assumes the language <strong>of</strong><br />

judgement and signifi cance, in the name <strong>of</strong> law and its force, in the<br />

mythic violence <strong>of</strong> pure positing. Th e magic <strong>of</strong> the prattle is the magic<br />

<strong>of</strong> evil, the magic <strong>of</strong> positing violence, which has to be diff erentiated<br />

from the magic <strong>of</strong> the pure naming which is the originary donation<br />

beyond violence. Before in the name, the name communicates<br />

nothing but that which communicates itself in the name; but now<br />

name becomes mere cognitive means <strong>of</strong> positing, and the name itself


196 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

falls outside itself, it is made to signify what comes from outside <strong>of</strong><br />

itself, namely, knowledge <strong>of</strong> good and evil, for ‘evil abandons the<br />

name’(Ibid., p. 71)<br />

Th e abandonment <strong>of</strong> the name, that abandonment <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>f ering<br />

<strong>of</strong> language itself, the promise that is given with that <strong>of</strong>f ering, the<br />

abandonment <strong>of</strong> this originary promise for the sake <strong>of</strong> predicative<br />

use <strong>of</strong> language at cognitive disposal where language is mere means:<br />

this is the birth <strong>of</strong> mythic law and its violence. Th is violence is the<br />

innermost reason <strong>of</strong> the lament <strong>of</strong> language, distinguished from the<br />

blissful melancholy <strong>of</strong> the paradisiacal naming beyond violence.<br />

Th erefore a critique <strong>of</strong> violence assumes the form <strong>of</strong> a remembrance<br />

<strong>of</strong> that originary <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language, the originary promise <strong>of</strong><br />

redemption, that opening beyond any positing act, the essential nonappropriation<br />

that placed into man’s hand fi rst <strong>of</strong> all the gift <strong>of</strong> the<br />

naming. To remember, which is otherwise than speculative-cognitive<br />

memory <strong>of</strong> a recuperative, apophantic process is to be permeated<br />

by a melancholy that comes with a renunciation <strong>of</strong> power, for all<br />

renunciation brings with it certain mournfulness.<br />

Thinking and Thanking<br />

Th e mournfulness intimates the one who remembers his originary<br />

fi nitude—that is his originary non-appropriation <strong>of</strong> the gift—and<br />

thereby renounces any appropriation <strong>of</strong> the gift. Th is mournfulness<br />

is not any ordinary mournfulness about a particular loss, but what<br />

Martin Heidegger calls (1980)—with Hölderlin in mind -‘the<br />

fundamental attunement’ (Grundstimmung) <strong>of</strong> mourning. With<br />

the welcoming <strong>of</strong> the coming to presence <strong>of</strong> the divine, Hölderlin’s<br />

poetry keeps the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary gift and promise <strong>of</strong><br />

language which is none but the promise <strong>of</strong> the coming itself. Th erefore<br />

the gift always is attuned to a certain tune <strong>of</strong> mournfulness. Th is<br />

tune and attunement <strong>of</strong> mournfulness is the task <strong>of</strong> fi nitude. in his<br />

lectures on Hölderlin’s two poems ‘Germanien’ and ‘Der Rhein’,<br />

Heidegger thinks this fundamental attunement (Grundstimmung) <strong>of</strong><br />

mournfulness in Hölderlin’s poetry as an essential endurance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> language:<br />

… Real renouncement, in other words one which carries itself<br />

authentically, is a power <strong>of</strong> creation and engendering. By letting go <strong>of</strong>


Pain • 197<br />

its old possessions it receives a gift, but not after the fact, as a reward:<br />

for within it the mournful endurance <strong>of</strong> necessary renouncement and<br />

giving away is a ‘receiving’. (Heidegger 1980, p. 94)<br />

What it receives by renouncing the old possessions, by renouncing<br />

mastery and force? It receives the gift <strong>of</strong> the advent. Th is gift is<br />

welcomed in the naming. Poetic saying is naming that welcomes the<br />

coming and receives this gift <strong>of</strong> coming. Th erefore poetic saying, like<br />

thinking, is thank-giving activity. In his series <strong>of</strong> lectures called What<br />

is Called Th inking? Heidegger shows the essential affi nity <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

(Denken) with thanking (Danken): thinking is thanks-giving for<br />

what comes to be thought, for ‘we never come to thoughts/ Th ey<br />

come to us’ (Heidegger 2001, p. 6). What the gift <strong>of</strong> thought <strong>of</strong>f ers is<br />

the unthought, <strong>of</strong> what is not presently given as thought but what is<br />

to come, the future <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th e advent <strong>of</strong> thinking is outside the<br />

conceptual, reductive totalizing System making metaphysics. What is<br />

called thinking is calling to come, welcoming this coming:<br />

To call is not originally to name, but the other way around: naming is a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> calling, in the original sense <strong>of</strong> demanding and commending.<br />

It is not that the call has its being in the name; rather every name is<br />

a kind <strong>of</strong> call. Every call implies an approach. We might call a guest<br />

welcome (Heidegger 1968, p.125).<br />

If the poets and creative artists, creative thinkers and philosophers<br />

are permeated by a melancholy—as Aristotle remarks—it is in so<br />

far as for the poets and the creative thinkers the naming maintains<br />

its relation to the originary non-appropriation, to the opening that<br />

opens with the gift and that is maintained by renunciation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> all appropriation and power <strong>of</strong> the positing law. the<br />

poetic Saying—unlike the predicative thinking that arrives at the<br />

thetic, categorial cognition <strong>of</strong> what is ‘presently given’ on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

the result <strong>of</strong> a process—renounces such a claim to appropriation in<br />

order to announce, or welcome the coming to presence. Th erefore each<br />

poetic Saying itself is renunciation, or rather to say with Heidegger<br />

‘renunciation is in itself a saying’ (1982, p. 150).<br />

Th e renunciation which is in itself a poetic saying is not therefore<br />

something negative but rather affi rmative, since it welcomes the<br />

coming to presence. To this affi rmation is owed, what Heidegger<br />

calls, ‘thanks’, thankfulness or gratitude for being able to affi rm or


198 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

welcome the coming, thankfulness for the gift <strong>of</strong> being the receiver<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming, gratitude for the arrival that language gives to us and<br />

promises us. In his lecture delivered at Vienna with the full title in<br />

German Dichten und Denken. Zu Stefen Georges Gedicht Das Wort,<br />

Heidegger attempts to think the originary event <strong>of</strong> coming to presence<br />

in language that is welcomed in poetic saying in relation to the<br />

renunciation that adheres in this welcoming, the renunciation <strong>of</strong><br />

any claim to appropriation which representational thinking makes.<br />

If non-appropriation alone, if renunciation alone enables the poetic<br />

saying to welcome the coming to presence, this event <strong>of</strong> arriving, then<br />

a ‘fundamental attunement’ <strong>of</strong> melancholy that permeates this poetic<br />

saying would be the attunement <strong>of</strong> language itself that fi rst disappropriating<br />

us, opens us to the event <strong>of</strong> language, to the event <strong>of</strong><br />

coming, to which we owe thanks. Th is gratitude is our gratitude in<br />

recognition, a gratitude born out <strong>of</strong> an originary non-appropriation<br />

and promise. Heidegger says,<br />

But the more joyful the joy, the more pure the sadness slumbering<br />

within it. Th e deeper the sadness, the more slumbering the joy resting<br />

within it. Sadness and joy play into each other. Th e play itself which<br />

attunes the two by letting the remote be near and near be remote is<br />

pain. Th is is why both, highest joy and deepest sadness, are painful<br />

each in its way. But pain so touches the spirit <strong>of</strong> mortals that the spirit<br />

receives its gravity from pain. Th at gravity keeps mortals with all their<br />

wavering at rest in their being. Th e spirit which answers to pain, the<br />

spirit attuned by pain and to pain, is melancholy. (Ibid., p.153)<br />

If by the renunciation <strong>of</strong> the claim to appropriation a redemptive<br />

relation to the originary opening is maintained, to that promise and<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> redemption, it is precisely thereby these creative poets and<br />

thinkers become those who are the excluded and exiled, the homeless<br />

and the lonely. If the works <strong>of</strong> poets that struggle to articulate the<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> the world and in this articulation welcome the world<br />

thereby, the world does not have place for these poets. Th e poets,<br />

seeking to maintain the originary opening <strong>of</strong> the world forever open,<br />

thereby are excluded from the world that is opened in this opening.<br />

Poets are therefore the strangers to the world, lonely, and homeless,<br />

for to keep the relation to the opening <strong>of</strong> the world is to renounce all<br />

appropriation and all power <strong>of</strong> the historical polis. Heidegger says in<br />

the Introduction to Metaphysics:


Pain • 199<br />

Th e polis is the historical place, the there in which, out <strong>of</strong> which, and<br />

for which history happens. To this place and scene <strong>of</strong> history belong<br />

the gods, the temples, the priests, the festivals, the games, the poets,<br />

the thinkers, the ruler, the council <strong>of</strong> elders, the assembly <strong>of</strong> people,<br />

the army and the fl eet. All this does not fi rst belong to the polis, does<br />

not become political be entering into relation with a statesman and a<br />

general and the business <strong>of</strong> the state. No, it is political, i.e. at the site<br />

<strong>of</strong> history, provided there be (for example) poets alone, but then really<br />

poets, priests alone, but then really priests, rulers alone but then really<br />

rulers. Be, this means: as violent men to use power, to become preeminent<br />

in historical being as creators, as men <strong>of</strong> action. Pre-eminent<br />

in the historical place, they become at the same time apolis, without<br />

city and place, lonely, strange, alien and uncanny, without issue amid<br />

the beings as a whole, without stature and limit, without structure<br />

and order, because they themselves as creators must fi rst create all this.<br />

(Heidegger 1999,p. 152)<br />

Th is dense paragraph from Heidegger problematizes the complex<br />

relationship between the poesis <strong>of</strong> the opening, the originary promise<br />

that opens the polis and the political ontology <strong>of</strong> the world, the<br />

political being <strong>of</strong> the polis, which must already have been opened<br />

by the opening falling outside the polis. Th is opening <strong>of</strong> polis, which<br />

cannot be posited within the polis, because it must already be there<br />

for there even to be positing, is the originary promise <strong>of</strong> redemption<br />

which language <strong>of</strong>f ers, and which the poets and creative thinkers,<br />

through renunciation <strong>of</strong> mastery and appropriation, keeps it open<br />

so that there to remain the possibility <strong>of</strong> coming redemption above<br />

and beyond the given, beyond violence and beyond the law. With the<br />

poets and creative thinkers language, instead <strong>of</strong> being mere means at<br />

the cognitive disposal, or being mere language <strong>of</strong> judgement that overnames,<br />

is the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary naming. Th is naming is<br />

redemptive, for it renders the <strong>of</strong>f ering <strong>of</strong> language as an enduring<br />

presence for us, the gift <strong>of</strong> being present to us, and to open us to<br />

the eternity <strong>of</strong> the gift. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> this redemptive gift given<br />

in language is the endowment <strong>of</strong> eternity. Th is is how the mortals,<br />

created and fi nite, experience eternity as eternity, as he is the one<br />

who experiences death as death. If it is from language alone that we<br />

experience death as death, it is also from language alone, or in it we<br />

experience eternity as eternity, for it promises us redemption beyond<br />

violence. Th erefore the poets and creative thinkers, in recognition <strong>of</strong>


200 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

this gift, render the reception <strong>of</strong> this gift an occasion <strong>of</strong> thankfulness.<br />

Gratitude must mark the reception and recognition <strong>of</strong> this gift,<br />

which is none but the gift <strong>of</strong> eternity itself.


§ Apollo’s Lightning Strike<br />

Th e tremendous element, the fi re <strong>of</strong> the sky and the silence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

people, their life within nature and their limitedness and satisfaction<br />

has continually aff ected me, and as it is said <strong>of</strong> the heroes, so I may<br />

say that Apollo has struck me.<br />

—Hölderlin (1988a, p. 152)<br />

The Lightning Flash<br />

In a letter to Casimir Ulrich Böhlendorff , this fascinating letter that<br />

demands to be quoted completely, Hölderlin writes to his friend:<br />

Th e tremendous element, the fi re <strong>of</strong> the sky and the silence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

people, their life within nature and their limitedness and satisfaction<br />

has continually aff ected me, and as it is said <strong>of</strong> the heroes, so I may say<br />

that Apollo has struck me (Hölderlin 1988a, p. 152).<br />

What is the relation between the poetic Saying and the lightning<br />

bolt that Apollo strikes the poet with? Is it that poetic saying itself<br />

is intimated with the lightning fl ash that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all places the poet<br />

in the midst <strong>of</strong> the entirety <strong>of</strong> existence and therefore places him<br />

in relation to the divine and the tremendous elements <strong>of</strong> nature, to<br />

the appearance and disappearance <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon in the open<br />

where the poet fi nds himself in its midst? Th ere in the open, exposed<br />

to the lightning and thunders, to his mortality as mortality, the poet<br />

encounters ‘face to face’ with, what Heidegger calls the fourfold: the<br />

divine, the mortals, the sky in its tremendous manifestations and the<br />

mournful, solitude <strong>of</strong> the earth.


202 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

What is this open then? Th e open where the poetic saying is<br />

intimated by the lightning fl ash: what is it? Th e open is the place <strong>of</strong><br />

encounter, not the place as ‘this’ place or ‘that’ place, but placing <strong>of</strong><br />

all places, the place that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all places any place, where encounter<br />

takes place, happens, occurs. In the open the poet encounters the<br />

tremendous manifestations <strong>of</strong> the sky, the divine lightning strike, the<br />

mournful solitude <strong>of</strong> the earth and the mortality <strong>of</strong> the mortals:<br />

Th e thunderstorm, not only in its highest manifestation but, precisely<br />

in this sense as force and appearance among other forms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sky; light in its eff ects, forming nationally and mode <strong>of</strong> destiny—<br />

that something sacred to us—its force in coming and going; the<br />

characteristic element <strong>of</strong> the woods and coinciding <strong>of</strong> various<br />

characters <strong>of</strong> nature in one area; all sacred places <strong>of</strong> the earth are<br />

gathered around one place, and the philosophical light around my<br />

window. (Ibid., p. 153).<br />

Th e open is the place <strong>of</strong> encounter that enables, before all else,<br />

the poetic <strong>of</strong> a destiny that is in advance free opening <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

to come, the sacred and the divine. In the open the poet is in the<br />

middle, at the center <strong>of</strong> these elements and beings. Th erefore—<br />

and this is important—himself is outside the center. What is<br />

poetic saying, if not then, born out <strong>of</strong> the central experience, that<br />

means, out <strong>of</strong> the experience <strong>of</strong> his mortality as mortality and his<br />

exposure to the elements—a central saying that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all enables<br />

the encounter to be told, which fi rst <strong>of</strong> all any encounter to be told,<br />

for itself is the encounter <strong>of</strong> all encounters? Th e open is the place <strong>of</strong><br />

encounter and the poetic saying is telling <strong>of</strong> this encounter, not in<br />

a predicative manner, as about an encounter, but: itself born out <strong>of</strong><br />

encounter, the poetic saying is the welcoming the coming to be <strong>of</strong><br />

this encounter, to the presencing <strong>of</strong> this encounter. Th e encounter has<br />

not become meanwhile a ‘presently given’ truth which will be told<br />

in a predicative manner, but the encounter in its coming to happen<br />

gives itself to a measure <strong>of</strong> a presentation, which is poetic saying. Th e<br />

poetic presentation as Saying is pre-predicative, unlike speculative<br />

representation as concepts.<br />

If there is a measure here, if poetic saying must itself be the<br />

measure, it is not the measure <strong>of</strong> a predicative truth, nor the measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> what Heidegger refers as ‘parameter’. It is rather the poetic


Apollo’s Lightning Strike • 203<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> what Hölderlin calls ‘eccentric path’ that introduces, in<br />

its welcoming <strong>of</strong> the divine coming, the caesura <strong>of</strong> the eccentric. If<br />

man must be, being fi nite and mortal, constantly fl eeing from the<br />

center—as Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> him—being the central being, that<br />

placed him at the abyss <strong>of</strong> the undecidable limit, then he must also<br />

be—precisely for that matter the most eccentric <strong>of</strong> all.<br />

Th e mortal can encounter the coming to presence only with the<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> an eccentric path, only because what comes to presence<br />

exceeds at each instance any measure. He then must measure what<br />

refuses measure; he must welcome the divine coming to presence on<br />

the way that eccentrically mediates what refuses all mediation. As a<br />

result what remains after all remaining is: the disjunctive space which<br />

fi rst <strong>of</strong> all enables space to be spacing, time to be timing, distance to<br />

be nearing and nearing <strong>of</strong> the distance <strong>of</strong> god to man and man to<br />

being. Th is disjunctive space fi rst <strong>of</strong> all to be there, at the limit, for<br />

there alone any encounter takes place, time comes to presence, not<br />

as an eternal monotony <strong>of</strong> homogenous successions <strong>of</strong> instants, but<br />

as the lightning fl ash in the stillness <strong>of</strong> the event. It is this stillness <strong>of</strong><br />

the lightning fl ash that Hölderlin refers as that which ‘Apollo strikes’<br />

him: the experience <strong>of</strong> the encounter with the togetherness <strong>of</strong> all<br />

time in their intensifi cation that welcomes what comes to presence and<br />

what is told in the poetic saying, the experience <strong>of</strong> being exposed to<br />

the divine elements and experience <strong>of</strong> mortality as mortality, time as<br />

timing, space as spacing, death as death.<br />

What is then poetic saying? It does not speak about anything—about<br />

something that has happened, about existing system <strong>of</strong> relations, or<br />

about cognizable state <strong>of</strong> aff airs. It is rather welcoming the coming to<br />

presence, the encounter in the open <strong>of</strong> what is mortal and the divine.<br />

It refuses the parameter <strong>of</strong> a predicative truth. Th ereby it opens itself<br />

to a time yet to arrive, the incalculable and un-predicated encounter<br />

with the advent <strong>of</strong> history. Th e reason why the poetic saying refuses<br />

to be measured by the parameter <strong>of</strong> a predicative truth is because the<br />

parameter <strong>of</strong> a predicative truth does not enable the coming to presence,<br />

the un-predicative and incalculable encounter with the presencing<br />

to be welcomed. For the un-predicative and incalculable encounter<br />

with the presencing to be experienced, and the coming to presence be<br />

welcomed, a saying entirely other than the conceptual language <strong>of</strong><br />

predicative proposition is to be thought, for the predicative language


204 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

can speak only about what has presently become. It demands that the<br />

encounter be undergone by the poets and creative thinkers on the<br />

Abgrund on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone there may erupt the welcoming<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise history for mortals.<br />

In his lecture on Th e Nature <strong>of</strong> Language, Heidegger attempts<br />

to think <strong>of</strong>—beyond the conceptual language <strong>of</strong> predicative<br />

proposition, beyond the parameters <strong>of</strong> representational thinking—<br />

the poetic saying that enables the face to face encounter with what<br />

Heidegger calls ‘ the fourfold’, the encounter with time as timing,<br />

and space as spacing. Th e measure <strong>of</strong> a predicative thinking that<br />

takes its measure as parameter does not experience time as timing,<br />

and space as spacing, and obstructs any possibility <strong>of</strong> the encounter<br />

with the advent <strong>of</strong> time, for time as timing to be experienced, it is<br />

necessary to experience a time otherwise than as eternal vacancy <strong>of</strong><br />

a conceptual time, that means, the eternal succession <strong>of</strong> indiff erent,<br />

homogenous instants. In the eternal succession <strong>of</strong> the indiff erent,<br />

homogenous instants, no encounter takes place, because there is no<br />

ecstatic diff erence there to be the movement in constellation, in so<br />

far only in a movement in constellation can there be encounter <strong>of</strong><br />

the ecstasies <strong>of</strong> past, presence and future; only in the movement <strong>of</strong><br />

this ecstatic constellation <strong>of</strong> temporality can there be distancing <strong>of</strong><br />

nearness, and nearing <strong>of</strong> distance. Th e encounter is the diff erence<br />

as together, distance as nearing, holding apart as holding-together,<br />

which is what Heidegger calls simultaneity <strong>of</strong> ecstatic temporalities.<br />

In the simultaneity <strong>of</strong> being-together <strong>of</strong> ecstatic temporalities, as<br />

Zusammenhang, time itself times and this time timing is what strikes<br />

the mortals with the lightning fl ash in the stillness <strong>of</strong> the event. Th e<br />

lightning bolt that strikes the mortals spaces the mortals in the open,<br />

times the mortals to his fi nitude, to his mortality, exposes him to the<br />

monstrous site where there occurs the advent <strong>of</strong> history. Th e shock<br />

<strong>of</strong> this eternity that tears open the closure <strong>of</strong> time is the darkness <strong>of</strong><br />

excessive illumination, this ‘heavenly fi re’ which the mortal cannot<br />

look with his mortal eyes. Th ere alone, at this monstrous site <strong>of</strong> history,<br />

the mortal struck by the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> simultaneity <strong>of</strong> all that has<br />

been, presencing and time to come, experiences this simultaneity as<br />

death, as if the mortal can experience the eternity <strong>of</strong> all time together<br />

only as his death. Mortality is the intensifi cation <strong>of</strong> time, an intensity<br />

<strong>of</strong> time to the point <strong>of</strong> bursting forth, to the point <strong>of</strong> burning <strong>of</strong> a


Apollo’s Lightning Strike • 205<br />

lightning bolt where becoming and perishing momentarily present<br />

together. Poetic saying is enduring <strong>of</strong> this intensity. Heidegger says,<br />

<strong>Time</strong> times—which means, time makes ripe, makes rise up and<br />

grow. <strong>Time</strong>ly is what has come up in the rising. What is it that time<br />

times? Th at which is simultaneous, which is, that rises up together<br />

with its time. And what is that? We have long known it, only we do<br />

not think <strong>of</strong> it in terms <strong>of</strong> timing. <strong>Time</strong> times simultaneously: the<br />

has-been, presence, and the present that is waiting for our encounter<br />

and is normally called the future. <strong>Time</strong> in its timing removes us into<br />

it threefold simultaneity, moves us thence while holding out to us<br />

the disclosure <strong>of</strong> the has-been, presence, and the present waiting the<br />

encounter. In removing us and bringing towards us, time move on its<br />

way what simultaneity yields and throws open to it: time-space. But<br />

time itself, in the wholeness <strong>of</strong> its nature, does not move; it rests in<br />

stillness. (Heidegger 1982, p. 106).<br />

So it is with space. Space that spaces is the open, the spacing <strong>of</strong> space<br />

which enables the encounter to take place, striking the mortals with<br />

the stillness <strong>of</strong> an eternity, as if annihilating, in a divine violence,<br />

<strong>of</strong> all spaces and all places. Th is experience <strong>of</strong> time as eternity is<br />

granted to man on the basis <strong>of</strong> his originary experience <strong>of</strong> death as<br />

death that means, on the basis <strong>of</strong> his non-basis, his impossibility,<br />

his non-presence to-be-there at the origin <strong>of</strong> his being. Or rather,<br />

should we say it is his coming to presence without his-being-presently<br />

present? Poetic saying, enabling this encounter, enables death to be<br />

experienced as death, and also enables thereby eternity to arrive in the<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> the encounter where time times and space spaces. Th is<br />

encounter arrives as the divine violence, in its sudden advent, that<br />

strikes the mortals with stillness, in a kind <strong>of</strong> beatifi c joy, a lightning<br />

that lightens, frees and releases man unto the open: this beatifi c joy <strong>of</strong><br />

lightning and lighting is inseparable from what Schelling calls ‘divine<br />

mourning’. Both the beatifi c joy and the divine mourning, therefore,<br />

in their own ways, make us silent in a sort <strong>of</strong>, what Rosenzweig calls<br />

‘completed understanding’ and which attune us mortals to eternity<br />

as eternity. In this encounter where we are placed outside the totality<br />

<strong>of</strong> all successive homogenous instants, this lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> eternity<br />

as simultaneity <strong>of</strong> timing is Apollo’s striking that exposes us to our<br />

innermost existence as our essential fi nitude. Th e lightning fl ash is<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> pure exposure <strong>of</strong> the abandoned mortal being, the


206 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

exposure <strong>of</strong> ‘experience’ as such to the non-experiential advent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent.<br />

The Divine Violence<br />

Is not this lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> Apollo’s striking the ‘divine violence’,<br />

which Benjamin (1986, pp. 277-300) speaks <strong>of</strong>? If the theticpositing<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the speculative-conceptual language in its<br />

metaphysical violence is inseparable from the mythic origin <strong>of</strong> lawpositing<br />

violence, then divine violence, which is beyond any lawpositing<br />

and law-preserving violence, is something like poetic saying<br />

that enables the mortals to encounter the messianic advent, and the<br />

divine, for the poetic saying, at each instance, exceeds the theticpositing<br />

conceptual and predicative nature <strong>of</strong> the concept. Th e poetic<br />

saying, without positing, welcomes what arrives beyond positing, the<br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the unapparent: the incalculable, un-predicative<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> the arriving, the messianic coming <strong>of</strong> redemption. If this<br />

reading is accepted, then divine violence is none but what is to arrive,<br />

what comes to presence, what is to be encountered as the incalculable<br />

violence without violence, a non-violent violence. Is this non-violent<br />

violence—which does not rob speech from the tragic hero 1 , nor is<br />

the silence <strong>of</strong> the resolute tragic man with his defi ance confronting<br />

his own death, but the poetic saying <strong>of</strong> welcoming poet—is this not<br />

what Hölderlin says as that Apollo strikes him? Th e divine violence<br />

is without any violence, beyond any law-positing and any lawpreserving<br />

and therefore beyond and before the law, whose measure<br />

is not the deduced from a dialectical-speculative process, but from<br />

elsewhere, that is, from an originary promise <strong>of</strong> a coming that is in<br />

advance given in language, in the poetic saying. Such a promise is<br />

kept in the remembrance <strong>of</strong> a poetic language, in a poetic saying,<br />

which is the messianic promise <strong>of</strong> an advent beyond any dialectic<br />

<strong>of</strong> thesis and anti-thesis, beyond any reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

historical-speculative dialectic.<br />

Th e transcendence <strong>of</strong> a divine violence, because it is outside all<br />

totality, is that which eternity strikes the mortal as death, since<br />

for the mortals the eternity is outside his capacity and power. At<br />

this sudden apparent <strong>of</strong> the unapparent, eternity and mortality are


Apollo’s Lightning Strike • 207<br />

united in the monstrous judgement that shocks the mortals with<br />

its divine violence. Divine violence is experience <strong>of</strong> the impossible<br />

that has its measure the immeasurable, a violence which is beyond<br />

violence, as if thereby the mortals are exposed to his mortality, to<br />

his death, to the limit <strong>of</strong> all possibilities on the (non) basis <strong>of</strong> which<br />

the mortal then must measure his possibility and his mastery, his<br />

history and his politics.<br />

It is this experience <strong>of</strong> death as death that is excluded by the dialecticalhistorical<br />

process <strong>of</strong> what Benjamin calls, ‘the homogenous empty<br />

time’ (Benjamin 1977, pp. 251-261). Th e speculative-dialectical<br />

thinking which makes death the end-result <strong>of</strong> a process where each<br />

instance monotonously passes into another indiff erent instance<br />

does not experience death as death, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as the unitary ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> these instances are grasped by the self-foundational principle <strong>of</strong><br />

immanence and therefore it has no place for the poetic-naming<br />

language that welcomes the coming to presence, for the redemptive<br />

affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future. It thereby evades encountering the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the destiny <strong>of</strong> the origin and the origin <strong>of</strong> destiny, for this encounter<br />

alone enables the question <strong>of</strong> the transformation <strong>of</strong> man’s historical<br />

existence to be addressed, a question that has to be thought outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> a speculative-regressive process. Divine violence, then, which<br />

the mortal encounters by being spaced in the open, exposed to the<br />

lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> eternity, and exposed to his mortality, is outside<br />

the dialectical-historical process <strong>of</strong> ‘homogenous empty time’. It is<br />

rather the experience <strong>of</strong> time in the simultaneity <strong>of</strong> all that has been,<br />

presence and the time to arrive, a simultaneity whose lucidity blinds<br />

us, whose language renders us silent, and whose coming stills and<br />

intensifi es speech that endures this monstrous, demonic presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity as presencing.<br />

What then Apollo strikes the poet with? It is the coming <strong>of</strong> the<br />

holy, the advent <strong>of</strong> the divine that strikes the poet. Poetic saying<br />

welcomes the coming <strong>of</strong> the divine. Since the coming <strong>of</strong> the divine is<br />

not welcomed without renouncing mastery and the mythic violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> force, therefore a ‘fundamental mood’ <strong>of</strong> mournfulness attunes<br />

Hölderlin’s poetic saying. For Hölderlin being the poet <strong>of</strong> welcoming<br />

that welcomes the coming to presence <strong>of</strong> the divine, he is also thereby<br />

the poet <strong>of</strong> renunciation.


208 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Language, then, even before being the cognitive means at the service<br />

<strong>of</strong> representational thinking, is more primordially the name-giving<br />

that calls and welcomes what comes to presence. Walter Benjamin, in<br />

his On Language as Such and on the Language <strong>of</strong> Man (1996) calls<br />

the pure naming <strong>of</strong> Adam as blissful, which is given to the mortal<br />

as an immemorial gift. Language, unimpaired by cognitive disposal,<br />

belongs to the movement <strong>of</strong> constellation which does not serve as mere<br />

medium <strong>of</strong> communication, but is the redemptive remembrance <strong>of</strong><br />

the originary promise. Th erefore all thanks-giving for the gift is also<br />

thereby a remembrance <strong>of</strong> the promise <strong>of</strong> the coming that prepares for<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> coming to presence. For Heidegger, therefore, remembrance<br />

is the destinal task <strong>of</strong> man’s relation to the event <strong>of</strong> coming to presence.<br />

Such a remembrance <strong>of</strong> inception (Anfang) demands a step back, a<br />

retreat from the conceptual categories that makes language a mere<br />

cognitive means, or as mere serving the interests <strong>of</strong> the universal Spirit.<br />

It is poetic saying and thinking at the end <strong>of</strong> a certain metaphysics<br />

that prepares for the event <strong>of</strong> coming to presence. Such a preparation<br />

is the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the inception, or origin which is still to come,<br />

a past which is still to arrive. Since such a remembrance is a step<br />

back from conceptual-categorial thinking, the inception or the origin<br />

cannot be traced back dialectically-historically, for the dialecticalhistorical<br />

is the categorial cognition <strong>of</strong> the ‘presently given’, and not<br />

what comes to presence. Since what comes to presence, understood<br />

in its verbal resonance, is the originary temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time, <strong>of</strong> what<br />

we have said above as timing <strong>of</strong> time—and not what is ‘presently<br />

given’—this coming to presence can only be said in the lightning fl ash<br />

<strong>of</strong> poetic Saying, and not in the predicative-categorial cognition <strong>of</strong><br />

‘presently given entities’.<br />

Th e lightning fl ash by striking us mortals, and enabling us to<br />

experience our mortality as mortality, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all places us to the<br />

temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time and to spacing <strong>of</strong> space. Th e lightning fl ash is<br />

face-to-face encounter, not with entities that have become and ‘given<br />

presently’, but an encounter with temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time itself. Th is<br />

temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time, as pre-predicative and pre-categorial disclosure,<br />

is attempted to be thought by Heidegger (1962) in his Being and<br />

<strong>Time</strong> far more primordially as existential, and not tracing back the<br />

apophantic and the predicative <strong>of</strong> Vorhandenheit. language is not<br />

thought here as categorial predication <strong>of</strong> ‘presently given entities’ but


Apollo’s Lightning Strike • 209<br />

more originally in relation to the temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time as disclosure,<br />

which is for that matter existential, since such temporalizing <strong>of</strong> time is<br />

not the end result <strong>of</strong> a process, but the event <strong>of</strong> time itself.<br />

What is then, the gift <strong>of</strong> language that man is endowed with? It is<br />

the gift in the naming, —unimpaired by cognitive manipulability—<br />

<strong>of</strong> being revealed to oneself, <strong>of</strong> coming to presence to oneself. In the<br />

naming-language man comes to presence to himself, to reveal himself<br />

as mortal and fi nite being. Th is revelation is the reward <strong>of</strong> cognition,<br />

unlike any categorial cognition, <strong>of</strong> his essential fi nitude, which<br />

bestows him with the mournful serenity <strong>of</strong> contemplation, which the<br />

mortal must acknowledge with a joyous gratitude, with thankfulness.


§ Revelation<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> revelation is <strong>of</strong> interest to the philosophers <strong>of</strong><br />

religion, to theologians as well to the philosophers <strong>of</strong> language. What<br />

is attempted here, in this little chapter, is to touch on the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong> revelation with fi nitude and language. If language,<br />

in its innermost connection with fi nitude, cannot be reduced to the<br />

categorical, predicative cognition <strong>of</strong> the ‘presently given entities’,<br />

then the more originary pre-predicative and pre-categorical opening<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world in its coming can only be thought, without being able<br />

to exhaust in any schematization and thematization, as revelation,<br />

or manifestation, which in its coming to presence and opening <strong>of</strong><br />

the world, brings together—in an eschatological manner without any<br />

eschatology—the temporalities <strong>of</strong> past, present and future. As such,<br />

revelation is the event <strong>of</strong> time which is bound up with language, in<br />

so far as this event <strong>of</strong> time manifests itself as Word, in the naming<br />

language, as the logos <strong>of</strong> the mortal beings. Th e coming together<br />

<strong>of</strong> past, presence and future—the constellation <strong>of</strong> temporalities—<br />

appear like what Hölderlin calls ‘heavenly fi re’, Heraclitus calls it<br />

‘fi re’, and Bhartrihari, the Indian philosopher calls ‘Sphota’ (which<br />

brings together the two fold senses <strong>of</strong> ‘bursting’ and ‘manifestation’).<br />

In that case, the thought <strong>of</strong> revelation is essentially that <strong>of</strong> event that<br />

brings together, as constellation, <strong>of</strong> past and presence and future,<br />

and time and eternity. As bringing together <strong>of</strong> temporalities, it is the<br />

pure presentation <strong>of</strong> the strife between a messianic destruction and<br />

a promise <strong>of</strong> an arrival, between dissolution without conservation<br />

and the promise <strong>of</strong> an arrival, between melancholy and joy. Th is<br />

simultaneity cannot be thought to belong to a successive period <strong>of</strong>


Revelation • 211<br />

a continuous history. Language then, even before cognition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

‘presently given’ world, is opening <strong>of</strong> the world, and exposure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mortals who speaks language to the opening <strong>of</strong> the world, to that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the strife where opposites are coupled as what Hölderlin calls ‘<br />

monstrous coupling’.<br />

*<br />

Poetry is the mother- tongue <strong>of</strong> the human race, as the garden is<br />

older than the ploughed fi eld; painting than writing; song, than<br />

declamation; parables than logical deductions; barter, than commerce.<br />

—Hamann (2007, p.63)<br />

THE ARGUMENT<br />

Th is originary revelation <strong>of</strong> language is love that precedes the<br />

distinction between good and evil. It shows, in a paradoxical manner,<br />

that love is an originary form <strong>of</strong> strife, which is more primordial<br />

than the strife between good and evil, which precisely explains—<br />

since love precedes the distinction between good and radical evil—<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th is possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption—<br />

which is the possible arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise Kingdom, <strong>of</strong><br />

the possible coming <strong>of</strong> the impossible, <strong>of</strong> a future incalculable—this<br />

promise bestows upon the mortals the task <strong>of</strong> renewing, repeating<br />

the originary form <strong>of</strong> strife in each instantiation <strong>of</strong> presencing, so<br />

that each instantiation <strong>of</strong> presencing itself becoming a form <strong>of</strong> strife,<br />

which is that <strong>of</strong> love as revelation. Since this revelation <strong>of</strong> love in each<br />

instantiation <strong>of</strong> presencing is only renewed in the mortal naming-<br />

language, therefore, one can go further to argue that the idea <strong>of</strong><br />

revelation is that <strong>of</strong> language in love and <strong>of</strong> love in language.<br />

One can say, to begin with, that at that beginning before beginning,<br />

at that immemorial past, before anything like signifi cation, or sense,<br />

there revealed love, or love reveals itself. Th e language <strong>of</strong> this love,<br />

since it precedes any predication <strong>of</strong> existence, is nothing less than<br />

announcing <strong>of</strong> existence coming into presence; in other words, we shall<br />

call this event <strong>of</strong> existence that is heralded in the language <strong>of</strong> love as the<br />

language <strong>of</strong> Word, or Name, before it assumes conceptual categories.<br />

It means Word is Love, or love reveals itself as Word. As revelation,<br />

the Word does not communicate anything apart from this event <strong>of</strong>


212 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

coming itself, on the basis <strong>of</strong> which, on the basis <strong>of</strong> its erasure, there<br />

comes to be signifi cation, or categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> the entities given<br />

there. What is attempted here to be thought, in the word ‘revelation’,<br />

nothing content like signifi cation, but the originary opening <strong>of</strong> sense,<br />

which is always the sense <strong>of</strong> the world which is to come, which as<br />

such is prior to signifi cation <strong>of</strong> the given world. Th is signifi cation at<br />

the service <strong>of</strong> the categorical disposal gives itself double illusion: that<br />

it itself is the originary event <strong>of</strong> truth, while it is merely inverse, like<br />

the mirror image, <strong>of</strong> the event; and secondly, it claims a totality which<br />

it doesn’t possess, like claims <strong>of</strong> self-presence, self-identity, while its<br />

claims for self-presence is—to evoke Jacques Lacan (2001, pp. 1-8)<br />

here—only a ‘misrecognition’, that is, it is based on an abyss which<br />

has already always erased itself, or to say—Schelling—fallen (Abfall),<br />

diverted itself and have relapsed itself into an irrecuperable, more<br />

ancient than any ancient past. In the following part <strong>of</strong> this work, this<br />

question <strong>of</strong> origin will be posed anew, which should be able to show<br />

the double, incommensurable character <strong>of</strong> revelation: it welcomes<br />

a presencing while absenting itself, something like what Heidegger<br />

calls the event <strong>of</strong> Lichtung which allows something to be unconcealed,<br />

while concealing itself. Th e event <strong>of</strong> language too has the double,<br />

incommensurable character: it communicates its coming to presence,<br />

and yet withdrawing its event character, so as it shelters itself from<br />

any reduction and totalization, from any predication, signifi cation, or<br />

concept in its thetic positing and preserving. Language that is in love<br />

is an infi nite excess, unsaturated phenomenon, which is the essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> manifestation or revelation. In the revealed entities <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> revelation itself is not exhausted; it remains unapparent<br />

in each and every visible forms <strong>of</strong> the given and thereby infi nitely<br />

opens itself to its own excess <strong>of</strong> presentation.<br />

Th erefore the infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the revelation in its verbal resonance,<br />

in any instantiation <strong>of</strong> presencing, the revelation always appears<br />

as futural, that means opening to the not yet. Revelation promises<br />

redemption, the messianic arrival <strong>of</strong> the not yet, which is only so far<br />

as the strife <strong>of</strong> the loving word is renewed in any fi nite, conditioned,<br />

historical presencing. At the heart <strong>of</strong> historical presence, an originary<br />

strife <strong>of</strong> the loving word is to be introduced, in such a way that this<br />

loving disrupts, interrupts, and transfi gures any historical-speculative<br />

totalization, or totalization <strong>of</strong> Sense, or it introduces interval in


Revelation • 213<br />

any continuity <strong>of</strong> the self-same, introducing like an infi nite excess,<br />

or infi nite surplus without equivalences <strong>of</strong> self-presencing instant<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘now’. All determination <strong>of</strong> the political and historical is only<br />

derivative <strong>of</strong> this originary strife <strong>of</strong> love, which is that <strong>of</strong> revelation,<br />

the non-contemporaneous disjunction in language between the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> coming to presence and what comes to presence as totalities <strong>of</strong><br />

revealed entities, so that what remains in excess <strong>of</strong> the totality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

revealed signifi cation is nothing other than this event <strong>of</strong> revelation<br />

itself.<br />

From this follows the following proposition <strong>of</strong> this work: that the<br />

metaphysical task <strong>of</strong> man to found, ground its own existence out <strong>of</strong><br />

his power, capacity, possibility—for signifi cation—demands to be<br />

opened up to the more originary event <strong>of</strong> revelation in love, which<br />

language enunciates itself even before language becomes predicative<br />

power at cognitive disposal. Th is event <strong>of</strong> love as language, since it<br />

must already reveal the world to man, or expose man to the world<br />

is more originarily political than any political. It is a political—<br />

which means here being in excess <strong>of</strong> itself, so that it is already<br />

always open to the others—the political before politics, before<br />

anything like man’s attempt to found community on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

power and law. Th is originary love opens, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, time to the<br />

world, on the basis <strong>of</strong> which man understands phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world as temporal, supra-temporal, or even a-temporal. Similarly<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> love must originarily open the world, so that on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> love, man understands something like politics, a-politics,<br />

and de-politicization. Love therefore, in its event character <strong>of</strong> its<br />

revelation, is no more politics than a-politics or even de-politics.<br />

Love’s polemos, love’s strife is more originary than contestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> power or forces <strong>of</strong> the given world that defi nes the juridicalpolitical<br />

closure. What is necessary, as the ethical task <strong>of</strong> our time,<br />

is to introduce into the closure <strong>of</strong> the juridical-political, the strife <strong>of</strong><br />

love, as an excess <strong>of</strong> the juridical-political closure.<br />

As excess it is opening up <strong>of</strong> time itself—the time <strong>of</strong> signifi cation—<br />

what is its immemorial past, and its messianic arrival to come, for<br />

revelation, as instantiation <strong>of</strong> presencing co-joins in a disjunctive<br />

manner, past, presence and future. Love, like language, co-joins<br />

what is disparate by introducing originary strife so that this strife


214 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

itself exceeds any political-historical-metaphysical totalization. What<br />

exceeds in the form <strong>of</strong> strife <strong>of</strong> love is what is prior to what Benjamin<br />

(1986, pp. 277-300) calls the two fold ‘law positing’ and ‘law<br />

preserving violence’. Th e excess <strong>of</strong> love and the excess <strong>of</strong> language<br />

which cannot be posited as such is this revelatory character: outside<br />

all communicability, it is the eschatological reserve or a messianic<br />

withdrawal, in the name <strong>of</strong> a future and not yet, outside any reductive<br />

totalization.<br />

Synthesis without Continuum<br />

It is Schelling, already before Nietzsche, who introduces the<br />

problematic <strong>of</strong> the strife <strong>of</strong> love as the event <strong>of</strong> revelation. While Hegel<br />

makes the beginning and the end <strong>of</strong> the process, or, the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> Spirit as the movement <strong>of</strong> concept that becomes, that comes to<br />

itself as this process, a movement that is autochthonous, Schelling on<br />

the other hand sees revelation in love, without positing it as concept<br />

or predicate, as the originary moment <strong>of</strong> a movement that remains<br />

un-autochthonous, fi nite but exposed to the infi nite. Th e ‘irreducible<br />

remainder’ <strong>of</strong> this moment <strong>of</strong> opening <strong>of</strong> the world remains, in<br />

respect to the world, as heterogeneous, unconscious, in-excess, the<br />

immemorial past that no apophansis <strong>of</strong> the predicative judgement<br />

can re-trace. Th e ‘unappeased melancholy’ that Schelling evokes in<br />

his Freedom essay, a melancholy due to this ‘irreducible remainder’,<br />

is also—in its remnant-character (an idea that Rosenzweig in his<br />

Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption, attempts to think in a messianic manner)<br />

an intensifi cation <strong>of</strong> hope, or an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future, which is the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> the arrival <strong>of</strong> redemption from radical evil. If language<br />

<strong>of</strong> love is the originary opening <strong>of</strong> the world, its irreducible remnant<br />

makes the idea <strong>of</strong> a messianic community possible, a community<br />

which is always to come. Th is idea <strong>of</strong> community, which is neither<br />

a regulative idea, nor a constitutive one, cannot be thought on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> the political, which is that<br />

<strong>of</strong> metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject. Th is idea <strong>of</strong> revelation, which has<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> redemptive fulfi llment, brings together the immemorial<br />

past and incalculable future through continuous disruption <strong>of</strong> selfpresence,<br />

so that this disruption does not found itself on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a continuum, whether it is Subject, or the logical principle <strong>of</strong>


Revelation • 215<br />

identity. A community to come does not have as its ground, or basis<br />

a continuum, a community without continuum. Th is disruption is<br />

the renewal <strong>of</strong> the strife <strong>of</strong> love in any given presence so that the<br />

unapparent may advent. Community to come is, however, though<br />

it is not grounded on the principle <strong>of</strong> continuum, is therefore no<br />

stranger to the idea <strong>of</strong> synthesis—between fi nitude and infi nitude—<br />

which is not to be understood in the speculative sense, but as a form<br />

<strong>of</strong> strife. What is sought to be introduced here is another notion <strong>of</strong><br />

synthesis, which is that <strong>of</strong> love, as eternal disruption <strong>of</strong> any closure,<br />

and yet bringing to proximity, through disruption <strong>of</strong> the fusion, into<br />

nearness the immemorial past and incalculable future.<br />

Language as Revelation in Schelling’s<br />

Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Freedom<br />

In his Philosophical Investigation into the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom,<br />

Schelling says,<br />

Only man is in God, and through this being- in- God is capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom. He alone is a central being, and therefore should also<br />

remain in the center. In him all things are created, just as it is also only<br />

through man that God accepts nature and ties it to him. (Schelling<br />

1936, p.92)<br />

‘Man is a central being’. From this Schelling derives the astounding<br />

insight: that, in so far as man alone is the central being—who belongs<br />

to the center, that means, to the limit, to the line that dis-joining<br />

co-joins the divine and the rest <strong>of</strong> created existence, that dis-fi guring<br />

co-fi gures, the copula <strong>of</strong> the judgement whose character <strong>of</strong> being<br />

is the abyss—to him alone, being central being, there belongs the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> evil. If only man is endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong> language<br />

so that the mediation is possible between the divine and the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

the created, that means through him revelation and the redemption<br />

is possible, then would it not be contradictory and even impossible<br />

that to this central being, the mortal as the medium <strong>of</strong> revelation<br />

and redeemer <strong>of</strong> nature, belongs the capacity <strong>of</strong> evil? Does there<br />

not lay the un-thinkability <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil in so far as this<br />

possibility renders God as the author <strong>of</strong> evil, and therefore makes the<br />

God less than the creator <strong>of</strong> the ‘best possible world’? Yet, since the


216 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

possibility and actuality <strong>of</strong> evil is undeniable, may this possibility not<br />

adhere in the fi nitude itself that is the revelation and the coming <strong>of</strong><br />

redemption itself? If that is so, then the mortal who alone is endowed<br />

with the gift <strong>of</strong> language, i.e., who alone is the medium through<br />

whom revelation makes manifest creation, and who alone for that<br />

matter redeemer <strong>of</strong> the rest <strong>of</strong> creation, only can he be capable <strong>of</strong><br />

evil. Because he is the danger, he is also the promise; because he is<br />

the abyss, through him alone there is connection and mediation, <strong>of</strong><br />

revelation and redemption; because he is endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

language, he is at once capable <strong>of</strong> evil, and for that matter, he is the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption. Th is means: being endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

language, the mortal essentially and in the inmost manner belongs to<br />

the fi nitude that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all enables his existence as essentially mortal<br />

and fi nite. Th e mortal is the being who, being endowed with the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, alone experiences his mortality as mortality, for only<br />

such a being is made the medium <strong>of</strong> revelation and the redeemer <strong>of</strong><br />

nature. If language itself is essentially intimated with fi nitude, for the<br />

mortal who experiences death as death is thereby endowed with the<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> language, then language is also, for that matter, the promise<br />

for the mortals.<br />

Th e originary promise <strong>of</strong> language is the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption. It is<br />

the mortals’ task to hearken to this promise, and keep this promise<br />

in remembrance so that essential transfi guration and redemption <strong>of</strong><br />

his historical existence is possible. Being endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

language, the mortal has not only become the redeemer <strong>of</strong> nature—<br />

by himself endowing the mute nature, the animals and the birds<br />

with the name, for he is the name-giver what is not yet named—<br />

but he himself becomes open to his own redemption in the time to<br />

come. Th e blissful naming which the mortal endows the mute nature<br />

and not yet named animals is their redemption. Hence man is the<br />

redeemer <strong>of</strong> nature; or rather it is he through whom mute nature,<br />

being endowed with name, becomes redeemed. In Philosophical<br />

Investigations into the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom, Schelling therefore<br />

calls this central being, endowed with the gift <strong>of</strong> language, who alone<br />

is capable <strong>of</strong> evil, as ‘redeemer <strong>of</strong> nature’:<br />

Man is the beginning <strong>of</strong> the new covenant through whom, as<br />

mediator, since he himself is connected with God, God (the last


Revelation • 217<br />

division being attained) also accepts nature and takes it to him. Man<br />

is the redeemer <strong>of</strong> nature towards whom all archetypes strive. Th e<br />

Word which is fulfi lled in man exists in nature as a dark, prophetic<br />

(still incompletely unspoken) Word. Hence the anticipations which<br />

have no exegesis in nature itself and are only explained by man. (Ibid.)<br />

Th e animals, receiving the names from Adam, leap away from him<br />

in recognition <strong>of</strong> the blissful nobility with which they are endowed<br />

with. In the On Language as Such and on the Language <strong>of</strong> Man, citing<br />

from Friedrich Müller’s poem, Walter Benjamin says <strong>of</strong> the blissful<br />

recognition in the naming language <strong>of</strong> man: ‘Th e life <strong>of</strong> man in pure<br />

language-mind was blissful. Nature, however, is mute. True, it can<br />

be clearly felt in the second chapter <strong>of</strong> Genesis how this muteness,<br />

named by man, itself becomes bliss, only <strong>of</strong> lower degree. Friedrich<br />

Müller has Adam say to animals that leave him after he has named<br />

them, ‘ And saw by the nobility with which they leaped away from me<br />

that the man had given them a name’(Benjamin 1986,p. 329). Man<br />

who is the name-giver and the redeemer <strong>of</strong> the mute, still unspoken<br />

nature is the exegete, not the exegete who masters what he reads, but<br />

the exegete who redeems what is not yet read through his redemptive<br />

reading. He reads and in him the nature fi nds the redeeming exegesis.<br />

Redemption <strong>of</strong> nature lies in the linguistic being <strong>of</strong> the mortals, for in<br />

him alone the whole <strong>of</strong> the created existence and himself is revealed.<br />

Th is possibility <strong>of</strong> revelation, which is granted to man along with, or<br />

by virtue <strong>of</strong> the gift <strong>of</strong> language, endows the mortals with Love, which<br />

in turn—with mortals lovingly encountering face-to-face with the<br />

rest <strong>of</strong> the created, the divine and himself—mournful solitude <strong>of</strong> the<br />

earth and the tremendous manifestations <strong>of</strong> the sky above—redeems<br />

his own existence. Th erefore the linguistic being <strong>of</strong> the mortals is<br />

essentially that <strong>of</strong> love, which in the face <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> the evil,<br />

whose possibility is given along with love in revelation—open the<br />

mortal himself towards his own redemption.<br />

Th erefore Schelling in his Philosophical Investigations into the<br />

Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom thinks language itself, the creative Word in<br />

which the mortal partakes <strong>of</strong> the divine creativity, as revelation. Th e<br />

mortal, in whom the divine Word completely articulates itself, must<br />

also be the one in whom the Spirit reveals itself. Th erefore the essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the linguistic being <strong>of</strong> the mortal is that <strong>of</strong> revelation, for it is to the


218 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

mortal alone—who as an existence relatively outside him—that God<br />

reveals himself as the image <strong>of</strong> his own essential being, that is, his<br />

creativity. So that there be revelation and redemption, so that there be<br />

love, the Word is sent to man as the ideal principle <strong>of</strong> love. Benjamin<br />

calls this endowing the mortal with language as ‘divine gift’: ‘only<br />

in man, then’, writes Schelling, ‘is the Word completely articulate,<br />

which in all other creatures was held back and left unfi nished. But<br />

in the articulate word the spirit reveals itself, that is, God as existing,<br />

in act’ (Schelling 1936, p.39). If there is evil as possibility whose<br />

inherent possibility is given in the necessity <strong>of</strong> revelation, that is so<br />

that there be the light <strong>of</strong> love, since love demands what is other than<br />

itself to be love, so that it transfi gures, subordinates what is other<br />

to itself. Th is transfi guration happens, if the Word lovingly accords<br />

what is diff erence—what Schelling calls the principle <strong>of</strong> light and<br />

the principle <strong>of</strong> darkness, the vowels and the consonant—then it is<br />

redemptive. Th e evil is not a lie, in that sense, but a simulacrum,<br />

a simulated accord, a diseased unity <strong>of</strong> the judgement. Th e mortal,<br />

being the center, the copula, the spacing, the opening, the limit, itself<br />

the cision—which I call the open—is open to both Good and Evil<br />

in equal measure, both to redemption and falling away, both to (to<br />

use Benjamin’s words) naming and overnaming, both to the blissful<br />

melancholic naming and the melancholic overnaming <strong>of</strong> judgement,<br />

both to danger and its ‘saving grace’. Since the mortal placed unto<br />

the open is the spacing which is undecidable, the abyss and the limit,<br />

and since the mortal cannot persist in this undecidable: hence,<br />

so Schelling explains <strong>of</strong> the necessity <strong>of</strong> decision in relation to the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> evil, there is a constant solicitation to evil, a constant<br />

drawing towards whose source is not discovered, or disclosed within<br />

time, but a time outside time.<br />

Th erefore, being gifted with the ideal principle <strong>of</strong> love in language,<br />

evil is also given to man as possibility, which itself is not evil, but only<br />

a possibility without actuality. Th erefore fi nitude on account <strong>of</strong> which<br />

there is revelation, and there the possibility <strong>of</strong> love and evil both are<br />

given, this fi nitude itself—for that matter—not evil, but is merely<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil . Now if that is so and this is our question:<br />

then language—in its intrinsic connection with fi nitude, for it alone<br />

enables man to experience his mortality as mortality—then language<br />

itself must be intrinsically connected with the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil. If that


Revelation • 219<br />

is so, then the overnaming must be given as possibility along with the<br />

pure divine naming; the language <strong>of</strong> judgement arising in evil must<br />

already be given as possibility with the blissful divine gift <strong>of</strong> language.<br />

Language, then, arising with the pure gift <strong>of</strong> language, as a principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> love, as promise in the name, as hope for redemption, a medium <strong>of</strong><br />

revelation, may become in man a language <strong>of</strong> judgement, a simulated<br />

accord <strong>of</strong> evil, a cognitive medium where language becomes a mere<br />

means and no longer as medium <strong>of</strong> revelation, a seeking to close<br />

the Open, transforming the originary undecidable <strong>of</strong> the open to the<br />

decision to evil and subordinating the loving unity to the totalizing<br />

particular will. Th is is the origin <strong>of</strong> evil. In Benjamin’s words, it is<br />

the origin <strong>of</strong> ‘the mythic origin <strong>of</strong> law’. If this possibility <strong>of</strong> evil is<br />

given as intrinsic possibility in man, and if the saving grace is called<br />

forth by danger, and if language <strong>of</strong> judgement calls for redemptive<br />

language beyond the ‘mythic origin <strong>of</strong> law’, then the Open—which is<br />

the spacing <strong>of</strong> the undecidable—must remain open. Th is remaining<br />

open <strong>of</strong> the Open, keeping the undecidable spacing as an open chasm,<br />

this alone keeps the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption open to mortals. Th at<br />

means, this is also what Schelling’s work <strong>of</strong> Freedom comes to say<br />

towards the end: the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil remains, but by infi nitely<br />

subordinating the evil to redemption, to love and to the promise <strong>of</strong><br />

language, by forever and interminably keeping evil as mere possibility,<br />

as mere ground unto the depth (since the mere possibility does not<br />

itself constitute evil), this melancholy in the overnaming can be<br />

transfi gured into the beatitude <strong>of</strong> redemptive name, the danger into<br />

promise in the coming, the abyss into the summit, the darkness into<br />

light, the past into an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> future, the unredeemed death<br />

into redemptive possibility <strong>of</strong> future.<br />

If the ethico-political task <strong>of</strong> the historical mortal who creates<br />

history with the gift <strong>of</strong> language is to remain open the Open, to<br />

keep open the undecidable spacing, then this task is inseparable<br />

from the task <strong>of</strong> remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary promise <strong>of</strong> language<br />

itself, given with the gift <strong>of</strong> language immemorially. From this it is<br />

affi rmed that the history <strong>of</strong> the historical man begins with revelation<br />

<strong>of</strong> love and to renew this originary poetry <strong>of</strong> love is our historical<br />

task, which itself keeps open history towards its redemption. Th is<br />

redemptive hope is given to mortals as possibility because though<br />

radical evil is, it is not as originary as love, for evil derives its eff ect


220 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

only as contrast, and not as independent principle <strong>of</strong> being. Th is<br />

history, which is remembrance <strong>of</strong> the originary poetic <strong>of</strong> love beyond<br />

violence, would not be grasped by the self-foundational immanent<br />

principle as a speculative process. History is then no longer conceived<br />

as homogenous succession <strong>of</strong> banal instants, but as ecstatic, disruptive<br />

coming to presence, the coming that presents itself in the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> constellation or confi guration as the simultaneity <strong>of</strong> ecstatic<br />

temporalities. Th is confi guration <strong>of</strong> temporalities is otherwise than<br />

mere accumulative unity <strong>of</strong> the successive, homogenous presents.<br />

Th e latter is the speculative unity <strong>of</strong> a dialectical-historical. Th e<br />

confi guration is rather co-fi guring <strong>of</strong> temporalities as simultaneity<br />

that means a discontinuous whole that presents itself in the suddenness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the lightning fl ash that strikes the mortals with excessive, blinding<br />

illumination. It makes manifest in the suddenness <strong>of</strong> a fl ash the<br />

whole <strong>of</strong> temporalities together as discontinuous presentation, which<br />

for that matter appears to the mortal as standing still, the very (dis)<br />

fi gure <strong>of</strong> mortality.<br />

Understood in this sense, more primordially than understanding<br />

as speculative process, revelation is historical (in the sense that it<br />

inaugurates history as such). In the Philosophical Inquires Schelling<br />

therefore thinks <strong>of</strong> the two-fold creation: as the principle <strong>of</strong> light<br />

and darkness belong to the realm <strong>of</strong> nature, arising out <strong>of</strong> divine<br />

longing; so the principle <strong>of</strong> spirit and dark principle <strong>of</strong> evil belong<br />

to the realm <strong>of</strong> history arising out <strong>of</strong> revelation. In this sense evil is<br />

historical. Th ere is no evil where history does not come to presence,<br />

where history does not make manifest the necessity <strong>of</strong> decision out <strong>of</strong><br />

undecidable. But this undecidable itself belongs to the ground which<br />

is groundless, the in-diff erence <strong>of</strong> freedom—but not identity—<br />

that remains as, what Schelling calls ‘irreducible remainder’, as the<br />

inscrutable, almost demonic essence <strong>of</strong> freedom. But this remnant,<br />

this ‘irreducible remainder’ itself for that matter is the occasion <strong>of</strong><br />

hope for redemption, even though man decides for evil out <strong>of</strong> his<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th ere remains something in history as remnant outside<br />

history, which does not enable the closure <strong>of</strong> history in immanence. Th is<br />

remnant <strong>of</strong> history is the possibility <strong>of</strong> its redemption.<br />

It is this possibility <strong>of</strong> redemption that is given with language<br />

to mortals who comes to presence to himself. He then founds<br />

community, the polis where there takes place the harvest and the


Revelation • 221<br />

feast, the war and reconciliation, the division <strong>of</strong> the space into<br />

political territories and founding <strong>of</strong> the Law <strong>of</strong> the earth. But this<br />

founding, at each time, must keep remembrance <strong>of</strong> the face-to-face<br />

encounter with the serene mournful earth, the rest <strong>of</strong> the created,<br />

what he is endowed with the gift, so that the historical man in his<br />

all consummating hunger for appropriation and dominion may not<br />

transform what is merely possible evil into its actuality. For evil is<br />

nothing but the all devouring lust, this all consummating hunger<br />

for being what ought to remain—what Schelling calls ‘non-being’,<br />

which is for that matter is not pure nothing, but non-being <strong>of</strong> a<br />

particular will striving for being as total, universal dominion. Th e<br />

consummating claim to appropriation what is to remain nonappropriation,<br />

this destructive fi re that is not fi re that gives warmth<br />

for the living but consumes it: this evil is nothing but simulacrum <strong>of</strong><br />

the event, itself not the event that redeems historical suff ering into<br />

messianic happiness. Th e terrible eff ect <strong>of</strong> evil, therefore, does not<br />

derive from its having being, but precisely in its not-having-being, its<br />

non-presence, and its eternal greed for attaining actuality. Th erefore<br />

evil is not event but simulacrum <strong>of</strong> the event, for the event keeps open<br />

the originary Open, the gift in the naming that enables fi rst <strong>of</strong> all the<br />

encounter with the coming and welcomes the coming to language.<br />

Th is event is the event <strong>of</strong> redemption the coming <strong>of</strong> which possibility<br />

demands renunciation <strong>of</strong> appropriation and mastery that the mortal,<br />

in his arrogance, seeks. Th erefore evil does not lie in the fi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

man but in the fi nite being’s self-abnegation <strong>of</strong> his fi nitude, though<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil is given with this fi nitude essentially, which<br />

does not itself, however, explain the actuality <strong>of</strong> evil. Schelling says<br />

in a footnote in his Philosophical Inquiries into the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

Freedom: ‘for the same reasons every other explanation <strong>of</strong> fi nitude,<br />

for instance by the concept <strong>of</strong> relations, must be inadequate as an<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong> evil. Evil is not derived from fi nitude, but from fi nitude<br />

which has been exalted to independent being’ (Schelling 1936, p.<br />

46). Th e historico-political task <strong>of</strong> the mortal is the attentiveness,<br />

the care that is required to transfi gure the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil into the<br />

event, to keep the originary poetic <strong>of</strong> history open, and to renew the<br />

naming language <strong>of</strong> the poetic saying to welcome the coming. In this<br />

open he must be open to what is other, otherwise than man, for what<br />

belongs to man does not belong to him as possession. Man is the


222 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

speaker <strong>of</strong> a language which is not his possession. To renounce this<br />

claim to possession so that he may receive what is infi nitely greater<br />

than possession, is to experience mortality, in a diffi cult and more<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound sense, as if this mortality itself becomes somewhat <strong>of</strong> a<br />

mortal task <strong>of</strong> man.<br />

Th is mortality itself is something like a gift. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

is to renew this thinking <strong>of</strong> mortality. Because thinking has a<br />

certain relation to mortality, thinking <strong>of</strong> the gift becomes the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. It is this essential relation <strong>of</strong> thinking with mortality<br />

that makes thinking an essential linguistic ‘activity’ (to use this word<br />

‘activity’ without having better word to say) <strong>of</strong> man. Th inking that<br />

takes seriously the question <strong>of</strong> mortality—for what touches the<br />

mortal more than his mortality, or mortality <strong>of</strong> the other?—must<br />

take seriously the question <strong>of</strong> language. At stake lies the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> the goal and purpose <strong>of</strong> his existence—if this old fashioned<br />

question is not to be renounced—the question <strong>of</strong> his redemption<br />

and affi rmative hope for future. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this affi rmative<br />

hope for future alone that any <strong>of</strong> our ethico-political questions make<br />

sense and will retain their sense.


Part III<br />

Event


§ Of Event<br />

The Question <strong>of</strong> Event and the Limit <strong>of</strong> Foundation<br />

For a long time in the history <strong>of</strong> a predominant thought, a thought that<br />

has determined the destiny and fate <strong>of</strong> that history and the historicity<br />

<strong>of</strong> that history itself, the event <strong>of</strong> coming into existence has always been<br />

subsumed, repressed, subordinated to the thought <strong>of</strong> Being and time<br />

to the point <strong>of</strong> oblivion <strong>of</strong> such a thought <strong>of</strong> an event. Th e notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the event is thought only conditionally, that means, on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a being already present, in its ‘given presence’ character. One can<br />

even say that such a thought <strong>of</strong> event as coming into existence really<br />

never occurred as such, apart from fugitive moments <strong>of</strong> that history<br />

that has furtively escaped from the memory <strong>of</strong> that history, or, rather,<br />

they are excluded from that history, moments that have appeared<br />

like lightning fl ash with an exceptional brilliancy that have made the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> that history opaque, dark, and deep which the intelligibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being cannot penetrate. Th is inscrutable abyss <strong>of</strong> that history is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> eruption <strong>of</strong> that history and not a consequence <strong>of</strong> that<br />

history’s process <strong>of</strong> accomplishment. It is the opening or inauguration<br />

<strong>of</strong> that history which as such—and this is important—is also its end<br />

(an ‘end’ which is without telos).<br />

Th e thought <strong>of</strong> the event is that thought which thought itself<br />

refuses, by a necessary logic in the thinkable itself, to confront and<br />

encounter its own abyss. It is what history <strong>of</strong> the thinkable—<strong>of</strong> the<br />

conditional event as given presence—refuses or forecloses in order for<br />

the thinkable to emerge into being that constitutes itself as history as<br />

such, memorial and monumental. It emerges itself as the process <strong>of</strong>


226 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

inscription <strong>of</strong> the grand marches <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity<br />

from nothingness <strong>of</strong> its being towards its fulfi lled self-presence. In<br />

this manner the unconditional arrival <strong>of</strong> the other already always<br />

becomes its buried presupposition, or rather its condition <strong>of</strong><br />

possibility. To expose this presupposition character <strong>of</strong> history itself<br />

is to open another inauguration, another inception which is the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking today. If thinking has been pre occupied itself with the<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> ‘ends’ today, that is only so far as it is already always and<br />

primarily an attempt to think <strong>of</strong> inauguration and inception in a<br />

more originary manner, that means unconditionally, affi rmatively,<br />

and without any closure. In other words, it is essentially concerned<br />

with the thought <strong>of</strong> event—not event as thought or as thinkable, but<br />

precisely in its intimate, pr<strong>of</strong>ound connection with abyss <strong>of</strong> fi nitude<br />

wherein this being called ‘mortal’ does not so much appropriates it, or<br />

owns it, but rather that this ‘mortal’ is immemorially, an-anarchically<br />

‘owned’ or appropriated by this event.<br />

Th is event is immemorially older, more ancient than ancient, and<br />

incalculably younger and newer than any future. It therefore does<br />

not belong to the economic calculation <strong>of</strong> the time <strong>of</strong> modernity<br />

wherein each instant, ‘now’ <strong>of</strong> presenting is instantly vanishing, and<br />

therefore is already going to be old, ineluctably and inevitably. Th e<br />

event here is rather to be thought in relation to a non-economic<br />

excess <strong>of</strong> revolutionary time that does not serve the measure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capital. Th e fugitive-character <strong>of</strong> this excessive moment is unlike the<br />

evanescent, ever-new instants <strong>of</strong> ‘sensuousness’ that in its departing<br />

enables the capital <strong>of</strong> sense to emerge in manifold pr<strong>of</strong>i ts. In this sense<br />

this excess <strong>of</strong> event does not belong to ‘time’ or to ‘history’ as such ;<br />

or rather, it evokes a time or history that is wholly otherwise, for what<br />

at stake here is the gathering <strong>of</strong> history that at once summons its<br />

very dispersal or dissolution. What remains, out <strong>of</strong> this revolutionary<br />

excess <strong>of</strong> presentation, is not self-sameness <strong>of</strong> what has once been<br />

present, but the remainder <strong>of</strong> the immemorial not yet.<br />

Th e fugitive excess <strong>of</strong> history does not completely belong to<br />

history without remnant. As such it is forever in departure, fl eeing<br />

from any immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence, and at the same time persisting<br />

in-apparently in each here and now. Th is inapparition does not so<br />

much constitute the ‘depth’ <strong>of</strong> history, as if beyond the totality <strong>of</strong><br />

history’s visible forms there exists ever the same invisible depth. Th e


Of Event • 227<br />

task <strong>of</strong> our ethico-political would, then, consist <strong>of</strong> ever retrieving<br />

the invisible depth to the visibility <strong>of</strong> manifestation, which is the<br />

light <strong>of</strong> history. Th e excess <strong>of</strong> the unapparent is to be thought outside<br />

such a phenomenological thought <strong>of</strong> the nocturnal depth <strong>of</strong> darkness<br />

and the light <strong>of</strong> history that makes manifest truth in visible forms.<br />

In this sense, the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> fugitive is outside the preview <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenology as such, at least in the dominant and strict sense <strong>of</strong><br />

what constitutes ‘phenomenology’, for here is the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

fugitive that does not belong to the mortal called ‘man’ and to the<br />

light <strong>of</strong> his consciousness. ‘Man’ belongs to the excess <strong>of</strong> the fugitive<br />

and to the unapparent: he is owned by it, and on the basis <strong>of</strong> this<br />

belonging character, man remains open to history and to the outside.<br />

Th e redemptive fulfi llment, whose promise is preserved by the messianic<br />

remnant, cannot occur within any history <strong>of</strong> self-presence. It occurs<br />

in a lightning fl ash when the whole <strong>of</strong> history, in it’s entirely, gathers<br />

itself unto that abyss—where another inauguration, another inception<br />

celebrates its feast. the essential thinking is concerned itself with its<br />

highest task: how to preserve those moments <strong>of</strong> lightning fl ash that<br />

are destined to disappear at the moment <strong>of</strong> their apparition which<br />

no phenomenological ontology that is based upon the categorical<br />

can attain to its grasp? Th e excess <strong>of</strong> unapparent event <strong>of</strong> presencing<br />

remains what Schelling calls ‘un-pre-thinkable’, the outside <strong>of</strong><br />

thought, or thinkable, since the event does not constitute the<br />

mere potency <strong>of</strong> concepts, but pure actuality <strong>of</strong> presencing without<br />

remainder. To preserve the moments <strong>of</strong> event which do not belong<br />

to the dominant history <strong>of</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> Being is the highest exertion<br />

<strong>of</strong> our thinking today. To preserve those exceptional moments <strong>of</strong><br />

exceptional clarity where the diff erence between the coming into<br />

existence and Being appear as an unapparent apparition is the highest<br />

exertion <strong>of</strong> thought, not only because we are no longer nearer to that<br />

‘heavenly fi re’ like Empedocles, but because it presents us, exposes<br />

us, abandons us to a thought which is the limit <strong>of</strong> the thinkable, the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> thinking’s power to present itself as sense and presence. To<br />

attain to the thought <strong>of</strong> event is to be exposed to the diff erence which<br />

is not so much the diff erence between categories <strong>of</strong> being but the<br />

diff erence between the coming into existence and Being.<br />

When Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> the ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent’,<br />

it is precisely the unapparent character <strong>of</strong> the manifestation <strong>of</strong> the


228 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

event is meant, which in turn is to be thought outside any eidetic<br />

phenomenology. Th at means the task <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking has<br />

changed today; or, rather, we feel the need, now than ever before, to<br />

invent new thinking, no longer the thinkability <strong>of</strong> Being and Being <strong>of</strong><br />

thought; for they (the thinkability <strong>of</strong> Being and the Being <strong>of</strong> thinking)<br />

follow the same law <strong>of</strong> movement, the same logic <strong>of</strong> origin, which is<br />

origin reductively determined as generation, or emanation—a thought<br />

as old as ‘the history <strong>of</strong> philosophy’ itself—and movement whose<br />

pure ecstatic transcendence is reductively totalized into the being <strong>of</strong><br />

time itself, which is then thought to be a duration as continuous fl ow,<br />

whose logic a phenomenology <strong>of</strong> pure transcendence will be able to<br />

discover. It is the logic <strong>of</strong> time which is none but the idea <strong>of</strong> being,<br />

or subjectivity itself. It is against this time <strong>of</strong> subjectivity in its false<br />

transcendence, which takes its inspiration from the idea <strong>of</strong> origin<br />

as generation or emanation, that we will introduce logic <strong>of</strong> origin<br />

as diff erential and multiple, as pure ecstatic transcendence rather<br />

than continuity as fl ow. Only that way the notion <strong>of</strong> the event as<br />

event allows itself to be thought, without subordinating itself to the<br />

substantial zed or nominalized determination <strong>of</strong> being or subjectivity.<br />

What philosophical thinking today, when the idea <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

itself is under question, thinks is its relation to event and thought’s<br />

relation to the diff erence between the coming into existence and Being as<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> existence. Th is abysmal diff erence is the spacing <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

from its own ground. It is what philosophy’s presupposition is; it is<br />

from where philosophy takes its birth as spacing <strong>of</strong> a diff erence that<br />

does not completely allow itself to be represented as the apparent character<br />

<strong>of</strong> the nominative or substantial. Th is diff erence as spacing manifests<br />

itself as unapparent apparition, beyond any phenomenological<br />

horizon <strong>of</strong> intelligibility, as thing-in-itself, as pure facticity, pure<br />

appearing or revelation, without any constitutive-constituting (self)<br />

consciousness underlying, without any egology, or transcendental<br />

Subjectivity. Instead the self-consciousness’ grasp <strong>of</strong> itself would<br />

already presuppose the more originary apparition <strong>of</strong> the unapparent<br />

as the fi nite opening <strong>of</strong> the world. Th is thing-in-itself which does not<br />

allow itself to be thought as subsistence <strong>of</strong> being nor as constituting<br />

dialectical-speculative-historical subject, is nothing other than<br />

the pure coming into existence which in relation to itself is pure<br />

immanence, but distinguishing from each and every predicate about


Of Event • 229<br />

the available, already happened entities <strong>of</strong> the world is actuality as<br />

pure transcendence. It is this coming into existence as thing-in-itself and<br />

as pure actuality—unconditional—that is what we call here as event.<br />

Perhaps now, when the logical thinking about the world—which<br />

has assumed the prestigious name called ‘metaphysics’—has come to<br />

an end, philosophy must give itself a new task <strong>of</strong> a new metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> facticity without any foundational and systemic pretension,<br />

a thinking <strong>of</strong> the pure facticity <strong>of</strong> the thing-in-itself, which is the<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> coming, not the coming that comes to<br />

pass away and then predicated on the basis <strong>of</strong> the intelligibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> phenomenological consciousness, but this coming itself in the<br />

purely verbal resonance before the nominative or substantive,<br />

in its ecstatic transcendence that precedes, in a certain manner <strong>of</strong><br />

speaking, anything that comes to pass away. Th is demands renewed<br />

inquiry, outside any phenomenological ontology and its systemic and<br />

foundational tasks, into the question concerning ‘the unapparent<br />

apparition’ <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> coming into existence as pure facticity, as<br />

pure actuality by distinguishing it from such traditional metaphysical<br />

distinctions between actuality and potentiality, between essentia<br />

and existentia etc. What needs to be introduced, then, outside such<br />

metaphysical distinctions, is a new thinking <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

and <strong>of</strong> a thinking <strong>of</strong> an actuality as pure facticity, which cannot be<br />

thought either as Being or Subject but as disclosive exposure to its<br />

radical futurity. With this we are already under the inspiration from<br />

Schelling’s later works, from his Positivphilosophie <strong>of</strong> what he calls the<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> empiricism. Such a transcendental empiricism that we are<br />

introducing here, without positing anything like transcendent being<br />

or subject, ego or transcendental consciousness (with the personal<br />

pronoun ‘I’) and at the limit <strong>of</strong> the foundational acts <strong>of</strong> thinking,<br />

should enable us to open ourselves to the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong><br />

the coming and its event character without, however, thematizing it<br />

within a noetic-noematic co-relation.<br />

What Schelling’s Positivphilosophie and its metaphysical<br />

empiricism inspires us is to think the facticity <strong>of</strong> actuality outside<br />

mere predicative potentiality <strong>of</strong> the concept, and the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event character <strong>of</strong> coming outside the philosophy’s project <strong>of</strong> totality<br />

and foundation on the basis <strong>of</strong> the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> Being/ Subject/<br />

Consciousness. In this way thinking is opened up to the more


230 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

originary notion <strong>of</strong> truth no longer on the basis <strong>of</strong> predication, and<br />

to the more originary event character <strong>of</strong> coming into existence that<br />

in a certain manner precedes Being or Subjectivity. In this manner<br />

the closure <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, and the dialecticalspeculative<br />

totality <strong>of</strong> history is hollowed inside out towards the abyss<br />

where the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong> the coming occurs and reveals<br />

itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> a radical fi nitude and mortality, and yet without<br />

founding on any positing assertion, or better predication, as truth.<br />

Here thinking confronts and encounters a limit that is not<br />

conquered or mastered within the possibility <strong>of</strong> the thinkable itself.<br />

If thinking is bound up with Being, then the event <strong>of</strong> coming into<br />

existence—in so far as it is incommensurable with the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

Being—is excluded from thought itself as thought’s failure, if thinking<br />

is satisfi ed as mere predicative grasp <strong>of</strong> a phenomena mere potential<br />

and not unconditional affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the pure, unconditional<br />

facticity.<br />

Th is aporia, which is the aporia <strong>of</strong> thinking, is simply aporia<br />

between the double demands on thinking: to be exposed to the<br />

consummate fi re <strong>of</strong> the event that seeks to annihilate thought<br />

on the one hand, and at same time to preserve event as event<br />

in memory and history, which means, to make it thinkable and<br />

operative in history and memory, to make the true exception, which<br />

is event, universal. It is this aporia, which is not just the aporia <strong>of</strong><br />

a hermetic thought, but an aporia that now defi nes the destiny <strong>of</strong><br />

our political and ethical concerns. Th is aporia does not allow to<br />

be thought as foundation <strong>of</strong> ‘political’ and ‘ethical’ legitimacy <strong>of</strong><br />

the dominant forces and powers, but rather that the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

the event must tirelessly expose, at any given moment, any form <strong>of</strong><br />

legitimacy under the force, power <strong>of</strong> the dominant, whether in the<br />

name <strong>of</strong> Being, Subjectivity or totality.<br />

To preserve this aporetic demands <strong>of</strong> a thought which is now, in so<br />

far as it is aporetic, does not allow an unequivocal unity or totality<br />

to emerge, even if is in the form <strong>of</strong> a cumulative movement that<br />

incorporates within itself the homogeneity <strong>of</strong> successive instants.<br />

What we have to think <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> coming now, if it does not have<br />

to sink its teeth into the banal passing <strong>of</strong> the accumulative, successive


Of Event • 231<br />

instants <strong>of</strong> dialectical-speculative history, is nothing other than<br />

thought itself as caesural, cisioned, torn asunder, and wholly inside<br />

out towards the open. Existence is not a pre-determined revealed<br />

truth which will then manifest itself as progressive, continuous work<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason; rather existence itself—understood in the event character<br />

<strong>of</strong> its coming, and which in so far as it is coming, is not a real predicate<br />

(to speak with Kant)—reveals itself as wholly incommensurable with<br />

itself, as multiple ecstasies that refuses any underlying fl ow <strong>of</strong> the same.<br />

Th is incommensurable multiplicity <strong>of</strong> the event is what threatens<br />

thought with constant solicitation to a madness, the madness that<br />

consists <strong>of</strong> thought’s inability to master the diff erence between event<br />

and Being, between a coming into existence and Being’s thinkability,<br />

between ‘presencing <strong>of</strong> presence’ and the given constant presence,<br />

between the infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the verbal ‘to’ and the nominative,<br />

substantive. To master this diff erence, philosophy conjure all its<br />

tricks to think the event on its own terms, attempting to think event<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> generation out <strong>of</strong> nothing or, an emanation from a<br />

pre-conceived, transcendental substance, being or whatever it is, or<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> revelation whose truth is manifested<br />

as the work <strong>of</strong> logos, reason, and on the basis <strong>of</strong> an auto-generative,<br />

auto-releasing and auto-contracting movement <strong>of</strong> immanence. As<br />

we will see, such tricks have exhausted their conjuring resources,<br />

and we will see that the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> their power <strong>of</strong> conjuration<br />

is the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> the foundational project <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, and<br />

the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> a dominant politics and ethics. Th e<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the event arrives here, anew, at the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> this<br />

foundational project to arrive at the thinkability <strong>of</strong> the world on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> Being.<br />

Today, more than ever before, with an urgency <strong>of</strong> a new<br />

millennium that demands new responsibility and new concept <strong>of</strong><br />

responsibility, the demand to think the political and the ethical anew,<br />

outside the foundational project <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics, cannot escape<br />

the problematic, the question <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> the coming outside<br />

the ontological project <strong>of</strong> the previous metaphysics. To answer the<br />

question why the question <strong>of</strong> the event has to be inscribed within<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> Being and time (and <strong>of</strong> thought and ground, <strong>of</strong> sense and<br />

presence that is governed by the necessity <strong>of</strong> a foundation): this


232 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

answer concerns the immense history <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics itself, one<br />

that cannot be undertaken here. Th is should be able to show why, and<br />

what manner, how the question <strong>of</strong> event is seen to belong to ground,<br />

or to foundation, to the giving <strong>of</strong> a ground and to accounting <strong>of</strong> a<br />

ground, which is always the question <strong>of</strong> Being as ground and Being<br />

<strong>of</strong> ground as ‘given presence’. Instead what is attempted here is the<br />

following: if Being is seen, most explicitly at the accomplishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> this history <strong>of</strong> thought, as giving <strong>of</strong> a ground, or Being itself as<br />

ground—in the two fold senses <strong>of</strong> permanent ground and most<br />

universal ground (<strong>of</strong> what Heidegger (1969) calls ‘onto-theo-logy’)—<br />

then the notion <strong>of</strong> event that is attempted to be introduced outside<br />

this history <strong>of</strong> thought has to be thought outside or otherwise than<br />

foundation or ground and co-relatively problematizing the relation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being to ground and to foundation. In other words, and that is<br />

why we shall begin with Schelling and Heidegger, in our attempt to<br />

think <strong>of</strong> the event outside foundation and ground (which should be<br />

our point <strong>of</strong> departure here), we begin with the question <strong>of</strong> event<br />

as (un)ground <strong>of</strong> diff erence (without reducing it to the dialectical<br />

opposition), or rather diff erence <strong>of</strong> unground (which is also question<br />

<strong>of</strong> the limit <strong>of</strong> foundation and ground) that has the character <strong>of</strong><br />

inception always to arrive.<br />

We therefore begin with reading Schelling who already, working<br />

in the tradition <strong>of</strong> German Idealism, and yet unworking at the same<br />

time, points to the simultaneous demand <strong>of</strong> ground and system, and<br />

the impossibility <strong>of</strong> that ground, and thereby hollowing inside out<br />

the immanent logic <strong>of</strong> mere potentiality based on predication, and<br />

opening itself towards the ecstatic logic <strong>of</strong> an event <strong>of</strong> coming whose<br />

pure actuality can only appear at the limit <strong>of</strong> any pheno-ontological<br />

foundation as unapparent apparition which precedes, for that matter,<br />

any predication. Th is unapparent apparition can only occur, not as<br />

mere conceptual, predicative generation as an immanent product <strong>of</strong><br />

the negativity <strong>of</strong> Being, but outside the logic <strong>of</strong> the Being and nothing<br />

as freely coming into existence, prior to Being and its negativity, as decision<br />

out <strong>of</strong> an abyss which can never again be grounded, or totalized in<br />

thinking and its predicates. Th erefore—and this would be our point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure here—we would begin with the notion <strong>of</strong> event in relation<br />

to the problematics <strong>of</strong> (un)ground (Abyss) and decision.


Freedom, <strong>Time</strong> and Existence<br />

(a) Freedom<br />

Of Event • 233<br />

Taking this point <strong>of</strong> departure from Schelling, and then proceeding<br />

to Heidegger and Rosenzweig, I should be able to bring to<br />

articulation—under the rubric <strong>of</strong> three questions: problematics <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom, time and existence—the elaboration <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> event<br />

as a messianic affi rmation <strong>of</strong> coming into presence, the not yet, which<br />

can only be affi rmed at the limit <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical foundation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being as ground or concept. As such, the event <strong>of</strong> thinking, or<br />

rather the thinking <strong>of</strong> the event is essentially a fi nite thinking, by<br />

which we mean an affi rmative thinking out <strong>of</strong> non-ground, which<br />

is the limit <strong>of</strong> thought, which is the vertigo <strong>of</strong> thinking that reveals<br />

thought’s inability to posit itself as identity, ground, being, or<br />

subjectivity. Beginning with Schelling’s great work Inquiries into<br />

the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom, and then proceeding to his later<br />

philosophical works like Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World and his Berlin Lectures<br />

on Positivphilosophie (Philosophie der Off enbarung and Philosophie der<br />

Mythologie), we shall examine Schelling’s deconstruction <strong>of</strong> Hegelian<br />

speculative Idealism, to show how Schelling’s Positivphilosophie seeks<br />

to articulate the notion <strong>of</strong> event as an unconditional affi rmation <strong>of</strong><br />

the outside which exceeds the logic <strong>of</strong> negation and positing; in other<br />

words, an affi rmation outside the logic <strong>of</strong> foundation and the law <strong>of</strong><br />

the ground, identity or subjectivity.<br />

What the three problematics <strong>of</strong> freedom, <strong>of</strong> existence and <strong>of</strong> time,<br />

each in its singular manner, and in its singular affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unground, allow us is to open before us, as the nothingness <strong>of</strong> an<br />

abyss, as the spacing <strong>of</strong> the abyss, to the intensity <strong>of</strong> the event,<br />

which is the intensity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> time, the event <strong>of</strong> freedom and<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> existence. we can say here that the thinking <strong>of</strong> event as<br />

fi nite thinking—which is thinking <strong>of</strong> abyss as spacing, as opening—is<br />

thought here as event as freedom, event as time and event as existence.<br />

Each time the event that is affi rmed precisely at the abyss and the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> foundation is an experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment and releasing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the event from any metaphysical notion <strong>of</strong> ground or Being. Th is<br />

releasement—in its two fold affi rmative (release towards) and negative<br />

(release from) —is thought here as the existence <strong>of</strong> freedom in its


234 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

pure actuality, or facticity whose inscrutable ground—in so far it is<br />

unground (Ungrund)—can neither be apprehended nor be grasped<br />

in concept, but whose experience for the fi nite, mortal being appears<br />

as pure potentiality, a potentiality which is to be distinguished from<br />

the potentiality <strong>of</strong> the concept. Here in this manner the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom is sought to be opened up to the more originary notions<br />

<strong>of</strong> actuality and potentiality outside their predicative, reductive<br />

totalization so that the event <strong>of</strong> freedom releases the mortals from<br />

the closure <strong>of</strong> signifi cation towards the event <strong>of</strong> signifi cation without<br />

result or fi nality, its coming to presence, which for that matter precedes<br />

any signifi cation, or predication about the world.<br />

With this problematic <strong>of</strong> freedom as facticity and releasement<br />

(Gelassenheit) we shall proceed to examine Heidegger’s<br />

problematization <strong>of</strong> freedom in relation to truth, thought in a more<br />

originary manner, so that truth in its apophantic disclosure already<br />

places the mortal, fi nite being to the free ‘play space’ <strong>of</strong> open, outside<br />

the closure <strong>of</strong> the categorical, predicative grasp, where the arrival <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation, on the basis <strong>of</strong> the expropriation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mortal Dasein from all appropriation, takes place. What is thought as<br />

event, its taking place, without reducing it to an accumulative process<br />

that appropriates its expropriation, is nothing other than the logic <strong>of</strong><br />

movement (but not process) and a logic <strong>of</strong> origin (but not generation<br />

or emanation) which traverses through, or better accompanies—<br />

as a necessary condition, as a structural moment <strong>of</strong> opening <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thought—an experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment and dispropriation which<br />

opens itself to the future as an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> coming without it<br />

being exhausted in what has come and pass by.<br />

(b) <strong>Time</strong><br />

Th e event carries, in its diff erential origin, as its arrival the two<br />

fold Grundstimmung—fundamental attunements—<strong>of</strong> joy and<br />

mournfulness. Th e mournfulness <strong>of</strong> this—abandonment or<br />

dispropriation is nothing merely negative about it but carries in it a<br />

certain relation to joy, which is joy in the unconditional welcoming<br />

and affi rmation <strong>of</strong> what is to come that demands a simultaneous<br />

work <strong>of</strong> undoing, unworking, or even destruction <strong>of</strong> the works <strong>of</strong><br />

foundation.


Of Event • 235<br />

Th is demonic, monstrous experience <strong>of</strong> time which itself is the<br />

essence <strong>of</strong> freedom, is truly ecstatic state <strong>of</strong> exception where the event<br />

arrives, where time itself presents itself as pure leaping into coming,<br />

as time-in-itself (therefore can neither be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

generation, or as emanation) that fl ashes before the mortal’s eye<br />

in a fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightning. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this danger—which<br />

the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the fugitive imply—that <strong>of</strong> being exposed to<br />

mortality as this abandoned, bare being in its pure transcendence<br />

(since it does not pre-suppose any transcendent), that the mortal,<br />

fi nite in its essential character, has a glimpse <strong>of</strong> the beatitude <strong>of</strong> the<br />

eternity, which is always to come, where the event reveals itself as<br />

event (and not merely as representation <strong>of</strong> the event)—the event as<br />

pure unapparent apparition—which no phenomenological ontology<br />

can thematize. Reading Schelling, and then going to the works <strong>of</strong><br />

Heidegger and Rosenzweig, the attempt will be made to illuminate<br />

this event <strong>of</strong> time and eternity in relation to mortality that does not<br />

allow itself to be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> generation, or<br />

emanation, but in relation to a new logic <strong>of</strong> origin where the ‘origin’<br />

is neither a logical category, nor a speculative-historical category, but<br />

nevertheless that manifests itself as historical where history does not<br />

allow itself to be totalized in the immanence <strong>of</strong> an accumulative,<br />

continuous universal process. Instead the epochal breaks themselves<br />

reveal to us their abyss which in rare moments, when history itself<br />

poses, we mortals experience as tragic joy. Th is is the moment <strong>of</strong><br />

revolutionary excess whose unapparent apparition does not present<br />

itself in the phenomenological-speculative history. Th is abyss that<br />

voids away the given without conversion (and without Hegelian<br />

speculative logic <strong>of</strong> Aufhebung), does not allow the mortals to master<br />

it as the own subjective property <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’, because he is already<br />

owned by it immemorially.<br />

Th e event is not the property <strong>of</strong> the human, <strong>of</strong> a free subject but<br />

a work (or better, <strong>of</strong>f ering, grant, donation) <strong>of</strong> freedom which gives<br />

itself to us beforehand out <strong>of</strong> our originary dispropriation, because<br />

we are already always belong to freedom. In the same way, the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> time cannot be understood as a continuous, cumulative, additive<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> Being itself as Concept, Subjectivity or Idea, but rather<br />

as concentration, or intensity <strong>of</strong> the absolutely singular moments,<br />

as in a constellation, when the whole <strong>of</strong> time itself as it were pauses,


236 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and which forces us the mortals, in a kind <strong>of</strong> divine violence, from<br />

the prison house <strong>of</strong> the banal, secularized mode <strong>of</strong> Being to the<br />

transcendence <strong>of</strong> the pure arrival, the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming <strong>of</strong> the<br />

divine. But this can be so in so far as these events concern the mortals<br />

in their mortality itself. It concerns the tearing the heart <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

opening to the sudden illumination <strong>of</strong> divine that manifests itself in<br />

the ‘secular’, banal, empty, successive instants as wholly otherwise<br />

illumination.<br />

(c) Existence<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> the mortality and fi nitude demands that the notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence itself to be thought anew, no longer on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

traditional distinction between essentia and existentia, neither on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> (nominalized) Being, nor as consciousness/ego, even<br />

‘the transcendental unity <strong>of</strong> apperception’. Th e event <strong>of</strong> existence—<br />

understood in its ex-sistence character (as Heidegger reminds us) —is<br />

the spacing <strong>of</strong> the open to its own infi nitude <strong>of</strong> its arrival (‘to come)<br />

which therefore cannot be enclosed within the system <strong>of</strong> predicates,<br />

but to be thought in a more originary apophantic manner, that<br />

means as fi nite manifestation out <strong>of</strong> a non-appropriable condition<br />

outside the system <strong>of</strong> visible forms <strong>of</strong> history. Beginning with the<br />

distinction between Being and existence in Schelling, we move to<br />

read Heidegger, Rosenzweig and Kierkegaard, to think with their<br />

help the event <strong>of</strong> existence in its fi nite character, where fi nitude would<br />

mean the exposure to what is to come on the basis <strong>of</strong> an originary<br />

non(ex)-sistence, a no-thing not posited by these being that exist, but<br />

rather that would mean that these beings themselves erupt, leap into<br />

existence from this nothingness, a non-posited grant, as the surprise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin.<br />

Freedom, time, existence: three questions, but in relation to the<br />

same problematic <strong>of</strong> event. In each case it is always the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> our essential fi nitude, which means, our open-ness<br />

to the pure taking place <strong>of</strong> the event to which the fi nite beings are<br />

thrown. To open to the event means to be abandoned, to be released,<br />

and to be thrown unto this nothing, to be abandoned from the given<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> mediation and foundation in Being unto the Not Yet.<br />

Th erefore the thought <strong>of</strong> the event, at fi rst appearing to be nihilist


Of Event • 237<br />

and negative, in so far as it is opened towards to the unground, is<br />

precisely because <strong>of</strong> its condition in a non-condition, is a redemptive<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> a utopia. Th is utopia is not to be thought here as an<br />

actualization <strong>of</strong> an already pre-conceived idea as mere potentiality.<br />

It is not a process which the movement <strong>of</strong> a universal history in each<br />

<strong>of</strong> its moments realizes, and reducing the disruptive breaks <strong>of</strong> history<br />

into the periodic variations <strong>of</strong> the same. Instead the arrival <strong>of</strong> utopian<br />

fulfi llment as a state <strong>of</strong> genuine exception, because it is outside law—<br />

either the physical law <strong>of</strong> motion or the moral law. It has something<br />

incalculable and yet imminence about it, which is the urgency <strong>of</strong><br />

concentrated time which is at once freeing, not just negatively, and<br />

eruption <strong>of</strong> coming into existence that is epochal, which is sudden<br />

dissolution and arrival without conversion <strong>of</strong> the past into future.<br />

To think such an impossible thought <strong>of</strong> event is the highest exertion<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophical thought today where the limit <strong>of</strong> the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy itself is incessantly played out and is touched upon,<br />

where the ‘end’ or ‘accomplishment’ (Vollendung) <strong>of</strong> philosophy calls<br />

itself <strong>of</strong> another inauguration, another beginning <strong>of</strong> thinking, which<br />

is, the ‘sense’ and ‘meaning’ <strong>of</strong> what is ‘to come’.<br />

Origin, Leap, Event<br />

What is to think <strong>of</strong> the event—not this or that event that already<br />

belongs to the speculative memory <strong>of</strong> a historico-dialectical narration<br />

but—the event <strong>of</strong> coming into existence itself?<br />

Th e relation <strong>of</strong> event with fi nitude cannot be understood on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the categories <strong>of</strong> thought but as the originary, pre-predicative<br />

revelation <strong>of</strong> language as lightning fl ash. Th is logic <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong><br />

origin cannot be discovered, or uncovered merely through regression<br />

into the originary past <strong>of</strong> the event in a kind <strong>of</strong> apophantic dialecticalhistorical<br />

memory, but through anticipation towards the coming<br />

Dawn in the Open, or through repetition <strong>of</strong> the origin, which is<br />

not the repetition <strong>of</strong> what has become but what has never ‘been’,<br />

what has never assumed any ontological status implied by ‘be’. Th is<br />

origin is to be distinguished from the empty logic <strong>of</strong> generation,<br />

from the dialectical-historical logic <strong>of</strong> ‘homogenous empty time’ that<br />

Benjamin (1977, pp. 251-261) speaks <strong>of</strong>. It is here only, for the fi rst<br />

time, the question <strong>of</strong> beginning is grasped in clearer light: the event


238 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

as beginning—or beginning itself as event—which is to come, in<br />

future and in a time that will remain.<br />

In the beginning <strong>of</strong> his Th e Origin <strong>of</strong> German Tragic Drama,<br />

distinguishing the event character <strong>of</strong> his notion <strong>of</strong> ‘origin’ as leap<br />

from the cognitive, categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> coming on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

the temporal modality as generative transition (which elsewhere, as<br />

mentioned above, Benjamin calls ‘homogenous empty time’), Walter<br />

Benjamin attempts to think with the notion <strong>of</strong> ‘origin’ neither a<br />

logical category, nor a speculative- historical category <strong>of</strong> coming as<br />

a homogenous process <strong>of</strong> successive, accumulative instants, but the<br />

diff erential, disclosive leap into presence, which is more originary than<br />

the violence impaired by cognitive grasp <strong>of</strong> entities through logicalhistorical<br />

categories. Th erefore for Walter Benjamin, the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

‘origin’ is not just a methodological gesture belonging to a well thought<br />

out epistemology, but a gesture that has a redemptive possibility,<br />

which is the messianic fulfi llment <strong>of</strong> mankind that redeems what<br />

has never been, what has been excluded by the violence <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

consciousness. Only in philosophical contemplation, which is always<br />

the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the origin as ideas rather than cognitive grasp<br />

<strong>of</strong> the generative process (which is the process <strong>of</strong> the ‘homogenous<br />

empty time’), that has an intimation, or rather attunement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

messianic fulfi llment, because it is not yet being impaired by the<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> cognition. Here is, then, thinking <strong>of</strong> event, on the other<br />

hand, that is leap or spring into the coming that is not mere transition<br />

and therefore does not belong to the temporal modality <strong>of</strong> time that<br />

has come down from Aristotle’s Physics onwards to Hegel’s Logic.<br />

Th e event is not a generative transition. Th erefore Walter Benjamin<br />

in his Th e Origin <strong>of</strong> German Tragic Drama distinguishes the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin (Ürsprung) —which is the leap into presence, <strong>of</strong> what<br />

be-comes and disappears—from the question <strong>of</strong> genesis thought on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> generation:<br />

Origin, although an entirely historical category, has nevertheless,<br />

nothing to do with genesis. Th e term origin is not intended to<br />

describe the process by which the existent came into being, but rather<br />

to describe that which emerges from the process <strong>of</strong> becoming and<br />

disappearance. Origin is an eddy in the stream <strong>of</strong> becoming, and in<br />

its current it swallows the materials involved in the process <strong>of</strong> genesis.<br />

(Benjamin 1998, p.45)


Of Event • 239<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> the origin and the event <strong>of</strong> coming therefore do<br />

not become categories serving the system <strong>of</strong> conceptual knowledge,<br />

or predication for logical proposition. Even for Speculative logic <strong>of</strong><br />

Hegel which is not satisfi ed with the immobility <strong>of</strong> the things present,<br />

but seeks to present the restless generation <strong>of</strong> coming to presence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the concept itself to itself, categories are determined as mobile<br />

that auto-generate themselves. If that is so, the question can come<br />

about as to how the categories themselves generate themselves on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> their own ground? Th e event is not, therefore, made into<br />

predication for the speculative proposition, but what the proposition<br />

in order to be able to predicate, must be opened towards, is to be<br />

exposed towards—in the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> language—that reveals to<br />

mortals, in astonishment at the origin, in wonder at the revelation, at<br />

the event leaping forth in joy.<br />

It is therefore Kant thought existence as irreducible to predication.<br />

In the lightning fl ash <strong>of</strong> language, man is himself torn open—in<br />

an originary manner—to his origin, to his beginning, to the event<br />

that lies in the eternity <strong>of</strong> future without result, without fi nality.<br />

It is therefore Benjamin rigorously distinguishes language as pure<br />

naming from the categorical, predicative, cognitive grasp <strong>of</strong> entities<br />

where language becomes mere medium <strong>of</strong> communication. Th e<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> philosophically contemplating, in remembrance, the<br />

origin is, therefore, for Benjamin, inseparable from the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

pure, paradisiacal language before language is submitted at cognitive<br />

disposal.<br />

Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> beginning anew and anew and so eternally, the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> giving birth to himself in an always coming time<br />

and being able to be present to himself by the event <strong>of</strong> future: if<br />

this alone redeems the fi nite being opened to the opening, exposed<br />

to the coming, then this event <strong>of</strong> coming demands remembrance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin outside empty generation and empty transition. If<br />

philosophical contemplation alone gives us the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

remembrance <strong>of</strong> the origin, not yet impaired by the violence <strong>of</strong><br />

cognition, then its truth is not so much the categorical, predicative,<br />

cognitive truth, but truth that is the truth <strong>of</strong> revelation itself, which<br />

is mortal’s originary opening to the promise <strong>of</strong> pure, paradisiacal<br />

language and its redemptive, messianic fulfi llment.


240 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Similarly, Heidegger, but in a diff erent registrar, thinks this advent <strong>of</strong><br />

the arrival as two fold leap and step back from the ‘onto-theological<br />

constitution <strong>of</strong> metaphysics’. Th is onto-theological constitution <strong>of</strong><br />

metaphysics is none other than the dialectical-historical metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘homogenous empty time’, <strong>of</strong> what in Being and <strong>Time</strong> the young<br />

Heidegger calls ‘vulgar time’. Th e leap <strong>of</strong> the event, which Heidegger<br />

calls ‘spring’ is the ‘event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’, which springs from Being<br />

as ground <strong>of</strong> beings into the abyss, event that appropriates man and<br />

Being in holding-together, or belonging-together. In his Identity and<br />

Diff erence, Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> the event as a relation to the arriving:<br />

Th is principle in the sense <strong>of</strong> a statement has in the meantime become<br />

a principle bearing the characteristics <strong>of</strong> a spring that departs from<br />

Being as the ground <strong>of</strong> beings, and springs into the abyss. But this<br />

abyss is neither empty nothingness nor murky confusion, but rather<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation... a spring demanded by the essence <strong>of</strong><br />

identity because it needs that spring if the belonging together <strong>of</strong><br />

man and Being is to attain the essential light <strong>of</strong> the appropriation.<br />

(Heidegger 1969, p.39)<br />

Th is holding or belonging together (but not: belonging together) in<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation as spring is a constellation, a diff erentiating<br />

perdurance between overwhelming and arrival. Heidegger writes,<br />

Th e diff erence <strong>of</strong> Being and beings, as the diff erentiation <strong>of</strong><br />

overwhelming and arrival, is the perdurance <strong>of</strong> the two in unconcealing<br />

keeping in concealment. Within this perdurance there prevails a clearing<br />

<strong>of</strong> what veils and closes itself <strong>of</strong>f —and this its prevalence bestows the<br />

being part, and the being towards each other, <strong>of</strong> overwhelming and<br />

arrival (Ibid., p.65).<br />

Th is event is outside metaphysics, because it is thinking <strong>of</strong> event<br />

as diff erence, which means, event that cannot be thought as ‘given<br />

presence’, in so far as the dominant metaphysics thinks phenomenon<br />

as ‘given presence’, and therefore cannot think diff erence as diff erence,<br />

event as arriving and coming to presence. Th e event is none but<br />

perdurance as opening—the in-between spacing (the Abgrund)—<br />

in relation to the arrival, to the coming to presence wherein there<br />

happens, occurs, takes place a spring, a leap into what comes in the<br />

coming, which occurs only so far as overwhelming <strong>of</strong> thinking is


Of Event • 241<br />

radically given over, is delivered towards the presencing <strong>of</strong> presence.<br />

But that happens only when there occurs, at the same time, a retreat<br />

from, i.e., a step back from the totality <strong>of</strong> the given history <strong>of</strong> beings.<br />

Th is means that event is the leap <strong>of</strong> Being as already given presence<br />

towards the arrival, or the coming which is not yet given—in the<br />

opening as diff erentiation <strong>of</strong> Being and beings, as perdurance between<br />

overwhelming and arrival. Th is happens when the fi nitude, and<br />

temporality <strong>of</strong> the coming is opened at the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> metaphysics<br />

to think the originary beginning, or inception <strong>of</strong> it as an inception<br />

to come, to arrive so that Being is no longer thought as ground <strong>of</strong><br />

beings, nor beings thought as ‘presently given beings’, but rather<br />

presence itself as ground <strong>of</strong> presents is now opened to the coming<br />

and arriving to presence. Th is is how the question <strong>of</strong> temporality<br />

and fi nitude as coming time or arriving constitutes the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation and the question <strong>of</strong> Being, in which case<br />

it is always the question <strong>of</strong> a remembrance, far more originary than<br />

dialectical-speculative memory, <strong>of</strong> the origin that discloses itself to us<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> an originary expropriation.<br />

In one <strong>of</strong> his most important series <strong>of</strong> lectures, published as Th e<br />

Principle <strong>of</strong> Reason, Heidegger thinks <strong>of</strong> leap as that which, at the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the thought <strong>of</strong> Being as ground or reason, inaugurates another—<br />

that <strong>of</strong> thinking being as Abgrund, as abyss:<br />

Th e leap remains a free and open possibility <strong>of</strong> thinking: this so<br />

decisively so that in fact the essential province <strong>of</strong> freedom and<br />

openness fi rst opens up with the realm <strong>of</strong> the leap (Heidegger 1991,<br />

p.).<br />

Th e leap <strong>of</strong> the event cannot be thought within metaphysics, or<br />

within the classical ontological determination <strong>of</strong> time and Being as<br />

given presence. Event is the leap from the overwhelming <strong>of</strong> the given<br />

presence to the arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise that can neither be<br />

thought as being, nor as negativity. Th e event leaps forth, or leaps<br />

into, not through the empty generation <strong>of</strong> Being pure and simple<br />

(with which Hegel’s logical movement begins), but through cision,<br />

through (in Heidegger’s words) ‘perdurance’ as opening—making<br />

something <strong>of</strong> ‘that has been’ into ‘that is to come’. Th is perdurance is<br />

a cision, a time <strong>of</strong> distress which the mortal being must undergo, and on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> which transformation occurs in the history <strong>of</strong> this existence.


242 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th is almost nothing (how to think this?) is not negative which Hegel<br />

talks <strong>of</strong>, for it is not the power that converts nothing into being.<br />

Th erefore this perdurance is not a continuous transition into being<br />

that negativity immediately passes into without leap, as smoothly<br />

with which all Hegelian categories mobilize themselves, nor is it<br />

generative nothing equal to Being, with which Hegelian logic begins.<br />

What is attempted both by Benjamin and Heidegger in their<br />

diff erent gestures, is nothing other than the question <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong><br />

coming into presence in relation to an originary truth (more primordial<br />

than predicative, cognitive truth <strong>of</strong> entities that has happened as the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> a process), to a logic <strong>of</strong> origin which is revealed to us on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> an expropriation, that is, on the basis <strong>of</strong> an originary fi nitude,<br />

yet which carries its promise towards its redemptive fulfi llment in a<br />

time yet to come.


§ Love and Death<br />

When Walter Benjamin, evoking Plato, conceives <strong>of</strong> philosophical<br />

contemplation as redemption <strong>of</strong> phenomena not yet impaired by<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition, he is not much distant from the Platonic<br />

discourse on love. In his Symposium, Plato at the beginning <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy speaks <strong>of</strong> loving and desiring as the movement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

origin <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, as the movement <strong>of</strong> philosophy’s coming<br />

into itself, which is the movement <strong>of</strong> procreation or begetting.<br />

Philosophy comes into existence—for philosophy is nothing but this<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> coming (the verbal resonance here is unmistakable)—in<br />

loving and desiring. In other words, in loving and desiring—which<br />

is not the act <strong>of</strong> an already fully formed Subject on the dialectically<br />

negative Object (hence a speculative dialectics <strong>of</strong> negativity that<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> desire that initiates action, as in Hegel for example, in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> subject and object, does not do justice to this movement)—there<br />

occurs something like ‘coming into existence’, which Plato repeatedly<br />

makes analogy with procreation.<br />

Here at the beginning <strong>of</strong> philosophy there occurs a moment in a<br />

lightning fl ash, in a blinding lucidity, in the darkness <strong>of</strong> a light that<br />

is subsequently forgotten, not the statement itself—for this saying<br />

has become one <strong>of</strong> the most quoted, discussed, analyzed saying in<br />

the whole subsequent history <strong>of</strong> philosophy—but something else<br />

that was at stake in this saying, that is not so much the relation<br />

between love and philosophy but the relation between the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> loving-desiring with the coming into itself, with the structural<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> the world, which is each time fi nite and mortal. What<br />

has remained unthought is the event <strong>of</strong> ‘facticity’, which is not ‘fact’


244 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘factuality’ (we have learnt from Heidegger to distinguish between<br />

the two), but the event <strong>of</strong> ‘actuality’ outside mere potentiality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept, this event <strong>of</strong> facticity and actuality <strong>of</strong> loving that each time<br />

opens the world—existential world—and welcomes the coming into<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> this world. ‘Marvelous’: such is the opening <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> infi nity within the heart <strong>of</strong> fi nitude and yet that does<br />

not belong to the fi nitude, an excess that in its eventive presencing is<br />

irreducible to statement or explanation, as if an eternity has inscribed<br />

itself at this movement <strong>of</strong> presentation—<strong>of</strong> philosophy’s emergence<br />

to itself. What has remained unthought is that <strong>of</strong> this event <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

that bears in itself the dark fate <strong>of</strong> mortality, that <strong>of</strong> its own erasure<br />

and oblivion. It is this con-juncture, jointure, co-fi guring <strong>of</strong> loving<br />

and dying, the monstrous coupling <strong>of</strong> lightning and darkening: this<br />

constitutes the event <strong>of</strong> coming into existence in its essential relation<br />

to fi nitude, that <strong>of</strong> its inapparition in the predicates <strong>of</strong> the world. It<br />

thereby essentially conceals itself, not behind the veil <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

or behind the visible entities that constitute the world as world. It<br />

conceals itself in its presentation from the eyes <strong>of</strong> the mortals who<br />

are always belated in relation to the emergence <strong>of</strong> the thought to<br />

itself. What thought cannot present to itself cannot be this or that<br />

attribute <strong>of</strong> the world or forms <strong>of</strong> thought that can acquire visibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> categories or predicates. It is the presentation <strong>of</strong> this presencing<br />

itself that thought cannot present itself to itself: it shies away from the<br />

sacredness <strong>of</strong> this fi re whose violence is not equivalent to the violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortals that mortals posit as law. It rather belongs to justice<br />

which erupts in the spacing between eternity and time, or rather, that<br />

which erupts as eternity in time, not as a dialectical synthesis between<br />

eternity and time, but as incommensurable inscription <strong>of</strong> eternity in<br />

time that at the same time annuls itself, for it has already opened all<br />

spaces, and it has opened its spacing itself. Justice is this pure spacing<br />

that summons, or conjures up the mortal to respond to the divine<br />

address, and he responds: ‘here I am’.<br />

What is the question raised by Plato in his Symposium? It is<br />

simply this: why loving and desiring?, or, closer to Plato’ words,<br />

‘what is this loving and desiring’? After various other interlocutors,<br />

including Aristophanes, having <strong>of</strong>f ered their interpretations and<br />

stories, sometimes praising the God <strong>of</strong> Love, Socrates tells the story<br />

<strong>of</strong> having met Diotima from whom he has derived insights into the


Love and Death • 245<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> love. Th ese insights can only be told, again, only in a story<br />

or narrative manner: Diotima’s story this time (for, how else to speak<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ‘nature’ <strong>of</strong> love, whose ‘nature’ consists in the non-form <strong>of</strong><br />

a ‘form’, a non-natured nature, as if, as it were, there is something<br />

‘monstrosity’ about love and loving). Love is neither ‘human’ nor<br />

‘divine’ but something ‘monstrous’, demonic: for while loving co-joins<br />

both fi nitude and infi nite, time and eternity, poverty and plenitude,<br />

giving and <strong>of</strong>f ering, mourning and joy, it in itself is none <strong>of</strong> these<br />

but an eternal spacing opening between the two, so that, as if, an<br />

irreducible void—in the heart <strong>of</strong> loving—opens the world. Th is void<br />

is not empty, pure nothing but the trace <strong>of</strong> the abandonment <strong>of</strong> time<br />

where eternity inscribes itself, where eternity <strong>of</strong> ‘tomorrow’ arrives<br />

‘today’.<br />

Love is, monstrous, daimonic because in its opening and manifesting<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world, it is without the world <strong>of</strong> its own. Th erefore love, so<br />

Diotima narrates, is immeasurably enriched and yet irreducibly<br />

impoverished at the same time. While it is an interminable subtraction<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself, love adds itself to itself in this movement <strong>of</strong> subtraction and<br />

becomes more and more overfl owing <strong>of</strong> itself in its impoverishment.<br />

Love is this eternal giving that receives itself by the cunning <strong>of</strong> this<br />

giving; an eternal impoverishment <strong>of</strong> itself that enriches itself by this<br />

cunning <strong>of</strong> impoverishment. Love is at once giving and receiving,<br />

plenitude and impoverishment, mourning and joy, subtraction and<br />

adding, yet none <strong>of</strong> these in itself. By being none <strong>of</strong> those what it<br />

unites and those whose natures therefore do not explain the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> this loving, loving is inexplicable in terms <strong>of</strong> those that it unites.<br />

It excludes itself because it makes any inclusion possible; it does<br />

not itself enter into the relation and yet permeates in the related<br />

elements as a whole while making possible this relation between<br />

impoverishment and plenitude, <strong>of</strong>f ering and giving, mourning and<br />

joy, subtraction and adding, fi nitude and eternity, transcendence and<br />

immanence. Love is, for Socrates, the highest thought <strong>of</strong> philosophy.<br />

It is the gesture that moves philosophy itself, which is to think not<br />

merely immanence but also transcendence, not merely fi nitude<br />

but also infi nitude, not merely excess but its impoverishment.<br />

In love, the gravity <strong>of</strong> thought acquires immeasurable grace. Love<br />

communicates itself neither in those communicated terms, because<br />

it itself is pure communication, pure language that refuses itself to


246 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

be inscribed in any totality or system <strong>of</strong> predicates. While the pure<br />

language is the condition <strong>of</strong> the predicative possibilities <strong>of</strong> cognitive,<br />

conceptual categories, love itself is without predicates <strong>of</strong> its own. Th is<br />

pure language <strong>of</strong> love that acquires the gesture <strong>of</strong> grace, for in this<br />

gesture it frees open to the timing <strong>of</strong> time and spacing <strong>of</strong> space, this<br />

pure language is the messianic language <strong>of</strong> fulfi llment where silence<br />

completes speech, and time comes to a halt.<br />

It is in this sense love is event, in the sense that Benjamin speaks <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> language which is the none but the language <strong>of</strong> naming,<br />

which is the language as pure communication. Th e pure communication<br />

is that, in so far nothing communicates in it, communicates the event <strong>of</strong><br />

its taking place. Love is this spacing, or unconditional predication.<br />

Irreducible to any signifi cation, love relates neither in those related<br />

terms because it itself is pure relation. Love does not itself come to<br />

pass into and pass away in those related fi gures because it is itself<br />

what is pure coming into existence, understood in the infi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

its verbal resonance ‘to come’, which is, the coming into existence<br />

as eternal remnant as this coming. Love closes itself and conceals<br />

itself in the light <strong>of</strong> the world because it is the opening <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

Th erefore the God Eros, according to Socrates, is at once the most<br />

ancient god and at the same time the youngest <strong>of</strong> all. As such loving<br />

is the event <strong>of</strong> the world. Because love is not what arises on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the result or fi nality <strong>of</strong> the world, it is pure striving, pure<br />

wanting, and pure movement <strong>of</strong> becoming; as pure becoming it is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> the coming into existence itself, not this or that coming<br />

but ‘to come’, always to come, a promise whose messianic intensity is<br />

experienced each time there takes place loving, not between subject<br />

and object, but in a confrontation with the wholly otherwise. Th e<br />

site <strong>of</strong> this confrontation, <strong>of</strong> this encounter is the demonic site—<br />

for love himself is this daimon, the spirit which is neither human<br />

nor divine but a monstrous synthesis or coupling <strong>of</strong> becoming and<br />

perishing, mourning and joy, fi nitude and eternity.<br />

What is then philosophizing? To philosophize is to be placed at<br />

this monstrous site <strong>of</strong> exposure (it is in this sense philosophy is this<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> loving-desiring) that opens the world in thought. Th e<br />

double movement <strong>of</strong> concealment and unconcealment, inclusion and<br />

exclusion, subtraction and addition at the heart <strong>of</strong> loving attunes the<br />

lover at once with melancholy and joy. Freud knew something about


Love and Death • 247<br />

this when he locates mournfulness at the movement <strong>of</strong> loving, as if,<br />

as it were there is a loss, a subtraction <strong>of</strong> the heart that overfl ows itself<br />

with love, and in loving this way ecstatically exceeds itself. Th erefore<br />

both the fi gures <strong>of</strong> the philosopher and the lover—in so far as they<br />

are the fi gures <strong>of</strong> the dis-fi gured—are monstrous, ‘daimonic’, neither<br />

in itself human nor divine, neither in itself temporal nor eternal.<br />

He is a non-place that inscribes itself as placing, a dis-fi guring that<br />

inscribes itself a fi guring <strong>of</strong> truth, and thereby conceals its truth.<br />

As such love which is pure communication or pure language that<br />

communicates itself, in its taking place keeps itself secret. It keeps to<br />

itself inexhaustible possibilities while it is itself pure giving. It keeps<br />

to itself ingenuous inventions that weave in the thread <strong>of</strong> history its<br />

own eternal future. Th is is the cunning <strong>of</strong> the event, the cunning <strong>of</strong><br />

loving, the secret <strong>of</strong> its promise that keeps to itself while abandoning<br />

itself to actualization in words <strong>of</strong> love, in the communication <strong>of</strong> a<br />

caress, in the work <strong>of</strong> the world, in the labour <strong>of</strong> a history.<br />

What is then the loving? To love is to be placed at the structural<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> communication. It means to be placed outside <strong>of</strong> the<br />

communicated, to suff er distress and eternal despair <strong>of</strong> being placed<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> communicable, and to have to carry the eternal remnant<br />

<strong>of</strong> the non-communicable, precisely because it is communication<br />

pure and simple. Philosophical contemplation, as Benjamin reminds<br />

us, takes its origin in this pure communication <strong>of</strong> love, to be<br />

ecstatically placed outside <strong>of</strong> oneself at the heart <strong>of</strong> oneself. Th e transimmanence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the movement <strong>of</strong> love unites within itself plenitude<br />

and impoverishment, procreation and death. Love and death are not<br />

opposites: loving carries within itself the darkness <strong>of</strong> mortality.<br />

Here Plato’s thought touches a point <strong>of</strong> limit, a moment <strong>of</strong><br />

dizzying abyss: love is only demanded <strong>of</strong> those who essentially are<br />

fi nite and mortal, for they alone feel the need <strong>of</strong> procreation, in the<br />

face <strong>of</strong> the undeniable ‘facticity’ <strong>of</strong> death. Love and death, which are<br />

the eternal agonistic elements, one that affi rms becoming and other<br />

perishing, one ecstasy and other melancholy, one affi rms eternity and<br />

the other insists on fi nitude and temporality, both are actually united<br />

in a monstrous coupling, which is at once structural opening (and<br />

closing), revelation (and concealment) <strong>of</strong> the world. Th e highest task<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy is to think the closure that opens the world, and which,<br />

for that matter is itself without world. As such loving is the event <strong>of</strong>


248 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

existence, for love is opening <strong>of</strong> our world, the opening <strong>of</strong> a heart, a<br />

strange place which beats for the other, palpitates and suff ers for the<br />

other, welcomes and smiles at the other who is coming towards it.<br />

As such love is the possibility <strong>of</strong> a pure community without fusion, a<br />

community whose coupling is forged with a demonic hiatus that lies<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> Eros.<br />

Th is event is the more originary facticity <strong>of</strong> existence whose facticity<br />

cannot be proved by any facts <strong>of</strong> the world. It is the more originary<br />

relation to the other, for other here is mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> the given<br />

genus, or an instantiation <strong>of</strong> the universal essence <strong>of</strong> ‘humanity’.<br />

Th e other who is approached in loving is without attributes. It is the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> revelation which is presupposed in the relation <strong>of</strong> dialectical<br />

negativity between man and man, because it promises fulfi llment<br />

outside the relation <strong>of</strong> labour and outside the logic <strong>of</strong> consumption.<br />

Not belonging to the totality <strong>of</strong> universal history, it is more originary<br />

political before any politics: it is a-polis is the originary polis, which is<br />

not signifi cation on the basis <strong>of</strong> the juridico-political determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> an already achieved co-existence <strong>of</strong> beings, but rather a more<br />

originary opening <strong>of</strong> being-towards-other. As such it bears witness,<br />

in each instance <strong>of</strong> juridico-legal execution <strong>of</strong> rights, the possibility<br />

or impossibility <strong>of</strong> justice, which for that matter precedes the realm<br />

<strong>of</strong> the juridico-political. As such this justice is messianic.<br />

Loving-desiring is the event <strong>of</strong> existence ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> procreation. Th rough its creative acts it welcomes the other in<br />

unconditional hospitality, the other who is to come, the singular other<br />

whose mode <strong>of</strong> being is not exhausted by the attributes <strong>of</strong> being. Th e<br />

facticity <strong>of</strong> loving cannot be proved in terms <strong>of</strong> itself but in terms <strong>of</strong>—<br />

and this is the paradox <strong>of</strong> loving—death. Loving therefore does not<br />

shrink from death, but looks death in its eyes. Th erefore is this saying<br />

that Rosenzweig loves to quote: ‘love is strong as death’. Th at love<br />

looks death in its eyes and does not shrink from death, is also to say<br />

that love is, if not superior, then equal to death. In the face <strong>of</strong> death<br />

love seeks eternal renewal <strong>of</strong> that structural opening, that naming<br />

language, that idea <strong>of</strong> justice at each hic et nunc. Th is renewal is what<br />

Plato calls ‘procreation’ that is granted to mortals, which is a fi nite-<br />

infi nity, a temporal- eternity, which is not achieved by the dialectical<br />

acts <strong>of</strong> reconciliation and synthesis. As against the pure eternity which<br />

Gods enjoy—because, as Schelling says, Gods have their condition


Love and Death • 249<br />

within themselves—mortals are those who must renew their eternity<br />

in presence, their infi nitude in fi nite time, the promise <strong>of</strong> redemption<br />

at each hic et nunc. Th erefore, loving demands that loving itself has<br />

to be renewed in each presentation <strong>of</strong> presencing, at each hic et nunc,<br />

without which love dies away, or withers away. It then forgets the<br />

originary event <strong>of</strong> existence and its immemorial promise given in<br />

the immemorial past. It forgets its character as messianic justice for<br />

unredeemed humanity and unfi nished world which is always to<br />

come, always coming.<br />

Th erefore loving, though it is the originary opening <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

though it is the immemorial past event <strong>of</strong> existence, this immemorial<br />

event can only appear to be anachronistic to the mortals. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as<br />

love appears as pure presencing <strong>of</strong> presence, pure renewing <strong>of</strong> the new,<br />

it appears to the fi nite being as if loving is without past and without<br />

future. Th erefore lovers exist immersed in this pure presencing <strong>of</strong><br />

presence, in this pure renewal <strong>of</strong> the ever new, as if neither past, nor<br />

future exists outside this pure presentation <strong>of</strong> presence, outside the<br />

caress <strong>of</strong> the ever new ‘this’ and ‘now’. In this renewal <strong>of</strong> the ever new,<br />

in this presentation <strong>of</strong> pure presencing, there occurs the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

renewal <strong>of</strong> the structural opening at the immemorial past in presence:<br />

the past renews itself in this ever new presentation <strong>of</strong> presence, and<br />

appears as ever new.<br />

To love means to renew the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> the past in<br />

presence, that means, to universalize the singularity <strong>of</strong> the event.<br />

Love co-joins, brings together, in the act <strong>of</strong> renewing the past<br />

promise, the singularity and universality: love singularizes the<br />

universal, and universalizes the singular, as it temporalizes the<br />

eternal and eternalizes the temporal, or, it makes infi nite into<br />

fi nite and fi nite into infi nite, both at once, and yet in none <strong>of</strong> them<br />

in themselves.<br />

Th erefore love does not subsist in itself. At each moment love extatically<br />

ex-sists <strong>of</strong> any stasis ; it transcends itself in the insistence<br />

and despite <strong>of</strong> its insistence in the presentation <strong>of</strong> itself. In the every<br />

immersion in this pure presentation <strong>of</strong> hic et nunc, it dis-invests<br />

itself, and thereby eternalizing each hic et nunc, universalizing the<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> the event, presenting the immemorial structural<br />

opening here and now. Loving then is the conjunction <strong>of</strong> the


250 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

disjunction, a kind <strong>of</strong> assemblage <strong>of</strong> temporality and eternity, fi nitude<br />

and infi nite, transcendence and immanence, and yet, as conjunction<br />

<strong>of</strong> disjunction it is anachronistic in relation to itself, disjoined from<br />

itself, non-contemporaneous with itself, without any subsistence <strong>of</strong><br />

its own, without a name because it must fi rst <strong>of</strong> all bestow all names,<br />

without language because it is itself pure language. Th is disjunction at<br />

the heart <strong>of</strong> loving, which is love’s ecstasy and its madness, constitutes<br />

love’s blissful, almost paradisiacal melancholy. But there is another<br />

melancholy, not this paradisiacal, blissful melancholy <strong>of</strong> lover’s<br />

beatifi c, completed communication in silence, but a melancholy in<br />

evil, when language forgets, or seeks to subjugate love’s completed<br />

understanding, when the event gets arrested, hypostatized, and then<br />

sought to be erased from language, and then an abyss opens up,<br />

swallowing love in loveless overnaming, which is called ‘evil’.<br />

Love is then the originary event <strong>of</strong> the world, the originary promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence, which is the promise <strong>of</strong> a redemptive fulfi llment, the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the messianic coming. Th is originary promise, this event<br />

<strong>of</strong> the immemorial demands, because <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the fi nite<br />

condition, an act <strong>of</strong> renewal or procreation in ever new presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence, since mortals are granted only this form <strong>of</strong> eternity<br />

and infi nitude, that is, in the form <strong>of</strong> a renewed eternity, which<br />

welcomes at each hic et nunc the coming into existence itself. But<br />

there arises, out <strong>of</strong> this fi nitude itself, not so much a counterforce<br />

with so much being, but a simulacrum <strong>of</strong> the event, a distortion,<br />

a disease, a fetish <strong>of</strong> the particular that in its over consuming lust<br />

for power and force abandons love, and seeks to subjugate it to its<br />

reductive totalization. Th en our politics and our history forget love,<br />

that originary structural opening in communication, that originary<br />

promise that bears a redemptive fulfi llment. Love suff ers, then, from<br />

melancholy, lamenting its un-fulfi llment and its dying, which is not<br />

the paradisiacal, blissful, ecstatic melancholy that has fi rst opened the<br />

heart for the other, at the beginning <strong>of</strong> history and politics, that has<br />

fi rst beaten for the other who is irreducible to any totality <strong>of</strong> visible<br />

attributes that are applied to him, but a melancholy that arises out <strong>of</strong><br />

malign disease where radical evil manifests its repulsive force.


§ Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom<br />

In this essay we will attempt to think freedom, not as that which is<br />

merely the conditioned realization, in the name <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual or State, or even ‘human’ right (‘natural’ or ‘historical’)<br />

<strong>of</strong> a necessary presentation <strong>of</strong> an Idea (regulative or constitutive)<br />

given beforehand as pure Universal, as an a priori principle, nor<br />

will we think freedom as that accomplishment <strong>of</strong> a reconciliation<br />

undertaken by man’s dialectical power <strong>of</strong> the negativity where this<br />

negativity appears as law, force, gaze <strong>of</strong> power. Th ese are, as we shall<br />

see, various forms <strong>of</strong> necessity, even when they attempt to open<br />

to, in the name <strong>of</strong> ‘freedom’, something heterogeneous, something<br />

(which is no ‘thing’, Unbedingt, nothing, and also un-conditional)<br />

entirely otherwise which philosophy cannot name. We shall see that<br />

this Unbedingt, this non-thing (or nothing), this un-condition, this<br />

Absolute <strong>of</strong> freedom is not an attribute <strong>of</strong> freedom but the occurring,<br />

erupting, arriving, and coming to presence <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. It is as<br />

Unbedingt, the nothing character <strong>of</strong> freedom erupts, occurs, arrives<br />

and comes to presence. In other words, as erupting, occurring,<br />

arriving, freedom is Unbedingt—a non-thing, a non-condition, an<br />

‘un-pre-thinkable’ (as Schelling says) on the basis <strong>of</strong> which there<br />

can be thoughts, philosophy itself—thoughts and works <strong>of</strong> right<br />

and Idea, law and force, power and gaze. And we shall see that as<br />

Unbedingt the freedom <strong>of</strong> event, or the event <strong>of</strong> freedom, is love.<br />

*<br />

We shall begin with love, freedom as love’s coming to presence as free<br />

coming, unconditionally, in a manner <strong>of</strong> no-thing that arrives and


252 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

passes away. We shall begin with love’s joyous, ecstatic (ex-tatic,<br />

love that exceeds any stasis, or installation, or En-Framing) coming<br />

to itself, not in the manner <strong>of</strong> a self-presence <strong>of</strong> a given thing, or<br />

available being’s parousia, but coming itself, in its verbal infi nitude<br />

‘to come’, in its unenclosed futurity <strong>of</strong> an interminable ecstasy—<strong>of</strong><br />

an always coming itself. Th erefore love appears to be so ungraspable<br />

a thing, whether in a concept (which is synthesis <strong>of</strong> sensibility and<br />

understanding) or in a name, for love never appears as a thing, an<br />

available entity, an already given present, or a sensible-phenomenal<br />

cognitive object to which there can be applied a logical predicate.<br />

Th erefore love never appears as a phenomenological entity or thing<br />

in any light <strong>of</strong> the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> Subject, because the apparition <strong>of</strong><br />

love is that <strong>of</strong> an apparition <strong>of</strong> a no-thing, an unapparent apparition,<br />

an unapparent coming that in a manner precedes, not logically<br />

like subject precedes predicate, but the manner that an apparition,<br />

understood in its no-thing character, precedes any available, given<br />

thing. Th at there is love is a facticity not <strong>of</strong> the manner <strong>of</strong> a factuality<br />

(that can be ideal or empirical fact—<strong>of</strong> a concept or <strong>of</strong> a thing);<br />

neither concept nor a thing, love is this apparition <strong>of</strong> a pure coming<br />

to presence, pure event, pure taking place.<br />

Th ere is love. Th e primordiality <strong>of</strong> love’s facticity precedes the order<br />

<strong>of</strong> law’s validity and its suspension. In that sense the primordiality<br />

<strong>of</strong> love lies in its immemoriality: it is the originary groundless that<br />

precedes the distinction between good and evil, and as such, bears the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> redemption <strong>of</strong> the radical evil that sway over the destiny <strong>of</strong><br />

man’s history, when man, forgetting his fi nitude, seeks to appropriate<br />

the whole <strong>of</strong> being, and in fact, Being itself. Th e primordial facticity<br />

<strong>of</strong> love’s groundless cannot be traced back in the manner <strong>of</strong> apophansis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the predicative proposition. Th erefore Schelling (1936) calls the<br />

originary groundlessness <strong>of</strong> love indiff erence that precedes all predicates<br />

<strong>of</strong> diff erence and identity, to which no predicates apply except the<br />

lack <strong>of</strong> predicates, the exuberant ‘un-pre-thinkable’ (Unvordenkliche)<br />

that elicits from us awe, in relation to which all mortal language<br />

and vanity falls silent, and all egotism is consumed in the fi re <strong>of</strong><br />

the centre. Yet this fi re at once, when the mortals do not seek to<br />

appropriate it within immanence <strong>of</strong> his ground, is pure donation,<br />

which is the gift <strong>of</strong> life, arising as free donation, the freedom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

gift. In this way the mortals can partake, share this eternity <strong>of</strong> love as


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 253<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> his life, as this creaturely, fi nite, mortal life. Th e mortal being,<br />

therefore, precisely due to his inextricable fi nitude and mortality, due<br />

to his conditioned existence, shares and partakes something <strong>of</strong> the<br />

no-thing, the no-condition, the ‘un-pre-thinkable’, the eternity <strong>of</strong><br />

love. Th is sharing and partaking <strong>of</strong> love, <strong>of</strong> love’s free <strong>of</strong>f ering and<br />

overfl owing, <strong>of</strong> love’s exuberant giving cannot be claimed by the<br />

mortals as their right/ work/ power/ possibility/ capacity/, for these<br />

arise only as a limitation <strong>of</strong> the all-permeating gaze <strong>of</strong> love. Th erefore<br />

in ancient Greek mythology, the God Eros is thought as the most<br />

ancient <strong>of</strong> all Gods, for it already always gives even before asked, in<br />

such an exuberant and in such an overfl owing plenitude, the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

life. If there arises the realm <strong>of</strong> law as the capacity <strong>of</strong> the mortal, this<br />

realm <strong>of</strong> capacity arises only as a limitation <strong>of</strong> the originary illimitable<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> love. Th erefore there may occur a limited out <strong>of</strong> unlimited,<br />

measure out <strong>of</strong> immeasurable, thing out <strong>of</strong> no-thing, condition out<br />

<strong>of</strong> no-condition, withdrawal out <strong>of</strong> giving, and abandonment out <strong>of</strong><br />

overfl owing. Th erefore love’s freedom is both at once: it freely gives in<br />

such a manner that the gifted one (one who is freely gifted with) can<br />

freely decide to abandon this gift itself—<strong>of</strong> freedom’s loving gaze, <strong>of</strong><br />

love’s free gaze. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> the erupting, occurring, arriving <strong>of</strong><br />

this decision (to affi rm or negate freedom’s gift) is the pure possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, or freedom that appears as pure possibility so that this<br />

possibility appears for the gifted mortal as the possibility to negate<br />

even this possibility itself.<br />

It is this possibility (that includes event the impossibility <strong>of</strong> this<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> freedom)—this pure free possibility—<strong>of</strong> decision, <strong>of</strong><br />

cision, <strong>of</strong> separating and partitioning, <strong>of</strong> dis-joining and <strong>of</strong> nonhinging<br />

between condition and conditioned, frees freedom itself<br />

from all necessity and causality. Th is is so in so far as freedom itself<br />

is none but joining, nexus, <strong>of</strong> what Schelling calls Zusammenhang:<br />

belonging together, confi guration, or constellation, an assemblage<br />

rather than system, or totality. It is the nexus <strong>of</strong> freedom in such a<br />

manner as joining freedom can also be dis-jointed, as co-fi guration<br />

freedom can also appear as dis-fi guration, as co-stellation such that<br />

it can also be dis-installed, as assemblage freedom can also be disassembled,<br />

as hinging so that freedom can also be de-hinged by decision,<br />

by partitioning, by separation <strong>of</strong> forces. Freedom frees itself<br />

from itself so that out <strong>of</strong> this freedom, there may occur un-freedom,


254 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

necessity, constriction, causality etc; there may occur evil, hatred,<br />

malice, wrath and disease <strong>of</strong> the will. Th ere may occurs falsifi cation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the assemblage, <strong>of</strong> dis-according <strong>of</strong> love’s loving separation in such<br />

a manner that mutations may occur in the nexus <strong>of</strong> forces that seeks<br />

to destroy this freedom itself.<br />

Th erefore the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom is always the thinking at<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> the thinkable itself, since no Subject can adequately<br />

measure the immeasurable apparition <strong>of</strong> freedom. For that to<br />

happen, the Subject <strong>of</strong> freedom must already always be given by the<br />

immemorial groundlessness <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. In order to measure<br />

the immeasurable apparition <strong>of</strong> freedom, the Subject must already<br />

be granted by freedom itself. Th erefore to measure freedom, it is<br />

necessary to think something more originary than the metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Subject. To think ‘freedom’ is, to free oneself to the risk <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom, to its immeasurable measure, to the irresolvable wager <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. It is to assume the risk that is the necessary precondition <strong>of</strong><br />

the tightrope walker who walks over an abyss so that the humanity<br />

<strong>of</strong> man may be transfi gured into the more affi rmative futurity by<br />

this leap, which is always the leap in freedom. If there remains for<br />

us now any sense <strong>of</strong> our very ethico-political at all, it is derived from<br />

this essential leap <strong>of</strong> freedom which is, as such, a free sense: it is at<br />

once a sense <strong>of</strong> freedom, and freedom <strong>of</strong> sense. As a sense <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

such a sense is freedom unto wager, unto the risk <strong>of</strong> the tightrope<br />

walker over the abyss—<strong>of</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> any given sense. If there still<br />

remains any sense <strong>of</strong> the political and ethical for us now, it is nothing<br />

other than this sense, which is not only the sense <strong>of</strong> risk, but the risk<br />

<strong>of</strong> a sense—<strong>of</strong> freedom itself, <strong>of</strong> freedom’s free fl owing giving and<br />

withdrawing, <strong>of</strong> freedom’s generous plenitude and impoverishment,<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom’s exuberant affi rmation and its own negation.<br />

Freedom is the groundless opening out <strong>of</strong> which the coming<br />

comes as free advent—a coming that is at once free to come and<br />

free not to come. An affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the coming is the thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom whose inscrutable ground is at once pure actuality and pure<br />

possibility, for while it is pure actuality in itself, becomes for mortals<br />

an unsaturated, inexhaustible phenomenon <strong>of</strong> pure possibility. If ‘to<br />

come’ is the unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong> the unenclosed futurity, as free<br />

futurity this future is free to come, or not to come. Not to arrive<br />

as future is the possibility <strong>of</strong> future, the possibility that future may


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 255<br />

not redeem what has already be-come in time, possibility that future<br />

may not be possible. It is the possibility that future may not bring<br />

the light into the voyaging ship that sets out in dark in the open<br />

sea, the possibility that the impossibility <strong>of</strong> freedom, evil, appears<br />

and that the light may sink into the abyss <strong>of</strong> the night. Th erefore<br />

freedom is inseparable from wager, or risk because freedom is the<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the possible, for as the principle <strong>of</strong> pure possibility,<br />

freedom appears as the incalculability <strong>of</strong> the future that bears witness<br />

the immeasurable measure <strong>of</strong> freedom itself.<br />

Th erefore there always remains in freedom something like what<br />

Ernst Bloch (1995) calls ‘In-Vain’. In each inauguration, in each<br />

inception <strong>of</strong> the voyage in the open sea—since freedom is this anarchic<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> inception or inauguration itself—there lies the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> In-Vain. Th is In-Vain lies in the perilous essence <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom itself that is in its radical incalculability to which no measure,<br />

no calculation <strong>of</strong> reason can attain. Th is peril <strong>of</strong> the voyage, voyage<br />

that loves the blue sky above and open sea, is opened at that moment<br />

when this opening is opened, when coming <strong>of</strong> the redemption is<br />

affi rmed at that singular moment, when interrupting the given<br />

foundation <strong>of</strong> existence one becomes free towards freedom.<br />

To be free is free towards light, but also darkness, to the redemption<br />

in future, but also the arriving <strong>of</strong> the un-hoped and ‘In-Vain’, since<br />

what arrives is free to arrive, or arrives out <strong>of</strong> freedom and out <strong>of</strong><br />

which freedom it may not arrive. It is free to arrive, and out <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom it arrives, and therefore it may not arrive; or what arrives<br />

may not be what ought to have arrived; or what arrives, at each<br />

singular moment, is only limitation <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> arriving<br />

itself.<br />

Freedom as the spacing <strong>of</strong> the possible—the possible that is<br />

immeasurable, incalculable, interminable—is the spacing for the<br />

play, or strife between arrival or non-arrival, light and darkness,<br />

limitation and illimitation, giving and withdrawing, <strong>of</strong>f ering and<br />

abandonment, concealment or unconcealment at the same time, at<br />

the same moment which no phenomenology or ontology <strong>of</strong> time can<br />

think as presence. Is it this play or strife on the spacing <strong>of</strong> the possible<br />

that what Heraclitus refers to that <strong>of</strong> the strife between the darkness<br />

and the light as primordial mystery <strong>of</strong> the coming and passing away?


256 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Is this strife or is this a play, <strong>of</strong> what ancient thinkers and mystics in<br />

India call Lila, the originary game <strong>of</strong> creation, the originary game <strong>of</strong><br />

lightness and darkness, <strong>of</strong> withdrawal and expansion, intensifi cation<br />

and an extensifi cation, <strong>of</strong> joy and melancholy? Is this what the Greeks<br />

named as Aletheia—<strong>of</strong> what Heidegger renders as concealmentunconcealment—as<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> origination, and coming to<br />

presence in the open? Th is play, or this strife, this interruption, takes<br />

place in the open. Since this opening enables the coming to come,<br />

we cannot name it with concepts that are at our cognitive disposal to<br />

handle, to possess the world and things that have already become for<br />

us and must have already revealed to us. Only the naming language<br />

that attains to the pure gesture <strong>of</strong> showing, and which exceeding the<br />

conceptual apparatus at the service <strong>of</strong> cognitive function, manifests<br />

and reveals—in fl ash <strong>of</strong> lightening—what is not yet, what is still<br />

always to come that transfi gures the immemorial promise into its<br />

fulfi llment unforeseeably, in the desert <strong>of</strong> hope.<br />

We speak <strong>of</strong> as Open is none but this spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom itself as<br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> origin, as the no-thing like, no-condition like exposure<br />

to the arrival. As logic <strong>of</strong> origin, freedom is the incalculable releasing<br />

to the immeasurable, unpredictable coming which is risked each time<br />

when freedom sways over being whose being lies in his fi nitude. If<br />

the messianic fulfi llment in redemption is a thought <strong>of</strong> future and <strong>of</strong><br />

the arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly other, then this future is a time that remains:<br />

this possibility is the unconditional gift <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. It is as if<br />

the melancholic existence <strong>of</strong> our unredeemed humanity can only<br />

redeemed on the basis <strong>of</strong> a gift that comes from wholly otherwise<br />

destination, from a site <strong>of</strong> a radical future. But for that to happen, the<br />

mortal being must already always be torn open by the act <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

from the heart <strong>of</strong> time and history and from the immanence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world, to the wound <strong>of</strong> eternity. It is only on the basis <strong>of</strong> the tearing<br />

open <strong>of</strong> immanence by the act <strong>of</strong> freedom that eternity may arrive<br />

‘today’, here and now. If man is a creative being who is endowed<br />

with the principle <strong>of</strong> beginning himself anew again and again, this<br />

is because this principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration or inception is granted to<br />

him by freedom itself. Th rough such a being as man, it is freedom<br />

itself that each time begins anew. In this manner man is opened up<br />

towards his own possibility <strong>of</strong> beginning himself out <strong>of</strong> an essential<br />

opening, that is, as spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom itself.


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 257<br />

It is necessary to think these entire questions again as in a<br />

confi guration. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> the coming time cannot evade<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th erefore not only Schelling, but Heidegger<br />

and Rosenzweig too—the free thinkers <strong>of</strong> future—make freedom<br />

as the center stage <strong>of</strong> their thinking: freedom that opens time to<br />

eternity to arrive here and now that cannot be predicated, grounded,<br />

cognized and conceptualized in categories <strong>of</strong> available entities. Such<br />

a thinking <strong>of</strong> freedom that opens us to the radical futurity demands<br />

a diff erent confi guration <strong>of</strong> time and history that is not regressive<br />

apophansis, but anticipative and progressive, a venturing beyond and<br />

opening towards the unforeseeable. Such an idea <strong>of</strong> freedom that<br />

is other than regulative idea, or other than being an infi nite telos<br />

that the immanence <strong>of</strong> indiff erent, homogenous series <strong>of</strong> successive,<br />

accumulative instants attain to, can no longer be determined here,<br />

as in Hegel, as the grounding act <strong>of</strong> the historical Subject in the<br />

Absolute Concept. It is rather a questioning <strong>of</strong> rupturing <strong>of</strong> such an<br />

immanence where the eternity <strong>of</strong> the Other may arrive today, against<br />

and for all hope and all anticipation, beyond all calculation and all<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> a historical, immanent reason.<br />

At each moment time is opened to future, freedom holds sway:<br />

how to name this freedom, this already and yet this yet to come—or,<br />

better, this yet to come <strong>of</strong> the already, the future <strong>of</strong> the past, this past<br />

<strong>of</strong> the future—this opening that is forever excluded from historical<br />

memory <strong>of</strong> a historical world, and yet that alone enables redemption<br />

to arrive, and transfi gures our melancholic memory into joy? How<br />

to name this that alone opens the name to what is to be named—<br />

elsewhere, another time, in a remaining time? It is as if such a name<br />

must be none other than the gift <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. No speculative<br />

memory and no predicative categories name this originary opening,<br />

this originary origin, this originary gift <strong>of</strong> freedom. Since our<br />

cognitive grasp <strong>of</strong> the entities/ objects/ things are only the grasp <strong>of</strong><br />

entities that has arrived for us as ‘lived experience’, the event <strong>of</strong> their<br />

arising and occurring, the event <strong>of</strong> opening <strong>of</strong> experience remains<br />

excluded from our categorical, speculative grasp due to the temporal<br />

non-in-diff erence in relation to this event <strong>of</strong> taking place as such.<br />

Th e statements and explanations are already always late in relation<br />

the pure event <strong>of</strong> presencing. Th erefore propositions that attempt<br />

to trace back the event to its origin and thereby include themselves


258 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

within the immanence <strong>of</strong> the systematic unity can grasp entities/ the<br />

world/ objects only on the basis <strong>of</strong> their available existent character,<br />

not their event <strong>of</strong> advent. We are too late in relation to the Open that<br />

has, fi rst <strong>of</strong> all, exposed us to the event.<br />

Th erefore we cannot predicate the event on the basis <strong>of</strong> the available<br />

being <strong>of</strong> ‘given presence’. Th erefore the name to name the event<br />

always touches the limit <strong>of</strong> the world, or the limit <strong>of</strong> being, exposing<br />

us thereby our own dispropriation from the event—<strong>of</strong> naming itself.<br />

Such a name, which is not a name like other names, is a name<br />

that must consume itself, peril itself in the originary violence—the<br />

archè-violence—<strong>of</strong> the event. It is the name that burns the tongue<br />

<strong>of</strong> the one who opens his mouth to utter it; it abandons the one who<br />

utters it to the desert <strong>of</strong> all hope and all meaning. It is the desert<br />

where all time has been annulled and spaces have burst open to the<br />

Other who is nameless, the Unapparent par excellence.<br />

Yet such a risk <strong>of</strong> peril must be assumed each time one welcomes on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the gift <strong>of</strong> freedom the pure event <strong>of</strong> arrival who redeems<br />

the world. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong> this fi nitude <strong>of</strong> naming and coming<br />

that arrives contra all hope, that arrives contra all anticipation (and<br />

thereby, precisely, demanding from us radical hope, more radical<br />

than hope itself) is there something like future at all, is something<br />

like sense <strong>of</strong> existence itself. What appears as sense <strong>of</strong> existence is<br />

not an accomplished self-presentation, but that arises from the<br />

non-in-diff erence between event and being. Th erefore only for the<br />

mortals future is meaningful, redemption a requirement, opening a<br />

presupposition <strong>of</strong> existence, let alone a condition for our being able<br />

to have propositions and categories. Th e mortal thinking or thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> mortality is not thereby calmed by a system that claims to have<br />

included the notion <strong>of</strong> existence and event within it, by making<br />

existence a category within categories. What it demands, instead,<br />

not a category <strong>of</strong> the thinkable—but a pre-thinkable remaining<br />

time, a pre-predicative redeeming future, a pre-categorical hope<br />

for possibility, a joy in the ever new beginning. In other words, it<br />

demands the act <strong>of</strong> freedom that abandons its sense to the burning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the tongue and to the desert <strong>of</strong> hope where the exemplarity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

name must risk each time its own peril, its own annihilation.


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 259<br />

With this a notion <strong>of</strong> open process and Possible is introduced. For the<br />

process to remain open to the coming, the confi guration <strong>of</strong> temporalities<br />

must not have the self-foundational character <strong>of</strong> a logical necessity, or<br />

metaphysical identity, but a contingency, in the highest sense as freedom.<br />

What is possible is the possibility <strong>of</strong> arising independently from<br />

any given condition in such a way that, due to this independent<br />

character, it can un-hinge, yawn open, dis-fi gure, dis-join, or disinstall<br />

from its condition, only because freedom is not a system but<br />

a life, a nexus <strong>of</strong> movements or forces, a constellation <strong>of</strong> becoming,<br />

an exuberance <strong>of</strong> existence. As an exuberance <strong>of</strong> existence, freedom<br />

is an unsaturated phenomenon, forever in-excess, a pure unfolding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the movement that transcends any immanent self-foundation.<br />

Freedom is, then, the unfi nished, un-totalized surging forward <strong>of</strong><br />

the bellowing Sea pregnant with future possibilities, which Plato so<br />

beautifully evokes in his Timaeus. Contingency in the highest sense<br />

is the possibility <strong>of</strong> the otherwise, belonging to Possibility and future<br />

itself in an essential sense, not the random variability <strong>of</strong> the indiff erent<br />

particulars which Hegel calls ‘contingency’, but the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

otherwise belonging to the open process <strong>of</strong> the Possible by virtue<br />

<strong>of</strong> its open-ness. Since the possibility is free to be possible, or since<br />

this possibility essentially belongs to freedom or itself is freedom,<br />

possibility may not pass over into being. Aristotle thinks, in his<br />

Metaphysics, this possibility—as free—which may not pass over into<br />

being, as potentiality <strong>of</strong> the matter, as dynamic, and not the static,<br />

unfolding towards realizing itself, or coming to be by its ‘nature’:<br />

Now natural comings to be are the comings to be <strong>of</strong> those things<br />

which come to be by nature; and that out <strong>of</strong> which they come to be<br />

is what we call matter... for each <strong>of</strong> them is capable <strong>of</strong> both <strong>of</strong> being<br />

and <strong>of</strong> not being, and this capacity is the matter in each. (Aristotle<br />

2001, p. 791).<br />

Schelling—the most important thinker <strong>of</strong> potentiality after Aristotle<br />

and Bruno, perhaps Leibniz including—inspired by Bruno, makes<br />

potentiality itself as essential question <strong>of</strong> freedom, especially in<br />

his Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World (Schelling 2000). In this work, Schelling<br />

conceives <strong>of</strong> God’s coming to presence as that infi nite becoming. God<br />

passes through the ecstatic potencies—which are also potentialities<br />

<strong>of</strong> time—<strong>of</strong> the eternal past, eternal presence, and eternal future,


260 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

which hold together in a confi guration which is without totality and<br />

is free. Th is process which in mortal condition is a dissoluble holdingtogether,<br />

a transfi nite relation, is what Schelling re-thinking the<br />

traditional logic, calls ‘judgement’ in his essay on Human Freedom<br />

(1936).<br />

What is happening here? Th e ground <strong>of</strong> freedom, or rather its<br />

unground in its essential relation to potencies in Schelling is not<br />

thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> the logical principle <strong>of</strong> self-foundational<br />

necessity, nor on the basis <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong> identity,<br />

but as: holding together, a disjoined joining, a caesural belonging <strong>of</strong><br />

ecstatic potencies <strong>of</strong> temporalities—<strong>of</strong> eternal past, eternal presence,<br />

eternal future—as confi guration. Th is is not a modality <strong>of</strong> autotransitional<br />

conceptual generation as in Hegel, but—in the absence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the self-foundational principle <strong>of</strong> logical identity and necessity—<br />

event leaps forth, the Possibility is hold open, since the nexus in<br />

freedom between the condition and the conditioned is dissoluble,<br />

dis-joinable. Th erefore Schelling, in his later philosophy—in fact<br />

from Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World (2000) onwards—has felt the increasing<br />

necessity to think the question <strong>of</strong> the coming and the origin<br />

otherwise than on the basis <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> generation as it is<br />

expressed in the negative philosophy. Instead the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coming and the origin is thought as confi guration <strong>of</strong> potencies, in<br />

Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World, where the relation—but not generation—<strong>of</strong><br />

potencies are caesural, <strong>of</strong> which Schelling calls Scheidung, cision. All<br />

coming to be and coming to presence—out <strong>of</strong> an essential freedom,<br />

releasing and opening—bears the mark <strong>of</strong> cision, an originary cut,<br />

or an originary falling away (Abfall). Th erefore existence does not<br />

have the self-foundational character <strong>of</strong> a logical necessity or identity,<br />

but as a confi guration <strong>of</strong> ecstatic potencies <strong>of</strong> temporalities—born<br />

out <strong>of</strong> cision, cut, or caesura, out <strong>of</strong> an originary disjunction and<br />

falling away—that are hold together as dissoluble assemblage without<br />

totality.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> freedom has somehow become a sort <strong>of</strong> aberration<br />

in our contemporary philosophical thought, as if abandoned by the<br />

waves <strong>of</strong> a great Sea, it has left only marks <strong>of</strong> a remote thought in the<br />

deserted sea shore, so that the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom has only become<br />

for us something like vague remembrance <strong>of</strong> a lost tradition <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking, questioning and interrogating which has now abandoned


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 261<br />

us, or that which has been abandoned. Not only the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom—this great question <strong>of</strong> philosophy—but the abandonment<br />

<strong>of</strong> this great question itself has appeared to have abandoned us. As a<br />

result raising again the question <strong>of</strong> freedom can never escape asking<br />

this question <strong>of</strong> this abandonment itself: the question <strong>of</strong> what is stake<br />

in this abandonment <strong>of</strong> the great question <strong>of</strong> freedom. For a long<br />

time, somehow it has been dimly perceived by the philosophers that<br />

the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom is no longer ‘contemporary’ anymore, that<br />

the great question <strong>of</strong> freedom has become—as what Adorno (1987,<br />

pp. 214-15) calls—‘obsolete’, aged, infertile. Or perhaps the thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, by a necessary logic <strong>of</strong> thought, is abandoned by itself to<br />

necessity. As a result, the question <strong>of</strong> freedom has been abandoned by<br />

itself, or is subjugated to the thought <strong>of</strong> necessity by being enclosed<br />

in the great tradition <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ontology <strong>of</strong> the thinkable. Th e thought <strong>of</strong> freedom, in so far as is<br />

made thinkable, is no longer free. It has become bound up, enclosed<br />

within the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> Being and subjectivity, which is none but<br />

the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> the necessity itself: we are no longer free to be<br />

free, we are no longer free to freely think freedom, for freedom has<br />

already abandoned the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom to closure <strong>of</strong> sense.<br />

Th erefore raising the question <strong>of</strong> freedom would demand from us<br />

the task <strong>of</strong> releasing, freeing the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom from all sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

necessity, from all sorts <strong>of</strong> closure—<strong>of</strong> the juridico-political, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, <strong>of</strong> the ontology <strong>of</strong> the thinkable. Th at<br />

is, however, not everything. If freedom is not merely to be negative<br />

freedom, but primarily affi rmative, then we must allow ourselves to<br />

open the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom to its un-thinkability, to its abyss, to its<br />

vertiginous limit so that, beyond the closure <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

subjectivity, beyond the systematic, totalizing, foundational attempts<br />

at necessity, the freedom <strong>of</strong> thinking itself arrive unconditionally—to<br />

thought itself so that thinking can welcome to itself its own condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> possibility. What is remained to be thought today—which is the<br />

task <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom—is to release the unconditional character<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, its event-character <strong>of</strong> eruption in the midst <strong>of</strong> existing,<br />

its (in)fi nitude from the closure <strong>of</strong> all sorts—metaphysical, juridicolegislative,<br />

theologico-political, etc.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the rare contemporary, systematic philosophical works<br />

on freedom—that <strong>of</strong> Jean Luc Nancy’s Th e Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom


262 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

(1993)—confronts this task <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom in an admirable<br />

manner, which is, that <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom as experience, understood<br />

in the singular manner <strong>of</strong> the philosopher as the unconditional limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinkable, as the passion <strong>of</strong> the limit, as perilous, pirated and<br />

therefore illegitimate seizure without foundation. Nancy says:<br />

It is a question <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>f ering human beings to a freedom <strong>of</strong> being, it<br />

is a question <strong>of</strong> presenting the humanity <strong>of</strong> the human being (his<br />

‘essence’) to a freedom as being by which existence absolutely and<br />

resolutely transcends, that is, ex-sists. In all movements <strong>of</strong> liberation, as<br />

in all vested institutions <strong>of</strong> freedom, it is precisely this transcendence<br />

which still has to be freed. In and through ethical, juridical, material<br />

and civil liberties, one must free that through which alone these<br />

liberties are, on the one hand, ultimately possible and thinkable and<br />

on the other, capable <strong>of</strong> receiving a destination other than that <strong>of</strong><br />

their immanent self-consumption: a transcendence <strong>of</strong> existence such<br />

that existence, as existence in- the-world, which has nothing to do<br />

with any otherworld, transcends (i.e., continues to accomplish) the<br />

‘’essence’’ that it is in the fi nitude in which it in-sists. (Nancy 1993,<br />

p. 13)<br />

It is this same task—that <strong>of</strong> releasing <strong>of</strong> the unconditional event—<br />

character from the closure <strong>of</strong> the realm <strong>of</strong> ‘the immanent selfconsumption’<br />

and thereby <strong>of</strong>f ering the closure <strong>of</strong> immanence to the<br />

transcendence <strong>of</strong> the open: it is this same task that guides this present<br />

work, albeit in a diff erent manner, in a diff erent gesture, in a diff erent<br />

style. Th e eruptive- event character <strong>of</strong> freedom, in its unthinkable<br />

and abyssal character, cannot be thought within the logic <strong>of</strong> being<br />

and subjectivity, but at the limit <strong>of</strong> foundation and its necessity as<br />

freely opening a world to come, in its messianic welcoming on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> a ground which refuses grounding. Th is opening demands<br />

the repetition <strong>of</strong> the tradition <strong>of</strong> the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom in such a<br />

manner so that the unconditional moments <strong>of</strong> freedom in thought<br />

leaps out, springs into the arrival as—what Heidegger (1969)<br />

calls—‘the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’ on the basis <strong>of</strong> a dispropriation<br />

or expropriation, that means on the basis <strong>of</strong> an ungrounded fi nitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence itself. Later we shall take up this question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude<br />

and existence. Here we shall begin, in a gesture <strong>of</strong> repetition—which<br />

is always here a gesture <strong>of</strong> reading—the reading <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s great


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 263<br />

treatise on freedom, that <strong>of</strong> his Philosophical Inquiries Concerning the<br />

Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom.<br />

If the question <strong>of</strong> freedom opens for us its radical opening only<br />

at the limit <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, or the metaphysical<br />

totalization in the principle <strong>of</strong> identity reductively understood—in<br />

other words, only at the limit <strong>of</strong> various reductive totalization <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom to necessity—then a radical attempt to open the question <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom has to confront again the question <strong>of</strong> the relation, dialectical<br />

or otherwise, <strong>of</strong> the supposed compatibility or incompatibility<br />

between freedom and system. Th is would demand a hollowing out,<br />

an unworking, or loosening, <strong>of</strong> tearing inside out <strong>of</strong> the solidifi ed<br />

artifi ce <strong>of</strong> the various forms <strong>of</strong> necessity—necessity that appeals<br />

for its foundation the metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong> identity, <strong>of</strong> ground<br />

and reason, <strong>of</strong> the ontology <strong>of</strong> subjectivity—so that a diff erence,<br />

a hiatus, a caesura, a dehiscence, an abyss be inscribed into the<br />

foundational, metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong> identity. Since various forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> necessity demand founding, or grounding, and appeal to selfidentity<br />

and subjectivity, they thereby in a necessary logic seek to<br />

abnegate the very freedom to constitute themselves as self-founding<br />

mythic totality. To deliver these various forms <strong>of</strong> necessity to their<br />

unconditional abandonment, it then becomes necessary to release<br />

free a diff erence that does not belong to its totality. Such was the<br />

deconstructive reading that Schelling performed when he repeats<br />

the very problematic again—<strong>of</strong> the supposed (in) compatibility<br />

between freedom and system, between diff erence and identity,<br />

between unground and ground, between the abyss and existence so<br />

that there remains an irreducible, ‘un-pre-thinkable’ remainder <strong>of</strong> the<br />

system that renders the system <strong>of</strong> freedom bereft <strong>of</strong> any innermost <strong>of</strong><br />

gathering or speculative unity. Unlike Hegel’s system, the system <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom is not an immanent one. Such a system <strong>of</strong> freedom would not<br />

have its own ground within itself but forever outside, a transcendence<br />

that can never be totalized, since it can never allow itself to be<br />

thought as subjectivity or being. Th is ‘irreducible remainder’, this<br />

remnant is the diff erence <strong>of</strong> system that emerges with the repetition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the very systemic task <strong>of</strong> metaphysics. Th is irreducible nonbeing,<br />

if not nothing pure and simple, that can never be eliminated,<br />

annihilated without remainder is the very inscrutable, unfathomable


264 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> the ground that spaces itself open equally—as the work<br />

and worklessness <strong>of</strong> freedom—to good and evil. What is released,<br />

in the very system <strong>of</strong> freedom, is none other than freedom itself, is<br />

none other than the unconditioned ground itself as the space <strong>of</strong> pure<br />

possibility that includes its abnegation, that is, the possibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

radical evil.<br />

Such is Schelling’s greatest contribution to the philosophical<br />

questioning <strong>of</strong> freedom: that Schelling, without renouncing the<br />

demand <strong>of</strong> system <strong>of</strong> freedom, could release, free open from the<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> freedom a movement <strong>of</strong> diff erence, a spacing <strong>of</strong><br />

the groundless, the unruly <strong>of</strong> the abyss, a drunkenness and a certain<br />

divine madness—understood in its radical fi nitude—that remains<br />

as an eternal, irreducible remnant <strong>of</strong> ground, <strong>of</strong> reason and <strong>of</strong><br />

subjectivity at a risk <strong>of</strong> giving over freedom to its extreme possibility,<br />

which is the possibility <strong>of</strong> freedom’s own negation in evil, that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

impossibility <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. Th erefore the question <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

arises in its extreme urgency, in its extreme possibility only at the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> freedom itself, and that is only when the<br />

system makes itself feel its strident necessity so that at the limit, out <strong>of</strong><br />

this abyss, in this movement <strong>of</strong> diff ering and spacing, the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> redemption also arises in love and in unconditional forgiveness,<br />

or in the creative act that affi rms a radical future beyond negations.<br />

Freedom is not only the possibility <strong>of</strong> good and evil—that is, the<br />

possibility that it would not even be possible—but also the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> forgiveness and redemption. Since this possibility arises, happens<br />

unconditionally, that means transcending all immanent closure <strong>of</strong> ‘<br />

self-consumption’, the happening which arising, leaping, bursting,<br />

overfl owing cannot be completely determined by the antecedent<br />

cause, freedom thereby acquires its event-character, which is its<br />

freeing itself from all closure <strong>of</strong> necessity and causality, <strong>of</strong> foundation<br />

and ground, <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and reason. It ex-sists any given-ness <strong>of</strong><br />

antecedent causality, so that freedom’s event character is that what<br />

frees, releases the unconditional, that means out <strong>of</strong> the unruly <strong>of</strong><br />

the abyss, out <strong>of</strong> the drunkenness <strong>of</strong> the ground, without which<br />

freedom gets tied to necessity, to the ontological closure <strong>of</strong><br />

subjectivity, to various determinant causalities. It is Schelling’s<br />

greatest contribution to make the claim <strong>of</strong> the ground, <strong>of</strong> system<br />

make felt in its highest, most strident necessity and yet—without


Th e Sense <strong>of</strong> Freedom • 265<br />

renouncing such a claim <strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>of</strong> ground and being—drinking<br />

the wine <strong>of</strong> the abyss.<br />

It has become common sense knowledge <strong>of</strong> the students <strong>of</strong><br />

the history <strong>of</strong> philosophy to see Schelling’s place in the history<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy as transitive idealist philosopher between Fichte’s<br />

inauguration and Hegel’s completion <strong>of</strong> Idealism. What has<br />

remained to be seen is the uniqueness, the singularity <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s<br />

contribution to thought <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> freedom, which is not one<br />

question among others but the essential question <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself:<br />

that <strong>of</strong> philosophy’s birth itself as freedom, out <strong>of</strong> the gift <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

and also—and this is important—freedom as opening <strong>of</strong> existence as<br />

whole, the entirety <strong>of</strong> what exists as such without making freedom<br />

property <strong>of</strong> that which exists. What exists belongs to the originary<br />

spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom, to the essential donation <strong>of</strong> freedom, and not vice<br />

versa. Already inaugurating along with Fichte what has come to be<br />

called ‘Idealism’, Schelling was already at the same time un-working<br />

the systemic task <strong>of</strong> Idealism, and thereby already opening to another<br />

inauguration, a more originary beginning <strong>of</strong> thinking at the limit <strong>of</strong><br />

the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and ground, <strong>of</strong> reason and its system.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> freedom for Schelling is not one question amongst<br />

other, but the question that has already freed, released him from the<br />

necessity unto freedom—which is that <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom neither<br />

in relation to causality nor to the free will <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical Subject.<br />

In this manner, outside and beyond the mere formal distinction in<br />

philosophy between sensibility and intelligibility, between nature and<br />

history, there is introduced a more originary thinking <strong>of</strong> freedom:<br />

Freedom as the event <strong>of</strong> opening <strong>of</strong> existence to its own arrival as<br />

such, which as such has to be freed from the categorical, predicative<br />

grasp <strong>of</strong> the presently given world, so that freedom is no longer<br />

seen as victory over brute sensibility, but free de-cision, out <strong>of</strong><br />

fi nitude—that means, out <strong>of</strong> unground, unconditionally—the<br />

decision between good and evil. Th is decision is the vitality, the life<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, for freedom in itself not a system as such but a life. But<br />

this freedom’s vitality is not that <strong>of</strong> mythic vitality <strong>of</strong> foundation’s<br />

self-immanence; precisely the otherwise, freedom interrupts the<br />

mythic vitality <strong>of</strong> ground’s immanence, and opens itself to ever<br />

anew, to ever renewed inauguration <strong>of</strong> existence.


266 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th is whole task <strong>of</strong> seeing freedom as event <strong>of</strong> existence as such, and<br />

not predicative, categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> already present entities demands<br />

diff erence in repetition be freed, released into the open. Th erefore<br />

Schelling repeats what needs to deconstructed: the metaphysical<br />

foundation <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement with its law <strong>of</strong> identity as its<br />

self-foundational principle, and its claim for freedom the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> system. Schelling’s unique, singular repetition demands that the<br />

claim <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement not be renounced and abandoned but<br />

precisely be demanded, and thereby releasing from its heart what does<br />

not belong to the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> judgement, but to—<br />

how to say this—to life. What does not belong to the metaphysics <strong>of</strong><br />

predication, but alone to life, is none but the event itself, the free event<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence coming to presence, the event <strong>of</strong> freedom that happens,<br />

occurs, erupts as life. Schelling’s treatise therefore beginning with<br />

the discussion about the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement with its law <strong>of</strong> identity<br />

ends with an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> life, with the vitality <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

becoming <strong>of</strong> the creature and <strong>of</strong> the divine.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> freedom is not one question among others. It<br />

is rather the question <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence itself from which any<br />

such sense <strong>of</strong> political and ethical be derived. Th e attempts to think<br />

the sense <strong>of</strong> the political and ethical in a more originary manner<br />

demand raising again the ‘aged’ question <strong>of</strong> freedom, to free us for a<br />

renewed youth <strong>of</strong> freedom’s vitality and life. Th is is only because the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> freedom as such, understood in a more originary manner,<br />

has never aged, but only been covered with soot and dust <strong>of</strong> the<br />

various foundational gestures <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and<br />

necessity. To give back freedom its youthful vitality demands that we<br />

give ourselves the task, not merely that <strong>of</strong> exposing the buried presupposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> our existence by unworking the sedimented structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> being and subjectivity, <strong>of</strong> causality and necessity, but also we learn<br />

to say a ‘yes’ to freedom again.


§ Th e Irreducible Remainder<br />

Th is chapter, taking Schelling’s Philosophical Inquiries into the Nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> Human Freedom as chief referent point, attempts to think the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> evil out <strong>of</strong> abyssal decision, decision that opens up each<br />

time out <strong>of</strong> the inscrutable, unfathomable abyss <strong>of</strong> human freedom<br />

that marks each time the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the creaturely existence, and<br />

at the same time the possibility <strong>of</strong> the creature’s self-abnegation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this fi nitude. Since the vitality <strong>of</strong> freedom each time leaps out,<br />

transcends, ex-sists any form <strong>of</strong> necessity, causality, or immanent selfenclosure,<br />

this vitality—in decision—is constantly solicited towards<br />

evil in the self-affi rmation <strong>of</strong> its creaturely freedom. Th erefore<br />

the eternal possibility <strong>of</strong> this radical evil, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it arises out <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom and out <strong>of</strong> the self-affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the fi nite existence, marks<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and all logics <strong>of</strong> necessity<br />

and causality, which at that limit points towards new inauguration<br />

<strong>of</strong> redemptive fulfi lment no longer on the ground <strong>of</strong> Subject’s selfassertion<br />

and appropriation <strong>of</strong> its condition, but in love which, at the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> mortal’s power <strong>of</strong> self-appropriation bestows upon mortals<br />

the gift <strong>of</strong> a redemptive happiness and beatitude.<br />

*<br />

When one asks the question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil—thereby<br />

understanding evil as ‘radical’ which is distinguished from mere<br />

brutality and accidental ‘human’ mistakes due to the limitation <strong>of</strong><br />

human understanding—what at stake there is not merely that <strong>of</strong><br />

raising one question amongst others, but the possibility and the


268 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> human freedom itself. the question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

evil is the most radical question <strong>of</strong> freedom, and the most radical<br />

question <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, as if under the name or the word ‘evil’<br />

not only the terrible images <strong>of</strong> destruction and malice are conjured<br />

up, but also the powerlessness <strong>of</strong> thinking itself—<strong>of</strong> philosophical<br />

thinking—that concerns itself with the limit <strong>of</strong> its own thought,<br />

thinking that fi nds itself unable to think the inexplicability <strong>of</strong> evil’s<br />

terrible power. From where evil draws its devouring malice, malice<br />

that does not abate its cruelty as if the whole world’s tears are not<br />

enough for its all consuming lust? Any essential thinking that is not<br />

satisfi ed merely with gathering empirical data that only explain the<br />

empirical conditions <strong>of</strong> evil’s actual manifestation once such events<br />

take place but more essentially concerned with the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil<br />

as such, the possibility <strong>of</strong> its very taking place as such, and not merely<br />

explaining away ‘this’ or ‘that’ evil, then it must be connected with the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> mortal’s existentiality <strong>of</strong> his existence itself in its intimate<br />

connection with mortal’s intrinsic, radical fi nitude, and the abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

human freedom. Only then ‘evil’ will not be explained away as mere<br />

accidental happenings, aberrations, mistakes, and man’s unfortunate<br />

oblivion or distraction, explanations that are carried with the help <strong>of</strong><br />

empirical studies through fi eld works, as if man’s possibility <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

can only go as far as bestiality, as the animal like behaviour. If that<br />

were so, evil would not have such terrible, all consuming, malicious<br />

appearance amidst our existence. In other words, evil would not be<br />

so radical. As if, as it were, the mortal’s freedom reaches its utmost<br />

possibility, or its utmost limit only as the limit <strong>of</strong> bestiality and no<br />

more. when Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> Franz Baader that ‘Baader is right in<br />

saying that it would be desirable if the rottenness in man could only<br />

go as far as animality; but unfortunately man can only stand above<br />

or beneath animals’ (Schelling 1936, p.49), what Schelling thereby<br />

seeks to articulate is not merely the radical nature <strong>of</strong> evil but also the<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> man’s freedom which, in its utmost possibility and limit,<br />

touches that point <strong>of</strong> decision—at the limit <strong>of</strong> the thinkable—which<br />

concerns the limit <strong>of</strong> man’s possibility and capacity, not merely <strong>of</strong> the<br />

terrible evil, but also the paradisiacal, beatifi c redemptive fulfi lment<br />

in forgiveness and love beyond measure.<br />

With the question <strong>of</strong> freedom, arising out <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> mortal’s<br />

condition touches at the limit <strong>of</strong> man’s possibility and capacity. Th is


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 269<br />

limit is none other than the eruption, occurring, happening <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immeasurable and the unconditional forgiveness and love in man<br />

who is nevertheless a fi nite and conditioned being. It is none other<br />

than the enigmatic appearing <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> unconditional<br />

forgiveness whose phenomenality no phenomenological ontology<br />

can grasp, the unconditional forgiveness whose necessity is felt<br />

precisely at that limit when evil threatens the condition <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

the basis or ground <strong>of</strong> existence itself as such. Th erefore the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom is the question <strong>of</strong> the unconditional as such, unconditional<br />

as the wager—not so much <strong>of</strong> accidental happening in life but as the<br />

wager—<strong>of</strong> existence itself as such.<br />

To exist (whose existentiality is this, to borrow this formulation<br />

from Heidegger, ‘ex-sistence’) as fi nite and mortal is to be thrown by<br />

freedom to freedom’s wager or risk <strong>of</strong> this existence itself. Freedom<br />

throws existence to its wager. Freedom is not the metaphysical<br />

task <strong>of</strong> subject’s freely grounding itself on itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

logical, ontological principle <strong>of</strong> identity, <strong>of</strong> reason and ground.<br />

Freedom is rather the unconditional wager <strong>of</strong> existence as such.<br />

To exist is to wager each time out <strong>of</strong> its thrown-ness that means,<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> mortal condition. Out <strong>of</strong> this wager which<br />

fi nds manifestation in decision, not the calculable, programmable<br />

decision, but out <strong>of</strong> the ‘un-pre-thinkable’ (Unvordenkliche), there<br />

arises each time not only the possibility <strong>of</strong> all consuming evil but<br />

also the unconditional beatitude <strong>of</strong> redemptive forgiveness and<br />

paradisiacal, blissful loving.<br />

Th erefore any dialectically accomplished universal morality <strong>of</strong><br />

reconciliation is so inadequate, so insuffi cient, not merely to explain<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> the radical nature <strong>of</strong> evil but also the unconditional<br />

demand <strong>of</strong> a non-programmable, incalculable, un-thinkable<br />

forgiveness, precisely because evil can be so unthinkably radical.<br />

Th erefore any conditioned ethics and politics <strong>of</strong> reconciliation out<br />

<strong>of</strong> calculative, programmable grounds demand not merely that<br />

they think evil in much more radical way, but that this radical evil<br />

itself calls forth unconditional forgiveness and love that cannot be<br />

calculated and programmed beforehand, that does not have logical<br />

necessity or metaphysical form <strong>of</strong> causality. Th erefore neither logical


270 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> necessity, nor any metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong> causality,<br />

nor any phenomenological ontology <strong>of</strong> manifestation can explain the<br />

pure taking place <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> forgiveness, as if it occurs itself out <strong>of</strong><br />

no-thing. Th is in itself demands that we think <strong>of</strong> freedom in relation<br />

to its inscrutable, unfathomable, unconditional ground in a manner<br />

that delivers, frees, and releases such a freedom from any conditioned<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> being wherein various determined forms <strong>of</strong> necessities and<br />

causalities work.<br />

In On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness (2001) Jacques Derrida,<br />

without however raising the question <strong>of</strong> freedom at all, brings out<br />

in an admirable manner the unconditional demand <strong>of</strong> a forgiveness<br />

and hospitality that cannot be reduced to the universal morality<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasoned, calculated, programmed acts <strong>of</strong> reconciliation. What<br />

Jacques Derrida thereby brings out is the necessity <strong>of</strong> our time to<br />

think at the limit <strong>of</strong> the thinkable (<strong>of</strong> the unthinkable unconditional<br />

forgiveness), the event-character <strong>of</strong> freedom beyond any immanent<br />

closure <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, causality, necessity, reconciliation etc.<br />

Th erefore unconditional forgiveness can only be event itself: it<br />

occurs, happens, and erupts in such a manner that its aleatory<br />

character cannot be thought within the calculable, programmable<br />

self-certainty <strong>of</strong> a decision on the basis <strong>of</strong> knowledge. In other words,<br />

it cannot be thought within any metaphysics <strong>of</strong> necessity, or causality<br />

or subjectivity. It has to arise that which is each time free—to arise<br />

or not to arise. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom now, more than ever, is<br />

none but this: to free the messianic moments in freedom that is, its<br />

moments <strong>of</strong> unconditional forgiveness, and affi rmation an arrival <strong>of</strong><br />

a redemptive fulfi lment which alone can redeem the evil so radical.<br />

Evil has not thereby lost the possibility <strong>of</strong> its appearance; only<br />

that this appearance cannot be grasped by any phenomenological<br />

ontology <strong>of</strong> appearance. Since it arises out <strong>of</strong> freedom (a freedom<br />

whose grounds remain inappropriable for the mortals), the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the eruptive character <strong>of</strong> evil remains as much as the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the event-character <strong>of</strong> the messianic, redemptive fulfi lment out <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. Evil is not explained away, but whose possibility remains.<br />

It is this question <strong>of</strong> an essential remainder that is the diffi culty<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking freedom, an ‘irreducible remainder’ which does not<br />

allow itself to be thought in relation to the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> ground,<br />

necessity, or reason. Hence no philosophy, no politics and no ethics


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 271<br />

can evade the wager <strong>of</strong> existence which freedom throws us to, but<br />

that, in so far as this wager, this dice-throw may make the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> evil actual, it precisely thereby makes possible—at that abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

the moment—the possibility <strong>of</strong> unconditional forgiveness and the<br />

beatitude <strong>of</strong> love, simply because the god Eros is older, and therefore<br />

younger than good and evil. But there is no certitude, no guarantee,<br />

and no calculated knowledge that gives us before-hand the intimation<br />

that the messianic moment is sure to arrive at a destined moment.<br />

Th is non-certitude <strong>of</strong> mortals’ calculations and programmes cannot<br />

intimate the imminence and intensity <strong>of</strong> that arrival, precisely because<br />

this coming itself is free coming, is itself pure donation <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

Perhaps the philosophy and politics <strong>of</strong> the future will be this politics and<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> wager. Has not always been so? Can there be the sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> politics and philosophy for us if there is not already freedom at<br />

work, for to deny, to minimize, to close freedom its gift <strong>of</strong> wager to us<br />

would mean the denial <strong>of</strong> that divine, blissful love’s redemption, that<br />

beatifi c forgiveness, that nobility <strong>of</strong> life that arises out <strong>of</strong> freedom’s<br />

gift. To deny this gift would itself be the most terrible radical evil.<br />

Th is chapter again, therefore, attempts to think all these questions as<br />

the urgent questions <strong>of</strong> our time: the question <strong>of</strong> the unconditional<br />

event <strong>of</strong> forgiveness and love, <strong>of</strong> freedom in relation to its abyssal<br />

condition, and above all, freedom as the originary donation <strong>of</strong> the sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence itself as such.<br />

Schelling’s great treatise on freedom is one <strong>of</strong> the rare works in<br />

the history <strong>of</strong> philosophy that attempts to think freedom essentially,<br />

that means, freedom not as one question amongst others but as the<br />

very question <strong>of</strong> philosophy and <strong>of</strong> existence itself at the limit <strong>of</strong><br />

the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity. Th e question <strong>of</strong> freedom is none<br />

other than the question <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence as such and as a<br />

whole. It is the question <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence at the limit <strong>of</strong> its<br />

condition, question concerning existence as the logic <strong>of</strong> its origin<br />

and be-coming, the sense <strong>of</strong> coming to presence to itself. While<br />

working within the dominant metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the time—which is<br />

the dominant metaphysical tradition <strong>of</strong> the ‘occident’—that means,<br />

repeating this metaphysics, Schelling’s treatise on freedom allows<br />

freedom as diff erence <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, drawing inside out <strong>of</strong> the heart<br />

<strong>of</strong> metaphysics, which is to say, to its freedom, to the wager <strong>of</strong> its<br />

free affi rmation, thereby loosening the sedimented artifi ce <strong>of</strong> the


272 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the time. In Schelling’s thinking, metaphysics no<br />

longer remains certain <strong>of</strong> itself regarding its self-constitution and<br />

ground but takes the name <strong>of</strong> a wager, an infi nite wager, an infi nite<br />

risk—and also an infi nite task—that <strong>of</strong> its own un-working. In<br />

Schelling’s thinking the system <strong>of</strong> freedom no longer is that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Subject’s act <strong>of</strong> self-grounding and self-appropriating on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

the power/ force/ gaze/ law <strong>of</strong> the negative, but precisely becomes an<br />

in-fi nite logic <strong>of</strong> be-coming <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence as a whole at the<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> the sense, so that freedom frees itself from any act <strong>of</strong> selfgrounding<br />

and self-appropriation. In Schelling’s thinking, system is<br />

that name <strong>of</strong> the jointure/ nexus/ confi guration/ constellation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

movements, becoming <strong>of</strong> existence as such which, in so far this jointure<br />

itself is none but free, is therefore free to be dis-joined/ dis-installed/<br />

dis-fi gured. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> this dis-fi guration/dis-installation/disjoining<br />

<strong>of</strong> the system is therefore not merely an accidental character<br />

<strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> freedom but it is rather the essential nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Schelling’s system that it is moved by the principle <strong>of</strong> becoming and<br />

not mechanical, logical, metaphysical principle <strong>of</strong> repetition. As such<br />

Schelling’s system <strong>of</strong> freedom is inseparable from the freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

life. Surged with life’s inexhaustible movement, freedom continually<br />

opens us to the unconditioned becoming. For Schelling freedom<br />

has never been that <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s primordial<br />

act <strong>of</strong> self-positing and its attempt at self-grounding but rather is<br />

the exuberance <strong>of</strong> life’s pure affi rmation, pre-subjectifi ed and preobjectifi<br />

ed, which is the movement <strong>of</strong> longing with which even God<br />

comes to his own existence. Th erefore for Schelling the system <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom never accomplishes itself as complete but that which carries<br />

an ‘irreducible remainder’, a Not Yet, and a yet to come. Since the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> longing which is freedom’s logic <strong>of</strong> origin never knows<br />

bounds and limit, since longing limitlessly exposes itself to its own<br />

limit, and thereby calls forth new inauguration <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

and the joyous acts <strong>of</strong> its creative freedom, therefore the system <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom may interrupt its own foundation, since it is system as life,<br />

and not mere inert, mechanical, emaciated product <strong>of</strong> spirit. In life’s<br />

limitless exposure <strong>of</strong> its own limit, life also exposes itself limitlessly to its<br />

own remainder, and hence the Not Yet <strong>of</strong> the system. System is here the<br />

name <strong>of</strong> the movement <strong>of</strong> accomplishment and fulfi lment, <strong>of</strong> life’s<br />

vitality in longing that confronts each moment its own limit and the


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 273<br />

demand <strong>of</strong> a non-limit at the same time. Th is in-satiety <strong>of</strong> system<br />

and its exuberance <strong>of</strong> life is nothing but the infi nite wager <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

itself which grants the mortals the possibility <strong>of</strong> its true fulfi lment<br />

that arrives from the Eschatos <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

What Schelling has tirelessly attempted to think is this wager <strong>of</strong><br />

existence as the donation <strong>of</strong> freedom. For him philosophy itself, as the<br />

highest and most joyous creative affi rmation, is none but a creative wager<br />

that seizes the existence <strong>of</strong> the creative thinker. If for the philosophical<br />

task <strong>of</strong> thinking existence is inseparable from the question <strong>of</strong> system,<br />

this system can never be a totality ruled by logics <strong>of</strong> necessity and<br />

causality, but a system that wages itself each time, limitlessly exposing<br />

itself thereby to its own limit. Since the system <strong>of</strong> freedom must be a<br />

free system—a system that is free to be no longer or not yet system—<br />

such a system <strong>of</strong> freedom can only be forever (a) tempted, each time<br />

anew, and can never arrive the defi niteness and the completion, such<br />

as for example Hegel’s speculative system <strong>of</strong> metaphysics.<br />

Perhaps this much explains Schelling’s failure, unlike his classmate<br />

Hegel’s success, to constitute a defi nitive and an accomplished<br />

system <strong>of</strong> the Absolute. What Schelling has to give way, since he gave<br />

himself to the task <strong>of</strong> system <strong>of</strong> freedom and not necessity, to the<br />

constant, endless (a) temptation <strong>of</strong> system that also demands, ever<br />

new unworking <strong>of</strong> the system. As a result he constantly has to expose<br />

himself to the vertigo <strong>of</strong> the abyss which is none but the abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

the system that, precisely in order to be constituted, must un-work<br />

itself again and again. the fate <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> freedom cannot avert<br />

from the yawning gaze <strong>of</strong> its abyss, which is the abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

its utter groundlessness and un-thinkability. For us who have come<br />

after Schelling it is this failure <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s system <strong>of</strong> freedom that<br />

has exposed us to the yawning abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom—that, what freedom<br />

exposes us to, to our groundlessness—it is this failure and the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the thinkable rather than the success <strong>of</strong> the constituted system<br />

that interests us more. Th is failure is none other than the failure <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy’s self-accomplishment and closure out <strong>of</strong> its own accord,<br />

the exposure <strong>of</strong> thinking to its own un-thinkability, the constant<br />

withdrawal <strong>of</strong> freedom from any closure <strong>of</strong> the system. It is this<br />

failure to which philosophy is interminably led by the movement <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom that animates it and animates the philosophical desire for<br />

the Absolute, <strong>of</strong> what is unconditional at the limit <strong>of</strong> all concepts


274 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and all thinkable. It is this failure rather than success that alone<br />

frees philosophy for a new inauguration <strong>of</strong> thinking, which means,<br />

that exposes us to the limitlessness, to the immeasurable, to the<br />

very ground <strong>of</strong> all being and existence that irreducibly lies outside<br />

all acts <strong>of</strong> grounding: namely, freedom itself. Th at is why thinking<br />

which is itself the gift <strong>of</strong> freedom, though constantly assailed by an<br />

‘unappeasable’ melancholy, is the name <strong>of</strong> joy, which is the ‘aristocracy<br />

<strong>of</strong> happiness’ (Bloch 1995a, p. 937).<br />

Perhaps the future philosophy will be joyous philosophy, and not<br />

merely the philosophy <strong>of</strong> joy. But we do not yet know whether that<br />

philosophy will still be called ‘philosophy’ or by some other name.<br />

Schelling’s treatise on freedom begins with the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the incommensurability between system and freedom, with the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> freedom itself as such.<br />

Since the dominant understanding about system as to its genesis and<br />

constitution, it structure and its mobility as system always relegates<br />

system to necessity—since the dominant system takes the logical<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> identity and judgement to be sovereign—the treatise <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom must therefore begin with the examination <strong>of</strong> the logical<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> identity and judgement, and the (restricted) notion <strong>of</strong><br />

the system itself. Th e systemic task <strong>of</strong> thinking freedom that must free<br />

freedom itself from necessity must loosen the sedimented structure <strong>of</strong><br />

the system <strong>of</strong> necessity, <strong>of</strong> its self-foundational character on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> its predicative, apophantic judgement character. Th ere then emerges<br />

the demand for thinking to re-think the logical principle <strong>of</strong> identity<br />

and judgement in such a manner so that through this repetition<br />

freedom itself emerges as system—not as system <strong>of</strong> necessity—but as<br />

free jointure, or constellation, or nexus <strong>of</strong> forces that is open to the<br />

unconditioned character <strong>of</strong> freedom, outside causality and outside<br />

necessity.<br />

Th is task <strong>of</strong> repetition in Schelling’s carrying out the systemic<br />

task <strong>of</strong> freedom leads to the unworking <strong>of</strong> the logical principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> identity and judgement in such a manner that the sovereignty<br />

<strong>of</strong> this metaphysics <strong>of</strong> identity is given itself to freedom, outside<br />

the dominant metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the ‘occident’. Th is is so far as in<br />

Schelling’s thought, the principle <strong>of</strong> judgement and identity is no<br />

longer understood as mere logical principle but as the principle <strong>of</strong>


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 275<br />

the becoming <strong>of</strong> life, as the logic <strong>of</strong> the origin <strong>of</strong> existence itself as<br />

such and as a whole, as a vital principle <strong>of</strong> freedom’s possibility to be<br />

free and not free, as a logic <strong>of</strong> movement and <strong>of</strong> longing with which<br />

created creature and divine life affi rms its own existence, and above<br />

all, as the arising <strong>of</strong> decision out <strong>of</strong> the abyss <strong>of</strong> wager <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

between good and evil itself. Th e self-affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the creaturely<br />

being, whose self-affi rmative character is to be traced back to the<br />

more originary groundlessness <strong>of</strong> freedom, and is irreducible to<br />

the apophantic tracing back <strong>of</strong> the predicative judgement: this self<br />

affi rmative character <strong>of</strong> this creaturely being is distinguished from<br />

‘entities presently given’ and from other beings precisely by virtue <strong>of</strong><br />

its freedom, that is, its utter groundlessness and its infi nite exposure<br />

to the abyss <strong>of</strong> its ground. Th e being that arises as this creaturely<br />

self-affi rmative being in the midst <strong>of</strong> beings as such is born with<br />

the dark fate <strong>of</strong> this abyss which is the condition <strong>of</strong> its eruption and<br />

also the very condition <strong>of</strong> its dissolution.<br />

In this manner the very formal, mechanical, logical principle <strong>of</strong><br />

identity and judgement is released to the movement <strong>of</strong> life, to the<br />

generosity and exuberance <strong>of</strong> freedom—a freedom whose generosity<br />

may even turn into the most terrible form <strong>of</strong> violence—so that with<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> identity and judgement it is not so<br />

much the formal, logical, predicative truth that concerns us, but the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> existence itself and as a whole inasmuch as existence itself is<br />

free, if not according to its genesis, but according to its essence. With<br />

that the dominant metaphysical notion <strong>of</strong> truth—as predicative,<br />

categorical in its formal, propositional structure—is de-structured,<br />

and released beyond its propositional structure unto the structure<br />

as joining, or constellation, or confi guration <strong>of</strong> the principles <strong>of</strong><br />

movements and becoming, the principles <strong>of</strong> life’s exuberant venturing<br />

itself beyond itself, like the bellowing waves <strong>of</strong> the pregnant Sea.<br />

In ancient philosophy, the modern logical distinction between<br />

subject and predicate in judgement is thought as the distinction<br />

between antecedent and consequent. Th e metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong><br />

the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement is, as we know, the principle <strong>of</strong> identity which,<br />

when sought to be reductively totalized in a manner metaphysical, is<br />

reduced to the principle <strong>of</strong> Same. the attempt to think in a more<br />

essential manner the question <strong>of</strong> freedom as event, in its free eruption-


276 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

character, demands unworking <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical foundation<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement, and to think judgement itself in a more originary<br />

manner. In a manner that Heidegger (1969) later deconstructs this<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> identity as Same in order to think in a more originary<br />

manner this principle <strong>of</strong> identity as belonging together rather than<br />

belonging together and thereby releasing diff erence <strong>of</strong> freedom, or<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> diff erence as the unthought <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, Schelling too<br />

deconstructs this principle <strong>of</strong> identity in the logical relation between<br />

antecedent and consequent in judgement in order to release the<br />

event character <strong>of</strong> freedom as diff erence from the logic <strong>of</strong> the Same<br />

by attempting to think identity in a more originary manner, that<br />

means, not in a predicative-categorical manner but existentially.<br />

Schelling grasps such a diff erence as ‘duality without opposition’ that<br />

holds together (while separating each from the other) the principles <strong>of</strong><br />

movement and becoming in a nexus, in a confi guration, in a jointure,<br />

in a constellation which is the nexus as freedom. As such the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom for Schelling touches, not so much the foundational<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement merely, but the event character <strong>of</strong><br />

existence as such. Freedom then, thought in more originary manner,<br />

is essentially question <strong>of</strong> identity as diff erence, necessity as freedom,<br />

system that is free for its own dis-joining and dis-installation.<br />

Freedom as such is life: life as nexus <strong>of</strong> forces, <strong>of</strong> movements and <strong>of</strong><br />

becoming, <strong>of</strong> overfl owing and exuberance, <strong>of</strong> longing’s limitless exposure<br />

to its own limit.<br />

What would then be thought as ‘life’ for Schelling? It is true<br />

that Schelling thought, in a manner that was prevalent in the<br />

philosophical thinking at that time, life organically, in a vitalistic<br />

manner. But what has remained not so explicitly thought in<br />

Schelling, but remained unthought—at least till the time that he<br />

wrote this text—in this term ‘life’ is something like an attempt to<br />

think in a more originary manner the event-character <strong>of</strong> existence, its<br />

free happening and occurring, independently <strong>of</strong> the conditions given<br />

as antecedents: the pre-predicative, pre-categorical, pre-conceptual<br />

truth <strong>of</strong> the arising and disappearing, <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> a movement <strong>of</strong><br />

existence, <strong>of</strong> existence’s eventive apparition in longing and desiring,<br />

its redemptive fulfi lment in loving and forgiveness, <strong>of</strong> the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the appearing <strong>of</strong> evil as countermovement <strong>of</strong> good so that life


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 277<br />

receives love as pure, unconditional gift, so that life may receive the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> its own becoming.<br />

What is ‘life’ for Schelling is this incommensurability, this futurity<br />

present in any hic et nunc, the in-saturation and in excess <strong>of</strong> this<br />

existence, its fi nitude that refuses to close itself at any point <strong>of</strong><br />

‘immanent self-consumption’ (Nancy 1993,p.13), the transcendence<br />

<strong>of</strong> a longing that never rests at any given mode <strong>of</strong> presence but<br />

may extend itself to the extent <strong>of</strong> desiring evil, the in-fi nity at the<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> a fi nite existence, and the eternal melancholy at the infi nite<br />

incompletion <strong>of</strong> existence’s self-presence. What then Schelling<br />

attempts to think with the question <strong>of</strong> freedom is this freeing <strong>of</strong> this<br />

life character <strong>of</strong> event (or, the event character <strong>of</strong> life) from various<br />

sorts conditioned mode <strong>of</strong> self-presence, from any closure <strong>of</strong> necessity<br />

and causality so that life be free, and freedom may acquire life: that<br />

means, life’s element <strong>of</strong> surprise and its unpredictable arrival <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wholly other coming that may redeem life, and give over suff ering<br />

to its redemptive happiness. Life in its manifestation <strong>of</strong> itself is the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> freedom; it is free to its own future without which life would<br />

only be mechanical product out <strong>of</strong> necessity but not free occurring<br />

itself.<br />

Let us come back to Schelling’s diff erential repetition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

metaphysics in respect to the logic <strong>of</strong> judgement. If the metaphysical<br />

principle—which is that <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> identity, <strong>of</strong> ground<br />

and reason—is not to be reductively totalized into the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

Same, then a belonging together, an ungrounding diff erence is to be<br />

introduced at the heart <strong>of</strong> identity. More originarily understood,<br />

the principle <strong>of</strong> identity will then be the thought <strong>of</strong> diff erence as<br />

belonging together, as in a constellation or assemblage, a montage—<strong>of</strong><br />

antecedents and consequents. In that sense diff erence—which is none<br />

but the movement <strong>of</strong> freedom—would precisely demand identity<br />

and the system, more originarily understood, a system and identity<br />

that is no longer the principle <strong>of</strong> the Same, but the logic <strong>of</strong> hiatus,<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dehiscence, <strong>of</strong> an originary cut or cision (which later Schelling<br />

calls Scheidung in his Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World), a spacing—which is none<br />

other than the spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom, or freedom as spacing. It is this<br />

diff erence <strong>of</strong> identity which sets free, releases the consequent from<br />

the antecedent (if not according to its genesis, but according to its


278 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

essence), and thereby enabling the consequent, conditioned, fi nite<br />

existence to have a life <strong>of</strong> its own essential nature, to have an infi nite,<br />

unconditioned freedom <strong>of</strong> becoming and decision between good and<br />

evil.<br />

As such, the principle <strong>of</strong> identity—understood in the manner<br />

discussed above as the spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom—is not same as Same. In the<br />

next chapter while discussing Heidegger’s discussing <strong>of</strong> the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> Identity we shall be able to articulate how identity understood as<br />

jointure is precisely the question <strong>of</strong> freedom, which thereby cannot<br />

be reductively understood as the principle <strong>of</strong> Same. Th erefore the<br />

logical relation between the antecedent and consequent is no longer to<br />

be thought as that <strong>of</strong> Same, but rather as that <strong>of</strong> diff erence as identity,<br />

diff erance <strong>of</strong> identity, as spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom. Discussing Spinoza’s<br />

logical relation <strong>of</strong> antecedent and consequent as one that between<br />

infi nite substance (=A) and infi nite substance as one <strong>of</strong> its modes,<br />

which is consequent <strong>of</strong> that infi nite substance (= A/a), Schelling<br />

argues,<br />

Th en that which is positive in A/a is, indeed, A. But it does not follow<br />

on this account that A/a=A, i.e. that infi nite Substance regarded<br />

in its consequences is to be considered exactly the same as infi nite<br />

Substance as such. (Schelling 1936, p.16)<br />

Th ough the consequent as fi nite, conditioned, creaturely existent is<br />

dependent in regard to its genesis to the antecedent that does not<br />

determine the essential nature <strong>of</strong> that existent. Th erefore in regard to<br />

its own essential being, the conditioned, fi nite, creaturely existence<br />

is free without condition, for only so far an existent is fi nite,<br />

conditioned, creaturely (in regard to its genesis) can it be free without<br />

condition, without any pre-given, pre-determined closure <strong>of</strong> archè-<br />

telos, that its freedom can touch the an-archic.,<br />

But dependence does not exclude autonomy or even freedom.<br />

Dependence does not determine the nature <strong>of</strong> the dependent, but<br />

merely declares that the dependent entity, whatever else that may be,<br />

can only be as a consequent <strong>of</strong> that upon which it is dependent; it does<br />

not declare what this dependent is or not. Every organic individual,<br />

ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it has come into being, is dependent upon another organism<br />

with respect to its genesis but not at all with regard to its essential<br />

being. (Ibid., p. 18)


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 279<br />

Th ere are few things that must be said immediately here. First<br />

there is something like an-archic about freedom that arises from<br />

the spacing-character, in that freedom’s exuberance is precisely<br />

that ex-sists any closure or totality determined by the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

archè-logy and teleology. Secondly freedom must be freed from any<br />

genetic condition, or from any metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> becoming on the basis <strong>of</strong> ‘emanation’, or ‘generation’.<br />

To understand freedom’s movement in relation to its event character, we<br />

shall use ‘origin’ which is to be distinguished from ‘genesis’, ‘emanation’<br />

and ‘generation’. Schelling, however, never uses the word ‘origin’, but<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘becoming’ which he distinguishes from any philosophy<br />

<strong>of</strong> emanation and generational process as the privation <strong>of</strong> a full,<br />

perfect being, for they all lead to the concept <strong>of</strong> immanence. Schelling<br />

says,<br />

First, the concept <strong>of</strong> immanence is completely to be set aside ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as it is meant to express a dead conceptual inclusion <strong>of</strong> things in God.<br />

We recognize, rather, that the concept <strong>of</strong> becoming is the only one<br />

adequate to the nature <strong>of</strong> things. (Ibid., p. 33)<br />

Th e concept <strong>of</strong> immanence as the logic <strong>of</strong> movement is inadequate<br />

enough to express the vitality <strong>of</strong> freedom’s self-affi rmation. Th is is so<br />

in so far as freedom is life, and life is freedom, the event-character<br />

<strong>of</strong> its spacing lays in its non-in-sistence in its genesis. Th is non-insistence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the genesis alone grants or bestows to the freedom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

creaturely, fi nite, and conditioned being its life. Th is alone, according<br />

to Schelling, explains the possibility <strong>of</strong> the human freedom which is<br />

not one possibility among others but the possibility <strong>of</strong> life, whose<br />

possibility cannot be explained by any predicates, attributes, properties<br />

or facts, but by that factuality, or facticity alone that existence is that<br />

which ex-sists, that non-in-sists, that transcends from all immanence<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-consuming predicates, from all closure <strong>of</strong> necessity and from<br />

the causality <strong>of</strong> the genesis, from the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Same. It is this non-insistence <strong>of</strong> freedom frees the consequent from<br />

the antecedent, not concerning the genesis <strong>of</strong> consequent in relation to<br />

antecedent, but regarding its essential being, that is, its essential exsistent<br />

character from any immanent condition. Freedom, regarded<br />

in this manner, is freedom from all immanence. As such freedom is<br />

trans-immanence; and as trans-immanence, freedom is life.


280 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Schelling never speaks <strong>of</strong> this non-in-sistence <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> life,<br />

and <strong>of</strong> the life <strong>of</strong> freedom, but this un-thought that we teased out<br />

<strong>of</strong> Schelling’s text, out <strong>of</strong> our repetition <strong>of</strong> Schelling, grants the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s thought its own life. From this un-thought<br />

we allow freedom to come to life in its non-in-sistence, which is life’s<br />

event as coming to presence to itself as life. Life is that which non-in-sists<br />

in its genesis. In this non-in-sistence, life allows itself to feel the tremor <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality, <strong>of</strong> death. It sacrifi ces itself for the sake <strong>of</strong> the freedom <strong>of</strong> this<br />

non-in-sistence, for the sake <strong>of</strong> this non-in-sistence <strong>of</strong> freedom. Since<br />

this non-in-sistence alone explains life’s eventive freedom character<br />

and since this non-in-sistence is dear to life more than anything else,<br />

it goes for the sake <strong>of</strong> non-in-sistence to the point <strong>of</strong> going against<br />

itself, to the point <strong>of</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> this freedom, so that in this extreme<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> negating freedom it can assert freedom in its extreme<br />

possibility, which is the possibility <strong>of</strong> a radical evil. Th is explains the<br />

possibility and actuality <strong>of</strong> evil in freedom.<br />

Freedom is the non-insistence in immanence, and it is non-insistence<br />

in the antecedent. As non-insistence in antecedent, the consequent is free,<br />

and not mere ‘consequent’: it now has a life <strong>of</strong> its own, its free fl owing<br />

abundance and plenitude so that as life, it freely calls for itself new<br />

inauguration for itself, new beginning after each end, last after every<br />

and each last. In this sense a free being, even the fi nite mortal being,<br />

has a relation to a time outside time, to a time outside all presence and<br />

all self-presence <strong>of</strong> the Subject. In other words, it has an intimation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a time beyond time 1 . a free Subject is no Subject, if Subject is<br />

the name for that which grounds itself in its self-presence so that<br />

the Subject can be beside itself. Between the Subject and its ground<br />

there is already always a distance <strong>of</strong> spacing which is the yawning<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom. It is freedom itself that spaces open this distance so<br />

that the Subject can be near to itself. Th erefore Subject is the name<br />

not <strong>of</strong> that which grounds itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> its self-presence and<br />

autochthony. It is rather the denomination <strong>of</strong> that which is opened<br />

by the spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom, the consequent that is freed and is released<br />

by freedom itself from its antecedent, though not according to its<br />

genesis but according to its essence. Th erefore judgement—as the<br />

relation between antecedent and consequent—belongs to freedom,<br />

and not vice versa. Only to the extent that judgement is free—to the<br />

disjoining <strong>of</strong> itself—it is judgement itself. Th e judgement character


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 281<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement is its freedom for disjunction, for caesura, for disinstallation.<br />

Here one can see Schelling’s unworking <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom from inside. Freedom as irreducible diff erence, as irreducible<br />

disjunction makes any speculative unity <strong>of</strong> the metaphysical Subject<br />

impossible. Th e judgement is already always torn apart by freedom<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone there can be something like—identity,<br />

as holding together <strong>of</strong> duality, a duality therefore that cannot be<br />

reduced to opposition, but to be understood as jointure or nexus,<br />

<strong>of</strong> what Schelling (2000) calls Zusammenhang. What is brought<br />

out, in a manner <strong>of</strong> Hölderlin’s introducing caesura at the heart <strong>of</strong><br />

the Speculative unity 2 a distinction unheard, a distinction that is<br />

going to set <strong>of</strong>f the whole project <strong>of</strong> German Idealism in an entirely<br />

diff erent direction, that is its own unworking <strong>of</strong> itself, the distinction<br />

that has introduced such irreparable, un-sublatable, un-groundable<br />

and inappropriable caesura or dehiscence—in so far as this is the<br />

distinction <strong>of</strong> freedom and not <strong>of</strong> necessity—is the distinction<br />

between ‘ Being ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it exists, and Being ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is the mere<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> existence’ (Schelling 1936, p. 31).<br />

Schelling’ distinction between ‘ Being ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it exists, and<br />

Being ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is the mere basis <strong>of</strong> existence’ (Ibid.) is a distinction<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, and not the distinction <strong>of</strong> necessity in the form <strong>of</strong><br />

predicative, propositional truth, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as this distinction concerns<br />

life’s eventive character and not <strong>of</strong> inert, mechanical abstraction.<br />

Since this distinction pertains to existence’ coming to itself as free<br />

coming, there is the possibility <strong>of</strong> dissolution, <strong>of</strong> disjunction or disjoining<br />

<strong>of</strong> the bond, <strong>of</strong> the jointure between that which is the mere<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> existence and the existent itself so that the Being in so far as it<br />

exists, may exist freely, independently <strong>of</strong> the ground even though it<br />

arises from this ground. Schelling extends this vitality <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

even to God in so far this God is not mere postulate, neither mere<br />

logical necessity, nor a conceptual abstraction, but a living God,<br />

longing and loving, suff ering and redeeming. within God too there<br />

is an irreducible cision, cut, (Scheidung), a distinction, a diff erence,<br />

a duality without opposition, a dis-joining <strong>of</strong> a jointure, a caesura <strong>of</strong><br />

an identity, a dehiscence <strong>of</strong> a hinge, a spacing <strong>of</strong> an abyss between<br />

God ‘in so as it exists’, and God which is the ‘mere basis <strong>of</strong> [his]<br />

existence’. Schelling’s God is not the God as mere abstraction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Idealists but a free, releasing God who is, for that matter, not abstract


282 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

system nor a totality but a life. Only as living God can be free to<br />

his own becoming; similarly, only because he is free, can he become<br />

diff erent, transcendent in relation to the inner basis <strong>of</strong> his existence.<br />

He is therefore living God, and that he is free for his own coming<br />

to existence. Th e source <strong>of</strong> life in God is God’s vital distinction or<br />

diff erence between God in so far as the inner basis <strong>of</strong> his existence and<br />

God that coming to presence to himself as this existing, actualized<br />

God. in God himself there is an opening out <strong>of</strong> himself, a spacing<br />

out <strong>of</strong> himself, a tearing asunder <strong>of</strong> himself, an outside <strong>of</strong> himself<br />

in longing where in this free space God himself give birth to itself<br />

. God’s Freedom also operates as the logic <strong>of</strong> origin: there in God<br />

himself arises the movement <strong>of</strong> longing to give birth to himself. It is<br />

the beginning <strong>of</strong> God’s becoming <strong>of</strong> himself, ‘the God begotten God’<br />

(Ibid., p. 35).<br />

Schelling sees freedom’s logic <strong>of</strong> origin as the partitioning <strong>of</strong> forces<br />

so that out <strong>of</strong> this diff erential, out <strong>of</strong> unhinging, out <strong>of</strong> (de)cision<br />

something comes to presence. one can say, following Schelling,<br />

that the event <strong>of</strong> freedom arises as the diff erential logic <strong>of</strong> origin<br />

that singularizes, individuates life as this life and no other, which<br />

as this singular for the fi rst time opens itself to itself and to others.<br />

Freedom is that at once diff erentiating and singularizing <strong>of</strong> the origin<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world, <strong>of</strong> Divine being and created existence. What we call<br />

life is the movement that in existing interminably diff erentiates and<br />

individuates at the same time. Life is none but movement singular<br />

multiple (or multiple singular). Since the distinction between ground<br />

and existence is a distinction <strong>of</strong> freedom and not <strong>of</strong> necessity, where<br />

the distinction is also identity as holding together, joining together<br />

(Zusammenhang), fi guring together, the free operation <strong>of</strong> what<br />

arrives as singular, individuated (Schelling calls particular will) does<br />

not prohibit the eternal remainder <strong>of</strong> the ground as universal Will<br />

to operate itself freely. All life is Zusammenhang, all life is a nexus<br />

(constellation/confi guration/jointure/ holding-together as holding<br />

apart) <strong>of</strong> principles/wills/forces. God’s life is also a jointure, a bond,<br />

apart from this distinction from the created being: that while this<br />

jointure is indissoluble in God, it is dissoluble in the mortals. It is<br />

this dissolubility <strong>of</strong> the bond, <strong>of</strong> the jointure, <strong>of</strong> the confi guration<br />

that explains, according to Schelling, while evil can be actual only in<br />

mortal, but not in divine life.


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 283<br />

Since life that manifests itself as becoming, it passes through stages<br />

from nature to Spirit where the jointure/ nexus appears again and<br />

again in new form, ever new jointure as free jointure that is free to<br />

be (free, or) not free. while this jointure appears at the stage <strong>of</strong> life’s<br />

becoming as nature as the jointure <strong>of</strong> the principles <strong>of</strong> darkness and<br />

light, so this jointure appears again in the stage <strong>of</strong> life’s becoming as<br />

Spirit as the jointure between the Wills—the Will <strong>of</strong> the Deep as<br />

particular Will and on the other hand, the Universal Will. As jointure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the two is not speculative unity <strong>of</strong> the Subject but Spirit’s revelation<br />

as Word which as such is the jointure <strong>of</strong> vowel and consonant.<br />

jointure—and not (Speculative, conceptual) unity—is not reason’s<br />

/Subject’s self-actualization as Absolute Concept; but this jointure<br />

is revelation <strong>of</strong> actual God to man that remains inappropriable to<br />

man. With this one stroke <strong>of</strong> genius Schelling’s already exposes the<br />

System <strong>of</strong> a Speculative Idealism to its limit, that life’s origin (in so<br />

far it is ‘life’) refers back to an ‘un-pre-thinkable’ (Unvordenkliche)<br />

manifestation, or revelation that reason cannot trace back, cannot<br />

appropriate as its own ground, that no predicate <strong>of</strong> reason can apply<br />

to it.<br />

Th is is the very ground <strong>of</strong> freedom, in so far as this ground excludes<br />

all grounding and appropriation, all predication and foundation, all<br />

subjectivity and objectivity, all categories <strong>of</strong> reason and irrational.<br />

It is the irreducible outside <strong>of</strong> all ground, and yet which alone is<br />

the condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> any grounding at all. As such the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> freedom is an irreducible diff erence: it is the diff erence <strong>of</strong> all<br />

diff erence and diff erence to all identities. A diff erence unheard: wholly<br />

otherwise diff erence that is the spacing <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th is diff erence<br />

is the groundless (Abgrund). It is, preceding all conditions, and<br />

remaining after all condition, is pure actuality without possibility,<br />

pure transcendence without transcendent. It is the unconditioned<br />

that enables all acts <strong>of</strong> beginning, <strong>of</strong> all beginning <strong>of</strong> all existence as<br />

such. Schelling says,<br />

Th e essence <strong>of</strong> the basis, or <strong>of</strong> existence, can only be precedent to<br />

all basis, that is, the absolute viewed directly, the groundless. But, as<br />

has been shown, it cannot be this in any other way than by dividing<br />

into two equally eternal beginnings, not that it is both at the at same<br />

time but that it is in both in the same way, as the whole in each, or a<br />

unique essence. But the groundless divides itself into the two equally


284 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

eternal beginnings only in order that the two which could not be in<br />

it as groundless at the same time, or there be one, should become one<br />

through love. (Ibid., pp.88-9)<br />

Th is ground that precedes all grounds, the abyss that remains<br />

irreducible to whatever comes to exist as conditioned is none other<br />

than the groundlessness <strong>of</strong> freedom itself, which as such is more<br />

originary than reason or its opposite irrational. Neither reason nor<br />

irrational, is freedom their in-diff erence. Th is abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom fi rst<br />

<strong>of</strong> all before any fi rst, in a past immemorial, and in a remaining<br />

future un-anticipatable, grants all that arrives the free gift <strong>of</strong> birth.<br />

As ‘un-pre-thinkable’ basis before all basis, it fi rst <strong>of</strong> all bestows the<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> basis and existence and precisely because it is destination from<br />

where gift arrives, it remains inappropriable and unconditional. It is<br />

because this basis before all basis remains as un-thinkable, thought is<br />

always—even the thought <strong>of</strong> freedom—is indebted thinking.<br />

Th inking in indebted to the unthinkable, for it is the un-thinkable<br />

that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all bestows upon thinking its nobility and dignity, its<br />

beauty and joy. It is because there always remains this basis before<br />

all basis, there also remains hope for redemptive fulfi lment and joy,<br />

however radical evil is, however terrible, devouring and malicious<br />

is evil’s all consuming desire to conquer everything.<br />

With the help <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s notion <strong>of</strong> an ‘un-pre-thinkable’<br />

remainder <strong>of</strong> (non) basis before all basis, what is introduced here<br />

is the unconditional, ever remaining promise <strong>of</strong> redemption for<br />

mortal which always remains, eternally, because it already always has<br />

dispropriated man from all power, force and the gaze <strong>of</strong> law. What<br />

ex-sists outside the law, outside appropriation and power, outside<br />

totality and system, outside the force <strong>of</strong> the negative, and outside all<br />

basis is this pure promise <strong>of</strong> redemptive fulfi lment that exceeds all <strong>of</strong><br />

man’s power <strong>of</strong> actualization and realization. Because it is beginning<br />

prior to all beginning, it is thereby the principle <strong>of</strong> beginning and<br />

inauguration. Evil is that will <strong>of</strong> the lawlessness that ceaselessly<br />

attempts to assume the law; it is that will <strong>of</strong> the non-being which<br />

interminably attempts to attain being; it is that non-yet-actuality that<br />

endlessly attempts to seize actuality. But a basis before evil precedes<br />

and follows evil. Th is un-groundable, while dispropriating man from


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 285<br />

all ground, alone gifts the mortal the most paradisiacal gift, which is<br />

that <strong>of</strong> redemption itself.<br />

What Schelling discovers, at the heart <strong>of</strong> the jointure <strong>of</strong> forces and<br />

<strong>of</strong> principles is the Abgrund which is the condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the jointure or system. As a result, as the condition <strong>of</strong> possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the holding-together, the Abyss remains the outside, the excluded,<br />

which refuses all name, all concepts, all categorical grasp, and all acts<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aufhebung (sublation). Th e system <strong>of</strong> system, then, bereft <strong>of</strong> any<br />

speculative Unity or centre does not coincide at any point, for the<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> this jointure itself remains outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> all totality, all system, all recuperation and grounding. Human<br />

freedom consists, therefore, according to Schelling, in that abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

the opening, or spacing which cannot be thought as Unity. Out <strong>of</strong><br />

this chasm emerges the diff erentiable and dissoluble nexus which is<br />

freedom’s self-realization in de-cision, for de-cision (between good<br />

and evil) to be possible, the jointure has to be free to be dis-joined;<br />

the system has to be free to give over to the possibility <strong>of</strong> dissolution.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> this decision which cannot be calculated, programmed, or<br />

predicated beforehand, but that arises, erupts, occurs as in a leap over<br />

a yawning abyss, there now emerges the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil and good.<br />

Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> good and evil in the fi nitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortal condition, as the creature’s self-assertion as particular<br />

Will, which as this particular Will should remain in the Deep, in the<br />

ground as particular. Since human condition is fi nite—means, its<br />

condition, its source, its origin is outside <strong>of</strong> itself as inappropriable<br />

transcendence—there remains the possibility <strong>of</strong> the dissolution <strong>of</strong><br />

the Wills. Hence the particular Will in its self-assertion can claim<br />

itself to be total, Universal, Absolute. In this all-consuming lust <strong>of</strong><br />

the particular Will to reach Totality, in this all devouring hunger <strong>of</strong><br />

non-Being to attain Being, there lies the possibility <strong>of</strong> the dissolution<br />

<strong>of</strong> the nexus, the dis-joining <strong>of</strong> the jointure <strong>of</strong> Wills. Evil is therefore<br />

neither Being nor non-Being, neither Totality nor particular, but<br />

non-Being’s all consuming hunger for Being, the particular Will’s<br />

endless lust to reach the Totality, which happens out <strong>of</strong> the fi nite<br />

freedom, or out <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> freedom, out <strong>of</strong> the dissoluble<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the jointure so that there can be inversion <strong>of</strong> wills, <strong>of</strong><br />

forces, <strong>of</strong> principles. Th e dark principle which should remain in the<br />

centre as mere basis, as mere possibility, as mere non-Being, lusts to


286 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

arrive at totality, at Being, at Actuality so that the nexus, the jointure<br />

is diseased, corrupted. Th is corruption or disease <strong>of</strong> will is evil.<br />

What is then evil? Evil is the particular Will’s all consuming<br />

desire to abandon the nameless to attain the Name as Absolute.<br />

It is that all devouring lust to abandon the non-yet-Being to<br />

attain Being as Absolute, to abandon the non-yet-predicative to<br />

attain the Absolute as Absolute Predicate. It is the Will’s desire<br />

to totalize itself completely without remainder, or rather, it is the<br />

lust to include each and every exclusion by naming each and every<br />

Unnameable, by predicating each and every un-predicative. In<br />

other words, evil is particular will’s attempts at self-foundation<br />

and thereby attempting at its own self-abnegation, since its very<br />

condition lies in the non-foundation, in ‘the irreducible remainder’<br />

which as such is without name, without predicate, and without<br />

Being or non-Being. Evil does not have a foundation <strong>of</strong> its own,<br />

and therefore it is this terrible, malicious, jealous lust to found<br />

itself, to ground itself, while there ought to remain that ‘irreducible<br />

remainder’, that Not Yet, that non-foundation . Th e task <strong>of</strong> the act<br />

<strong>of</strong> creative freedom lies, therefore, in the abandonment <strong>of</strong> this evil’s<br />

abandonment <strong>of</strong> the nameless, in the abandonment <strong>of</strong> the evil’s<br />

abandonment <strong>of</strong> the un-predicative, unnameable, the not yet, so<br />

that through this abandonment <strong>of</strong> abandonment there remains—<br />

that non-foundation, that unnameable, that un-predicative, the<br />

Not, the remnant, the groundless (Abgrund), the unconditioned.<br />

Th is Not Yet as the ‘irreducible remainder’ <strong>of</strong> fi nite, human condition<br />

is the highest task <strong>of</strong> free thinking which is to open itself to the<br />

unconditioned. Th e whole project <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s entire life time’s<br />

exhaustion <strong>of</strong> thought has never been anything other than this:<br />

to think the highest, the utmost, the summit <strong>of</strong> thinking which is<br />

for that matter its limit. To think each time is to be exposed to a<br />

condition that can never be founded in any conditioned foundation,<br />

that can never be named in any name, that can never be predicated<br />

in any predication, that can never be appropriated in any ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason, simply because it is the event <strong>of</strong> naming itself, <strong>of</strong> naming<br />

coming to presence to itself, and it is, above all, the event itself, not<br />

this or that event, but the freedom <strong>of</strong> event, or, the event <strong>of</strong> freedom.


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 287<br />

Th erefore Schelling has to fail, over and over again, to complete any<br />

and each <strong>of</strong> his systems because what he wanted is none but the<br />

system <strong>of</strong> freedom itself, the system that is destined to be abandoned<br />

by freedom so that system never reaches at any point an absolute selfactualization<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself. In Schelling’s thinking not only mortals and<br />

Gods, but even the system itself turns to be veiled by indestructible,<br />

unappeasable, unnameable originary mournfulness. Th is originary<br />

mournfulness lies in the mortal’s originary non-power/noncapability/non-possibility<br />

to appropriate his own condition, to make<br />

his own ground his ‘own’, his ‘proper’, his ‘property’, since freedom<br />

grants him, loans to him, gifts him beforehand as an inappropriable,<br />

un-foundable origin <strong>of</strong> a gift.<br />

Freedom can never be a property for man, though man’s particular<br />

Will attempts to appropriate freedom as its creaturely self-assertion,<br />

which is evil. Th erefore human freedom is essentially fi nite freedom<br />

which, while it is the source <strong>of</strong> man’s ‘veil <strong>of</strong> sadness’ (Ibid., p.79),<br />

it is also thereby the possibility <strong>of</strong> the Not Yet redemptive, messianic<br />

fulfi lment and acts <strong>of</strong> joyous creation. Th e freedom for mortal is that<br />

fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens the world for him and reveals him to the rest <strong>of</strong> the<br />

created existence. Th erefore freedom is essentially revelation which as<br />

such is more originary than man’s free power to act and transform the<br />

given world through his power <strong>of</strong> negation. Th erefore Schelling too,<br />

like Heidegger following, thinks freedom in a more originary manner<br />

as spacing-open, or manifesting the world on the (non)basis <strong>of</strong> which<br />

man founds his historical world. Freedom’s unconditional exposure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mortal to the world and language is not to be exhausted by<br />

the language <strong>of</strong> the world, but this is not a mere limitation, but a<br />

limitation that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all limitlessly exposes the mortals to name, by<br />

gifting him this possibility to name itself. Th e originary melancholy<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> fi nite existent that Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> is not due to<br />

a lost origin but to an eff aced <strong>of</strong> origin, a withdrawal <strong>of</strong> ground, an<br />

abandonment <strong>of</strong> power/ force/ gaze <strong>of</strong> mastery. It is on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

this abandonment alone is the mortal free, for as free being alone<br />

may he speak, live, and creates the world.<br />

As possibility <strong>of</strong> evil, but also the possibility <strong>of</strong> redemptive<br />

fulfi lment, freedom is the wager <strong>of</strong> existence. Th erefore freedom always<br />

appears as event, since all event is a wager, the possibility <strong>of</strong> deciding,<br />

happening, occurring, erupting something wholly otherwise which


288 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

cannot be programmed, calculated, anticipated beforehand. At each<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> freedom, existence exposes itself to its limit to infi nity,<br />

to the whole <strong>of</strong> the possible at once. Th e decision <strong>of</strong> existence arises<br />

therefore not out <strong>of</strong> calculations and predications but out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

undecidable, out <strong>of</strong> an infi nite host <strong>of</strong> wager. To appropriate this<br />

wager and undecidable <strong>of</strong> freedom itself assumes the terrible faces <strong>of</strong><br />

evil and destruction. With this ‘irreducible remainder’ <strong>of</strong> wager and<br />

the undecidable, the possibility <strong>of</strong> evil itself remains there as eternal<br />

possibility, but only as possibility; it becomes actualized only when<br />

out <strong>of</strong> decision existent decides to wholly appropriate the wager and<br />

undecidable character <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th erefore to maintain the wager <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom and its undecidable is the highest, at the same time the most<br />

strenuous, the most diffi cult, the impossible ethico-political task <strong>of</strong><br />

our time which itself is task <strong>of</strong> wagering when each time there arises<br />

out <strong>of</strong> freedom the necessity to assume decision out <strong>of</strong> undecidable.<br />

If evil is the decision to appropriate the originary dispropriation,<br />

then the appropriation <strong>of</strong> this appropriation is an event <strong>of</strong> decision<br />

which each time demands that we wage, not between one decidable<br />

and another, one name and the other, one predication and another,<br />

one act <strong>of</strong> foundation and another, but between the decision and<br />

undecidable, between the naming and the unnameable, between<br />

the demands <strong>of</strong> predication and the unconditional demand <strong>of</strong> the<br />

un-predictable, between the conditioned realization as this politics<br />

and this ethics and the unconditional, between the conditioned<br />

this or that event and event as such, irreducible to any this or that<br />

conditioned event that is destined to pass away. What the philosopher<br />

Jacques Derrida calls aporia is this thinking itself as decision, and as<br />

waging that each time adheres itself to decision.<br />

What Heidegger calls ‘the event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’ (1969) is<br />

none but this appropriation <strong>of</strong> appropriation which appropriating<br />

appropriation, delivers, abandons the mortals to his originary<br />

dispropriation. Th en another destiny, another inauguration or<br />

inception, another task for mortals begins on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constellation, or confi guration, <strong>of</strong> the belonging-together as<br />

ontological diff erence. Th is constellation <strong>of</strong> ontological diff erence is<br />

itself the donation <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th e ‘event <strong>of</strong> appropriation’ (Ereignis)<br />

is this attempt to remember that originary dispropriation, withdrawal<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being, or abandonment on the abyssal basis <strong>of</strong> which alone there


Th e Irreducible Remainder • 289<br />

is for mortals a redemptive future. But this is not the work <strong>of</strong> man<br />

which man can create out <strong>of</strong> his own possibility, capacity and power,<br />

but itself must be freely given as pure gift <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

Schelling’s pr<strong>of</strong>ound infl uence on Heidegger is marked by acute<br />

thinkers and readers. For Schelling however, unlike Heidegger,<br />

freedom’s principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration is always love. Love is archè<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, but an archè that arrives after each and every end,<br />

and therefore it is also last <strong>of</strong> the last. Th erefore love is so redeeming.<br />

Permeating all throughout existence, love is the eventive presentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom in existence. Its redeeming presentation in our existence<br />

is not in the manner <strong>of</strong> necessity’s closure, not in any manner <strong>of</strong><br />

evil’s ‘immanent self-consumption’ (Nancy 1993, p.13), but in a<br />

discontinuous presentation which is the pure transcendence <strong>of</strong> love.<br />

As discontinuous presentation in each presence, in each hic et nunc<br />

love thereby makes each hic et nunc unconditionally transcend itself,<br />

and makes each hic et nunc eternal, paradisiacal, redemptive, happy,<br />

joyous. Love’s joyous presentation in its loving jointure, in its ever<br />

renewed constellation at each hic et nunc cannot be understood on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the subject,<br />

but rather as unconditional free giving itself as unity <strong>of</strong> dualities,<br />

as loving ‘belonging-together’ rather than belonging-together’, as<br />

diff erential principle <strong>of</strong> unity. Schelling writes,<br />

Th is is the secret <strong>of</strong> love, that it unites such beings as could each<br />

exist in itself, and nonetheless neither is nor can be without the other.<br />

Th erefore as duality comes to be in the groundless, there also comes<br />

to be love, which combines the existent (Ideal) with the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

existence. (Ibid., p.89).<br />

Love’s diff erential unity, since it is more ancient than anything, which<br />

is there even before good and evil, is not an arrival as mere consequent<br />

to evil, but rather otherwise. Th e diff erence between event and evil<br />

is not just that <strong>of</strong> the inversion <strong>of</strong> the principles. It is more radical<br />

than that. While evil borrows its appearance <strong>of</strong> being from event, the<br />

event does not need to borrow its existent character from evil. Event<br />

is rather that it frees what is still positive in evil and gives it to the<br />

unconditional affi rmation <strong>of</strong> another inauguration, since the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom is none other than the principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration. In this<br />

manner the particular Will is transfi gured into love; or, rather love


290 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

appropriates it and redeems it. If philosophy arises out <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

it is ins<strong>of</strong>ar as philosophy is already ‘love <strong>of</strong> wisdom’ (Philo-Sophia).<br />

As such philosophy always carries when it is not reduced to totalizing<br />

metaphysics, the most ancient promise <strong>of</strong> a redemptive, messianic<br />

fulfi lment. Th ere is no such thing as ‘philosophy <strong>of</strong> freedom’, for<br />

philosophy is already the gift that arises freely, the gift <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

itself. Th e task <strong>of</strong> thinking is to listen to this promise in the face <strong>of</strong><br />

various totalizing attempts <strong>of</strong> metaphysics so as to abandon thinking<br />

to its freedom itself.


§ Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom<br />

Th is chapter attempts to examine Heidegger’s dealing with the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> freedom in his lecture course on Th e Essence <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

Freedom. Taking Heidegger’s destructive reading <strong>of</strong> Kant as point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure, the chapter in a Heideggerian manner attempts to think<br />

freedom in a more originary manner: not as man’s property, but the<br />

unconditional opening, or possibility <strong>of</strong> existence itself as such. In<br />

this sense freedom is the event <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> existence itself<br />

which breaks through in man who is essentially fi nite and mortal.<br />

Man grounded in this manner in freedom is open to the ground<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own existence in so far as he is the ‘most fi nite <strong>of</strong> all being’.<br />

Finitude is not an impossibility <strong>of</strong> freedom but the possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

existence itself. Freedom is no longer thought here as man’s will to<br />

determine itself on its own ground, but freedom as the groundless site<br />

<strong>of</strong> history’s inauguration and is irreducible to any causality, whether<br />

transcendental causality or practical causality <strong>of</strong> Kantian type. As the<br />

groundless condition <strong>of</strong> the mortal’s event <strong>of</strong> existence, freedom is<br />

not one question <strong>of</strong> amongst others but the question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude itself<br />

out <strong>of</strong> which existence erupts. Th is event <strong>of</strong> freedom, understood, is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> leap from the grounding principle <strong>of</strong> reason, even if it is<br />

practical reason and the principle <strong>of</strong> causality to the un-groundable<br />

event <strong>of</strong> inauguration <strong>of</strong> fi nite history itself.<br />

*<br />

Human freedom now no longer means freedom as a property <strong>of</strong> man,<br />

but man as a possibility <strong>of</strong> freedom. Human freedom is the freedom<br />

that breaks through in man and takes him up into itself, making man


292 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

possible. If freedom is the ground <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> understanding<br />

being in its whole breath and fullness, then man, as grounded in his<br />

existence upon and in this freedom is the site where beings in the<br />

whole become revealed, i.e. he is that particular being through which<br />

being as such announce themselves.<br />

Heidegger (2005, pp. 94-95)<br />

The No-Thing <strong>of</strong> Freedom and the Finitude <strong>of</strong> Man<br />

Any attempt to think freedom essentially must begin with the<br />

spacing, or opening that is opened by the works <strong>of</strong> Heidegger.<br />

Free from the systemic task <strong>of</strong> freedom—that means, freedom<br />

understood as the ideal <strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>of</strong> ground and foundation <strong>of</strong><br />

being (that is, from onto-theology <strong>of</strong> any type), or freedom in its<br />

own specifi c, non-phenomenal causality irreducible to any cognitive<br />

or conceptual determination, or even as free will <strong>of</strong> the ‘human’ (as<br />

if freedom were man’s property)—Heidegger’ deconstruction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dominant metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and foundation has freed,<br />

released, opened the space <strong>of</strong> freedom to that which fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens,<br />

manifests, reveals, un-conceals the world and the entirety <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

to the mortals on the basis <strong>of</strong> his essential fi nitude, that means, on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> a non-basis or the groundlessness. For Heidegger freedom<br />

is no longer reason’s self-grounding act or self-unifying act on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, but rather is the event <strong>of</strong> existence as such.<br />

Th e facticity <strong>of</strong> existence itself is nothing else but arises out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> the facticity <strong>of</strong> freedom itself: freedom’s existence is fi rst <strong>of</strong><br />

all a fact. Th is facticity concerns Dasein’s free open-ness towards<br />

its own abyss, to its own nothingness, to its own impossibility and<br />

groundlessness, towards the event <strong>of</strong> closure that at once releases<br />

this closure to its impossibility, namely, its inalienable fi nitude.<br />

Th erefore for Dasein, as Heidegger recounts in Being and <strong>Time</strong>, death<br />

always appears as an unenclosed futurity even at the moment <strong>of</strong> its<br />

imminent arrival, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it presents itself as, or appears itself as<br />

impossibility, as no-thing, as non-phenomenal arriving, a non-present<br />

presentation, precisely because death presents itself purely without<br />

reserve. If the existentiality <strong>of</strong> Dasein’s existence concerns, not so<br />

much with any ‘given presence’ (Vorhandenheit) but with the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> a non-phenomenal arriving, then this free opening is none but the


Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom • 293<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> futurity <strong>of</strong> existence, <strong>of</strong> existence’s event character, ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as Dasein’s existence is already always a ‘to come’, understanding this<br />

coming in the infi nitude <strong>of</strong> its verbal resonance, and not in the manner<br />

<strong>of</strong> Vorhandenheit, <strong>of</strong> entities ‘presently given’. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as Dasein is not<br />

to be understood as the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and therefore, its<br />

essence is not the essence <strong>of</strong> acting and positing, Dasein’s no-thing is<br />

to be distinguished from the negativity, for example, <strong>of</strong> a dialectical,<br />

speculative nature. Th is non-thing is none other than no-thing <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom itself, <strong>of</strong> freedom’s non-apparent apparition no longer in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> ‘this’ or ‘that’ thing, but this coming itself.<br />

Th erefore the apparition <strong>of</strong> freedom does not occur amongst the<br />

entities <strong>of</strong> the given world. In his lecture on What is Metaphysics?<br />

Heidegger therefore distinguishes the Not <strong>of</strong> a nothingness from the<br />

Not <strong>of</strong> negativity (Heidegger 1998, pp. 82-96). Th e manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> nothing in relation to which alone freedom manifests itself to the<br />

mortal, fi nite existence which is Dasein, is more originary than the<br />

annihilation-character <strong>of</strong> the measure <strong>of</strong> negativity. Th is means the<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom cannot be measured by negativity; only the originary<br />

nothingness can measure up to freedom only so far as the essence <strong>of</strong><br />

this measure consists in its transcendence <strong>of</strong> all measure, or, rather, the<br />

nothingness is already always beyond all measure. Th is measure is the<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> transcendence ins<strong>of</strong>ar Dasein who is called upon to assume<br />

its existence (out <strong>of</strong> its fi nitude) by freedom, itself is that being that<br />

already always transcends. Taking this point from Heidegger we can<br />

further speak <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> existence itself as such—that there<br />

is world, personality, self—only because they are the donation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immeasurable where the immeasurable appears itself as nothingness<br />

without annihilating anything. Th e measure <strong>of</strong> transcendence—the<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> freedom—is not something lying outside the beings<br />

as a whole, but that which manifests itself in the appearing <strong>of</strong> the<br />

beings as a whole in the receding <strong>of</strong> beings, in their withdrawal and<br />

abandonment. Th is is only in so far as Dasein itself is not an ‘entity’<br />

(‘presently given’), nor an object with animated freewill at disposal,<br />

a zōo somehow got attached with bio, but because Dasein itself is<br />

the free spacing or opening which opens itself to the Nothing where<br />

beings as a whole manifests itself in the movement <strong>of</strong> withdrawal and<br />

abandonment. In his What is Metaphysics? Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong> this<br />

holding out into the open as transcendence,


294 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Dasein means: being held into the nothing. Holding itself out in the<br />

nothing, Dasein is in each case already beyond beings as a whole.<br />

Such being beyond beings we call transcendence. If in the ground <strong>of</strong><br />

its essence Dasein were not transcending, which now means, if it were<br />

not in advance holding itself out into the nothing; then it could never<br />

adopt a stance toward beings nor even toward itself.<br />

Without the original manifestness <strong>of</strong> the nothing, no selfhood and no<br />

freedom.<br />

(Ibid., p.91, Italics mine in this sentence)<br />

Freedom manifests itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> the manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

nothing, which is none but the appearing <strong>of</strong> being in its withdrawal<br />

and abandonment. Heidegger’s thought <strong>of</strong> this double, agonistic<br />

character <strong>of</strong> revealing and receding <strong>of</strong> beings as a whole, its donation<br />

and abandonment, makes manifest to us a deeper, far reaching,<br />

and abyssal thinking <strong>of</strong> freedom. Freedom is that which granting<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> existence, withdraws or recedes from all phenomenal<br />

appearing. what is implicit in this text <strong>of</strong> Heidegger, the unthought in<br />

thought is the abyssal, agonistic manifestation <strong>of</strong> freedom: that arising<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom out <strong>of</strong> the groundlessness <strong>of</strong> the nothing, agonistically<br />

and in the manner <strong>of</strong> strife—between Day and Night, life and Death<br />

that Heraclitus speaks <strong>of</strong>—that gives and withdraws, manifests and<br />

recedes at the same time, and thereby copulating the elements in a<br />

monstrous, agonal copulation that Hölderlin speaks <strong>of</strong>: the arising<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise precisely at the moment when history pauses<br />

absolutely; that moment which revealing, manifesting the whole <strong>of</strong><br />

history in an absolute presentation, reveals to us the receding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

whole <strong>of</strong> history, and thereby yawning open the void precisely at<br />

the moment <strong>of</strong> its accomplishment, <strong>of</strong> its plenitude and fulfi lment.<br />

If freedom is nothing else but the principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration, <strong>of</strong><br />

inception, then freedom reveals itself here at this moment, each time<br />

as absolutely fi rst before everything else. History inaugurates with<br />

freedom, granted by freedom.<br />

Th e ethico-political task <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> our time therefore must<br />

take the question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude seriously, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as what remains<br />

for us the sense <strong>of</strong> ‘ethico-political’ is none but that <strong>of</strong> fi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

itself. Our sense <strong>of</strong> the ethico-political—that means, our sense <strong>of</strong><br />

the world—demands that we maintain this impossible tie with the


Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom • 295<br />

agony and strife <strong>of</strong> freedom itself, to assume the risk that freedom<br />

opens us to, and to assume the task <strong>of</strong> this assumption, that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

leap from given-ness <strong>of</strong> immanence to the holding sway <strong>of</strong> being .<br />

To minimize this wager <strong>of</strong> freedom, <strong>of</strong> freedom’s agony and strife<br />

through various programmatic, calculative apparatus <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

technological reason would be to deny the principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> which our sense <strong>of</strong> the ethico-political rests. What,<br />

then, Heidegger’s thought has opened for us and with which we<br />

must begin here, taking care <strong>of</strong> what is at stake in Heideggerian<br />

thought, is this thought <strong>of</strong> freedom as event in its intrinsic relation<br />

with the groundlessness <strong>of</strong> fi nitude itself. Th e transcendence <strong>of</strong> this<br />

fi nitude is a constant, interminable wager out <strong>of</strong> which there arises<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> a new ethics and new politics, for what<br />

we want to understand here by ‘politics’ as agonal manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. Th is agonal manifestation <strong>of</strong> freedom, its irreducible strife<br />

cannot be reducible to the dialectical oppositions <strong>of</strong> principles with<br />

its Aufhebung.<br />

To come to Heidegger, the thought <strong>of</strong> the care for Dasein now,<br />

after so many years <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s speaking <strong>of</strong> it, makes sense for<br />

us only because it gives us the thought <strong>of</strong> a freedom free from all<br />

immanent totalization. To understand the sense <strong>of</strong> freedom as wager<br />

is to understand fi rst <strong>of</strong> all our ethics and our politics itself as wager.<br />

Th is is only so far as the wager <strong>of</strong> freedom is none other than freedom<br />

as strife, as agonal manifestation <strong>of</strong> diff erential partitioning <strong>of</strong> forces.<br />

As such, the question <strong>of</strong> freedom concerns the possibility <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

itself as man’s existence who is <strong>of</strong> all beings the ‘most awesome’,<br />

because he is the most fi nite <strong>of</strong> all beings. He is this possibility to<br />

open-ness to the whole <strong>of</strong> beings only ins<strong>of</strong>ar as he is essentially this<br />

being, inextricably fi nite and inalienably mortal. Th is mortal’s openness<br />

to the world and to the futurity happens not out <strong>of</strong> mortal’s free<br />

will to determine itself on its own ground, but out <strong>of</strong> a groundless<br />

essence <strong>of</strong> freedom itself.<br />

Causality as a Problem <strong>of</strong> Freedom<br />

Heidegger’s lectures on Th e Essence <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom are his most<br />

systematic attempt to understand the enigmatic question <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

Taking Kant’s grounding <strong>of</strong> freedom as a problematic <strong>of</strong> causality


296 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

as a point <strong>of</strong> departure—in its tw<strong>of</strong>old transcendental freedom and<br />

practical freedom—Heidegger attempts to think freedom in a more<br />

originary manner: not—freedom as a problematic <strong>of</strong> causality but<br />

rather—causality as a problematic <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

If Heideggerian attempt to think <strong>of</strong> causality as a problem <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom and not vice versa is taken into account, then freedom<br />

can neither be understood merely as the principle <strong>of</strong> inauguration<br />

that inaugurates the series <strong>of</strong> events and occurrences, and as mere<br />

extension <strong>of</strong> causality, nor freedom be understood as practical reason<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fi nite being in relation to his pure will willing itself. Freedom<br />

would then has to be understood in a more originary manner as the<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> the being, which is Abgrund, which means the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence as such on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone there may be willing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pure will so that this fi nite being determines itself as selfdetermining<br />

personality. Freedom is the site where the events occur<br />

as such in their multiple singularities, but this multiplicity <strong>of</strong> events<br />

does not occur as temporal succession <strong>of</strong> nows. Following Heidegger,<br />

we are no longer understanding events here as particular occurrences,<br />

homogenous, where the relation <strong>of</strong> discontinuity between events<br />

belongs to the causal sequence. What we want to think with<br />

Heidegger is something that has remained not so explicitly brought<br />

out in Heidegger himself, in so far as Heidegger’s deconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

Kant’s notion <strong>of</strong> causality has remained (at least in this lecture course)<br />

in the giving over causality to the site <strong>of</strong> freedom. What we want to<br />

understand, taking Heidegger’s controversy with Kant as point <strong>of</strong><br />

departure is this radical notion <strong>of</strong> event that does not yet belong to<br />

the temporal, relative succession <strong>of</strong> occurrences, that is no longer<br />

the relative, sequential, accumulative, homogenous discontinuity <strong>of</strong><br />

occurrences that points to the ‘absolute spontaneity’ that begins with<br />

itself only so that it does not have to regress or progress ad-infi nitum.<br />

What we want to learn from Heidegger is rather the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> events that inaugurating absolutely, that means without<br />

ground and foundation, is yet universal, which is thought no longer<br />

as accumulative totality <strong>of</strong> present particular instances that are to<br />

follow in their letting-follow in a temporal, causal sequence, nor as<br />

will purely determining itself in a time before time, but the universal<br />

that arrives each such letting follow as from an outside, not merely


Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom • 297<br />

regulating the sequence as a regulative principle, but de-formalizing<br />

the sequence each time it arrives absolutely.<br />

It is this pure arrival that we want to call event, and not occurrences<br />

that belong to the sequential order <strong>of</strong> letting follow or just running<br />

ahead <strong>of</strong> only because it does not adequately express the universality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the moral law. What we want to call in the name <strong>of</strong> ‘event’,<br />

neither belongs to the universality <strong>of</strong> the moral law and to the<br />

universality <strong>of</strong> the dialectical-speculative history, nor to a mere<br />

instantiation <strong>of</strong> the universality in the particular eruption <strong>of</strong> ‘now’<br />

that follows other nows in a sequence forming a uniform procession<br />

or progression. What we call ‘event’ is rather the de-formalization <strong>of</strong><br />

any such a sequential progression, which erupting in an irreducibly<br />

singular manner, nevertheless is an inscription <strong>of</strong> universality. Such<br />

idiomatic universality or singular universality is a disruption <strong>of</strong><br />

the immanence <strong>of</strong> the formal temporality which is accomplished<br />

through visible, apparent forms <strong>of</strong> phenomenality. Such an event<br />

is to be understood in its exemplarity. Th is exemplarity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event is the inscription <strong>of</strong> universality in the singular, where the<br />

immanence <strong>of</strong> particulars instants <strong>of</strong> eruption forming a causal<br />

chain is hollowed inside out, to welcome the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wholly other.<br />

Th is thought is already implicit in Heidegger’s deconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

Kant’s notion <strong>of</strong> freedom when, for example, Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom as the ground <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> event as such, where it<br />

would have been possible for him to distinguish at that time between<br />

occurrences and the event <strong>of</strong> arrival. Th en it would have been possible<br />

for him to release the thought <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> arrival from either the<br />

particular occurrences belonging to the temporal sequence in their<br />

letting-follow or from the irreducibility <strong>of</strong> the universal moral law<br />

in particular instantiation <strong>of</strong> it in willing this or that. But what has<br />

opened by Heidegger in this work on human freedom is the question<br />

concerning the grounding <strong>of</strong> the will <strong>of</strong> man in the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> man,<br />

in the Abgrund <strong>of</strong> the ground so that freedom is seen as the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> Dasein which is irreducible either to transcendental<br />

freedom or to practical freedom. Instead both the transcendental


298 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

freedom and the practical freedom are to be opened up to the<br />

Abgrund, to that the abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom which is the possibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fi nite existence <strong>of</strong> man. Causality, as one ontological determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> beings among others, belongs to freedom which alone is the<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> the manifestation <strong>of</strong> beings. Heidegger could say:<br />

Causality is, however, one ontological determination <strong>of</strong> beings among<br />

others. Causality is grounded in freedom. Th e problem <strong>of</strong> causality<br />

is a problem <strong>of</strong> freedom and not vice versa (Heidegger 2005, p. 207)<br />

Here the inaugurating principle <strong>of</strong> freedom is no longer merely that<br />

<strong>of</strong> inaugurating the series <strong>of</strong> sequences <strong>of</strong> occurrences in a temporal,<br />

causal succession, nor the inaugurating a series <strong>of</strong> ethical actions as<br />

the will that purely determines itself, but inauguration <strong>of</strong> the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the occurrence <strong>of</strong> existence as such and <strong>of</strong> the mortal who arises out <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom. Manifestation <strong>of</strong> beings: the event <strong>of</strong> freedom. What Heidegger<br />

here attempts to understand is the event character <strong>of</strong> freedom which<br />

is the manifestation <strong>of</strong> being on the basis <strong>of</strong> which alone can there<br />

be the causality, can there be inauguration <strong>of</strong> the series <strong>of</strong> sequential<br />

occurrences. Th at means freedom cannot be understood on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> causality, but that what is presupposed in any causality as the<br />

unconditioned opening and revealing <strong>of</strong> beings. Th e event <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

is no longer to be understood on the basis <strong>of</strong> ‘given presence’, or as<br />

‘constant presence’, but coming into presence which is irreducible to<br />

any ‘given presence’ or ‘constant presence’. Heidegger here is clear in<br />

this point:<br />

As a category, causality is a basic character <strong>of</strong> the being <strong>of</strong> beings.<br />

If we consider that the being <strong>of</strong> beings is proximally comprehended<br />

as constant presence—and this involves producedness, producing<br />

fi nishing in the broad sense <strong>of</strong> actualizing—it is clear that precisely<br />

causality, in the traditional sense <strong>of</strong> the being <strong>of</strong> beings, in common<br />

understanding as in the traditional metaphysics, is the fundamental<br />

category <strong>of</strong> being as being-present. If causality is a problem <strong>of</strong> freedom and<br />

not vice versa then the problem <strong>of</strong> being in general is in itself a problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom (Ibid., pp. 205-6).<br />

What is presupposed in the dominant, traditional metaphysical<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> causality is a certain determination <strong>of</strong> time as<br />

‘given present’, as ‘constant presence’. What Heidegger here attempts


Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom • 299<br />

to problematize by deconstructively reading Kant’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom can be traced back to the concerns <strong>of</strong> Being and <strong>Time</strong>. In<br />

Kant as in the traditional, dominant metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong><br />

being, being is understood on the basis <strong>of</strong> the reductive, derivative<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> time as ‘constant present’, as ‘given present’ which<br />

has remained unquestioned, un-interrogated. Kant understands<br />

freedom as a problematic <strong>of</strong> causality. Th is causality presupposes the<br />

dominant, metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> beings as ‘entities given<br />

present’ which in turn tactically presupposes the vulgar notion <strong>of</strong><br />

time as ‘constant presence’ which can be categorically grasped in the<br />

predicative determination that means apophantically. What has then<br />

remained unthought is the event <strong>of</strong> coming itself—not this or that<br />

coming, nor the occurrences that can be arranged in causal, which<br />

is also temporal, succession <strong>of</strong> homogenous instants, but—that<br />

arises groundlessly out <strong>of</strong> the abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom. Th e event <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

then can no longer be understood as a conditioned arriving, but since it<br />

occurs freely, that means unconditionally, it can never be thought on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> causality. Th erefore the dominant, traditional, metaphysical<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> event on the basis <strong>of</strong> the understanding <strong>of</strong> time as<br />

‘constant present’ that can be arranged on a causal scale <strong>of</strong> various<br />

attenuated, accumulative, homogenous instants (nows) is inadequate<br />

to grasp the event <strong>of</strong> freedom that erupts incalculably, unpredictably<br />

that brings history to a standstill. Here time would then thought in<br />

a disjunctive simultaneity that inaugurates history itself anew which<br />

cannot be reduced to the inauguration <strong>of</strong> new series <strong>of</strong> the causal chain<br />

<strong>of</strong> temporal instants. Since this abyss <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> time—which is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> freedom—does not present itself in any self-presence,<br />

its unapparent apparition can only be that <strong>of</strong> an infi nite coming, a<br />

transcendence without transcendent. Th is transcendence <strong>of</strong> freedom is<br />

the moment <strong>of</strong> history’s coming to presence, as if for the fi rst time,<br />

which defi nes the historicity <strong>of</strong> history, which is not the occurrences<br />

within a causal chain <strong>of</strong> succession, or within a scale that assimilates<br />

the sequential, periodic, attenuated, relative discontinuities, but<br />

the moment <strong>of</strong> radical arriving when the whole sequence comes to<br />

standstill. What we learn from Heidegger’s deconstructive reading <strong>of</strong><br />

the dominant metaphysical determination <strong>of</strong> freedom is this thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> the infi nite fi nitude <strong>of</strong> freedom as the event <strong>of</strong> pure arrival, <strong>of</strong><br />

history’s coming into presence to itself.


300 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Philosophy as Strife<br />

If philosophy is concerned not with this or that mode <strong>of</strong> ‘presently<br />

given entities’ or, with this or that area <strong>of</strong> ‘the presently given entities’<br />

but the coming to presence <strong>of</strong> existence itself as such, then philosophy<br />

cannot be reduced to be one amongst other academic disciplines,<br />

for philosophy as the unconditional thinking erupts out <strong>of</strong> no-thing<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom itself. From where, then, the name ‘philosophy’ is to be<br />

derived? As if, as it were, this strange name ‘philosophy’, erupting,<br />

occurring out <strong>of</strong> no-thing and no-ground, can only be the name <strong>of</strong><br />

a thinking, from such an Archimedean point, <strong>of</strong> the unnameable<br />

and non-condition itself. Philosophy is such a state <strong>of</strong> exception in<br />

relation to the presently given mode <strong>of</strong> existence in the world, in<br />

such a manner that philosophy, instead <strong>of</strong> merely and only relatively<br />

re-working the presently given mode <strong>of</strong> existence in the world, seeks<br />

complete transformation <strong>of</strong> the world as an epochal inauguration,<br />

arising together with the epochal break, <strong>of</strong> which Hölderlin speaks<br />

as ‘monstrous copulation’. Philosophy, wherever it occurs, appears as<br />

an inauguration <strong>of</strong> an entirely new relation to the world, or rather,<br />

the world happens there, in the open site <strong>of</strong> freedom, as if for the<br />

fi rst time. Th is occurring <strong>of</strong> the world, or, lets say, the ‘worlding’<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world from where alone we mortals derive our sense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world, constitutes the event <strong>of</strong> the world. Th is event <strong>of</strong> the ‘world<br />

occurrence’ which inaugurates an entirely new relation to the world,<br />

no longer merely re-working the given mode <strong>of</strong> existence, cannot<br />

be understood as merely an event <strong>of</strong> causality, but as an event <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom itself, arising out <strong>of</strong> freedom, whose ungrounded condition<br />

is freedom. While referring to Schelling’s notion <strong>of</strong> philosophy as<br />

an event <strong>of</strong> freedom, Heidegger refers to philosophy and poetry,<br />

wherever they occur, as ‘world occurrences’:<br />

Where they are essential, thinking and writing poetry are a world<br />

occurrence, and this is not only in the sense that something is<br />

happening within the world which has signifi cance for the world,<br />

but also in the sense in which and through which the world itself<br />

arises itself anew in its actual origins and rules as world. Philosophy<br />

can never be justifi ed by taking over and reworking the realm what<br />

is knowable from some areas or even all areas and delivering things<br />

that knowable from this, but only by opening more primordially the


Th e Abyss <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom • 301<br />

essence <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> what is knowable and discoverable in general<br />

and giving a new path and a new horizon to the relation to the beings<br />

in general. (Heidegger 1985, p. 58)<br />

What is thought as philosophy is what is essential in philosophy:<br />

philosophy that welcomes the pure taking place <strong>of</strong> the world rather than<br />

merely knowledge <strong>of</strong> the given world and as such, not being concerned<br />

with this or that conditioned presence, welcomes the unconditional<br />

in pure coming as such. Philosophy, since it is the work <strong>of</strong> freedom,<br />

does not concern itself with naming the nameable, but naming the<br />

unnameable and the un-naming the nameable. Philosophy in this<br />

manner, again, manifests the strife <strong>of</strong> freedom: philosophy manifests<br />

itself as agonal manifestation <strong>of</strong> the nameable and unnameable, the<br />

condition and unconditional, joy and mourning at the same time, in<br />

a disjunctive constellation. Philosophy as such is essentially aporetic:<br />

not between the condition and another condition, not between a<br />

name and another, or even less, between a concept and another<br />

concept, but rather: between conditioned and the unconditioned,<br />

both at once, as wager. Each time there is philosophy is there a risk, a<br />

madness, or even impossibility, in so far as it is demanded as the task <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy which arises out <strong>of</strong> freedom that, on the one hand it must<br />

the name the unnameable, so that philosophy constantly confronts<br />

the enigma <strong>of</strong> its own disappearing at the moment <strong>of</strong> its fulfi lment<br />

and other hand, that the unnameable must remain irreducible to<br />

each and everything in the world that is named and predicated so<br />

that it can welcome, unconditionally, what is not yet, and what is<br />

pure taking place <strong>of</strong> the event. Th is is so far as freedom itself calls<br />

forth as it’s other in an agonistic manner, in the manner <strong>of</strong> strife, its<br />

opposing other, which is necessity to which it holds itself by being<br />

separated from the other, like the elements <strong>of</strong> strife in Heraclitus.<br />

When Schelling (1936) refers to the contradiction <strong>of</strong> necessity and<br />

freedom, which is a higher form <strong>of</strong> contradiction than between<br />

spirit and nature, he is alluding precisely to the highest agonistic<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself: the strife between the condition and<br />

unconditioned, the disappearance and arriving, the unapparent and<br />

the apparition <strong>of</strong> freedom itself. Th is agony <strong>of</strong> strife, while animating<br />

the movement <strong>of</strong> philosophy each time when philosophy announces<br />

itself, remains unapparent to the eyes <strong>of</strong> the world. It is, in other


302 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

words, secret. Referring to this strife that arises out <strong>of</strong> philosophy or<br />

philosophy itself as this strife, Heidegger says,<br />

Philosophy is intrinsically a strife between necessity and freedom and<br />

in that it belongs to philosophy as the highest knowledge to know<br />

itself, it will produce from itself this strife and the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

system <strong>of</strong> freedom. (Ibid.)<br />

Philosophy as the system <strong>of</strong> freedom is essentially and intrinsically<br />

strife and in its form <strong>of</strong> strife, it articulates the strife character <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opening <strong>of</strong> the world. In this way philosophy preserves and reserves<br />

the essential truth <strong>of</strong> the world while opening the world to the light <strong>of</strong><br />

truth. Th at philosophy has to erupt in the midst <strong>of</strong> human existence<br />

is not an accidental aff air. It has to do with the strife character <strong>of</strong><br />

the existence itself and the world to which man is exposed, to which<br />

he is revealed open, in the manner that Kierkegaard calls, in an<br />

entirely diff erent gesture, ‘ the wound <strong>of</strong> the negative’. Man’s essential<br />

character lies in this pure exposure to the outside, for he is essentially<br />

that being who is free. Or rather, because the mortal is free, he can be<br />

the free site <strong>of</strong> exposure to the pure taking place, to the eruption <strong>of</strong> that<br />

which is not mere apparent, but the unapparent apparition. Th e task<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophical contemplation is to preserve this truth <strong>of</strong> exposure<br />

which is none but the truth <strong>of</strong> existence itself, and not to lose this<br />

exposure to the conditioned self-consumption in various immanent<br />

closures. Th e necessity <strong>of</strong> philosophy for human existence lies in this,<br />

if not elsewhere. If the great Plato thinks <strong>of</strong> philosophy as anamnesis,<br />

it is in this sense <strong>of</strong> remembrance that preserves the truth <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

in thinking. Th e truth <strong>of</strong> existence, which is the Eidos or idea <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenon, is its event <strong>of</strong> coming into existence which cannot be<br />

predicated on the basis <strong>of</strong> result or fi nality, which cannot be thought<br />

on the modality <strong>of</strong> the propositional structural <strong>of</strong> language but<br />

rather as bursting forth in lightning fl ash when language for the fi rst<br />

time arrives to itself—as Idea <strong>of</strong> itself before concepts. Because this<br />

lightning fl ash exposes us to the event <strong>of</strong> pure possibility, and since<br />

this pure possibility is unconditional and free, philosophy in itself<br />

only can arise as the free activity <strong>of</strong> the mortal’s existence in the world.


Part IV<br />

Messianicity


§ Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love<br />

What consists in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love: in the love for the wholly<br />

Other who is absolutely singular, and what this love transforms itself<br />

to, to the love for the others who are the placeholders <strong>of</strong> Not Yet,<br />

the neighbour who opens us to the radical futurity <strong>of</strong> a redemptive<br />

fulfi lment? Irreducible to the order <strong>of</strong> law—both the law positing and<br />

law preserving order, the arrival <strong>of</strong> love is the event <strong>of</strong> time that opens<br />

the seal <strong>of</strong> immemorial promise given in the immemorial past to<br />

the absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> love’s presentation and to the<br />

radicality <strong>of</strong> the incalculable futurity, that is the coming <strong>of</strong> Messiah.<br />

In the name <strong>of</strong> Franz Rosenzweig, this article attempts to think an<br />

ethics <strong>of</strong> exemplarity which is love’s generosity, an exemplarity that<br />

consists <strong>of</strong> addressing to the singularity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> love and that<br />

<strong>of</strong> its immemorial promise on the one hand, and yet at the same<br />

time that affi rms the necessity <strong>of</strong> translation <strong>of</strong> this singular language<br />

<strong>of</strong> love to the universality that is yet to come. What it demands is<br />

the re-thinking <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> our ethico-political that must open<br />

itself to the thought <strong>of</strong> a promise beyond the violence <strong>of</strong> a historical<br />

Reason. Th is sense is the sense <strong>of</strong> exemplarity which is opened up in<br />

the generosity <strong>of</strong> love, beyond the dialectic <strong>of</strong> the autochthony <strong>of</strong> the<br />

particular and anonymity <strong>of</strong> the homogenous progress <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

history. What consists in this commandment <strong>of</strong> love is the promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the messianic fulfi lment beyond the violence <strong>of</strong> the order <strong>of</strong> law,<br />

the promise that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens the mortals to time and history, to<br />

being and truth so that the messianic community, which is always to<br />

come, may not be enclosed in the autochthony <strong>of</strong> the given people.<br />

‘Love thy neighbour’: this commandment <strong>of</strong> love is essentially


306 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the commandment <strong>of</strong> translation whose exemplarity consists in<br />

the impossible double demands on the lover/beloved—that the<br />

absolutely singularity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> love, in its un-translatability,<br />

be opened to translation, to universality on the one hand, and on<br />

the other hand, the singularity <strong>of</strong> the eventive character <strong>of</strong> love be<br />

maintained in its un-translatability. If there remains for us any sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ethico-political, when wide spread horror at annihilation <strong>of</strong><br />

sense is the prominent mood today, then this sense consists in this<br />

exemplarity <strong>of</strong> love’s ethical commandment and in the irreducibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the aporia <strong>of</strong> translation, which, as we shall see here, is the aporia<br />

<strong>of</strong> our ethico-political today.<br />

*<br />

It [redemption] bursts open every space and in this way it annuls<br />

time.<br />

—Franz Rosenzweig (2005, p. 394)<br />

Exemplarity <strong>of</strong> Translation<br />

In his seminar on Onto-Th eology <strong>of</strong> National Humanism Jacques<br />

Derrida (1992a)dwells extensively on a question that appears to me<br />

the concentration and intensity <strong>of</strong> his philosophical questioning as<br />

such: how to think, on the one hand, <strong>of</strong> the absolute singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the idiomatic which as such is untranslatable, irreducible to<br />

anything like the order <strong>of</strong> universality and translatability, and on<br />

the other hand, without renouncing the universal aspiration which<br />

is the passion <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, so that there be translation <strong>of</strong><br />

the absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the event into the language <strong>of</strong> new<br />

cosmopolitanism beyond all immanent closures <strong>of</strong> particularistic,<br />

parochial claims <strong>of</strong> autochthonous community, people, nations<br />

etc. No doubt, such a community to come—since it is not yet<br />

given—would be exemplary 1 in the messianic sense <strong>of</strong> ‘messianicity<br />

without messianism’ (Derrida 1998, p. 68), an idea <strong>of</strong> exemplarity<br />

that Derrida has attempted to develop in his later so called ‘ethicopolitical’<br />

works. Th e idea <strong>of</strong> a ‘messianicity without messianism’ is,<br />

in this sense, an exemplary thought in the sense that it attempts at<br />

an inscription <strong>of</strong> the transcendence <strong>of</strong> universality in each idiomatic<br />

and singular, and opening up each singularity and idiomatic beyond


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 307<br />

any autochthonous claims to the unconditional, which is the radical<br />

opening to the pure event <strong>of</strong> future. Th erefore Derrida’s ‘messianicity<br />

without messianism’ is not reducible to any system <strong>of</strong> eschatology<br />

or theological messianism in the sense <strong>of</strong> belonging to a particular<br />

dogmatic system <strong>of</strong> thought, but an attempt to think in an exemplary<br />

manner in the name <strong>of</strong> an uncommon sense <strong>of</strong> messianicity a more<br />

originary (non) phenomenon <strong>of</strong> Eschatos: that is, the extremity <strong>of</strong><br />

futurity as a site <strong>of</strong> pure arrival (l’avenir) which is always to come,<br />

precisely because it may even come today, at this moment, hic et nunc.<br />

If the violence <strong>of</strong> the historical reason—and not merely that but<br />

also the possibility <strong>of</strong> radical evil—arises in the autochthonous claims<br />

<strong>of</strong> the particular, whether in the name <strong>of</strong> a particular community,<br />

nation or other identities, attempting to assume thereby the<br />

transcendence <strong>of</strong> the universal, then it would necessitate, beyond<br />

such autochthony, the exemplary task <strong>of</strong> a ‘messianicity without<br />

messianism’. For Derrida, such a task is inseparable from exemplarity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> translation: that <strong>of</strong> the demand to be faithful to the<br />

absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the event in its un-translatability, and yet<br />

without renouncing the task <strong>of</strong> translation, to give the task <strong>of</strong><br />

universalizing the singular and idiomatic as such; on the one hand,<br />

to address the specifi city <strong>of</strong> the particular history and the idiomatic<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the cultural mode <strong>of</strong> being, and yet, so as not merely<br />

to be enclosed in the immanence <strong>of</strong> linguistic, cultural or historical<br />

relativism, not to renounce the task <strong>of</strong> thinking a transcendental<br />

history or language, to what the passion <strong>of</strong> philosophy always aspires<br />

in a very exemplary manner, where philosophy itself is transformed<br />

to its own unforeseeable futurity, that <strong>of</strong> welcoming the others who<br />

are always to come. In his early works, Derrida attempts to think the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> exemplarit0pas the question <strong>of</strong> iterability: diff erance and<br />

the unforeseeable eruption <strong>of</strong> the absolutely new and the other in act<br />

<strong>of</strong> repetition so that repetition, like the act <strong>of</strong> translation, is never<br />

mimetic reproduction <strong>of</strong> anything like given but the condition <strong>of</strong><br />

opening to the Eschatos <strong>of</strong> the future in the heart <strong>of</strong> presence which<br />

is always non-self-identical and non-contemporaneous with itself.<br />

Refl ecting on this question Derrida says later in an interview,<br />

Th is expression (‘une fois pour toutes’) states in a highly economical<br />

way the singular event and the irreversibility <strong>of</strong> what or who only<br />

comes about or come along once, and is repeated no more. But at the


308 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

same time it opens up onto all the metonymical substitutions that<br />

would take it somewhere else. Th e unprecedented arises, whether we<br />

like it or not, in the multiplicity <strong>of</strong> repetitions. Th at is what puts on<br />

hold the naive oppositions between tradition and renewal, or memory<br />

and future, or reform and revolution. Th e logic <strong>of</strong> iterability wrecks<br />

in advance the certainties <strong>of</strong> all sorts <strong>of</strong> discourses, philosophies,<br />

ideologies... (Derrida 2005, pp. 136-37).<br />

Th e logic <strong>of</strong> iterability is the logic <strong>of</strong> exemplarity that un-works in<br />

advance the oppositions between the irreducible singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

idiomatic on the one hand, and on the other hand the universality<br />

in the ‘uncommon’ sense. It consists <strong>of</strong> ‘the irreplaceable inscription<br />

<strong>of</strong> the universal in the singular’ which is ‘the unique testimony to the<br />

human essence and to what is proper to man’ (Derrida 1992b). For<br />

Derrida this logic <strong>of</strong> exemplarity is inseparable from that <strong>of</strong> ethical<br />

responsibility: that is, welcoming the event <strong>of</strong> future that is always<br />

an ‘yet to come’ beyond the autochthonous claims <strong>of</strong> all sorts <strong>of</strong> selfconsuming<br />

immanent politics without, however, disclaiming that<br />

irreducible element <strong>of</strong> the idiomatic that takes place only once (une<br />

fois) without repetition.<br />

Such a messianic thought <strong>of</strong> exemplarity or such an exemplary<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> the messianic that is concerned with the opening <strong>of</strong><br />

the verbal resonance <strong>of</strong> temporality beyond the autochthony<br />

<strong>of</strong> immanent self-presence to the event <strong>of</strong> pure future and to the<br />

immemoriality <strong>of</strong> the past is essentially a question <strong>of</strong> promise and<br />

redemptive fulfi lment. Only in this way the thought <strong>of</strong> messianicity<br />

that welcomes the incalculability <strong>of</strong> the advent <strong>of</strong> eternity in the<br />

midst <strong>of</strong> time can radically deconstruct the violence <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

reason’s claim to totality and immanence. Here we shall take up Franz<br />

Rosenzweig’s Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption and some <strong>of</strong> his other shorter<br />

philosophical and theological essays to show how Rosenzweig’s<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> immemoriality <strong>of</strong> promise and its redemptive fulfi lment<br />

that consummates history is essentially concerned with the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> exemplarity that seeks radically to deconstruct the violence <strong>of</strong> what<br />

he calls ‘the messianic politics’ <strong>of</strong> the world. Here Rosenzweig takes<br />

up the biblical commandment <strong>of</strong> love, in the name <strong>of</strong> an exemplary<br />

universality, to open up ‘the messianic politics’ <strong>of</strong> the world to the<br />

kingdom to come which is as such always to come, and nevertheless<br />

may arrive just now, today or tomorrow. Th is exemplarity <strong>of</strong>


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 309<br />

love consists in its infi nite act <strong>of</strong> translation <strong>of</strong> the extremity <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemoriality <strong>of</strong> the past to Eschatos <strong>of</strong> the last where alone<br />

originates the pure future. Th e commandment <strong>of</strong> love here is, more<br />

<strong>of</strong> an event <strong>of</strong> temporality that revelation opens human existence<br />

to its redemptive fulfi lment than that <strong>of</strong> ‘facts’ <strong>of</strong> existence that can<br />

be cognitively grasped and thematized by the acts <strong>of</strong> indication and<br />

intentions constituting the totality <strong>of</strong> knowledge. For Rosenzweig<br />

this inextricable facticity <strong>of</strong> human existence—that is opened by<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> revelation to its redemptive fulfi lment in the Eschatos <strong>of</strong><br />

pure future that may come today—makes existence irreducible to the<br />

reductive totalization <strong>of</strong> a theodicy <strong>of</strong> history. If such a theodicy <strong>of</strong><br />

history constitutes the ‘messianic politics’ <strong>of</strong> the world, and reducing<br />

messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> existence to the immanence <strong>of</strong> fate, it would<br />

then be necessary to welcome the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the pure arrival<br />

which as such is without fate, without goal and that is not completely<br />

determined by the intentions <strong>of</strong> human acts. For Rosenzweig such<br />

an intensity <strong>of</strong> existence that exposes it to the fateless order <strong>of</strong> the<br />

messianic transcendence reveals itself in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love<br />

as pure event that alone is able to strive against the power <strong>of</strong> death<br />

that seeks to enclose the immemoriality <strong>of</strong> promise in the immanent<br />

order <strong>of</strong> fate.<br />

It is with this exemplarity <strong>of</strong> love that we are concerned here, an<br />

exemplarity that is inseparable from the question <strong>of</strong> the translation<br />

<strong>of</strong> promise into its fateless messianic fulfi lment arriving from an<br />

extremity <strong>of</strong> an Eschatos. Th e event <strong>of</strong> love here appears to be the<br />

exemplary (non)phenomenon <strong>of</strong> existence par-excellence. To exist, it<br />

so appears from Rosenzweig’s text, is to be exposed to this event <strong>of</strong> love<br />

that infi nitely translates us and transports us to that phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

transcendence which cannot be enclosed within the immanent order<br />

<strong>of</strong> a theodicy <strong>of</strong> history. If to release this event <strong>of</strong> transcendence from<br />

the immanent order <strong>of</strong> fate with which the theodicy <strong>of</strong> history curves<br />

back into itself as in a circle is the highest task <strong>of</strong> existence today, then<br />

this task adheres itself in this act <strong>of</strong> love that arrives as commandment<br />

and not as the order <strong>of</strong> law. If that is so, then the act <strong>of</strong> translation<br />

is to be understood less as an intentional act <strong>of</strong> transmission <strong>of</strong> a<br />

given knowledge or memory that is oriented by a determinable order<br />

<strong>of</strong> telos and fulfi lled in an immanent historical consummation. It<br />

is rather to be understood as an infi nite task <strong>of</strong> translation <strong>of</strong> an


310 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

immemorial promise that has never originated in the intentional act<br />

and can never appear in the determinable movement <strong>of</strong> a telos; its<br />

consummation is never immanent to the historically realized Eschatos<br />

but an incalculable consummation that consummates history itself.<br />

Translation is essentially a redemptive, messianic task orienting our<br />

history to its fulfi lment in a pure language which for Benjamin, as<br />

we shall see later, is ‘the language <strong>of</strong> truth’. Th is ‘language <strong>of</strong> truth’<br />

never arises in the intentional act <strong>of</strong> transmission <strong>of</strong> given element<br />

<strong>of</strong> history or tradition. It arrives as wholly unforeseen eruption <strong>of</strong><br />

something entirely new and radically other that alone consummates<br />

history. It is in this sense the task <strong>of</strong> translation is exemplary. But we<br />

shall come to Benjamin’s exemplary task <strong>of</strong> translation little later.<br />

Let’s come back to Rosenzweig’s question <strong>of</strong> love.<br />

For Rosenzweig, as for Benjamin, the task <strong>of</strong> translation is<br />

essentially bound up with the messianic conception <strong>of</strong> redemption<br />

which as such, beyond the violence <strong>of</strong> historical reason, constitutes<br />

the condition <strong>of</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> opening up what is unforeseeable<br />

eruption <strong>of</strong> the radically new. For Rosenzweig such a task is essentially<br />

existential in so far as existence—which is irreducibly verbal and<br />

irreducibly singular—is opened by the generosity and exuberance<br />

<strong>of</strong> love. It is this generosity and exuberance <strong>of</strong> love that enables the<br />

translation <strong>of</strong> eternity in time, <strong>of</strong> an unforeseeable tomorrow to erupt<br />

here and now so that the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> the immemorial<br />

past is not remained sealed in the dark abyss <strong>of</strong> the past but that can<br />

be eternally renewed in each here and now so that through this act <strong>of</strong><br />

renewal <strong>of</strong> love’s pure event <strong>of</strong> presentation the immemorial promise<br />

can be open to its fulfi lment in a futurity which is always to come.<br />

If this interpretation <strong>of</strong> Rosenzweig is accepted, albeit at this initial<br />

moment, then love appears to be the event <strong>of</strong> exposure <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

to eternity that wounds it, that bursts open the immanent closure<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-presence—to the immemoriality <strong>of</strong> the promise (given in the<br />

immemoriality <strong>of</strong> a past) on the one hand and to the incalculable,<br />

infi nite, unforeseeable transcendence <strong>of</strong> pure futurity on the other<br />

hand. Love here appears to be an infi nite act <strong>of</strong> translation, always<br />

passing through the infi nite threshold <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> time—that is, its<br />

pure presentation that is renewed each moment—that translates the<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> promise into the universality <strong>of</strong> a messianic<br />

community which is yet to come, a coming community where the


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 311<br />

singularities are not immersed or absorbed into the ‘common’, into<br />

some kind <strong>of</strong> universality <strong>of</strong> an ‘essence’ or ‘genus’. Love’s exemplarity<br />

is not the translation, one that is reductively totalized, <strong>of</strong> particularity<br />

(which is seen as mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> the universality <strong>of</strong> ‘essence’<br />

and ‘genus’) into the faceless, anonymous, indiff erent universality<br />

through the acts <strong>of</strong> negativity (<strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Subject). It<br />

is rather an infi nite translation <strong>of</strong> promise that immemorially, already<br />

always founds us, and opens us to truth and time for the fi rst time<br />

before any fi rst, in an already always whose dark abyss no apophantic<br />

act <strong>of</strong> the Subject’s Parousia can trace back to, and which through the<br />

eternal renewal in each here and now opens us to the extremity <strong>of</strong><br />

future coming towards us that cannot be calculated beforehand, for<br />

it has already always been future. Th is futurity—which is also in a<br />

certain sense eternity for us—must already always have been opened<br />

by the promise in that immemorial past. Only in this sense, there can<br />

be futurity in the extreme sense <strong>of</strong> the eschatological intensity, that<br />

<strong>of</strong>, the coming <strong>of</strong> the Messiah.<br />

The Aporia <strong>of</strong> Love<br />

What consists in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love: ‘love thy neighbour’? in<br />

the love for the Other who is absolutely singular, the wholly Other<br />

and what this love transforms itself to, to the love for the others who<br />

are the placeholders <strong>of</strong> Not Yet, the neighbour who opens the door for<br />

us, unhinges the seal <strong>of</strong> presence to the radical futurity <strong>of</strong> a redemptive<br />

fulfi lment, which is the futurity <strong>of</strong> a coming community? Is not this<br />

door the threshold—at the limit between exteriority and interiority,<br />

between the ‘own-most’ or ‘innermost’ and the ‘foreign’, the other—<br />

that translation passes through and never ceases to pass through as<br />

the act <strong>of</strong> hospitality, welcoming the wholly other to arrive here and<br />

now, the eternity to come today, not today that I inhabit as owner <strong>of</strong><br />

a dwelling, but a today which is any today and yet each time singular<br />

that cannot be calculated beforehand? In that sense, the neighbour<br />

is anyone and yet absolutely singular, irreducible to all attributes and is<br />

absolved from genus: to speak with Emmanuel Levinas for whom the<br />

proximity <strong>of</strong> this ‘anyone’ <strong>of</strong> the neighbour who fi rst comes to pass<br />

by is precisely for that matter the other <strong>of</strong> ‘exclusive singularity’,


312 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Absolving himself from all essence, all genus, all resemblance, the<br />

neighbour, the fi rst one on the scene, concerns me for the fi rst time….<br />

in a contingency that excludes the prior. Not coming to confi rm<br />

any signalling made in advance, outside <strong>of</strong> everything, the a prior,<br />

the neighbour concerns me with his exclusive singularity without<br />

appearing … (Levinas 1991, p. 86).<br />

In the commandment: ‘love thy neighbour’, it is not the particular<br />

entity that is mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> the genus or the empty universality<br />

<strong>of</strong> essence that is being addressed. Th e neighbour—who is anyone and<br />

yet singular and each time unlike anyone—is the exemplarity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

example here: as if the heart <strong>of</strong> love is divided here—between anyone<br />

and unlike anyone, absolutely unlike anyone, exclusively singular—<br />

and yet in this division <strong>of</strong> the heart, in this incommensurability<br />

and non-contemporaneity within the heart <strong>of</strong> heart there arrives<br />

the commandment, love’s commandment which itself is absolutely<br />

singular (since it is irreducible to the order <strong>of</strong> generality that<br />

constitutes the order <strong>of</strong> law) on the one hand, and yet universal,<br />

since it is addressed to anyone, anyone who ‘fi rst comes to the scene’,<br />

to love the neighbour. Love’s commandment demands from the<br />

one that the division <strong>of</strong> the heart <strong>of</strong> love may remain irreducibly<br />

wounded, exposed, torn open by this division, and yet on the other<br />

hand, the commandment consists <strong>of</strong> obliging a response, <strong>of</strong> eliciting<br />

a response from each one <strong>of</strong> us, and yet each one absolutely singularly<br />

and from ‘me’ before everyone, wholly from me and therefore without<br />

division <strong>of</strong> my heart, a whole and complete response: ‘here I am’.<br />

For such a response to arrive— ‘here I am’ to the commandment <strong>of</strong><br />

love: ‘love thy neighbour’—my response to the other must be wholly<br />

and exclusively singular: there must not be indecisiveness on ‘my’<br />

part, for I am already always summoned by love’s commandment,<br />

and moreover I cannot assume a certain amount to time which<br />

assumption <strong>of</strong> a decision would require. I don’t have time; I must<br />

respond absolutely now with utmost urgency, without delay and<br />

without procrastination. Later reading Rosenzweig we shall attempt<br />

to articulate this eventive character <strong>of</strong> temporality that is pure<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> presentation that makes response to the commandment<br />

<strong>of</strong> love irreducible to the immanent order <strong>of</strong> indication or statement,<br />

<strong>of</strong> intention and thematizing knowledge. love’s commandment: ‘love<br />

thy neighbour’ is neither a statement nor explanation to which I


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 313<br />

could have responded posteriori, namely, taking ‘my’ time, evaluating<br />

what at stake in love’s commandment, and what it demands <strong>of</strong> me.<br />

Love’s commandment is rather an non-economic event that addresses<br />

‘me’ here and now, at this moment and at this place, individuating<br />

and isolating myself, alienating me from the rest <strong>of</strong> the world. Such<br />

must be the response from ‘me’ that must be immediate, urgent and<br />

that cries loud here: ‘here I am’.<br />

Strange is the commandment or demand <strong>of</strong> love: it divides the<br />

heart—each one and everyone’s heart—and yet calls forth this<br />

division to give a wholly singular, indivisible, univocal response here<br />

and now, a response for that matter is wholly indivisible, complete<br />

in-itself, like a silence that completes language itself. At the same<br />

time, that means, at the presencing <strong>of</strong> presence where the event <strong>of</strong> love<br />

announces itself, this presencing is divided now and here. Th ere is<br />

always a tomorrow today—a hope contra and beyond all hope—<br />

and there is always a today which is wholly otherwise than ‘today’.<br />

Translation is this infi nite passing through this division, this<br />

threshold between a today and a tomorrow, time and eternity where<br />

love itself traverses and never ceases to traverse. In this traversal and<br />

through this act <strong>of</strong> renewal, love bears witness the promise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial past which is always yet to be fulfi lled, a tomorrow that<br />

may suddenly, incalculably, unforeseeably erupt today, even at this<br />

moment when I am least prepared. For tomorrow to advent today,<br />

for eternity to come here and now, this coming itself must not be<br />

conditioned by the logic <strong>of</strong> auto-generation <strong>of</strong> instants interminably<br />

following other instants in the manner <strong>of</strong> being able to be arranged<br />

on the indiff erent, homogenous, vacant scale <strong>of</strong> time. Th e act <strong>of</strong><br />

translation is infi nite, since it always exposes us to what is irreducibly<br />

un-translatable, to what is always to come and the not yet, but that<br />

this eternity <strong>of</strong> translation may complete itself here and now, or today:<br />

this messianic advent <strong>of</strong> translation can only be thought if tomorrow<br />

may arrive today, only if the universal ‘kinship’ or ‘harmony’ <strong>of</strong><br />

languages, as Benjamin says (Benjamin 1996b., pp. 253-63), may be<br />

able to inscribe itself in the singularity <strong>of</strong> the event that exists as if<br />

without past and without future. For the absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

promise which is untranslatable—for it has never arrived in time,<br />

for it has already always arrived in a time immemorial—not to be<br />

enclosed in the dark seal <strong>of</strong> an immemorial past, this event <strong>of</strong> promise


314 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

must be open to time, to history, to truth. In other words, it must be<br />

translated and renewed each time and every time; it must be exposed<br />

to the wound <strong>of</strong> futurity. It is only on this basis eternity may arrive<br />

today which never arrives in a today that is exhausted or saturated in<br />

its merely following other todays in the indiff erent, vacant manner <strong>of</strong><br />

linear, accumulative progression. Love’s commandment conjures up<br />

diff erent times at the same time, or two responses at the same time:<br />

not just two diff erent instants belonging to the same, indiff erent,<br />

homogenous scale <strong>of</strong> temporality, but the diff erance between eternity<br />

and time, between tomorrow which is always to come and a today<br />

which never ceases to arrive here and now when tomorrow may<br />

momentarily advent as in a lightning fl ash and thereby arresting or<br />

halting the continuity <strong>of</strong> the entirety <strong>of</strong> history coming to standstill.<br />

Th e whole intensity <strong>of</strong> Jacques Derrida’s work seems to me<br />

to lie in the articulation <strong>of</strong> what seems to be a fundamental problematic<br />

in Rosenzweig’s philosophy as well, which is: the welcoming <strong>of</strong><br />

the event <strong>of</strong> transcendence ‘to come’ today conjures up an impossible<br />

and abyssal experience <strong>of</strong> incommensurability <strong>of</strong> temporalities that<br />

does not allow itself to be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> an immanent order<br />

<strong>of</strong> a theodicy <strong>of</strong> history, an impossibility that on the one hand wrecks<br />

in advance the possibility <strong>of</strong> a messianic fulfi lment on the basis <strong>of</strong> a<br />

cumulative, quantitative progression <strong>of</strong> a telos, and yet, at the same<br />

time, is the condition <strong>of</strong> arrival <strong>of</strong> a messianic consummation <strong>of</strong> history<br />

by releasing the event to come from the immanent order <strong>of</strong> the<br />

homogenous scale <strong>of</strong> cumulative time <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

Revelation <strong>of</strong> Love<br />

1. Constellation <strong>of</strong> Elements<br />

It is in this context <strong>of</strong> love’s commandment shall we discuss today<br />

Franz Rosenzweig’s Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption. Franz Rosenzweig’s<br />

Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption begins with a radical deconstruction <strong>of</strong><br />

the systemic metaphysics <strong>of</strong> logos. Th is dominant metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> logos—Rosenzweig calls it ‘the philosophy <strong>of</strong> All’—<strong>of</strong> which<br />

Rosenzweig takes Hegel’s speculative philosophy to be the uttermost<br />

accomplishment is, according to Rosenzweig, a disavowal <strong>of</strong> the


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 315<br />

place <strong>of</strong> mortality for the individual’s existence. It willingly forecloses<br />

the undeniable, imminent facticity <strong>of</strong> fi nitude in mortal’s existence,<br />

for this facticity is the element—which no phenomenology <strong>of</strong> visible<br />

forms can adequately grasp on the basis <strong>of</strong> its categorical cognition—<br />

it is this element that isolates the individual in his/her individuality<br />

from any possibility <strong>of</strong> including it within the universality <strong>of</strong> genus.<br />

Death appears to be the element or phenomenon which is like an<br />

indigestible remainder <strong>of</strong> the system that cannot be formalized or<br />

recounted —, death which is not a phenomenon <strong>of</strong> a telos with<br />

which the destiny <strong>of</strong> existence curves back into itself, like a circle,<br />

but a facticity that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens thought to its way, to its futurity<br />

which is incalculable, unforeseeable and that, because <strong>of</strong> its radical<br />

incalculability and purity <strong>of</strong> its eventive character, does not allow<br />

itself to be curved back into the geometric fi gure <strong>of</strong> being or <strong>of</strong> logos<br />

as circle. What Rosenzweig is concerned above all is the event <strong>of</strong> being<br />

that cannot be enclosed within the philosophical discourse <strong>of</strong> totality.<br />

If with this deconstruction <strong>of</strong> the ‘the philosophy <strong>of</strong> All’ Th e Star<br />

<strong>of</strong> Redemption begins, it is only towards its end the de-formalization<br />

<strong>of</strong> the geometric fi gure <strong>of</strong> the circle <strong>of</strong> being’s curvature— ‘the<br />

intrigue <strong>of</strong> being’ as Levinas says from which, one can say, an<br />

intrigue <strong>of</strong> logos is inseparable (the tradition <strong>of</strong> ‘the intrigue <strong>of</strong> being’<br />

that spreads its sovereignty from ‘Ionia to Jena’)—can be explicitly<br />

elaborated. It is only here and now when it has been shown that<br />

creation, revelation and redemption—in relation to God, Man and<br />

World—are elements <strong>of</strong> reality that has arisen from infi nitude and<br />

opening to an infi nitude that does not curve back into itself, it is here<br />

that the notion <strong>of</strong> confi guration—which is a deformalization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mathematical-geometrical fi gure <strong>of</strong> the circle—may be introduced.<br />

Th is mathematical-geometrical fi gure <strong>of</strong> the circle is, as we know, the<br />

speculative fi gure <strong>of</strong> the ontology <strong>of</strong> the historical reason that excludes<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> being. It is only now when it has been shown that ‘the<br />

absolute magnitude’ <strong>of</strong> these elements can at best be seen as the<br />

limit-concept <strong>of</strong> mathematical-geometrical idea where the singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the points do not form the homogeneity <strong>of</strong> the geometricmathematical<br />

line curving back into itself, the confi guration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Star <strong>of</strong> redemption can be introduced where ‘the new unity’ is not a<br />

totality but an assemblage <strong>of</strong> paths, each one inaugurating a metahistorical<br />

path towards an infi nity <strong>of</strong> the future. Th is infi nity is not


316 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the infi nity <strong>of</strong> the historical reason that cumulatively moves towards<br />

its telos that will not come today, but at the end <strong>of</strong> the line curving<br />

back to its origin. It is however a ‘good infi nity’ in so far as the Star<br />

is still a confi guration. hyperbola <strong>of</strong> this ‘good infi nity’ cannot be the<br />

realization <strong>of</strong> the mathematical idea, but rather ‘the good infi nity’ <strong>of</strong><br />

the absolute magnitude according to a ‘supra-mathematical principle’,<br />

the principle for which—unlike the idealist philosophy <strong>of</strong> totality—<br />

the unity is not here the presupposition but a result that ‘exists only<br />

in becoming’ (Rosenzweig 2005, p. 276). Rosenzweig writes,<br />

For confi guration is diff erentiated from fi gure by the fact that certainly<br />

the confi guration could be composed <strong>of</strong> mathematical fi gures.<br />

Yet that in truth its composition did not take place according to a<br />

mathematical rule, but according to a supra-mathematical principle;<br />

here the thought furnished the principle <strong>of</strong> characterizing the<br />

connections <strong>of</strong> the elementary points as symbols <strong>of</strong> a real happening<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> any realizations <strong>of</strong> a mathematic idea.(Ibid., p. 275).<br />

Th e deformalization <strong>of</strong> the geometric-mathematical fi guration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

curvature—which demands de-structuration <strong>of</strong> the circle <strong>of</strong> the logos<br />

<strong>of</strong> being—is inseparable from Rosenzweig’s de-formalization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

historical time that is, constituted <strong>of</strong> discreet unites as instants, forms<br />

a homogenous line curving back into itself where the end touches<br />

and completes the beginning, where each discreet, additive unite<br />

as the instant fl ees away, irrevocably, with the speed <strong>of</strong> an arrow.<br />

Th e messianic intensity with which the arrival <strong>of</strong> the Messiah who<br />

consummates history is awaited, on the other hand—not allowing<br />

itself to be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> speculative-historical time curving<br />

back into itself—is a radical de-formalization <strong>of</strong> the totality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

discreet unites <strong>of</strong> the instants additively constituting the cumulative,<br />

homogenous line <strong>of</strong> determinable historical progress. Th e messianic<br />

intensity whose de-formalization <strong>of</strong> the fabric <strong>of</strong> time is a violent<br />

disruption, therefore, appears to be the order, or rather disorder <strong>of</strong><br />

a ‘perhaps’. ‘Eternity’, says Rosenzweig, ‘must be hastened, it must<br />

always be capable <strong>of</strong> coming as early as ‘today’; only through it is<br />

it eternity’ (Ibid., p. 306). In order for the eternity to come today,<br />

this absolute magnitude must de-formalize the quantitative infi nite<br />

made up <strong>of</strong> discreet unite <strong>of</strong> instants, additive and cumulative 2 .<br />

Confi guration for Rosenzweig is not a fi gure <strong>of</strong> a quantitative


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 317<br />

infi nitude but a ‘secret’ pre-history that invisibly operates whose<br />

‘secret’ character constitutes its messianic dimension, contra all<br />

historical determination and calculation, contra all the historical,<br />

autochthonous aspiration <strong>of</strong> the messianic politics.<br />

2. Fate<br />

It is in this confi guration <strong>of</strong> ‘elements’ that Rosenzweig articulates the<br />

unfolding <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> revelation as the commandment <strong>of</strong> love.<br />

Irreducible to the immanent order <strong>of</strong> the theodicy <strong>of</strong> history, there<br />

is a messianic dimension that passes through history like a secret<br />

password that constitutes a text <strong>of</strong> so many disruptive moments <strong>of</strong><br />

intensities which the intentional act <strong>of</strong> historical deciphering cannot<br />

reveal. Th ese intensities are not inscription or codifi cation <strong>of</strong> law that<br />

arises from the positing power <strong>of</strong> the intentional act that continually<br />

and progressively—in so far as it is emptied <strong>of</strong> all content—manifests<br />

itself as history, orienting the historical movement irresistibly to its<br />

telos. if is from this pure power <strong>of</strong> positing where discreet unites<br />

<strong>of</strong> instants appear as what Benjamin calls ‘the homogenous empty<br />

time’ (1977, p. 258) that history derives the power <strong>of</strong> its judgement<br />

character in the pr<strong>of</strong>ane world, the intensity <strong>of</strong> messianic advent<br />

on the other hand, in so far as this intensity is irreducible to the<br />

intentional act <strong>of</strong> law-positing judgement, is a judgement upon<br />

history. Th is judgement upon history arrives in the name <strong>of</strong> a fi delity<br />

to an immemorial promise, ethical, <strong>of</strong> a redemptive fulfi lment.<br />

If that is so, then the violence <strong>of</strong> the historical reason cannot be<br />

justifi ed within the immanence <strong>of</strong> a historical telos: it demands an<br />

ethical judgement transcending the historical Reason. It is towards<br />

this ethical judgement that arrives as messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> justice,<br />

without telos—for it may arrive today: it is in this light the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> exemplarity and love as commandment must be understood.<br />

Th erefore Rosenzweig in his Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption, like Walter<br />

Benjamin, evokes a wholly otherwise notion <strong>of</strong> history where the<br />

intensity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> revelation does not so much assume the<br />

intentional act <strong>of</strong> pure law-positing that continually, progressively<br />

manifests as the power <strong>of</strong> judgement, but rather as commandment<br />

<strong>of</strong> love, irreducible to law, whose fullness and exuberance <strong>of</strong> its<br />

pure presencing and pure eruption cannot be thought on the basis


318 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> a temporal and historical determination that is homogenous and<br />

emptied <strong>of</strong> all content. Th erefore for Rosenzweig the intensity and the<br />

exuberance <strong>of</strong> the commandment <strong>of</strong> love can only be a translation <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial promise which is not homogenous and continuous<br />

with settled, sedimented content <strong>of</strong> given tradition, but disruptive,<br />

discontinuous and infi del in the name <strong>of</strong> a more originary fi delity<br />

whose secret password is not judgement and law that constitutes the<br />

messianic politics <strong>of</strong> the world and <strong>of</strong> history and the autochthonous<br />

aspirations <strong>of</strong> particular communities, but that <strong>of</strong> welcoming the<br />

exemplary universality <strong>of</strong> redemption to which all communities<br />

aspire. Yet this possibility <strong>of</strong> the incalculable eruption <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

redemption in the midst <strong>of</strong> time presupposes that there is an essential<br />

‘kinship’ or ‘harmony’ <strong>of</strong> all communities to which all communities<br />

and each community in a singular manner aspires. Beyond the<br />

claims <strong>of</strong> universality by autochthonous particular communities that<br />

constitutes ‘the messianic’ politics, the messianic idea <strong>of</strong> redemption<br />

is an exemplary idea <strong>of</strong> universality which is inseparable from the task<br />

<strong>of</strong> translation. It is here a discussion <strong>of</strong> Walter Benjamin’s thought <strong>of</strong><br />

translation will be most helpful.<br />

In Th e Task <strong>of</strong> the Translator (1996b, pp. 253-63) Benjamin attempts<br />

to think <strong>of</strong> such an exemplary idea <strong>of</strong> universality, given in the task <strong>of</strong><br />

translation, as the messianic end <strong>of</strong> language. Th e possibility <strong>of</strong> this<br />

redemptive, paradisiacal fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> language which for Benjamin<br />

is Adamic language <strong>of</strong> naming, is based on a ‘suprahistorical kinship<br />

between languages [that] consists in this: in every one <strong>of</strong> them<br />

as a whole, one and the same thing is meant’ (Ibid., p.257). Th is<br />

universality <strong>of</strong> the messianic end <strong>of</strong> fulfi lment, <strong>of</strong> the fulfi lment <strong>of</strong><br />

utopian potentialities is not dialectical sublation <strong>of</strong> singularities <strong>of</strong><br />

each language into homogenous consummation <strong>of</strong> universal history<br />

in so far as the irreducible singularity <strong>of</strong> each language resists such<br />

a reductive translation as transmission <strong>of</strong> a communicable content.<br />

Th ere always remains something like a remnant <strong>of</strong> un-translatability in<br />

each language that constitutes the singularity <strong>of</strong> each language. While<br />

such remnant <strong>of</strong> un-translatability makes translation—understood<br />

as translation <strong>of</strong> a communicable content—into the homogenous<br />

consummation <strong>of</strong> universal history impossible, it precisely thereby<br />

opens to the possibility <strong>of</strong> translation in an exemplary sense that is<br />

directed to the messianic realization <strong>of</strong> the originary, immemorial


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 319<br />

promise that consummates history itself, not by the transmission <strong>of</strong><br />

a communicable content, but rather as complementation by ‘the way<br />

<strong>of</strong> meaning it’. the exemplary universality toward the messianic end <strong>of</strong><br />

which the task <strong>of</strong> translation aspires is not the communicative aspect<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, that is ‘what is meant’, but the symbolizing capacity<br />

<strong>of</strong> language, that is, ‘by the way <strong>of</strong> meaning it’. Here co-relative <strong>of</strong><br />

Benjamin’s distinction between the intention <strong>of</strong> ‘what is meant’ and<br />

‘the way <strong>of</strong> meaning it’ is the distinction between the communicative<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> language and the symbolic aspect. While the former exists<br />

‘only in the fi nite product <strong>of</strong> language’, the latter does so ‘in the<br />

evolving <strong>of</strong> the languages themselves’ towards the pure language,<br />

which is the messianic end <strong>of</strong> all language by ‘the way <strong>of</strong> meaning it’.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> translation for Benjamin consists in the regaining <strong>of</strong> this<br />

pure language, the original, immemorial ‘language <strong>of</strong> truth’ through<br />

perpetual renewal, or through perpetual creation <strong>of</strong> the ever new<br />

‘until the messianic end <strong>of</strong> their history’ (Ibid.). Th is pure language<br />

where lies the ultimate essence <strong>of</strong> all languages is now, being released<br />

from all transmission <strong>of</strong> the communicable content, ‘no means or<br />

expresses anything but is, as expressionless and creative Word, that<br />

which is meant in all languages’ (Ibid., p. 261).<br />

Such a pure language which, now being released from the<br />

instrumental, functional character <strong>of</strong> transmitting a communicable<br />

content, is a language which, meaning or expressing nothing but<br />

itself, appears as itself in its purity: language that is given as originary<br />

promise in an immemorial past. Th is pure language is for Rosenzweig<br />

silence which is not a reticence or defi ance <strong>of</strong> the tragic hero, or the<br />

mute suff ering <strong>of</strong> nature, but the language <strong>of</strong> redemption where<br />

language completes itself, that is, it universalizes itself in an exemplary<br />

manner. Such universality is the restitution <strong>of</strong> the immemorial<br />

promise through ever renewed invention <strong>of</strong> the new, which is never a<br />

mimetic reproduction <strong>of</strong> the given, but ever new invention that opens<br />

time to the incalculable eruption <strong>of</strong> the messianic end <strong>of</strong> history<br />

itself. For Rosenzweig and also for Benjamin such a possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

ever renewing invention <strong>of</strong> the new is essentially related to the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> revelation that opens up language beyond its medium character <strong>of</strong><br />

communication to the pure language <strong>of</strong> truth.<br />

Such an ever renewed invention <strong>of</strong> the new that is immersed only in<br />

the ever new presentation <strong>of</strong> ‘now’ moment, irreducibly singular each


320 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

time is also an infi delity to the past or future. For Rosenzweig such is<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> revelation that love tears open existent from the closure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the past, and exposes it to the ever new event <strong>of</strong> pure presentation.<br />

For the beloved who is evoked and invoked by the commandment <strong>of</strong><br />

love, existence is wholly presencing, oblivious <strong>of</strong> past and future. Th is<br />

infi delity alone releases the event <strong>of</strong> love from the order <strong>of</strong> creation<br />

sealed in the past, and also from the order <strong>of</strong> the violence <strong>of</strong> law<br />

that presupposes its duration in the future. Only in its infi delity, love<br />

can appear as pure event, as irreducible act <strong>of</strong> renewal that opens<br />

time beyond the thematizing order <strong>of</strong> statement and beyond the<br />

order <strong>of</strong> law-positing violence. Without this infi delity—which is also<br />

the infi delity <strong>of</strong> translation in that it never mimetically reproduces<br />

the given tradition—to the sedimented past in the name <strong>of</strong> a more<br />

originary fi delity, the immemorial promise assumes the character <strong>of</strong><br />

fate (Moira) that is then sealed <strong>of</strong>f from all messianic realization in<br />

here and now; it then sinks into the immanence <strong>of</strong> the dark abyss<br />

<strong>of</strong> the past, and assumes various closures <strong>of</strong> necessity. To wrest the<br />

immemorial promise from such immanent closures with which death<br />

seals it <strong>of</strong>f requires a work <strong>of</strong> translation equally powerful as death. It<br />

must be able to struggle against death, against death’s imminence and<br />

necessity, to release the immemorial promise from the character <strong>of</strong><br />

fate. Such is the strife <strong>of</strong> love against death which is also translation <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial promise in the ever renewing presence here and now.<br />

It is now we can properly begin to read Rosenzweig, at that moment<br />

where Rosenzweig himself begins: with the proverb that says ‘love as<br />

strong as death’.<br />

3. Eruption and Presencing<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> translation is essentially a messianic task whose secret<br />

password is not history but redemption. Its password is given<br />

as promise immemorially, in an already always <strong>of</strong> a past that has<br />

never been a phenomenon <strong>of</strong> history’s immanent Parousia. It is not<br />

the intentional act <strong>of</strong> the pure power <strong>of</strong> positing (that posits the<br />

judgement <strong>of</strong> history as the source <strong>of</strong> the meaning <strong>of</strong> events) but an<br />

immemorial promise that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens the world, time and truth,<br />

and its consummation alone can assume the intensity <strong>of</strong> justice.<br />

Rosenzweig calls this originary opening <strong>of</strong> the world, the origin


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 321<br />

that no memory can ever retrieve and hence can only be a past, an<br />

immemorial past: creation. Here the infl uence <strong>of</strong> Schelling’s later work<br />

on Rosenzweig is remarkable. In Schelling (2000) a logic <strong>of</strong> origin is<br />

thought in relation a past (gewesen) that is already always, a beginning<br />

before any beginning that has receded into the dark abyss <strong>of</strong> past that<br />

is forever unfathomable, an ‘irreducible remainder’ that cannot be<br />

grounded in the historical reason, or in the theodicy <strong>of</strong> history. For<br />

Rosenzweig, the abyss <strong>of</strong> this origin that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens the world<br />

is also the origin <strong>of</strong> promise. Th e promise is given already always,<br />

groundlessly, once and for all, in the manner that is absolutely singular<br />

and absolutely heterogeneous in relation to the immanent becoming<br />

<strong>of</strong> the theodicy <strong>of</strong> history. Yet that which has occurred only once and<br />

for all, as that singular event that has groundlessly erupted, and that<br />

can never be repeated once again is the secret password <strong>of</strong> a messianic<br />

history that must be passed on and be eternalized and universalized.<br />

Here continuity <strong>of</strong> the secret password does not function like the<br />

Hypokeimenon <strong>of</strong> the Subject <strong>of</strong> the predicative-speculative universal<br />

history; it is rather the continuity <strong>of</strong> the immemorial promise that<br />

occurs throughout that other history in an exemplary fashion in the<br />

act <strong>of</strong> translation that means, through the acts <strong>of</strong> supplementation<br />

and complementation.<br />

Th e translation <strong>of</strong> the absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> promise is<br />

given only once, and that can never be repeated into the language <strong>of</strong><br />

universal, or rather it can only be repeated each time singularly, each<br />

time anew, that means, in an act <strong>of</strong> infi delity to the tradition that<br />

is founded by, or opened by the immemorial, originary, founding<br />

event <strong>of</strong> promise. Th is translation is never mimetic (understood<br />

in a reductive sense) reproduction <strong>of</strong> the ‘original’ but only occurs<br />

in an exemplary manner, in the act <strong>of</strong> remembrance that Walter<br />

Benjamin associates with philosophical contemplation, which is<br />

always the remembrance <strong>of</strong> the immemorial which is each time to<br />

be recovered, and each time through an act that is radically new,<br />

incalculable eruption <strong>of</strong> the something wholly other. In that way<br />

the immanent order <strong>of</strong> historical violence, or the immanent order<br />

<strong>of</strong> tradition based on memorial act <strong>of</strong> transmission is opened up, by<br />

an infi nite act <strong>of</strong> translation, to the intensity <strong>of</strong> a messianic justice<br />

whose arrival cannot be anticipated in the innermost ground that


322 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

is the gathered by the memorial act <strong>of</strong> tradition, because it opens up<br />

to a dimension <strong>of</strong> an immemorial founding event that has already<br />

opened us to truth and to justice, beyond intention, and precisely<br />

thereby, is beyond the order <strong>of</strong> fate. Th is opening to the fateless order<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice is evoked for man by the commandment <strong>of</strong> love, in the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> revelation, that turns itself to the affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a universal<br />

community to come, the Kingdom <strong>of</strong> God as Rosenzweig says. It is<br />

towards this event <strong>of</strong> coming community, which nevertheless may<br />

erupt today, despite the logic <strong>of</strong> historical reason, that the infi nite<br />

task <strong>of</strong> translation is oriented.<br />

Here I have taken up the theme <strong>of</strong> exemplarity that Jacques Derrida<br />

elaborated. Th e inscription <strong>of</strong> the universal in the singular, according<br />

to Derrida, is never that <strong>of</strong> inscription <strong>of</strong> law in the particular where<br />

the particular (in so far as the particular is the mere instance <strong>of</strong><br />

genus), through its negativity—that means, as a ‘work <strong>of</strong> death’—<br />

passes into the anonymity <strong>of</strong> the universal foundation. Th erefore,<br />

the translation in the exemplary sense where the immemorial promise<br />

invisibly operates throughout meta-history can be renewed only on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the eruption <strong>of</strong> the ever new event <strong>of</strong> love (understood in<br />

the irreducible sense <strong>of</strong> its verbal resonance)—which is the work <strong>of</strong><br />

love—that means, only in the act <strong>of</strong> infi delity <strong>of</strong> love which knows<br />

only presence, and none other. Th e event <strong>of</strong> love is a commandment<br />

and not law, for it is oriented to the intensity <strong>of</strong> a justice which as<br />

such is without fate and without goal.<br />

Th e immemorial promise given in an originary origin must be<br />

translated. Th is translation for Rosenzweig is translation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

promise given in creation into the event <strong>of</strong> love in revelation. Th is<br />

is the fi rst demand <strong>of</strong> translation: that the absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

promise given in the irrecuperable past must be renewed in each here<br />

and now, in the event <strong>of</strong> revelation and as work <strong>of</strong> love so that the<br />

promise may not be lost in the eternal abyss <strong>of</strong> the past. Translation<br />

that does not mimetically reproduce the originary promise but<br />

only by the eruption <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> the new hic et nunc, precisely<br />

through this infi delity <strong>of</strong> impermanence, invisibly orients that<br />

promise towards redemption <strong>of</strong> the world. Th e absolute singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the promise whose absolute eventive character (irreducible to the<br />

language <strong>of</strong> predicates and explication), if it is allowed to remain


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 323<br />

in the absoluteness <strong>of</strong> singularity, acquires Moira: the fate character<br />

<strong>of</strong> necessity that remains sealed <strong>of</strong>f from becoming and movement.<br />

Th erefore it is necessary in order to open this immemorial promise<br />

be opened to time and the world, a reversal <strong>of</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

promise that tends to seal itself <strong>of</strong>f in the immanence <strong>of</strong> creation.<br />

Th e act that would forcefully open the seal <strong>of</strong> fate where promise<br />

is imprisoned is itself a violence, an assertion <strong>of</strong> freedom against<br />

Moira which is an act <strong>of</strong> love irreducible to ‘law-positing’ and ‘law<br />

preserving’ violence which for Water Benjamin (1986, pp. 277-300)<br />

constitutes ‘the mythic violence’. Th e absolute singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial promise is now open to the possibility <strong>of</strong> renewal in ever<br />

new eruption and presencing, each time making itself reveal as if for<br />

the fi rst time. Th is eruption and presencing, each time absolutely new<br />

and absolutely promising is an event <strong>of</strong> pure presencing that cannot be<br />

explicated on the basis <strong>of</strong> predicative proposition that can arise only<br />

belated to the event. Rosenzweig here distinguishes this event <strong>of</strong> pure<br />

presencing that erupts as the lightning fl ash ‘in the blink <strong>of</strong> the eye’<br />

from the immanent logos <strong>of</strong> historical reason which manifests itself as<br />

in a continuous, homogenous and cumulative manner moving to a<br />

determined telos. While here for Rosenzweig ‘the blink <strong>of</strong> the eye’—<br />

where the revelation is the event <strong>of</strong> eruption and pure presencing—is<br />

wholly ‘word uttered aloud’, for Benjamin this fl ash is ‘the dialectical<br />

image’ which is the weak, impoverished refl ection—as in a mirror—<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity. Rosenzweig writes,<br />

[Revelation] can be nothing other than self negation <strong>of</strong> a merely mute<br />

essence by a word uttered loud, the opening up <strong>of</strong> something locked,<br />

<strong>of</strong> a silently reposing permanence by the movement <strong>of</strong> a blink <strong>of</strong> the<br />

eye. In the illumination <strong>of</strong> such a blink <strong>of</strong> the eye there resides the force<br />

to transform the created-being that is touched by this illumination by<br />

turning the created ‘thing’ into the testimony <strong>of</strong> a Revelation that has<br />

come to pass’ (Rosenzweig 2005, p. 174).<br />

And,<br />

It is only in this way—when it is no longer a testimony <strong>of</strong> the<br />

revelation that has occurred in general, but the externalization <strong>of</strong> a<br />

Revelation that occurs ‘just now’ at this moment—it is only then that<br />

the thing steps out <strong>of</strong> the past <strong>of</strong> its essence and enters into its living<br />

light (Ibid., p. 175).


324 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th e immemorial, eternal promise—which must always be there,<br />

eternally opening history to its immemorial origin—now entering<br />

into the ‘testimony <strong>of</strong> revelation’ through the act <strong>of</strong> translation which<br />

is the event <strong>of</strong> love is also entering into infi delity, adhering in the<br />

translation itself, only because the highest fi delity to the immemorial<br />

promise demands the act <strong>of</strong> translation. Love must translate the<br />

untranslatable: this infi delity <strong>of</strong> translation is for Rosenzweig the<br />

infi delity <strong>of</strong> love, for only on the basis <strong>of</strong> infi delity eternity can be<br />

translated in the non-permanence <strong>of</strong> the here and now, which is not<br />

mere a particular instantiation <strong>of</strong> the universal history but ‘now’<br />

time—<strong>of</strong> what Benjamin calls Jetztzeit—<strong>of</strong> God’s commandment<br />

exposing the past <strong>of</strong> creation to the event <strong>of</strong> revelation. Th e event<br />

<strong>of</strong> love is here a fi nite-infi nitude—pure presencing <strong>of</strong> the eternal<br />

here and now—not the infi nitude as in Hegel that will have fi nitude<br />

within it as sublated but an infi nitude that exposed to and wounded<br />

by fi nitude. To translate means each time the task <strong>of</strong> exposure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immanent order <strong>of</strong> tradition guaranteed by the unifying, internalizing,<br />

totalizing act <strong>of</strong> memory to the event <strong>of</strong> the immemorial opening<br />

through each time eruption <strong>of</strong> the incalculably new; it is to expose<br />

the self-satisfaction <strong>of</strong> an immanent ground to its own unworking<br />

only to open up the speculative tradition to its consummation by the<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> the messianic justice.<br />

Th ere is the translation <strong>of</strong> the absolute heterogeneity and singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> immemorial promise into the universal only on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pure exposure to the peril <strong>of</strong> fi nitude. Th is fi nitude does not function<br />

like the logic <strong>of</strong> mediation as in Hegelian logic. For Rosenzweig this<br />

fi nitude is essentially the peril <strong>of</strong> love where man himself ‘dies in<br />

becoming lover and is reborn as lover’ (Ibid., pp. 176-177). Th e<br />

exemplarity <strong>of</strong> translation lies in its essential perilous character: the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>oundest fi delity to the immemorial past promise demands the deepest<br />

infi delity <strong>of</strong> the non-permanence <strong>of</strong> eruption and pure presencing. 3<br />

Th e eruption and pure presencing <strong>of</strong> love that are immersed in the<br />

ever renewing here and now as if ‘every dead yesterday and tomorrow<br />

are one day swallowed into this triumphant today’ (Ibid., p. 178).<br />

Th is makes the revelation <strong>of</strong> love an event and not an attribute.<br />

Rosenzweig writes: ‘love is not an attribute, but event, and there<br />

is no place in it for an attribute’ (Ibid., p. 177). Irreducible to the<br />

conditioned order <strong>of</strong> predicates, indications and explanation where


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 325<br />

language appears as mere medium <strong>of</strong> transmitting given content,<br />

here language <strong>of</strong> love itself is the pure communication that in ‘the<br />

blink <strong>of</strong> the eye’ transforms the creational aspect <strong>of</strong> the created being<br />

into its unconditional eruption and presencing to presence, that is,<br />

to the order <strong>of</strong> revelation. In revelation therefore nothing is really<br />

revealed—a content that pre-determined and existed in a pre-given<br />

form. In this sense revelation is not a mimetic reproduction <strong>of</strong><br />

the given original promise as a simple translation <strong>of</strong> a pre-existing<br />

content. In the event <strong>of</strong> revelation the world now, released and<br />

purifi ed from its fate character, becomes wholly language, where<br />

language appears itself in its purity where the lover calls the beloved<br />

in her proper name. Th is language is not the language <strong>of</strong> indication<br />

and explanation, <strong>of</strong> statement and predicative proposition that arises<br />

only after the event <strong>of</strong> revelation. It is rather language itself erupts<br />

and presences but without summoning itself fate or goal. In this fateless<br />

and goal-less world, everything becomes word 4 . Rosenzweig says,<br />

In the world <strong>of</strong> revelation everything becomes word, and that which<br />

cannot become so is either before or after it (Ibid., 193).<br />

As pure eruption and presencing <strong>of</strong> language, language itself is an<br />

event <strong>of</strong> the world that is revealed as essentially linguistic. Th is event<br />

<strong>of</strong> language is prior to the language <strong>of</strong> objectivity and knowledge, <strong>of</strong><br />

intentionality <strong>of</strong> the communicative agent that would then enable<br />

the codifi cation <strong>of</strong> law. Th erefore the event <strong>of</strong> language can only arise<br />

as commandment that assumes the form <strong>of</strong> ‘I’ <strong>of</strong> the proper name,<br />

and that can only appear in the suddenness <strong>of</strong> eruption, in ‘the blink<br />

<strong>of</strong> the eye’.<br />

4. Th e Proper Name<br />

Th e readers <strong>of</strong> Hegel’s Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit remember that<br />

language <strong>of</strong> the proper name is essentially an exposure <strong>of</strong> oneself to<br />

death. One who says ‘I’ exposes himself or herself thereby to the<br />

pure power <strong>of</strong> annihilation <strong>of</strong> its sensuous immediacy. It is here the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> the universal that now assumes the law <strong>of</strong> judgement arises<br />

as the possibility <strong>of</strong> annihilation <strong>of</strong> the sensuous particularity, and<br />

restitution <strong>of</strong> the universal in its place. For Rosenzweig on the other<br />

hand, the proper name denominates that singularity that irreducibly


326 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

places itself outside the universality <strong>of</strong> genus, and that erupts, as the<br />

pure event <strong>of</strong> language, in the revelation <strong>of</strong> the commandment <strong>of</strong><br />

love. As such, the proper name denominates for Rosenzweig the event<br />

<strong>of</strong> being invoked by the commandment <strong>of</strong> love. It is this eruption<br />

<strong>of</strong> the being that erupts in the vocative and not as nominative that<br />

irreducibly places such a being outside the philosophical totality. Th is<br />

being is not the part <strong>of</strong> the intrigue that by exposing being to death<br />

restitutes the power <strong>of</strong> law-positing and law-preserving violence, that<br />

is, the universal that posits itself as the power <strong>of</strong> totality. Th is event<br />

<strong>of</strong> being invoked by the commandment <strong>of</strong> love and which is open to<br />

itself, beyond the order <strong>of</strong> fate and creatureliness in the proper name,<br />

is fi rst <strong>of</strong> all denomination <strong>of</strong> the event that opens it to an universality<br />

in an uncommon sense, in an exemplary sense. Th is universality<br />

is the order <strong>of</strong> redemption which is a community always to come,<br />

and therefore that cannot be understood as the order <strong>of</strong> genus or by<br />

‘common essence’ underlined by the unity <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Subject.<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> revelation in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love as the<br />

eruption <strong>of</strong> the name and <strong>of</strong> language does not constitute the law <strong>of</strong><br />

universal history. Outside law, outside the judgement <strong>of</strong> a theodicy<br />

<strong>of</strong> history and more originary than the order <strong>of</strong> the inscription <strong>of</strong> the<br />

universal in the particular through the intentional act <strong>of</strong> positing,<br />

is this event <strong>of</strong> revelation that opens the singular being bearing the<br />

proper name to the call <strong>of</strong> love that asks this singular being: ‘where<br />

art thou?’ the proper name for Rosenzweig is the gift <strong>of</strong> love that<br />

arises with the event <strong>of</strong> revelation addressing the singular being to<br />

respond to the commandment to love. Th e proper name is not here<br />

the defi ant ‘I’ <strong>of</strong> the tragic hero. Rosenzweig distinguishes here the<br />

defi ant ‘I’ <strong>of</strong> the tragic hero whose decline constitutes, precisely at<br />

the utmost limit <strong>of</strong> its passivity confronting his fate, his selfi cation<br />

from the ‘I’ with a proper name here whose defi ance is not that <strong>of</strong><br />

the tragic hero <strong>of</strong> fate but that <strong>of</strong> the one who has entered the fateless<br />

order <strong>of</strong> love, that is, the linguistic order <strong>of</strong> commandment <strong>of</strong> love<br />

where the eruption <strong>of</strong> love’s commandment tears away the defi ance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the created being enclosed in the immanence <strong>of</strong> its creativeness.<br />

In this order, unlike the tragic hero, man does not gain immortality<br />

by his death, by assuming the danger <strong>of</strong> his peril; here man passes<br />

away without fate and reborn as lover, as the one whose entire


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 327<br />

being is immersed and absorbed in the in the event <strong>of</strong> love. Th e<br />

linguistic order <strong>of</strong> the proper name consists <strong>of</strong> being called by love,<br />

<strong>of</strong> being summoned by the commandment <strong>of</strong> love. It is the order <strong>of</strong><br />

evocation and vocative, and not nominative that exposes being to<br />

transcendence: where are you? Only such a singular individual who<br />

is now aroused to the fateless order <strong>of</strong> love can be radically open to<br />

the messianic consummation <strong>of</strong> history arriving from the extremity<br />

<strong>of</strong> future which is to come. Since this singular individual who is lover<br />

is not a mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> genus 5 , he is irreducible to the realm <strong>of</strong><br />

the totality <strong>of</strong> the objects designated by concepts and that is covered<br />

over by the indefi nite and defi nite articles. Only he escapes the order<br />

<strong>of</strong> violence <strong>of</strong> the historical reason.<br />

Here the proper name <strong>of</strong> the lover steps forth, outside the<br />

totality <strong>of</strong> the predicates, indications and explanations, as a pure<br />

presencing, as pure event <strong>of</strong> time, as singularity <strong>of</strong> response to the call<br />

or commandment coming from the wholly other. Proper name is<br />

naming man himself as pure singular who is torn open, exposed and<br />

wounded open by the call <strong>of</strong> the other. Proper name is a responding<br />

answer which, in its singularity does not belong to the general<br />

order <strong>of</strong> validity—that is, the intentional, positing realm <strong>of</strong> law and<br />

cognition—an answer responding to the transcendence <strong>of</strong> the other.<br />

Revelation is ‘a matter <strong>of</strong> invoking the name’, the name which is the<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> space into the site where Revelation radiates.<br />

In the place <strong>of</strong> his general concepts ... there appears that which cannot<br />

run and is simply called the particular, that which has no concept<br />

and slips away from the domain which both articles, the defi nite and<br />

the indefi nite... Th e proper name which exactly not a proper name,<br />

not a name which was given arbitrarily to man, but the name that<br />

God himself took for him and which for this reason only—to be a<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> the creation—properly belongs to him. To God’s question:<br />

‘where are you?’? a man still remained a you, as a defi ant, obstinate<br />

itself ; when called by name twice, with the strongest fi xity <strong>of</strong> purpose<br />

to which one cannot remain deaf, the man, totally open, totally<br />

unfolded, totally ready, totally—soul, now answers: ‘ I am here’.(<br />

Rosenzweig 2005, p. 190).<br />

If for Rosenzweig the proper name does not designate the particular<br />

as mere instantiation <strong>of</strong> the universal, but the denomination <strong>of</strong><br />

that irreducible singularity outside the order <strong>of</strong> totality constituted


328 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

by general concepts and articles, then here for the fi rst time the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> an exemplarity arises in<br />

an originary manner. Th e thinking <strong>of</strong> exemplarity is the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> a denomination and the verbal, irreducible to the indications<br />

and explanations, <strong>of</strong> articles indefi nite and defi nite. Exemplarity is<br />

attention to this messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> denomination and verbal that<br />

marks the event <strong>of</strong> language erupting in the presencing <strong>of</strong> revelation,<br />

in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love. Here it is the question <strong>of</strong> language as<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> pure presentation than that <strong>of</strong> representation that opens<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> translation, oriented to the messianic ‘language <strong>of</strong><br />

truth’—as Benjamin used to say—<strong>of</strong> the immemorial presence to the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> presencing and to the event <strong>of</strong> a messianic future always,<br />

eternally to come, which for that matter may arrive even today.<br />

5. Messianicity<br />

Th ough the event <strong>of</strong> revelation opens the seal <strong>of</strong> the immemorial<br />

presence from the dark abyss <strong>of</strong> creation and hereby translating<br />

the mute, speechless death into the event <strong>of</strong> language that erupts<br />

in love, the promise is not yet consummated. Th e world is not yet<br />

completed, history is not yet consummated and redeemed: hence<br />

the necessity, <strong>of</strong> one more (that means infi nite) act <strong>of</strong> translation<br />

that would transform the pure presencing <strong>of</strong> revelation into an<br />

affi rmation <strong>of</strong> the pure future, where the love between man and<br />

God, immersed in the exuberance <strong>of</strong> the here and now, where love<br />

does not reach beyond the plenitude <strong>of</strong> pure presencing, this love<br />

needs to be opened up beyond presence to the eternity <strong>of</strong> the future<br />

which is always to come. Here Rosenzweig’s messianic conception <strong>of</strong><br />

history, beyond dialectical closure, opens to the messianic event <strong>of</strong><br />

pure arrival that is truly exemplary: that is, the notion <strong>of</strong> messianic<br />

fulfi lment as consummation <strong>of</strong> history coming from an extremity <strong>of</strong><br />

time, from an extremity <strong>of</strong> future that translates the extremity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immemorial promise that passes through, as invisible, secret password<br />

<strong>of</strong> history. Here Rosenzweig combines two diff erent forms <strong>of</strong> utopian<br />

fulfi lment: the possibility <strong>of</strong> reactivation <strong>of</strong> the immemorial past on<br />

the one hand, which is just as redemptive as hope in the eruption <strong>of</strong><br />

the radically new.


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 329<br />

Stéphane Mosès in his Th e Angel <strong>of</strong> History (2009) distinguishes<br />

these two tendencies <strong>of</strong> Jewish messianism: restorative, or<br />

archaeological on the one hand, and utopian or eschatological on the<br />

other hand that constitutes the ambivalence <strong>of</strong> messianism. While<br />

the restorative messianism is concerned with the re-establishment <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial, originary promise, the eschatological messianism is<br />

concerned with fi nal consummation <strong>of</strong> history that can only be radical<br />

upheaval or radical eruption <strong>of</strong> the absolutely new, heterogeneous<br />

to all that has become, for truth exists only in this eruption <strong>of</strong> the<br />

new, in the becoming that is never dialectical, for this eruption that<br />

does not close itself up like the geometric fi gure <strong>of</strong> the logos as circle.<br />

In his brilliant and remarkable study <strong>of</strong> the early messianic works<br />

<strong>of</strong> Walter Benjamin and Gershom Scholem, Eric Jacobson (2003)<br />

poses this question as the central question regarding messianism:<br />

does the Messiah initiates or consummates history? Here Jacobson<br />

distinguishes the messianic consummation <strong>of</strong> history from the telos<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dialectical historical reason,<br />

[Messianic] that is placed in relationship to creative act is an end that<br />

harbours no worldly telos, no self-generation, no intention, no motor<br />

<strong>of</strong> history—it is merely the inverse <strong>of</strong> beginning. Towards creation<br />

it appears messianic, for it alone completes creation. A determinate<br />

end, which is understood in relation to creation and constituted as<br />

messianic, is therefore an end in redemption. (Jacobson 2003, p. 26)<br />

Th e archaeological, restorative tendency <strong>of</strong> the messianic is not<br />

incommensurable from the eschatological consummation <strong>of</strong> history.<br />

Th is alone makes Rosenzweig’s messianicity—to which above remarks<br />

are applicable—an exemplary thought, for on the basis <strong>of</strong> this alone<br />

the fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> the immemorial and original promise that initiates<br />

history can arrive from the extremity <strong>of</strong> future, not as archè that<br />

necessarily, in a determinate manner fulfi ls itself as telos in the pr<strong>of</strong>ane<br />

history, but incalculably, in an unforeseen manner, the logic <strong>of</strong> which<br />

invisibly operates in history whose secret password is redemption.<br />

Th is exemplarity that brings together in the Now the extremities <strong>of</strong><br />

messianic temporality in the act <strong>of</strong> translation that secretly passes<br />

the immemoriality <strong>of</strong> the past promise through presencing <strong>of</strong> the<br />

presence <strong>of</strong> revelation to the consummation <strong>of</strong> history (which may


330 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

be yet arrive here and now): such is the messianic task <strong>of</strong> translation<br />

given in the commandment <strong>of</strong> love.<br />

If that is so, then the commandment <strong>of</strong> love that Rosenzweig<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> can be understood as the commandment <strong>of</strong> translation:<br />

translate the immemoriality <strong>of</strong> promise into its redemptive,<br />

messianic fulfi lment. Since it is the question concerning translating<br />

the untranslatable, such a messianic demand never fi nds satisfaction<br />

in the historical realization <strong>of</strong> utopia, for it speaks in the name <strong>of</strong><br />

an absolute that does not recognize its face in any given epochal<br />

manifestation that arises out <strong>of</strong> historical Reason. It demands <strong>of</strong> an<br />

arrival <strong>of</strong> an eternity here and now: a radical rupture or interruption<br />

<strong>of</strong> the continuity that marks the telos <strong>of</strong> a historical time. How does,<br />

then, the eternity—which is the extremity <strong>of</strong> the future—arrive here<br />

and now? Th is is the question that concerns Rosenzweig in his Th e<br />

Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption. For Rosenzweig such an impossible possibility,<br />

or rather the possible impossibility is revealed in the commandment<br />

<strong>of</strong> love. Th is is revealed in the fact that love is not satisfi ed merely<br />

being revealed love that is immersed in the absoluteness <strong>of</strong> the pure<br />

presencing <strong>of</strong> presence between God and man; it demands translation<br />

in the world, in the community so that love does not merely remain<br />

between ‘I’ and ‘You’. a step beyond the love between the two and<br />

a step beyond the event <strong>of</strong> presencing is necessary ; a community, a<br />

Kingdom to come, a futurity whose radicality is not that <strong>of</strong> a telos,<br />

needs to be opened up beyond the presencing <strong>of</strong> revelation, for the<br />

world still appears to be incomplete, unfi nished, unconsummated.<br />

Th e event <strong>of</strong> love is not exhausted in the love between the lover and<br />

beloved, that <strong>of</strong>, its affi rmation <strong>of</strong> opening time by breaking open<br />

the seal <strong>of</strong> the past creation; it also demands opening up the seal <strong>of</strong><br />

the self, immersed in the exuberance <strong>of</strong> presencing, to the world,<br />

unfi nished, uncompleted, unconsummated: ‘Th e self had to emerge<br />

from its muteness to become speaking self’ (Rosenzweig 2005, p.<br />

224).<br />

‘Love thy Neighbour’ is a translation <strong>of</strong> the commandment <strong>of</strong> love<br />

revealed in God’s question: ‘where are you?’ where God’s love turns<br />

towards to the world, to the neighbour who is the ‘placeholder’ <strong>of</strong><br />

future. It is here the singularity <strong>of</strong> the pure presencing <strong>of</strong> presence<br />

where love between man and the wholly other is revealed turns


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 331<br />

to the universality and community which is always coming, since<br />

it is not yet completed and not yet fi nished, a coming community.<br />

Such a coming community or universality, for Rosenzweig, is not<br />

exhausted in the predicates about the world, neither is it defi ned<br />

by an ontological, ‘common’ essence that autochtonously grounds<br />

that which constitutes the messianic politics <strong>of</strong> community, states,<br />

etc., nor can it be thought as the general order <strong>of</strong> validity legitimized<br />

by the a priori <strong>of</strong> a moral law. Such a world cannot be grasped by<br />

the logical application <strong>of</strong> cognition. It is in this sense a meta-logical<br />

world, for what Rosenzweig is concerned here with is not so much<br />

an immanent order <strong>of</strong> necessity or a totality <strong>of</strong> objects and entities<br />

which can be predicated by apophansis: it is rather the worlding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world or opening <strong>of</strong> the world that as such is not yet fi nished, and<br />

not yet consummated but always to come. To turn the commandment<br />

<strong>of</strong> love erupted in revelation to the world <strong>of</strong> the neighbour who is<br />

absolutely absolved from genus is to turn to a world that advents<br />

from an extremity <strong>of</strong> future. It is at once absolved from the order <strong>of</strong><br />

law, and the violence <strong>of</strong> immanent historical reason, as it is absolved<br />

from the logical, categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> cognition. As such it is only an<br />

infi nite awaiting for the messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> justice that alone may<br />

redeem the world. Rosenzweig says,<br />

In the love <strong>of</strong> the neighbour, it is the rupture, unceasingly begun<br />

over again <strong>of</strong> the lasting form <strong>of</strong> the character through the always<br />

unforeseen irruption <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> love. What this act consists <strong>of</strong> in the<br />

particular case cannot be told in advance for precisely this reason; it<br />

must be unforeseen; if it could be pointed out in advance, this would<br />

not be an act <strong>of</strong> love (Ibid., p. 232).<br />

Th e coming community <strong>of</strong> redemption is not the universal realization<br />

<strong>of</strong> the historical telos with which the unfolding <strong>of</strong> the theodicy <strong>of</strong><br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>ane world curves back into itself, into the immanence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Parousia <strong>of</strong> the historical Subject. It is rather a community that is a<br />

singular universal, or idiomatically universal which can only be nonautochthonous,<br />

the unfolding <strong>of</strong> which is not the auto-generative<br />

growth <strong>of</strong> historical time. Th e growing that moves towards the<br />

messianic end ‘does not have any relationship to time’ but to the<br />

eternity <strong>of</strong> coming which is not an unattainable, quantifi able length


332 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, but an abundance or exuberance <strong>of</strong> an eternity which may<br />

arrive just tomorrow. Th is eternity to come tomorrow time must<br />

have a relationship to eternity which not the ripening or growing<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, but it invokes a time that arrives or unfolds in a reverse<br />

direction, a future that is coming towards us from the extremity <strong>of</strong><br />

its site, rather than merely we are going towards it as if we are driven<br />

to a defi nite goal by the irresistible, irreversible wind <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

becoming. Eternity is for Rosenzweig not a very long time but,<br />

…[A] tomorrow that just as well could be today. Eternity is a future,<br />

which, without ceasing to be a future, is nevertheless present. Eternity<br />

is a today that would be conscious <strong>of</strong> being more than today. And to<br />

say that the Kingdom is eternally coming means that its growth is no<br />

doubt necessary, but that the rhythm <strong>of</strong> this growth is not defi nite, or<br />

more exactly: that the growth does not have any relationship to time<br />

(Ibid., p. 241).<br />

Such an uncommon understanding <strong>of</strong> community to come which,<br />

‘without ceasing to be a future’ may nevertheless advent ‘today’<br />

demands a radical deformalization <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> historical time<br />

as ‘growth’ or a ‘ripening’ which posits its telos at an unattainable<br />

length which for that matter, because <strong>of</strong> its irreversibility, cannot be<br />

last today. Th e messianicity <strong>of</strong> the coming community on the other<br />

hand, a community where redemption renders the task <strong>of</strong> translation<br />

complete in the universality <strong>of</strong> its harmony and in an exemplary<br />

manner, rends each moment that can be the last. for Rosenzweig<br />

the thought <strong>of</strong> messianicity and exemplarity does not consist in the<br />

inclusion <strong>of</strong> the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the particular within the universal totality<br />

<strong>of</strong> being that makes telos into the ripening or growing <strong>of</strong> time, but<br />

rather the possibility <strong>of</strong> a radical reversibility <strong>of</strong> time where eternity<br />

can be the last. Th is is truly the site from where there occurs the<br />

origin <strong>of</strong> futurity and not merely as the end or goal <strong>of</strong> time. It is in<br />

this sense the messianic arrival where translation <strong>of</strong> the promise here<br />

and now makes eternity to come today is goalless: without entering<br />

into the order <strong>of</strong> fate, such a time without time can only be thought<br />

as eternal awaiting or anticipation. ‘Th at every moment can be the<br />

last’ says Rosenzweig ‘renders it eternal. And just the fact that every<br />

moment can be the last makes it the origin <strong>of</strong> the future, as a series<br />

<strong>of</strong> which every member is anticipated by the fi rst one’ (Ibid., p. 243).


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 333<br />

It is in this sense redemption as the messianic fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

community is an exemplary thought in that without subsuming the<br />

particular within the universal essence <strong>of</strong> being, makes each time the<br />

universality into singular and singularity into universal affi rmation.<br />

Th is intensity <strong>of</strong> desire operates as invisible dimension <strong>of</strong> historical<br />

time, that messiah be arrived before his time, and that other equally<br />

incommensurable demand from where the infi nite movement <strong>of</strong><br />

anticipation originates, that ‘ at every moment it fails to unite for the<br />

end’ (Ibid.). Th at eternity <strong>of</strong> the radical future may arrive today, and<br />

that universality <strong>of</strong> the community—without being ontologically<br />

grounded in ‘common essence’—may arrive in the singular: the<br />

exemplarity lies in the translation <strong>of</strong> the commandment <strong>of</strong> love. It<br />

is in the arriving <strong>of</strong> the neighbour who is fi rst to come by, always<br />

the singular and yet anyone who is fi rst, there the eternity may<br />

arrive today from the extremity <strong>of</strong> its future: ‘for all taking action is<br />

projected into the future and the neighbour whom the soul seeks is<br />

always right before it and is only anticipated in the one who in this<br />

moment is there in front <strong>of</strong> it’ (Ibid., p. 244).<br />

In this sense the fi gure <strong>of</strong> the neighbour itself is exemplary: the<br />

place holder <strong>of</strong> the farthest who may, at any time, unforeseeably<br />

present himself as the nearest, ‘the fi rst to come by’. Th e neighbour<br />

presents himself less as the universality <strong>of</strong> the genus but as the<br />

conjunction <strong>of</strong> redemption denominated as And, which Rosenzweig<br />

rigorously distinguishes from dialectical synthesis <strong>of</strong> speculative time.<br />

Th e neighbour here is the example <strong>of</strong> the bond that consummates<br />

messianic end, which is the covenant between God and man, between<br />

creation and revelation, between eternity and time, between distance<br />

and nearness. In the face <strong>of</strong> the neighbour—and here Levinas takes<br />

as his point <strong>of</strong> departure from Rosenzweig—God reveals himself,<br />

in that the commandment <strong>of</strong> love in his revelation turns to the<br />

commandment <strong>of</strong> love to the neighbour, an ethical commandment<br />

but now as law. Th e world that is opened in this ethical obligation<br />

is not the realization <strong>of</strong> a telos <strong>of</strong> the immanent pr<strong>of</strong>ane history; it<br />

is rather a coming community without genus and without ‘common<br />

essence’. Th e futurity <strong>of</strong> this coming community cannot think as the<br />

end or goal, as in the Hegelian metaphysical-historical schema <strong>of</strong><br />

time as essentially sequential, additive and accumulative. Th e future<br />

here is rather the caesura <strong>of</strong> time that advents in the heart <strong>of</strong> presence


334 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

without ceasing itself to be future. Th e neighbour, as Levinas says,<br />

is anyone who may arrive anytime, and yet always arriving for the<br />

fi rst time, before any fi rst. It is this anonymity <strong>of</strong> the singular and<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> the anonymous that for the fi rst time opens us to the<br />

‘we’ <strong>of</strong> community and to the indefi niteness <strong>of</strong> futurity. It is here the<br />

furthest may advent in the nearest and the nearest is seen as far, far<br />

than any further, at the extremity <strong>of</strong> the remote. Th e irreducibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the neighbour into either ‘I’ and ‘You’ for Rosenzweig—and also for<br />

Levinas who takes the problem into more elaborate articulation—<br />

makes the ‘we’ <strong>of</strong> community not a community <strong>of</strong> ‘common’ essence<br />

belonging to genus: it rather denominates the exemplarity that opens<br />

time beyond the event <strong>of</strong> presencing into the pure event <strong>of</strong> future,<br />

into the universality <strong>of</strong> a collective without yet being given as a given<br />

totality or systemic entity; an exemplary universality which is also the<br />

name <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> pure future. It is the denomination <strong>of</strong> a site <strong>of</strong><br />

unforeseeable, unpredictable occurrence whose time no one knows,<br />

and which is not a result <strong>of</strong> an intentional act <strong>of</strong> the one; a site <strong>of</strong><br />

occurrence where there may take place the encounter between the<br />

farthest and the nearness, between eternity and the moment; a site<br />

<strong>of</strong> encounter where eternity ‘must be hastened’ to arrive as early as<br />

today’.<br />

Past and future, otherwise strangers to each other, the one drawing<br />

back when the other’s turn comes—here they grow into one: the<br />

begetting <strong>of</strong> the future is a direct bearing witness to the past. (Ibid.,<br />

p.317).<br />

Such a coming community for Rosenzweig, understood in the<br />

above mentioned sense <strong>of</strong> exemplarity is to be distinguished from<br />

autochthony <strong>of</strong> a community that makes the idea <strong>of</strong> ‘homeland’ its<br />

common essence, from a community consisting <strong>of</strong> the ‘peoples <strong>of</strong><br />

the earth’ and soil, and that in the name <strong>of</strong> this self-identifi cation<br />

enters the historical telos <strong>of</strong> its politics. Such a politics <strong>of</strong> autochthony<br />

Rosenzweig calls ‘messianic politics’ where the silence <strong>of</strong> an exemplary<br />

community—which for Rosenzweig Jewish community, not in the<br />

given sense—would not take root in the soil <strong>of</strong> language. Th is is the<br />

reason, says Rosenzweig, why for Jewish existence there is such a deep,<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound suspicion <strong>of</strong> language and such ‘a heartfelt confi dence in<br />

the power <strong>of</strong> silence’ (Ibid., p. 321).


The Theologico-Political<br />

Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 335<br />

Th e community that would not take its root in the soil <strong>of</strong> language, in<br />

the night <strong>of</strong> territory and in the ground <strong>of</strong> temporality (that additively,<br />

cumulatively progresses towards its telos), such a community cannot<br />

be understood by any given ‘common essence’, or by the predicates<br />

that constitute the logic <strong>of</strong> the world. What then for Rosenzweig<br />

constitutes the exemplarity <strong>of</strong> the community is rather the event <strong>of</strong> a people<br />

that exists in the vocative and not in the nominative. Th is is evoked by<br />

Rosenzweig in a paradoxical manner as a community <strong>of</strong> blood which<br />

he distinguishes from the spiritual communities. Th is alone explains<br />

for Rosenzweig what it means to be ‘chosen people’, a people—<br />

withdrawn from territoriality that determines the long march <strong>of</strong> its<br />

history, a non-territorial and non-autochthonous people—is a people<br />

which arises in the pure invocation that constitutes its vocation to be<br />

‘people’, that means without being able to be people in any given<br />

sense: a non-peopled people, if the reader allows me to coin such a<br />

term, in an ‘uncommon’ sense, a people by virtue <strong>of</strong> not-being-ableto-be-people<br />

in any given sense. Th is non-peopled people, because<br />

it is withdrawn from all positive predicates that determine ‘peoplehood’:<br />

territoriality, language <strong>of</strong> soil, and temporality <strong>of</strong> victorious,<br />

triumphant march <strong>of</strong> historical memory 6 —in this singularity (and<br />

this is the paradoxical logic <strong>of</strong> exemplarity) is open to the universality.<br />

Not being a community that is a particular instantiation <strong>of</strong> the genus<br />

<strong>of</strong> community as such that constitutes the totality <strong>of</strong> communities,<br />

the community in an exemplary sense is for Rosenzweig at once<br />

singular and yet universal. Such a community must, says Rosenzweig,<br />

Conceal the polar oppositions in themselves in order to be able to<br />

be singular, defi nite, something particular, a God, a human, a world<br />

and yet simultaneously everything, God, man, the world (Ibid., 325).<br />

Th e logic <strong>of</strong> exemplarity is a paradoxical logic. Th e thought <strong>of</strong><br />

exemplarity is at once excess (<strong>of</strong> any given predicates that defi ne<br />

community at large) and yet defi cit in the sense <strong>of</strong> its retreat<br />

or withdrawn character. Unlike the triumphant march <strong>of</strong> other<br />

communities that draws their permanence and also their lively<br />

character from their putting at stake the life and death <strong>of</strong> their<br />

existence, the Jewish existence is marked by withdrawn from such


336 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

stakes <strong>of</strong> their existence. Th is marks the defi cit character <strong>of</strong> their<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> existence: it lacks the spontaneity, freedom, and openness<br />

to express its suff ering in a language <strong>of</strong> its soil, in a language <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immanence <strong>of</strong> its self-presence, in a language <strong>of</strong> the autochthony <strong>of</strong><br />

its self-grounding. Th is makes the proximity <strong>of</strong> itself in relation to<br />

itself that <strong>of</strong> an irreducible distance and non-contemporaneous, seen<br />

from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the world-history and secular chronology.<br />

Yet precisely this defi cit and withdrawn mode <strong>of</strong> its being releases<br />

it from the vain consolation in the illusory character <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ane<br />

happiness that the messianic politics <strong>of</strong> the world-history pursues in<br />

the work <strong>of</strong> the state, that is, in the incessant founding, un-founding<br />

and re-founding <strong>of</strong> law from which the lawful violence <strong>of</strong> the state<br />

is inseparable. the logic <strong>of</strong> exemplary is at once defi cit and yet excess<br />

which, by taking from it its full participation in the triumphant<br />

march <strong>of</strong> world history that constitutes the messianic politics <strong>of</strong><br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>ane world, releases it towards a full participation in an<br />

universality in an uncommon sense, that ‘<strong>of</strong> everyone with God’<br />

which one does not need ‘to win in the long march <strong>of</strong> a world history’<br />

(Ibid., 351).<br />

Th erefore for Rosenzweig the idea <strong>of</strong> ‘choosenness’ does not imply<br />

the merely privileged position <strong>of</strong> the Jewish community in the name<br />

<strong>of</strong> which it wages ‘the war <strong>of</strong> faith’ against other communities or<br />

even exercise supremacy in the name <strong>of</strong> a territorial autochthony,<br />

even if it is in the name <strong>of</strong> the universal. For Rosenzweig neither ‘the<br />

war <strong>of</strong> faith’—which, according to Rosenzweig, lies in the mythic<br />

past <strong>of</strong> its existence—and nor Augustinian union <strong>of</strong> the war <strong>of</strong> faith<br />

and the political war, can denominate the exemplary character <strong>of</strong><br />

choosenness. What exists as war is for the Jew is purely political war.<br />

While this separates the Jewish existence for which eternity is present<br />

today in the cycle <strong>of</strong> liturgical year from the secular chronology <strong>of</strong><br />

the world history for which eternity is arrested, masterfully seized<br />

in the violence <strong>of</strong> law-positing and law preserving act, this noncontemporaneity<br />

between—to speak with Walter Benjamin—the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ane order where happiness is pursued and the messianic order <strong>of</strong><br />

justice, alone explains exemplary character <strong>of</strong> a community which is<br />

singular and yet universal. Th e ‘choosenness’ is only that <strong>of</strong> beginning;<br />

that does not yet explain the redemption in the sense <strong>of</strong> the fulfi lment<br />

<strong>of</strong> all utopian potentialities,


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 337<br />

No one knows more exactly than he [the Jewish man] does that to<br />

be God’s well-beloved means only a beginning and that man is still<br />

unredeemed as long as only this beginning is realized. Opposite Israel,<br />

the eternally beloved <strong>of</strong> God, the eternally faithful one and eternally<br />

complete one, there stands the one who eternally comes, eternally<br />

waits, eternally wanders, eternally thrives, the Messiah (Ibid., p. 326).<br />

Taken in that sense, we can argue that the notion <strong>of</strong> exemplary in<br />

Rosenzweig is also a radical critique <strong>of</strong> violence. Th is is seen not only in<br />

Rosenzweig’s distinction between the community <strong>of</strong> blood—which<br />

is not to be taken in any organist sense, as Derrida is sensitive to point<br />

towards—and the spiritual community, but also in the distinction<br />

between the two modes <strong>of</strong> eternity, a distinction that is co-relative to<br />

the former distinction. If for the Jewish community the presencing<br />

<strong>of</strong> eternity today takes the cyclic form <strong>of</strong> liturgical enactment, it is<br />

thereby released from the circular intrigue <strong>of</strong> law that founds, unfounds<br />

and re-founds the messianic politics <strong>of</strong> the world-historical<br />

communities for which eternity is always at an unattainable end,<br />

but never present today. Th erefore it is not so much in the eternity<br />

that seized and enacted in the world-history by the power <strong>of</strong> law,<br />

but in the ethical commandment <strong>of</strong> love that opens the ‘we’ to the<br />

messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> justice that the notion <strong>of</strong> exemplarity fi nds it<br />

true vocation. How, then, does the state enacts the eternity in time<br />

by its power <strong>of</strong> law?<br />

It is in the forceful insertion or inscription <strong>of</strong> life into law wherein<br />

the metaphysical violence <strong>of</strong> the state consists. In the work <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state that continuously solves and resolves the contradiction between<br />

life in its immanent movement <strong>of</strong> becoming and law that freezes<br />

such a movement as its foundational act: it is this work that turns<br />

the image <strong>of</strong> law into a violent image. Th e eternity seized through<br />

law is the metaphysical image <strong>of</strong> the violence <strong>of</strong> the world history.<br />

Rosenzweig writes,<br />

Violence gets life brought to its law against the law. Since the State<br />

is violent and not merely lawful, it remains at life’s heels. Th is is the<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> all violence, that it founds new law. It is now a disavowal<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law, as one probably thinks, fascinated by its revolutionary<br />

conduct, but on the contrary its foundation. But a contradiction is<br />

hidden in the idea <strong>of</strong> a new law. Law is as regards its essence old law.<br />

Now it shows itself as what violence is: the renewer <strong>of</strong> old law. In


338 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the violent act law continuously turns into new law. And the State<br />

is therefore equally as much lawful and violent, refuge <strong>of</strong> the old law<br />

and source <strong>of</strong> the new; and in this double shape as refuge <strong>of</strong> law and<br />

source <strong>of</strong> law the State places itself above the mere fl owing <strong>of</strong>f the<br />

life <strong>of</strong> the people in which custom unceasingly and non-violently<br />

multiplies and law changes…at every moment the State violently<br />

settles the contradiction between preservation and renewal, old and<br />

new law. It is that continuous solution <strong>of</strong> the contradiction which the<br />

life course <strong>of</strong> the people constantly only postpones <strong>of</strong> its own accord<br />

through the fl owing on <strong>of</strong> time: the State takes it in hand; in fact it<br />

is nothing other than this solving, re-solved every moment, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contradiction (Ibid., p. 353).<br />

Distinguished from the eternity which is the eruption <strong>of</strong> the newest<br />

that arises from the violent settlement with the old by the pure<br />

positing power <strong>of</strong> the law is the other order <strong>of</strong> messianic justice which<br />

is to come, which is always to come, which may even erupt today.<br />

Rosenzweig’s thought <strong>of</strong> exemplarity is above all the question <strong>of</strong> the<br />

eternity <strong>of</strong> a promise and its fulfi lment that cannot be understood<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> the immanence <strong>of</strong> a world-historical reason. Th e<br />

ways <strong>of</strong> the Messiah is not the ways <strong>of</strong> the world-history. What seems<br />

to me here the basic problematic <strong>of</strong> Rosenzweig thought is none but<br />

this: that the violence <strong>of</strong> the world-historical reason that assumes<br />

the forms <strong>of</strong> the theodicy <strong>of</strong> history that immanently seeks to atone<br />

itself cannot be justifi ed on the ground <strong>of</strong> this immanence. Only<br />

the exposure <strong>of</strong> the forms <strong>of</strong> the world-history to the transcendence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the messianic fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> an immemorial promise can redeem<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> historical reason. And that exposure happens in the<br />

commandment <strong>of</strong> love in the two-fold love <strong>of</strong> God and the love <strong>of</strong><br />

the neighbour where the immanence <strong>of</strong> the world-historical order is<br />

opened to an eternity which is only granted to man as pure gift, and<br />

therefore is not the object <strong>of</strong> masterful seizure through the violence <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation. To prepare for it, it would be necessary that mankind<br />

learns to renounce violence as such, not ‘this’ or ‘that’ act <strong>of</strong> violence<br />

but that metaphysical violence that lies in seeking to appropriate and<br />

master the pure gift <strong>of</strong> eternity. Only then man is opened to the other<br />

and to others and realizes what he essentially is: an essentially fi nite<br />

existence open to the gift <strong>of</strong> eternity.


Th e Commandment <strong>of</strong> Love • 339<br />

For Rosenzweig, 7 such a critique <strong>of</strong> violence is inseparable from a<br />

certain notion <strong>of</strong> end <strong>of</strong> philosophy. Th is philosophical discourse—<br />

the whole brotherhood from Ionia to Jena, as Rosenzweig loves to<br />

say—in its obsession with totality itself is a form <strong>of</strong> metaphysical<br />

violence, which with its pure power <strong>of</strong> positing <strong>of</strong> the concept (that<br />

begins with Th ales’ assertion ‘everything is water’), already eff aces<br />

the singular being that is exposed to its own irreducible morality.<br />

If such a philosophical discourse <strong>of</strong> totality reduces the language<br />

<strong>of</strong> redemption and messianic justice into the immanent language<br />

<strong>of</strong> historical reason, that means, into the messianic politics <strong>of</strong><br />

autochthony, it leads straight into the abyss <strong>of</strong> evil and totalitarianism<br />

<strong>of</strong> all sorts. Th is is the warning that implied implicitly in every page<br />

<strong>of</strong> Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption. Hence, we can argue, the arrival <strong>of</strong> the<br />

messianic Kingdom cannot adequately coincide with the telos <strong>of</strong><br />

the immanent historical reason, that means, with the goal or end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the messianic politics <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>ane world; or, rather, we can say<br />

that such a founding act <strong>of</strong> the world entirely through and by the<br />

intentions and power <strong>of</strong> human actions must draw its reason, its<br />

sense and meaning from an obligation that exceeds such intentions<br />

and powers, from an ethical (or rather, ‘meta-ethical’: to be more<br />

precise with Rosenzweig’s idea) transcendence outside the ethicophilosophical<br />

discourse <strong>of</strong> totality.


Part V<br />

On Philosophy


§ Erotic and Philosophic<br />

What follows is an attempt to think anew the ancient question, as<br />

ancient as the birth <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, <strong>of</strong> the relationship between<br />

erotic and philosophy. Philosophy hereby is no longer thought as<br />

one academic, university discipline amongst others, but as a mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> being in the world, as a way <strong>of</strong> life, a certain aesthetic and ethics<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence. Th is mode <strong>of</strong> being is concerned less with the ideal <strong>of</strong><br />

intelligibility at cognitive, conceptual disposal, but that is concerned<br />

with the event <strong>of</strong> thinking, with the truth <strong>of</strong> phenomenon that has<br />

messianic, redemptive possibilities. Philosophy then, more essentially<br />

understood, is less concerned with cognition <strong>of</strong> the presently given<br />

phenomenon than with the unconditioned event <strong>of</strong> existence, with<br />

the unconditioned as such. Taking up Plato’s beautiful dialogue<br />

Symposium, and referring to Walter Benjamin’s certain texts, this<br />

article above all is concerned with re-thinking <strong>of</strong> the ‘place’, or<br />

‘site’ <strong>of</strong> university, accompanied by a critical interrogation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contemporary knowledge production, in order to open this ‘site’ <strong>of</strong><br />

university to the messianic advent <strong>of</strong> the unthought, or better, to the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> thought as such in its unconditionality, so that the violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> instrumental knowledge be given over to the redemptive truth <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenon, which the erotic <strong>of</strong> the philosophy, as it is conceived by<br />

Plato, Benjamin and Nietzsche has always been primarily concerned<br />

with.<br />

*<br />

It is Eros and the erotic that concerns us here. And we shall see that it<br />

is essentially the question <strong>of</strong> existence and philosophy par excellence:


344 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

philosophy as a way <strong>of</strong> life, as it is said, as a specifi c mode <strong>of</strong> being in<br />

the world. To philosophize is, then, if one understands philosophy<br />

essentially and not as one academic discipline amongst others within<br />

the space called ‘university’, to philosophize is essentially to be<br />

seized by existence even at the limit <strong>of</strong> life. Th at is the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

Montaigne’s famous saying (2003, pp.67-81), who paraphrases the<br />

saying <strong>of</strong> Socrates in Phaedo, ‘that to philosophize is to learn to die’.<br />

To affi rm truth at the limit when the philosophical existing itself is<br />

pushed to its limit, to the border <strong>of</strong> life, to the edge <strong>of</strong> the world: this<br />

means, to philosophize is to think the limit <strong>of</strong> thought or thinkable,<br />

which is the dizzying abyss <strong>of</strong> death or even madness. Th is is the<br />

meaning, apart from the sacrifi cial signifi cance it can have for us, <strong>of</strong><br />

Socrates’ taking the step <strong>of</strong> death. To philosophize is to take, ever and<br />

ever again, the step <strong>of</strong> death. Schelling speaks <strong>of</strong> this step <strong>of</strong> death as<br />

necessary beginning <strong>of</strong> philosophy as follows:<br />

He who wishes to place himself in the beginning <strong>of</strong> a truly free<br />

philosophy must abandon even God. Here we say: who wishes to<br />

maintain it, he will lose it; and who gives up, he will fi nd it. Only he<br />

has come to the ground <strong>of</strong> himself and has known the whole depth<br />

<strong>of</strong> life who has once abandoned everything, and has himself been<br />

abandoned by everything. He for whom everything disappeared and<br />

who saw himself alone with the infi nite: a great step which Plato<br />

compared to death. (Quoted in Heidegger 1985, pp. 6-7)<br />

Philosophy as a way <strong>of</strong> life, philosophy as a certain aesthetic and<br />

ethics <strong>of</strong> existence is always a question <strong>of</strong> limit, <strong>of</strong> border, <strong>of</strong> the edge<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world. Above all, it is the question <strong>of</strong> death.<br />

Here we shall take up to read perhaps the most beautiful dialogue<br />

<strong>of</strong> Plato called Symposium (Plato 2001), to meditate once again on the<br />

essential relation between existence and philosophy as it is thought<br />

at the inception <strong>of</strong> philosophy. We shall see that at this moment <strong>of</strong><br />

the birth <strong>of</strong> philosophy, philosophy has concerned itself with the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> birth, <strong>of</strong> creation, <strong>of</strong> coming to presence <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

itself. And that philosophy erupts in the midst <strong>of</strong> human existence,<br />

it comes into being as philosophy, it takes its birth out <strong>of</strong> love, out <strong>of</strong><br />

desire and longing <strong>of</strong> Eros.<br />

Understood in this sense, we are attempting understand what<br />

we call ‘philosophy’ in a more originary manner: not as one


Erotic and Philosophic • 345<br />

specialized academic discipline amongst others within this space<br />

called university, academic life; and is not that which is concerned<br />

with this or that regional area <strong>of</strong> inquiry or research, as for example<br />

biology is concerned with ‘biological’ life <strong>of</strong> animate beings, history<br />

is concerned with historical unfolding <strong>of</strong> events in human’s historical<br />

life, etc. But, then, which area, or region <strong>of</strong> beings that is philosophy<br />

concerned with? As if philosophy does not occupy itself with specifi c<br />

objects, or even with specifi c areas <strong>of</strong> beings; as if bereft <strong>of</strong> objects,<br />

philosophical thinking is concerned with nothing as such, with nothing<br />

as such. Yet it is precisely the question <strong>of</strong> no-thing, this nothing<br />

as such that concerns philosophical thinking, which is not yet nothing<br />

pure and simple, but nothingness out <strong>of</strong> which something comes<br />

to presence unconditionally. Now what comes to presence we call<br />

‘existence’- not ‘this’ or ‘that’ area, nor ‘this’ or ‘that’ specifi c existent—<br />

but existence as such. Philosophy is a thinking which is unlike any<br />

other thinking: it is what preoccupies itself with the unconditional<br />

as such, with existence as such—with its value and sense—and above<br />

all, philosophy is concerned with this ‘as such’ itself. To philosophize<br />

is not to grasp in the generality <strong>of</strong> the concept ‘what’ is ‘existence’.<br />

Unlike other regional mode <strong>of</strong> inquiries, philosophy is not concerned<br />

primordially with concept, and therefore not with knowledge. It is<br />

not the ontic or ontological intelligibility <strong>of</strong> phenomenon, nor is<br />

it the ideal <strong>of</strong> knowledge that can be accomplished in the concepts<br />

through categories that is the concern <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking.<br />

Rather philosophical thinking is concerned with the truth <strong>of</strong> the<br />

phenomenon, its event-character. Th e event-character <strong>of</strong> phenomena<br />

lies in the coming to presence <strong>of</strong> something, its erupting character, it’s<br />

arising and taking place; it is the birth and origin <strong>of</strong> phenomenon.<br />

What erupts, as we said above, is ‘existence’. Existence is therefore an<br />

event par excellence. Th e philosophical thinking is concerned with<br />

this event <strong>of</strong> existence.<br />

Th e philosopher is not a scholar and is rather quite a diff erent<br />

being from a scholar. Th e scholar is concerned with ‘this’ or ‘that’<br />

specifi c region <strong>of</strong> beings following ‘this’ and ‘that’ sophisticated<br />

‘method’ which in a manner accumulative and progressive leads to<br />

the knowledge <strong>of</strong> phenomena. Th e philosopher on the other hand,<br />

since he is concerned with truth and not knowledge, is concerned<br />

with the truth <strong>of</strong> the event, or, better, with the event <strong>of</strong> truth—<strong>of</strong>


346 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

existence as such. Now, this eruption <strong>of</strong> existence is always singular,<br />

and yet whose eff ect—because it does not completely exhaust itself<br />

at any given moment <strong>of</strong> discursive signifi cation—renews itself each<br />

moment as unsaturated futurity and thereby universalizes itself. Since<br />

concept cannot grasp this singular universal, only idea embodies this<br />

universality in each singular being. Th erefore unlike scholars, the<br />

philosopher who is concerned with truth <strong>of</strong> the event, is less <strong>of</strong> a<br />

conceptual grasp <strong>of</strong> already present existent, but rather is ideational<br />

opening to the futurity <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon. Th is is the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

Plato’s notion <strong>of</strong> Eidos, or idea.<br />

In what sense existence and event is singular? In the sense,<br />

negatively speaking, existence in its event-character cannot be<br />

thought either belonging to the order <strong>of</strong> generality, that means, to<br />

the order <strong>of</strong> the concept, nor is existence particular instance <strong>of</strong> that<br />

general species, like apple belongs to the species ‘fruit’. Th e scholarly<br />

grasp <strong>of</strong> the given phenomenon is concerned with cognitive,<br />

conceptual determination <strong>of</strong> that phenomenon within an already<br />

given, presupposed theoretical, metaphysical foundational paradigm;<br />

it does not concern itself with this foundation itself as such.<br />

Th erefore all regional inquiries are only conditional. In contrast,<br />

philosophical foundation is concerned with the foundation itself as<br />

such, and as such is unconditional inquiry, because it is not concerned<br />

only with the already given entity, but with the event character <strong>of</strong> any<br />

being. It is only on the basis <strong>of</strong> the truth, which is always the truth <strong>of</strong><br />

the event, can there be knowledge <strong>of</strong> any phenomenon.<br />

As we know that what we call ‘academic’ came from Plato’s<br />

founding <strong>of</strong> ‘academy’ around 385 B.C in a place called Akademeia<br />

near Athens. What is sought in Plato’s academy is not philosophical,<br />

scholarly discourse about things present, but the dialectical that<br />

means ideational grasp <strong>of</strong> the event character <strong>of</strong> existence which<br />

for that matter refuses to be grasped in the conceptual language <strong>of</strong><br />

discursive signifi cation. Th is is the reason why for Socrates knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> existence can only be extended to its ignorance.<br />

In his dialogue Th eatetus Socrates pr<strong>of</strong>esses that the only thing<br />

that he knows is that he knows nothing. when in Republic Socrates<br />

was challenged by his interlocutors to give a positive, that means,<br />

the conceptual defi nition <strong>of</strong> what is ‘justice’, Socrates confessing


Erotic and Philosophic • 347<br />

his inability, says that what can be considered as justice can only<br />

be shown, but not said in the conceptual signifi cation <strong>of</strong> generality,<br />

by Socrates himself in his singular manner <strong>of</strong> existing as just being.<br />

To philosophize is not to grasp a phenomenon ‘what is justice’<br />

in cognitive, conceptual apparatus and thereby defi ning in the<br />

intelligibility <strong>of</strong> knowledge ‘what is justice’, but rather grasping the<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> justice in the mode <strong>of</strong> the philosopher’s existing in<br />

this world as singularly just being, that means by showing justice<br />

as irreducible to any predicates. Th is means, to philosophize is to<br />

transform one’s own existence, to eff ect such a transformation in the<br />

very mode <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> the philosopher so that he own existing<br />

validates the truth <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> justice: the philosopher must be<br />

the one whose existence is the site <strong>of</strong> taking place <strong>of</strong> justice. Th is<br />

singularity <strong>of</strong> the taking place <strong>of</strong> justice is too rich to be conveyed<br />

in the conceptual language <strong>of</strong> signifi cation. On other hand, justice<br />

in its event-character must seize the existential <strong>of</strong> the philosopher’s<br />

innermost heart <strong>of</strong> existence and transform him, making him other<br />

<strong>of</strong> himself, to what he is not yet, the heart <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

philosopher who philosophizes justice. the event-character <strong>of</strong> justice,<br />

and its unconditional taking place can only be shown at the limit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cognitive language <strong>of</strong> signifi cation, at the limit <strong>of</strong> the state <strong>of</strong><br />

settled aff airs <strong>of</strong> the world; in other words, at the limit <strong>of</strong> conditioned<br />

knowledge. Since what Socrates is interested is not knowledge, but<br />

the truth <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon called ‘justice’, it can only be shown as<br />

existential, that means as an aesthetic and ethics <strong>of</strong> existing and dying<br />

as just existing and just dying.<br />

Philosophical thinking is less concerned with the ontological<br />

intelligibility <strong>of</strong> the given world than with the event character <strong>of</strong><br />

the world’ messianicity; it is concerned with the worlding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world, or opening <strong>of</strong> the world. Outside the reproduction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

given, accomplished world in the form <strong>of</strong> discursive intelligibility,<br />

philosophical thinking envisions, intimates the redemptive<br />

possibility by releasing the event character <strong>of</strong> pure taking place<br />

and arriving. Philosophical thinking is concerned with this pure<br />

possibility and its transcendence in relation to the accomplished<br />

form <strong>of</strong> the world’s historical process. Th is concern with the pure


348 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

possibility which ecstatically exceeds each moment from each form<br />

<strong>of</strong> the realized is the concern with the value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

itself.<br />

To give an example again, when Glaucon in Republic (Plato 2003,<br />

pp. 40-52) refutes Socrates that his notion <strong>of</strong> justice self-refutes<br />

itself because such a notion <strong>of</strong> justice does not have predicates in the<br />

given world, that in this world always the unjust rules and is happy,<br />

Socrates invites Glaucon to think justice without predicates, in its<br />

pure unconditional possibility <strong>of</strong> taking place, which is demanded in<br />

its utmost urgency precisely at that moment when justice seems to<br />

have lost all meaning and all predicates in the world. Such an event <strong>of</strong><br />

justice as pure unconditional possibility <strong>of</strong> taking place without predicates<br />

is the thought <strong>of</strong> the messianic.<br />

What the philosopher is primarily concerned with this: the pure<br />

taking place <strong>of</strong> the messianic justice without predicates and in its<br />

unconditionality. Because the philosopher is concerned with the<br />

pure taking place, in relation to the settled mode <strong>of</strong> existence, such<br />

a pure taking place only appears as atopic, that means without<br />

dwelling and without place, which is the meaning <strong>of</strong> utopic or<br />

utopian. Th at the settled state <strong>of</strong> aff airs <strong>of</strong> the world does not know<br />

what is just, but has erased any sense <strong>of</strong> justice does not negate any<br />

urgency or messianic necessity <strong>of</strong> the pure taking place <strong>of</strong> justice,<br />

but precisely demands with its utmost urgency, at this moment, hic<br />

et nunc that pure taking place <strong>of</strong> justice, that justice be existential,<br />

that means without predicates and without condition.<br />

Wherein lies the Eros <strong>of</strong> the philosophical thinking and existing?<br />

Th e answer is this: it lies in the desire, or longing to know that one<br />

knows nothing; it is to desire and yearn for the truth <strong>of</strong> the nonknowledge,<br />

<strong>of</strong> that which is without predicates, that takes place<br />

purely, that means, unconditionally and yet without having its own<br />

place and dwelling. Th e erotic <strong>of</strong> philosophy lies in the philosophical<br />

desire from the state <strong>of</strong> non-knowing that one knows nothing to<br />

the knowing that one knows nothing. It is this erotic desire that<br />

Socrates infl amed in the heart and existence <strong>of</strong> the Athenian youths:


Erotic and Philosophic • 349<br />

to eff ect that transmutation in the heart <strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> each one,<br />

the transmutation from the non-knowing that one does not know to<br />

knowing that one does not know anything. It is for this erotic appeal,<br />

all Athenian youths, including great Alcibiades; the most beautiful<br />

youth <strong>of</strong> Athens fell in love with the ugliest man, who is Socrates.<br />

For this is the ambiguity <strong>of</strong> Eros: because Eros, being the most<br />

ancient God, gives place to everything, for everything is procreated<br />

out <strong>of</strong> love, he is thereby without a place <strong>of</strong> his own. Because Love<br />

is that which infi nitely gives away riches in abundance, he is also<br />

thereby always poor, without cloth and without shoes. Because Eros<br />

is this ever lasting longing for beauty, Eros himself not beautiful;<br />

he is like the philosopher, neither human nor divine but a daemon.<br />

the ancient philosophers including Plato, who is called beginner <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy, thought philosophy as the erotic activity par excellence,<br />

longing and desiring in love as the creative moment <strong>of</strong> the origin,<br />

where the world is opened up to the mortals on the basis <strong>of</strong> which the<br />

mortal understands the world. Th is is the meaning <strong>of</strong> philo-sophia:<br />

desire and longing for wisdom. Even before cognitively thematizing<br />

the world in knowledge, even before it is knowledge <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

thinking is a movement <strong>of</strong> loving, an opening <strong>of</strong> the world in love.<br />

With philosophical contemplation the world opens up before the<br />

gaze <strong>of</strong> love, <strong>of</strong> the loving gaze <strong>of</strong> the one who philosophizes. Th is<br />

marvellous gaze <strong>of</strong> love, which Plato calls ‘wonder’ or astonishment,<br />

is more essential and redemptive, unimpaired by the violence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the gaze <strong>of</strong> force and power <strong>of</strong> the one who cognitively grasps<br />

the world. It is in this sense that Walter Benjamin (1998) speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophical contemplation as redemptive. Unlike the thetic<br />

violence <strong>of</strong> the concept which is the metaphysical foundation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law-positing violence, in philosophical truth on the other hand, the<br />

phenomenon redeems itself. It is not for nothing that the god Eros<br />

is considered in a certain Greek myth as the oldest God. Th erefore<br />

Plato in his Symposium compares philosophers to pregnant women,<br />

linking the idea <strong>of</strong> creation with procreation, and affi rming what<br />

the philosopher is to do, as pregnant women do, is to welcome the<br />

unborn, the not yet, the coming, the redemptive arrival <strong>of</strong> the future.<br />

Th erefore the philosopher must cultivate, so Plato thinks, an ethics<br />

<strong>of</strong> Eros, an ethics <strong>of</strong> loving, which is also an ethics <strong>of</strong> philosophy in


350 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

its irreducibility to knowledge, though a confrontation has already<br />

been felt there, that is, the incommensurability between the idea <strong>of</strong><br />

creation and procreation.<br />

In the dinner party organized on the occasion <strong>of</strong> Agathon winning<br />

the prize for the best tragic poet in Athens, Socrates who was there<br />

among others speaks the following story, which he has heard from<br />

Diotima, <strong>of</strong> the birth <strong>of</strong> Eros. On the occasion <strong>of</strong> Aphrodite’s birth,<br />

the god Zeus has organized a banquet which was attended by Poros,<br />

who is the god <strong>of</strong> effi cacy and wealth. Penia, the beggar woman,<br />

fi nding Poros drunk and lying, devised to have a child by him so that<br />

she can share a bit <strong>of</strong> his immortal wisdom and wealth. Eros is born,<br />

a child <strong>of</strong> the immortal father and an impoverished mortal woman,<br />

thereby sharing qualities from both parents. Since Love is this eternal<br />

desire for beauty, and since we desire what we do not yet have, Love<br />

is neither beautiful, but not also ugly. Love gives in abundance but<br />

he himself, like his mother, is poor. Th is is why Love is always naked<br />

and without cloths. Because he is not yet wise but not yet ignorant<br />

fool, Love eternally desires wisdom and is ingenuous, infi nitely bold,<br />

intense, a sorcerer and an enchanter. Neither divine nor mortal, and<br />

yet sharing the qualities <strong>of</strong> both, Love is the intermediate Spirit,<br />

who is daemon. Neither wise nor fool, neither rich nor poor, neither<br />

beautiful nor ugly, Eros is this demonic philosopher who eternally<br />

fi xes his eyes on wisdom and perfect spiritual beauty. He is not the<br />

ignorant one who does not know that he does not know nor is he<br />

the wise who knows that he knows, but the intermediate demon<br />

who knows only this much, that he knows that he knows nothing.<br />

Th erefore the demonic and the erotic philosopher is essentially atopic,<br />

the one who is without dwelling but eternally exiled, abandoned and<br />

to whom no predicates apply. Th e only predicate that is applicable to<br />

the philosopher is that there is no predicate for him. Articulating the<br />

world and opening the world, the polis and the topos or the places, the<br />

philosopher himself does not completely belong to the world, but is<br />

an exiled being, homeless, atopic and excluded. He lives at the edges<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world, at the limit <strong>of</strong> knowledge, at the border <strong>of</strong> all places and<br />

predicates. By being placed at the non-place, by being conditioned in<br />

unconditional, by being predicated in un-predicable, the philosopher<br />

is the demonic fi gure. He has to be so only because he has to open the<br />

world, to space opens all topos and all predicates. Th erefore Aristotle


Erotic and Philosophic • 351<br />

(1971, pp. 953-7) says that the philosophers and poets are essentially<br />

melancholic spirits.<br />

Why I am evoking the bygone thoughts <strong>of</strong> the ancient Plato<br />

today? What is symptomatic <strong>of</strong> the contemporary methodologically<br />

result oriented culture <strong>of</strong> knowledge production at instrumental<br />

service is this complete absence <strong>of</strong> the ethics <strong>of</strong> love and erotic from<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th e philosopher must be the erotic<br />

individual par excellence; this is why Socrates is the paradigm <strong>of</strong> all<br />

philosophers. Bereft <strong>of</strong> this erotic experience, academic research and<br />

university studies have become separated from the idea <strong>of</strong> procreation<br />

and creation, and thereby becoming banal, emasculated products at<br />

the service <strong>of</strong> instrumental use whose violence we cannot even guess.<br />

Th e university, now the burial ground <strong>of</strong> passionate, creative, great<br />

souls, is no longer to be thought like ‘a metaphor, as an image <strong>of</strong> the<br />

highest metaphysical state <strong>of</strong> history’ (Benjamin 1996, p.37).<br />

What is to be renewed is a new metaphysics <strong>of</strong> erotic. Such<br />

a metaphysics is called forth by Walter Benjamin who in one <strong>of</strong><br />

his early essays called Th e Life <strong>of</strong> Students (Benjamin 1996, pp.<br />

37-47) marks not only the separation <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> creation and<br />

pro-creation, but the absence <strong>of</strong> an erotic outside the bourgeois,<br />

legitimate norm as the condition <strong>of</strong> the sterile, spiritless condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the life <strong>of</strong> the students now. Th is life <strong>of</strong> the students is no longer<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> assuming that form whose task is to liberate ‘the future<br />

from its deformed existence in the womb <strong>of</strong> its present’ (Ibid., p.46).<br />

What is lost, in the absence <strong>of</strong> such an erotic and ethics <strong>of</strong> desire, is<br />

not only the creative moments <strong>of</strong> spiritual infi nity that is opened up<br />

by the experience <strong>of</strong> philosophy, in so far as the life <strong>of</strong> students have<br />

been made to conform to demands <strong>of</strong> the bourgeois society, but also<br />

that ‘expansive friendship’ that is ‘bereft <strong>of</strong> greatness and loneliness’:<br />

Th at expansive friendship between creative minds, with its sense <strong>of</strong><br />

infi nity and its concern for humanity as a whole even when those<br />

minds are alone together or when they experience yearning in<br />

solitude, has no place in the lives <strong>of</strong> the university students. (Ibid.)<br />

What Benjamin brings out is valid now more than ever before.<br />

Th e university now, equipped with the accumulative results <strong>of</strong> its<br />

knowledge production, with its ideal <strong>of</strong> intelligibility is at cognitive<br />

disposal, has long lost that ethics <strong>of</strong> love and with it lost itself as the


352 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

site <strong>of</strong> event, which is its messianic task to liberate, free, release the<br />

unconditional futurity immanent in present condition, but that which<br />

lacks predicates . Th e university as the site messianic affi rmation <strong>of</strong><br />

futurity, and the not yet—which Plato grasps with the two fold ideas<br />

<strong>of</strong> creation and procreation—is replaced with banal, homogenous,<br />

accumulative, sterile knowledge without the existentiality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

philosopher’s existence being seized. What are an academic and a<br />

student for whom the event <strong>of</strong> truth is not opened from the very<br />

heart <strong>of</strong> his singular existence? In order for truth not to be consumed<br />

away in immanent, conditioned self-consumption in knowledge, it<br />

would be necessary to open up the thought <strong>of</strong> the unconditioned,<br />

without predicates, from the heart <strong>of</strong> academic life. Th erefore it is<br />

necessary to introduce an erotic and an ethics <strong>of</strong> love that must be<br />

able to seize the existentiality <strong>of</strong> the existence called ‘student’ and<br />

‘academic’ so that philosophy may become again a passion <strong>of</strong> life,<br />

where ‘justice’ and ‘truth’ become an Idea, that means ‘event’ which<br />

alone can rescue a deformed, damaged, sterile university life to the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> a redemptive possibility <strong>of</strong> the pure taking place.<br />

It means that the present condition <strong>of</strong> the university as a site<br />

<strong>of</strong> producing knowledge at the disposal <strong>of</strong> the techno-scientifi c<br />

civilization where the event character and the messianic intensity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the existential thinking is levelled <strong>of</strong>f to the homogeneity <strong>of</strong><br />

instrumental knowledge, is to be replaced with another sense and<br />

value <strong>of</strong> existence, another sense and value <strong>of</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> life which<br />

calls forth a new language <strong>of</strong> erotic and ethics <strong>of</strong> event. Th e university<br />

would then to be seen less a factory <strong>of</strong> discursive production at the<br />

cognitive disposal than as the site <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> truth, which in<br />

turn calls forth invention and creation <strong>of</strong> ever new forms <strong>of</strong> life, an<br />

aesthetic and ethics <strong>of</strong> existence. Here a more originary experience<br />

and a more originary saying <strong>of</strong> existence is called forth, outside the<br />

ideals and telos <strong>of</strong> knowledge, indicating towards which is irreducible<br />

to the ontological thematization, a more originary experience and<br />

saying that is irreducible to a cognitive disposal, to the apparatus, to<br />

the regime <strong>of</strong> conceptual truth. Th is saying and this more originary<br />

experience is, outside such banal distinctions between ‘objective’ and<br />

‘subjective’ knowledge, is the event <strong>of</strong> thinking, or thinking itself as<br />

event, as an event <strong>of</strong> saying that occurs, in sudden leap or eruption, as<br />

moments <strong>of</strong> truth. It is an event <strong>of</strong> disruption which truth introduces


Erotic and Philosophic • 353<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> existence, rendering the thinker into what Plato calls<br />

<strong>of</strong> a philosopher ‘a gadfl y’ (Plato 2001, p. 303). Th erefore even Kant<br />

makes thinking irreducible to knowledge, the thinker who makes<br />

the ideals <strong>of</strong> Reason irreducible to cognition and to the concepts,<br />

even to absolute knowledge. Th is experience <strong>of</strong> thinking, this event<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking coming towards is the messianic state <strong>of</strong> exception, outside<br />

any law <strong>of</strong> sovereignty whose intensity is experienced by mortals<br />

abandoned to non-knowledge, for it is on the basis <strong>of</strong> the Socratic<br />

non-knowledge alone, on the basis <strong>of</strong> this abandonment, something<br />

like messianic event <strong>of</strong> thinking reveals itself.<br />

Philosophy has an essential relation to non-knowledge and unthought.<br />

What is unthought is the not yet thought, the not yet birth<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. At each moment <strong>of</strong> philosophizing the philosopher is<br />

beholden to the not yet birth <strong>of</strong> thinking coming to presence. Th is<br />

beholding is the erotic gaze par excellence, without violence and not<br />

yet damaged. Th is joyousness <strong>of</strong> the life <strong>of</strong> thinking, pregnant with<br />

the unborn, is the experience <strong>of</strong> hope for the messianic arrival <strong>of</strong><br />

the otherwise. Th erefore love is experienced in its highest intensity<br />

and beatitude when the whole possible infi nity <strong>of</strong> time opens up<br />

before us, which is the occurring <strong>of</strong> truth. Only then the thinking<br />

can touch the essential <strong>of</strong> existence and thereby transform the given<br />

form <strong>of</strong> existence itself. A thinker, if he is traversed by an essential<br />

thinking at the heart <strong>of</strong> her existence, experiences this event in a<br />

state <strong>of</strong> abandonment. Th is joyous abandonment in love is also a<br />

certain melancholy, in so far as it abandons us to our dispropriation,<br />

and which through this dispropriation, gives us the gift <strong>of</strong> truth and<br />

time. Th e melancholy <strong>of</strong> this experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment, for it calls<br />

forth renunciation (<strong>of</strong> cognitive mastery, <strong>of</strong> the ideals <strong>of</strong> knowledge);<br />

this melancholy thereby is inseparable from a certain experience <strong>of</strong><br />

joyous gratitude for the coming <strong>of</strong> thinking. It is in this sense Martin<br />

Heidegger (1968) thinks this event <strong>of</strong> thinking, Denken, inseparably<br />

bound up with Danken, from the experience <strong>of</strong> thanking for the gift<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. Herein lays the nobility and dignity <strong>of</strong> a creative thought.<br />

Th e ethical task <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking is to keep open the site<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘the university’ to the arrival <strong>of</strong> the unthought and to attune us<br />

to the attunement <strong>of</strong> joyous melancholy which is the fundamental<br />

attunement <strong>of</strong> the creative life.


§ On Philosophical Research<br />

THE THOUGHT OF DEATH<br />

It is the question <strong>of</strong> mortality that concerns us here. From Socrates<br />

to Heidegger, philosophical contemplation, where the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

‘philosophy’ itself is at stake, concerns not merely philosophical<br />

thought as such but the very philosopher’s existence as philosophical<br />

existence. It is in this sense Socrates is thought to be the paradigm<br />

<strong>of</strong> the philosopher, not in the sense that he is greater than other<br />

philosophers who have come before or after him, but that, in the<br />

very existing <strong>of</strong> his existence as philosopher; his is this essential<br />

exposure to death. Philosophy, as if, it appears to us, is born out <strong>of</strong> this<br />

encounter with this border <strong>of</strong> life, with this edge <strong>of</strong> the world, with<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> thinking. It is this essential exposure to its own limit that<br />

incessantly summons the philosopher’s existence into this exposure.<br />

As if philosophy’s birth, it seems, is inseparable from this necessary<br />

encounter with this peril where thought or the thinkable risks itself,<br />

and yet from this very peril there would need to be resurrection <strong>of</strong><br />

truth that is born out <strong>of</strong> this encounter with its peril.<br />

May be there is a possibility, or rather necessity to think another<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> death, a more pr<strong>of</strong>ound ‘experience’ <strong>of</strong> death which is at<br />

the limit <strong>of</strong> philosophy or, rather outside philosophy: not in relation<br />

to the death <strong>of</strong> the philosopher where the very ‘I’ <strong>of</strong> the philosopher<br />

is exposed to its peril, and no longer as the question <strong>of</strong> truth, but<br />

rather that <strong>of</strong> the exposure to the death <strong>of</strong> other from which ethical<br />

responsibility, outside dominant ontology, arises. It is in confrontation<br />

with the other’s death that the thinking <strong>of</strong> death as death inaugurates


On Philosophical Research • 355<br />

itself. Henceforth, since one is exposed, for the fi rst time, to the<br />

other’s death—as the story <strong>of</strong> Gilgamesh testifi es—the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

death inaugurates a new life <strong>of</strong> thought, as if philosophical thinking<br />

has to begin precisely at that moment <strong>of</strong> utter powerlessness in the<br />

face <strong>of</strong> death. Th e question <strong>of</strong> mortality is no longer one question<br />

among other philosophical questions. It concerns the existentiality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the philosopher’s existence in relation to the other’s death, as if the<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> the ethical, if it does not have to put death into its service<br />

for the sake <strong>of</strong> cognitive mastery, has to begin with the thought <strong>of</strong><br />

an essential fi nitude that aff ects us with inconsolable grief, seizes<br />

us with unspeakable fear and trembling. Th e opening to the world<br />

and our exposure to the other’s face already always is aff ected by the<br />

grief in the possibility <strong>of</strong> the other’s disappearance without return. If<br />

philosophical writing by a necessary reason has to assume the form <strong>of</strong><br />

the written discourse, no longer the pure ‘draft’ (Heidegger 1968, p.<br />

17) <strong>of</strong> the spoken, then writing in its essential relation to death and<br />

dying has an ethical dimension, which is that <strong>of</strong> opening to the world<br />

and to the others in responsibility.<br />

It is none other from Emmanuel Levinas (2000) that we have<br />

come to learn this responsibility, essentially in its ethical aff ection,<br />

in relation to death, primarily that <strong>of</strong> the other’s death. Levinas’<br />

ethical thought <strong>of</strong> responsibility arises out <strong>of</strong> the recognition that<br />

the dominant ontology as such—which is, the intelligibility <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge and the luminosity <strong>of</strong> being—encloses the infi nity <strong>of</strong><br />

the other (the infi nity that is beyond all totality <strong>of</strong> being and its<br />

immanent self-presence) by inscribing the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the other only<br />

as moment <strong>of</strong> an overarching totality <strong>of</strong> an anonymous Universal<br />

history. According to Levinas, such an insistence on the intelligibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> being privileges certain reductive notion <strong>of</strong> truth over the Good,<br />

the Good that consists <strong>of</strong> our infi nite responsibility to the other as<br />

other. For such a reductive discourse <strong>of</strong> totality, the other’s death is<br />

only a death <strong>of</strong> homogenous particulars which, through their death,<br />

works towards the constitution <strong>of</strong> an anonymous universal historical<br />

totality (Levinas 1969). In this way, that is, by means <strong>of</strong> sacrifi cing<br />

the others for the sake <strong>of</strong> the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> being that philosophy<br />

as ontology constitutes itself. According to Levinas, philosophy<br />

understood as ontology is the negation <strong>of</strong> the ethical responsibility<br />

to the infi nite other. Such ontology constitutes itself by forgetting


356 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

that immemorial loss, that already always disappearance <strong>of</strong> the other<br />

from any immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence that no phenomenologicalmemorial<br />

works <strong>of</strong> retention and protension can retrieve.<br />

In Hegel’s philosophical discourse <strong>of</strong> history, the universal—the<br />

community, the State etc—arises only on the basis <strong>of</strong> the sacrifi ce <strong>of</strong><br />

the death <strong>of</strong> the particular individuals, <strong>of</strong> all particular ‘I’s in so far<br />

each one that belongs to the universal is ‘I’ only to the extent that<br />

this ‘I’, which each one speaks, is also the power <strong>of</strong> negating <strong>of</strong> itself,<br />

<strong>of</strong> its ‘I’-ness. for Hegel the ethical arises precisely at that moment<br />

when this ‘I’ (which is the homogenous, particular ‘I’) eff aces itself<br />

from its enclosure <strong>of</strong> particularity, from its own particularized totality<br />

so that it can thereby open to the universality in which each other<br />

‘I’ can partake, participate in the universal recognition <strong>of</strong> each one’s<br />

right to dwell on earth. Th is begins to happen at that moment when<br />

the particular individual confronts his death, death which is the pure<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> its annihilation or dissolution. Th is is also the moment<br />

the philosopher is born when he confronts the vanity and nullity <strong>of</strong><br />

one’s own ‘I’. Even the predator animal, so Hegel speaks in a famous<br />

passage in Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit, is immeasurably anguished, seeing<br />

the dissolution and annihilation <strong>of</strong> the prey in his act <strong>of</strong> eating; it<br />

thus immediately jumps on the prey without delay and destroys it.<br />

In this manner, Hegel recognized death only as annihilation to<br />

which every homogenous, particular existent, by virtue <strong>of</strong> its mere<br />

existent character, must yield. From this negativity Hegel derives<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> a universal ethics and a universal philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

history on the basis <strong>of</strong> this recognition <strong>of</strong> death as annihilation. In<br />

this manner Hegel has already totalized history by excluding the<br />

non-annihilation character <strong>of</strong> death, which is the non-negativity<br />

<strong>of</strong> death which does not serve the pr<strong>of</strong>i t and meaning <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

history: this is the other’s death, the other who cannot be sacrifi ced<br />

for the universal history <strong>of</strong> anonymity. Th erefore for Levinas, ethics<br />

does not arise from the recognition <strong>of</strong> the annihilation character <strong>of</strong><br />

death <strong>of</strong> the homogenous, particular individuals, but precisely other<br />

way, from the non-annihilation character <strong>of</strong> the other’s death, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

other who is not ‘I’ like other ‘I’ but infi nitely without ‘I’, and which<br />

is thereby without history, at least without the universality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dialectical-speculative. Th e infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the outside history lies in<br />

the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the other who is already always un-sacrifi ciable and


On Philosophical Research • 357<br />

as such, it bears witness the promise <strong>of</strong> an eternal remnant <strong>of</strong> a time<br />

outside the immanence <strong>of</strong> the anonymous, universal historical time.<br />

Th is promise <strong>of</strong> the immemorial comes from the future, in that it is<br />

a promise <strong>of</strong> a time to come, outside the violence <strong>of</strong> negativity which<br />

the universal history posits.<br />

Th is work, as other <strong>of</strong> my attempts, to a great extent is indebted<br />

to Levinas’ thought. However the responsibility born out <strong>of</strong> one’s<br />

own fi nitude, if not so originary ethical as Levinas’, is not to be<br />

abandoned, but to be rethought in a more originary manner than<br />

Hegel’s determination <strong>of</strong> death as annihilation. In this sense the<br />

ethics here—which is inseparable from the ethics <strong>of</strong> existing out <strong>of</strong><br />

the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> each one <strong>of</strong> us—would mean the opening the heart<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fi nite being to the immemorial <strong>of</strong> the Good beyond being, to<br />

the gift <strong>of</strong> the Good that is already always there before any presence.<br />

Already in the inception <strong>of</strong> philosophy, Plato (Plato 2003, p. 234)<br />

recognizes the Good beyond being, the Good that is the excess <strong>of</strong><br />

being to which being never attains on the basis <strong>of</strong> its own luminosity.<br />

Th e immemorial excess that founds us and gives us being is the Good<br />

that, while giving us the gift <strong>of</strong> being, blinds the eyes <strong>of</strong> being with a<br />

light so excessive that being perils itself in its gift. To be fi nite is not<br />

to enclose into the fi nitude <strong>of</strong> one’s own being: it is to open to the<br />

infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the Good that exceeds us, that aff ects us, wounds us,<br />

and tears us away from ourselves; it is that exposes us to the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial, and to the ‘peril <strong>of</strong> being’ (Chrétien 2002, p. 22).<br />

Death is the name <strong>of</strong> this peril that is neither mere annihilation,<br />

nor mere negativity. It is rather the exposure <strong>of</strong> being to its own<br />

non-enclosure, to its excess where being is open to the other’s death,<br />

singular each time and un-sacrifi ciable.<br />

Th is means, philosophy in its advent bears in itself the promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ethical, an ethical recognition <strong>of</strong> the Good beyond being, and<br />

which is beyond any onto-thanatology. Th e philosopher is neither<br />

the one who is enclosed in the narcissistic contemplation <strong>of</strong> his own<br />

death nor the one who is immersed in the contemplation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

universal immanent in the particular objects out <strong>of</strong> his recognition <strong>of</strong><br />

the pure annihilation character that immanently lies in the particular,<br />

sensuous objects themselves. Philosophy is essentially ethical in<br />

its essential ‘experience’ <strong>of</strong> ‘the peril <strong>of</strong> being’ where philosopher<br />

himself risks his own being—a peril that cannot be enclosed into


358 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

any totality <strong>of</strong> ontology—he is thereby open to what exceeds being,<br />

to the immemorial Good that cannot be annihilated simply because<br />

it founds us, and gives us, already always, this gift <strong>of</strong> being. If at all<br />

for a philosopher philosophy has become a manner to exist and to<br />

die, it is because to exist philosophically is to expose oneself to ‘the<br />

peril <strong>of</strong> being’ and through it, to open oneself to the Good beyond<br />

being; it is to let thinking confront its own fi nitude so that at its<br />

limit it may exceed to that which lies beyond any mastery and selfappropriation—that<br />

is, to the pure event <strong>of</strong> the Good. Th is pure<br />

event <strong>of</strong> the Good presents itself as pure presencing when being<br />

recedes from the immanent task <strong>of</strong> its self-grounding. It is thrown<br />

to its excess, to its outside, to its essential peril. Th e pure event <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Good presents in its presencing itself when being exposed, abandoned<br />

in the open, the fi nite being is given over to the immemorial. It is in<br />

this sense philosophical thinking is essentially ethical: not because<br />

philosophy, with the power <strong>of</strong> negativity, exceeds from the sensuous<br />

to the intelligible, but that, in its exposure to ‘the peril <strong>of</strong> being’, it<br />

opens itself to the excess <strong>of</strong> being, to the Good beyond being, to<br />

the immemorial that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens truth and time to being and<br />

thereby opens the futurity that is always to come. Only in this sense<br />

philosophical thinking has a redemptive, messianic dimension.<br />

Philosophical Research<br />

Today a vast accumulation <strong>of</strong> knowledge and learning is produced,<br />

reproduced and consumed at each instant. Th is work, which my<br />

future reader will be kind enough to read, if there will be any, neither<br />

hopes to be a scholarly academic treatise intended to contribute to<br />

the immense industry <strong>of</strong> knowledge production that constitutes<br />

our contemporary academic world, nor does it mean itself to be a<br />

systematic treatise <strong>of</strong> the great history <strong>of</strong> philosophy. Th is work has<br />

neither a thesis to prove or disprove (therefore it can hardly even be<br />

called ‘research’, or even an academic work), nor does it have what is<br />

called a ‘method’, since this work does not cherish ‘knowledge’ as its<br />

telos to which research is supposed to be oriented towards. What it<br />

presents are merely manifold pathways <strong>of</strong> thinking that never cease<br />

to inaugurate ever new paths <strong>of</strong> thought. Th is work, in that sense,<br />

hardly even be called a ‘work’, which means, it has hardly any hope


On Philosophical Research • 359<br />

to produce something—a cultural product—for the sake <strong>of</strong> which<br />

the mind invests the energy <strong>of</strong> thinking, accumulates datas which are<br />

gathered through fi eld works and analyzes them with the help <strong>of</strong> the<br />

most sophisticated scientifi c-technological methods that supposed to<br />

give them ‘objective’ knowledge <strong>of</strong> the ‘world’. Th ere is something<br />

excessive and demonic about philosophy—since philosophy is a<br />

child <strong>of</strong> freedom—an excessive and demonic character that prohibits<br />

philosophy to be completely amendable to the economy <strong>of</strong> the<br />

demand and supply toward which the domain called ‘culture’ tends<br />

to strive.<br />

Th e questions that are raised in this work, are, therefore, not so<br />

much the questions <strong>of</strong> knowledge, and therefore ontological is not<br />

what is its ideal, for knowledge, in its metaphysical determination<br />

fi rst and last desires the intelligibility <strong>of</strong> the ‘ontological’ as its<br />

raison d’art. Whether it is ‘objective’ or ‘subjective’ knowledge, such<br />

knowledge is essentially metaphysical. It is rather the question <strong>of</strong><br />

value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence that this work poses: existence as value and<br />

existence as sense where the meanings <strong>of</strong> value and sense themselves<br />

are at stake, which means that they are not taken here as ‘presently<br />

given entities’ somehow attached to this ‘objectively’ graspable entity<br />

called ‘existence’. It is rather that they are themselves what need to be<br />

interrogated. Th erefore value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence is not ‘subjective’<br />

any more than ‘objective’. Beyond such ‘subjective’ or ‘objective’<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> given entities which constitutes today’s sciences at<br />

the academy, whether social sciences or physical sciences, it is felt<br />

necessary here to introduce the passion <strong>of</strong> an existential experience, a<br />

passion <strong>of</strong> life which is outside the ‘objective’ and ‘subjective’ pathos<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ideal <strong>of</strong> knowledge, in so far this strange, enigmatic ‘existence’<br />

is neither a ‘presently given entity’ (Vorhandenheit), nor an entity<br />

‘ready to hand’ (Zuhandenheit).<br />

What is sought, in the manner that is deeply infl uenced by<br />

Heidegger’s Being and <strong>Time</strong>, is the thought <strong>of</strong> the existential—in<br />

the sense <strong>of</strong> its event-character which is more originary than either<br />

the categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> Vorhandenheit or that <strong>of</strong> Zuhandenheit. Th e<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence—which for Heidegger is the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘meaning’ (at least at that stage <strong>of</strong> his philosophical career)—can no<br />

longer be thought within the ontology <strong>of</strong> subjectivity or objectivity,<br />

since such ontology essentially constitutes the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the


360 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

categorical. Herein lays Heidegger’s critique <strong>of</strong> Husserl: that even<br />

Husserl’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘categorical intuition’ has failed to open itself to<br />

the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the ‘presencing that itself presences’ (Heidegger<br />

2003). Th e existential event <strong>of</strong> the presencing which is beyond the<br />

categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> ‘the given presence’ in the apophantic judgement<br />

is irreducible to the eidetic phenomenological consciousness. It must<br />

open itself to the more originary phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent;<br />

to the pure event <strong>of</strong> presencing which is other than any ‘given presence’<br />

or ‘constant presence’.<br />

Th e question <strong>of</strong> the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the world is not the same as the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> existence. If philosophical thinking is worthy <strong>of</strong><br />

its name, that means essential thinking, and if the question <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

is the highest concern for philosophical thinking, then philosophy<br />

cannot be thought merely to be one academic subject among others<br />

in our universities, in so far the ideal <strong>of</strong> knowledge production that<br />

serves the dominant regime <strong>of</strong> truth (which our university most <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

propagates, an ideal <strong>of</strong> knowledge which presupposes a certain notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> ‘scientifi city’ guided by most sophisticated ‘methodology’, in other<br />

words, an ideal <strong>of</strong> knowledge that presupposes the intelligibility <strong>of</strong><br />

the ontological whose sovereignty is hardly ever put into question)<br />

is precisely under question in philosophical thinking, to open and<br />

release the event <strong>of</strong> thinking outside the apparatus <strong>of</strong> the knowledge<br />

production, and outside the closure <strong>of</strong> the ontological intelligibility.<br />

Th inking is essentially and primarily an event <strong>of</strong> disclosure, and only<br />

subsequently and derivatively knowledge. Th ere is something about<br />

thinking that is irreducible to any cognitive, categorical grasp <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. Th is ‘something’ is none but the event character <strong>of</strong> thinking<br />

itself. If existence is not one available entity among other given,<br />

available entities <strong>of</strong> the given world, and if this strange question <strong>of</strong><br />

existence cannot be thought within the normative cognitive apparatus<br />

(dispositif) that orients our academic researches today, it is in so far<br />

as the existence is always to come, not yet impaired by the violence <strong>of</strong><br />

cognition. As such, the matter <strong>of</strong> thinking that welcomes the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence to seize us (particularly the existence <strong>of</strong> the philosopher<br />

in his very existentiality) has to raise the whole academic question,<br />

not only <strong>of</strong> ‘method’, but the very status <strong>of</strong> knowledge in relation<br />

to mankind again and anew, when the methodologically oriented<br />

research at the cognitive disposal is not taken as normative standard


On Philosophical Research • 361<br />

with unquestionable validity, but one that needs interrogation,<br />

deconstruction, questioning, in order to open up thinking itself to<br />

its messianic possibilities, that means, to its redemptive affi rmation.<br />

Only then philosophical thinking becomes worthy <strong>of</strong> its name,<br />

which for ages has never ceased to inspire if not mankind but a few<br />

in each generation to see in a glimpse the marvel <strong>of</strong> wisdom, which is<br />

to be understood in its messianic transcendence.<br />

What is understood as ‘wisdom’ is nothing other than the excess<br />

character <strong>of</strong> hearing to the essential that is <strong>of</strong>ten covered over by<br />

the dispositif <strong>of</strong> knowledge production in the service <strong>of</strong> demand<br />

and supply, use and exchange value. What governs in our academic<br />

existence is a certain ideal <strong>of</strong> an instrumental knowledge whose<br />

reductive, totalizing metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity and objectivity<br />

serves the dominant regime <strong>of</strong> power. It would then be necessary<br />

to examine the historical origin <strong>of</strong> the notions like ‘method’ and<br />

‘thesis’ and its co-relating origin <strong>of</strong> the epistemology and ontology<br />

as the sovereign sciences, not just philosophy but as the originary<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> modern sciences. It would then be necessary to examine<br />

the thetic, unexamined presuppositions <strong>of</strong> such an epistemological<br />

and ontological intelligibility, and to question the sovereign status<br />

<strong>of</strong> such epistemological, ontological intelligibility as to its value and<br />

sense for us.<br />

Th is important question—the question <strong>of</strong> value and sense—though<br />

not raised in such thoroughgoing manner in this work, is implicit<br />

not merely in the matter at stake, that <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> existence,<br />

<strong>of</strong> time and death, but in the manner, style, gesture, or rhythm <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking that is pursued here, a manner or style <strong>of</strong> thinking that<br />

does not subordinate the matter <strong>of</strong> thinking to results at cognitive<br />

disposal nor however, does it think <strong>of</strong> wisdom as mere ineff able,<br />

mystic intuition <strong>of</strong> a pure transcendental object lying somewhere in<br />

heaven. Instead <strong>of</strong> subordinating thinking, philosophical thinking<br />

to the violence <strong>of</strong> cognition, philosophical thinking needs to be<br />

opened up to its originary event <strong>of</strong> coming in the intensity <strong>of</strong> a<br />

creative passion. Shorn <strong>of</strong> the existential tremor that is the tremor <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality, today’s philosophers no longer seem to be concerned with<br />

an existential engagement, and are emptied <strong>of</strong> any creative passion.<br />

In other words, academic research and existentiality <strong>of</strong> the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the researcher seem to have fallen apart, and this falling apart is


362 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

suitable to the dispositif <strong>of</strong> cognitive results that would not want true<br />

event <strong>of</strong> thinking to take place, for in that way the creative passion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the spirit which is singular, exceptional and unique each time can<br />

be incorporated into the homogeneity <strong>of</strong> a false universality, which<br />

then can be sociologized, politicized by any parochial, instrumental<br />

ideology. In the name <strong>of</strong> this false universality there are inspired<br />

ceaseless cultural products that serve the regime <strong>of</strong> cognitive truth for<br />

the sake <strong>of</strong> which the human minds invest the energy <strong>of</strong> thinking,<br />

and that way reducing the utopian, messianic moment in each<br />

singular work <strong>of</strong> art and philosophy. Th erefore it would be necessary<br />

to invent for each individual thinkers in relation to the singularity<br />

<strong>of</strong> an event <strong>of</strong> a thought, a singular ethics <strong>of</strong> the event, the event <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking coming to presence that would seize with such tremor,<br />

and transforming the thinker’s mode <strong>of</strong> existence and his mode <strong>of</strong><br />

dying. Such an ethics <strong>of</strong> singularity can only be approached from its<br />

futurity in the immanent here and now, but not from any reductive<br />

sociologized, historicized understanding <strong>of</strong> the work as homogeneous<br />

product <strong>of</strong> a given, totalizable historical epoch.<br />

When Schelling somewhere speaks <strong>of</strong> truth as that which exists<br />

as such only as ‘wrested truth’, he indicates thereby that redemptive,<br />

untimely, messianic and utopian element that is given in each hic<br />

et nunc that cannot be completely exhausted in the generalized,<br />

homogenized characteristics <strong>of</strong> a given totality <strong>of</strong> a historical epoch.<br />

Th at means a messianic thinker has to be essentially a philologist<br />

whose philological task is devoted not so much to read what is<br />

readable, but rather what is not yet read, what is unreadable in each<br />

reading, rather than merely reworking over and again in ever new<br />

confi guration what is already read. Th ose works that are at the service<br />

<strong>of</strong> cognitive disposal, these cultural products produced by the human<br />

mind with such an unimaginable amount and speed each day in our<br />

contemporary world, have their values <strong>of</strong> course, for in their banal<br />

homogeneity they call forth the counter pressure <strong>of</strong> the messianic<br />

event <strong>of</strong> thinking. As each movement <strong>of</strong> universal has its own counterpressure,<br />

its eccentric path—<strong>of</strong> diversion and disruption—and this is<br />

true even to the movement <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th erefore each moment the<br />

messianic event <strong>of</strong> thinking always appears to be untimely, older then<br />

the old and yet younger than the young, for older it grows younger<br />

it becomes, more exuberant, and more youthful, whose timeliness


On Philosophical Research • 363<br />

does not take its parameter from serving the cognitive demands<br />

<strong>of</strong> the spirit <strong>of</strong> the age. Each essential thinker inevitably confronts<br />

the task <strong>of</strong> creating, inventing his eccentric path through which<br />

he invents himself: not only concepts to ‘hammer’ with, but also<br />

laughter, madness, ecstasy and outbursts <strong>of</strong> wit. Nietzsche is perhaps<br />

the most fascinating example <strong>of</strong> such eccentricity through which<br />

thinking, through the step back, welcomes the immemorial presencing<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence.<br />

Th erefore Nietzsche envisions his own philosophical<br />

contemplation as ‘untimely’. Th ere is something in philosophy that is<br />

not completely assimilable to the spiritual demands <strong>of</strong> a passing historical<br />

epoch. In each contemporary historical epoch, philosophical thinking<br />

introduces the moment <strong>of</strong> an interval, caesura, an excess, a pause that<br />

makes itself non-contemporaneous with its age. Th is in turn calls<br />

forth another notion <strong>of</strong> historicity and epochal break that cannot<br />

be recounted in the conventional narrative practices <strong>of</strong> the historical<br />

periodization, simply because it opens us to the immemorial promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> presence that has already always escaped from all memory and<br />

all immanence <strong>of</strong> self-presence. In so far as philosophical thinking<br />

welcomes the event <strong>of</strong> presencing itself, it must thereby call forth the<br />

very problematic <strong>of</strong> history anew, for it is time and again confronted<br />

with the question: what is relationship <strong>of</strong> the event <strong>of</strong> existence, <strong>of</strong><br />

truth and love with the event <strong>of</strong> history itself? Th is inevitable and<br />

essential question <strong>of</strong> the philosophical thinking demands that this<br />

thinking is not to presuppose and accept this presupposition as<br />

sovereign measure <strong>of</strong> truth the ontological intelligibility, the telos<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge and the cognitive demands <strong>of</strong> the age. Each historical<br />

epoch, as it has its own cognitive demand, so has its own parameter<br />

to test the timeliness <strong>of</strong> each cultural product which passes away once<br />

the epochal demands become obsolete. Without renouncing the<br />

demands <strong>of</strong> the current spiritual- historical epoch—it is necessary, as<br />

is said by Hegel that each one should read the daily newspapers—it<br />

is also necessary, outside such demands that are <strong>of</strong>ten imposed upon<br />

a thinker, to rescue from the vast sea <strong>of</strong> cultural-historical products<br />

moments <strong>of</strong> utopian elements that exceed each historical epoch. Such<br />

is the truly universal moment in historical specifi city peculiar to that<br />

epoch which is the truly historical moment that not yet historicized.<br />

To rescue the moments <strong>of</strong> wonder from the banality <strong>of</strong> dead, lifeless


364 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

knowledge, and to give such moments a messianic intensity <strong>of</strong> hope<br />

is the highest task <strong>of</strong> an essential thinking, which demands the two<br />

fold task <strong>of</strong> step back and welcoming the arrival <strong>of</strong> the otherwise.<br />

What is thinking if thinking does not seize us with fear and<br />

trembling, if thoughts were not mortal thoughts? Th is is the question<br />

that Socrates asks the Sophists and the Rhetoricians <strong>of</strong> Athens. It<br />

appears that today, when the academic researches have become<br />

devoid <strong>of</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> such experiences, when questions are not<br />

pushed to the limit <strong>of</strong> their thinkability (to the limit when questions<br />

open their abyss to the questioner in such a way that the questioner,<br />

once exposed to the abyss, no longer remains the same but become<br />

someone else, someone other, someone unknown, a stranger and an<br />

exiled); Socrates’ questioning has become more and more <strong>of</strong> necessity<br />

now than ever before. Th e transformation and the transfi guration <strong>of</strong><br />

the philosopher’s existence that demands that it traverses through this<br />

essential experience <strong>of</strong> mortality, which Socrates calls as ‘the step <strong>of</strong><br />

death’ (Heidegger 1985, pp. 6-7) is not felt as requirement anymore in<br />

our university life, without which the essential questions <strong>of</strong> existence<br />

and mortality have remained unasked. It is the incessant interruption<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> the thinker, this caesura at the heart <strong>of</strong> thinkability,<br />

this rendering <strong>of</strong> existence as un-predicative, and becoming oneself<br />

stranger to oneself, or even monstrous: experience <strong>of</strong> thinking is this<br />

transformation, from which an academician fl ees, as if from a central<br />

fi re. Th is academician does not allow, and constantly fl ees from the<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> thinking, which is the experience <strong>of</strong> abandonment, pure<br />

and naked abandonment when existence is touched by the experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> the non-condition, that is, by the abyss <strong>of</strong> our mortality. Th is<br />

experience, in its impossibility to be apparent in thought, this little<br />

thing that washes away the thinker’s existence with tears and prayers,<br />

this little thing does not interest today’s academician. No doubt<br />

today’s university, at least what is near to us, has become the burial<br />

ground <strong>of</strong> spirit that has long lost even the melancholic longing<br />

for the creative passion <strong>of</strong> questioning in an essential manner that<br />

transforms the thinker’s individuality, expanding her soul to the<br />

infi nite. Th e academic has become someone who is not transformed<br />

by the fi gures <strong>of</strong> his own thought, whose existence is divorced from<br />

his experience <strong>of</strong> thinking, each one becoming a non-individuated<br />

homogenous mass, where each one resembles every one, a mere


On Philosophical Research • 365<br />

bundle <strong>of</strong> ideas or concepts without life. Th e academic scholar has<br />

become what Nietzsche speaks <strong>of</strong> the Platonic Ideas as ‘the last fumes<br />

<strong>of</strong> evaporating reality’ (Nietzsche 1968, p. 37) a negation and not<br />

an affi rmation <strong>of</strong> life, when neither existence enriches thinking, nor<br />

thinking enriches existence.<br />

Th e truth <strong>of</strong> Nietzsche’s saying has become more visible now than<br />

ever before, when in the realm <strong>of</strong> knowledge there is taking place<br />

complete mechanization <strong>of</strong> knowledge at the disposal <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

mastery <strong>of</strong> given phenomena. Instead <strong>of</strong> the diversion <strong>of</strong> positive<br />

knowledge from metaphysics, there is happening a realization <strong>of</strong> a<br />

certain metaphysical mastery at the extreme limit <strong>of</strong> its possibility<br />

where this metaphysics appears as a totality that constantly delimits<br />

itself while constituting itself, each time, as a dispositif, as all totalizing<br />

apparatus. An essential vigilant thinking must be able to show the<br />

enigmatic, paradoxical nature <strong>of</strong> this metaphysics: the simultaneous<br />

forming an apparatus and delimiting <strong>of</strong> it, and through which the<br />

state <strong>of</strong> exception becomes included, or the true state <strong>of</strong> exception<br />

takes a false name, that is, it attempts to exhaust the unnameable in<br />

overnaming. At this moment it is necessary to introduce an eccentric<br />

movement—how to say this?—A movement full <strong>of</strong> cunning<br />

and ingenuous invention that introduces incessant movement <strong>of</strong><br />

diversion, which is not what Hegel meant by ‘diremption’ <strong>of</strong> a ‘bad<br />

infi nity’ (Hegel 1998). It is to introduce at each moment a ‘not yet’<br />

at each hic et nunc: this diversion is the moment <strong>of</strong> non-thought, or<br />

unthought irreducible to knowledge at cognitive disposal, a moment<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth not yet impaired by cognition. Th is hic et nunc is the messianic<br />

moment when history itself comes to a halt or pause, a pause that<br />

cannot be narrated to belong as historical period <strong>of</strong> an accumulative,<br />

progressive movement <strong>of</strong> universal history. Th is hic et nunc is the<br />

paradisiacal messianic moment that enriches thinking itself, without<br />

which existence becomes malicious and acquires resentment against<br />

life. Th e resentment against life becomes concepts that do not know<br />

anything outside its cognitive functionality. In other words, concepts<br />

that is devoid <strong>of</strong> the passion <strong>of</strong> life become mere negativity and loses<br />

their pure potentiality <strong>of</strong> redemptive fulfi lment. Th ey sink themselves<br />

in the violence <strong>of</strong> their cognitive functionality. Once concepts are<br />

served at mere cognitive disposal, they become amenable to system<br />

or totality. To rescue thinking from such cognitive disposal will be


366 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the redemptive task <strong>of</strong> experiencing thinking as thinking. It is in this<br />

sense, thinkers like Nietzsche can be highest inspiration for whom<br />

philosophy is less a wrestling with concepts but with existence itself,<br />

not so much with knowledge but with the moments <strong>of</strong> truth that<br />

erupts something like an abyss at the heart <strong>of</strong> existing. Here alone<br />

lays the possibility to rescue or wrest such a moment that tastes the<br />

summit <strong>of</strong> mountains whose freedom Nietzsche loved so much.<br />

Such a thinker like Nietzsche who loves the open blue sky and<br />

height <strong>of</strong> mountains renounces the ideals <strong>of</strong> petrifi ed knowledge.<br />

His feet are too light to carry the heavy weight <strong>of</strong> knowledge that<br />

makes scholars walk with ponderous, languishing gait. He is rather<br />

a wanderer and quite a light footed wanderer is he—for he must be<br />

in readiness at any moment to make leap over abyss—the wanderer<br />

<strong>of</strong> the winding paths <strong>of</strong> mountains from where he has a glimpse <strong>of</strong><br />

the abyss below. As a wanderer, it is his condition, or better, his noncondition<br />

that he is constantly assailed by the non-condition and the<br />

impossible. Th erefore in his laughter there resonates a certain joyous,<br />

cheerful madness, for, as Plato speaks <strong>of</strong> it (and here Nietzsche<br />

reports): ‘it is through madness that the greatest good things have<br />

come to Greece’ (Nietzsche 1982, pp. 14-16), a divine madness that<br />

loves the demonic weather and the perilous paths to truth. In his<br />

wanderings, he strays away from the other street, well lit up and<br />

thickly populated, that leads to knowledge. ‘Ah, give me madness’,<br />

say these solitary and agitated minds,<br />

You heavenly powers! Madness, that I may at least believe in myself!<br />

Give deliriums and convulsions, sudden lights and darkness, terrify<br />

me with frost and fi re such as no mortal has ever felt, with deafening<br />

din and prowling fi gures, make me howl and crawl like a beast: so<br />

that I may only come to believe in myself ...the new spirit which is<br />

in me, whence is it if it is not from you? Prove to me that I am yours;<br />

madness alone can prove it’ (Ibid.).<br />

Dark is his solitary path where non-knowledge suddenly fl ashes up<br />

like lightning and sounds like thunders. Th is imminent undecidable,<br />

or this undecidable imminence <strong>of</strong> the event, whose arrival is<br />

irreducible to the logical march <strong>of</strong> a historical necessity, cannot<br />

be incorporated into the homogenous, universal history. At best<br />

what a poet-thinker thinker can do is to wander, at fi ts and starts,


On Philosophical Research • 367<br />

discontinuously, sometimes even at the risk <strong>of</strong> being led astray from<br />

the path and allowing out <strong>of</strong> these discontinuities <strong>of</strong> wandering in the<br />

solitary mountain paths, repetition to emerge, not the repetition <strong>of</strong><br />

what is already the accomplished result <strong>of</strong> researches, but the not yet<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought, the unthought. Th is repetition is like the ruminating <strong>of</strong> a<br />

cow. Nietzsche’s analogy between the poet thinker and the cow befi ts<br />

here: a poet thinker is like a cow that ruminates (Nietzsche 1989, p.<br />

23). Th e thinker is like a wanderer in a strange land where he lost his<br />

tongue: he moves from here to there in search <strong>of</strong> the land yet to be<br />

known, exposed to the lightning and thunders which through sudden<br />

advent surprises and astonishes him and thereby bestows upon him<br />

this strange gift <strong>of</strong> non-knowledge <strong>of</strong> coming, this intimation <strong>of</strong><br />

mortality and fi nitude. Th is ecstatic experience <strong>of</strong> the outside makes<br />

his existence an open existence to himself, to others and to the world.<br />

Th is makes the thinker’s own existence something like an event. To<br />

render one’s own existence into an event: this is the highest task <strong>of</strong> an<br />

intellectual-spiritual history <strong>of</strong> a thinker’s existence; its pr<strong>of</strong>undity is<br />

proved by the exemplary manner that a thinker has lived and died. Th e<br />

integrity <strong>of</strong> such thinking is not an academic aff air, but an existential<br />

aff air <strong>of</strong> a life. Such an integrity and dignity <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking<br />

constitutes the singular ethics <strong>of</strong> a singular thinker. It is the way that<br />

a thinker lives and dies as thinker, no longer merely sinking one’s<br />

teeth on settled knowledge, but where thinking and existing together<br />

constitutes an ethics, singular ethics that constantly throws oneself<br />

into the perilous sea <strong>of</strong> non-knowledge.<br />

Unlike an academic scholar who has its his disposal a prior<br />

methodology or a well formulated thesis in advance, the poet thinker<br />

has to make sudden leaps at undecided moments when he fi nds<br />

himself in the abyss <strong>of</strong> the in-between, between the end <strong>of</strong> a path<br />

and beginning <strong>of</strong> another path, end <strong>of</strong> a night and beginning <strong>of</strong> a<br />

morning. Long is this path, and long is this turning and this twisting.<br />

To take the leap, where the advent <strong>of</strong> thinking happens is a risk that<br />

the wanderer has to affi rm or wager the risk <strong>of</strong> life and death. Th e<br />

truth that the thinker rescues comes out <strong>of</strong> a wager that must be<br />

reaffi rmed again and again if truth is not to sink its teeth in the sand<br />

<strong>of</strong> imbecile knowledge. It is the moment when the thinker walks, like<br />

Nietzsche’s tight rope walker in Zarathustra, as if over an abyss. Here<br />

instead the truth <strong>of</strong> thinking is validated by the event <strong>of</strong> existing alone.


368 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Its truth is shown in the movement <strong>of</strong> the leap itself, and not outside <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Such a philosophical thinking can be called existential thinking since<br />

it is concerned less with the cognition <strong>of</strong> the given world at cognitive<br />

disposal, but with the value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence itself.<br />

Notes on this Work<br />

Th is work, while it has never abandoned the necessity <strong>of</strong> a systematic<br />

presentation (which is a diff erent question than system), has remained<br />

incomplete, un-accomplished. Th e conclusion could not be reached,<br />

and the path <strong>of</strong> thought, instead <strong>of</strong> leading to some kind <strong>of</strong> result<br />

through a progressive, linear movement, rather opened up ever new,<br />

multitudinous paths, to ever new books to come, to future books<br />

which will perhaps never be written, which can never be written.<br />

What is fascinating that when one sets to work on a book, or that one<br />

has given a certain form, it summons in its dream other books which<br />

will never be written, which could not be written, which could never<br />

have been written: impossible books, books that have already always<br />

erased itself from all actuality. All books seem to share this same<br />

fate: they give the dream <strong>of</strong> other books which will never be written,<br />

and for that matter will never exist. Th ey are the books <strong>of</strong> pure<br />

potentiality, the pure possibility. One may call them ‘dream books’<br />

not only in the sense that one only dreams them, but in the sense,<br />

more importantly, that they dream us, they dream in us, they send<br />

us to dream them. Each book which one has just begun, or that one<br />

has just given a certain form, is only a dream <strong>of</strong> a never book where<br />

a movement <strong>of</strong> thinking which threatens to become interminable<br />

will fi nally be reposed, and will have a Sabbath. But such a book,<br />

since it is a never book, is never written and as a result, like our<br />

existence, no book ever attains completion and accomplishment. All<br />

book is unfi nished, uncompleted, not because it will be completed<br />

one day or another, but that it is already always uncompleted and<br />

unfi nished; yet precisely this opens us to the future <strong>of</strong> the book as<br />

such, <strong>of</strong> each and every book which is always to come. Th e book to<br />

come which will never come to pass away is not only the occasion <strong>of</strong><br />

an infi nite distress for the writer, but also the very occasion <strong>of</strong> its joy<br />

and festivity that there will always be books, albeit always incomplete<br />

and already unfi nished. Each book arises out <strong>of</strong> this melancholy <strong>of</strong>


On Philosophical Research • 369<br />

the immemorial that dreams give us, but for that matter, it is also the<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> the structural opening <strong>of</strong> each book that we write, each<br />

being a failed book, uncompleted and unfi nished book, especially<br />

those books that we write putting our very existence at stake, where<br />

we allow our own existence to write its own dreams, those infi nite and<br />

interminable dreams that never cease coming toward us, whether we<br />

asleep or awake, haunting us, infi nitely murmuring within us, within<br />

the eardrum <strong>of</strong> our soul. Th ese are the dreams that keep vigilance on<br />

us while we are asleep, dreams <strong>of</strong> books which will—not so much<br />

will enclose our existence in them, but—be one with our existence so<br />

that dream and existence can become one, when a plenitude will be<br />

reached where our being fulfi ls itself, and then, only a silence would<br />

follow, by erasing this book, each and every book, from all memory<br />

and traces. Th e completion <strong>of</strong> the book which fulfi ls itself in this<br />

co-incidence <strong>of</strong> being and its dreams, <strong>of</strong> the book and existence,<br />

will be that book that will result in the cancellation <strong>of</strong> that book or<br />

erasure <strong>of</strong> that book from all monumentality and memorial traces.<br />

Th e future <strong>of</strong> that book that dreams within us is to attain the nobook,<br />

which like silence fulfi lling and completing language, will be<br />

a book <strong>of</strong> silence, not because the book will not speak anymore, nor<br />

that there is nothing more to speak, for the book has now said the<br />

essential absolutely, without remainder. When such a book will come,<br />

each and every word <strong>of</strong> it will become ‘citable’: ‘Erst der erlösten<br />

Menschheit ist ihre vergangenheit in jedem ihre Momente zitierbar<br />

geworden . Jeder ihrer gelebten Augenblicke wird zu einer citation a<br />

l’ordre du jour—welcher Tag eben der jügste ist’ (Benjamin 1977,<br />

p.252). Let us translate these words <strong>of</strong> Benjamin: ‘only a redeemed<br />

mankind receives the plenitude <strong>of</strong> its past, that is to say, only for<br />

a redeemed mankind its past becomes citable in all its moments.<br />

Each moment it lives becomes a citation a l’ordre du jour—that<br />

day is Judgement day.’ In each book that we write and that sees the<br />

light <strong>of</strong> the day, another book or rather a never- book invisibly, in<br />

the nocturnal depth <strong>of</strong> the night, writes itself. Each visible book is<br />

only a partial fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> that invisible book: the task <strong>of</strong> writing<br />

is to open each and every book to its invisible other book which is<br />

always to come, a promise is given in the immemorial past, which<br />

for that matter exceeds each and every book. It is the Idea <strong>of</strong> the<br />

book itself.


370 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Th is work is neither an exegesis nor a commentary on any thinker.<br />

If ‘philosophy’ is understood to be objective cognition <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

then this work does not even merit being a work <strong>of</strong> philosophy.<br />

Instead this peculiar work in which the existentiality <strong>of</strong> the writer’s<br />

existence is involved, does not claim to bear the status <strong>of</strong> ‘objective’,<br />

anymore than the ‘subjective’ cognition <strong>of</strong> the world. It is rather the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> the value and sense <strong>of</strong> existence that this work is concerned<br />

with. Th e writer who raises the question <strong>of</strong> the sense and value <strong>of</strong><br />

existence rather than the question <strong>of</strong> the cognition <strong>of</strong> the ‘objective’<br />

world, cannot but ask the question regarding the relation between<br />

the writer and writing itself, which is the following: what happens<br />

to the ‘I’ who bears a proper name, supposing ‘Hegel’, or ‘Kant’,<br />

in so far as the writer ‘I’ seems to have become, precisely by virtue<br />

<strong>of</strong> the linguistic-thinking exercise called ‘philosophy’, something<br />

other than the empirical, this specifi c, unique individual bearing a<br />

proper name calling itself ‘I’? It is as if philosophical writing already<br />

in advance tempers the one who says ‘I’ with mortality, so that<br />

one who philosophizes no longer remains the being to appropriate<br />

his own existence, so that displacing his proper name mortality<br />

enables something else to emerge, which is the event <strong>of</strong> thinking. Th e<br />

philosopher is nothing but the site <strong>of</strong> event <strong>of</strong> thinking that bears,<br />

henceforth, its own singular signature <strong>of</strong> its coming into presence.<br />

Henceforth mortality will temper each draft <strong>of</strong> thinking with its<br />

own invisible signature, displacing and de-centring the ‘subject’<br />

philosopher from any possibility <strong>of</strong> appropriation, abandoning him<br />

to the pure spacing <strong>of</strong> the event, which is singular and universal at<br />

the same time. In this sense to write is to render oneself non-proper,<br />

not actively, but in passivity beyond being active and being passive.<br />

Th is pure passivity is the spacing that abandoning the philosopher-<br />

writer to the space <strong>of</strong> death calls forth the event <strong>of</strong> thinking to<br />

come to presence. Th erefore this ‘I’, who writes this pronoun ‘I’, is<br />

only the name <strong>of</strong> the nameless, the non-propriety <strong>of</strong> the ‘proper’,<br />

only the appearing <strong>of</strong> the unapparent, the manifestation <strong>of</strong> a nonmanifestation—which<br />

is the event <strong>of</strong> thinking coming to presence.<br />

Th erefore the writer knows, with this peculiar knowledge that is<br />

bestowed by mortality itself, that what he is attempting to say is


On Philosophical Research • 371<br />

essentially a failed attempt, an attempt that is destined to be a failure,<br />

which is the failure <strong>of</strong> dream-thinking to attain actuality. Yet the<br />

‘failure’ <strong>of</strong> a thought, which is also thought’s open-ness to its own<br />

futurity and its event-character, are precisely what calls thinking forth.<br />

It is what is at stake in thinking, what summons thinking to inscribe<br />

the invisible promise <strong>of</strong> fulfi lment in each and every signature. Like<br />

the greatness <strong>of</strong> a book that lays in its essential failure, so the greatness<br />

<strong>of</strong> a thought is also the greatness <strong>of</strong> its essential failure to accomplish<br />

itself. Failing to accomplish itself, thought interminably calls to<br />

itself that is outside <strong>of</strong> all thought, which on that event can never be<br />

measured in thought: the immeasurable in relation to which thinking<br />

fails to ground itself, and thereby risks itself ever and again; the peril<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought that opens thought to the unthinkable, to that which is<br />

the excess <strong>of</strong> thought, the measurelessness <strong>of</strong> the unthinkable.<br />

How to name this? Th e thinker, unlike scholars, is not certain about<br />

this. Unlike the scholar who is guided in the most strict methodology<br />

that step by step, in a manner progressive-accumulative, leads him to<br />

the certitude <strong>of</strong> knowledge—<strong>of</strong> what is called ‘objective’ cognition—<br />

the thinker on the pathway <strong>of</strong> thinking is never sure <strong>of</strong> his path,<br />

for there to be pathway <strong>of</strong> thinking, thinking must constantly clear<br />

the way each time anew. Th inking is at once clearing, lightening<br />

the space and presenting at the same time, for the presencing itself<br />

to present there must already be the open. Unlike the telos <strong>of</strong> the<br />

scholar—which is that <strong>of</strong> knowledge production—that is given<br />

beforehand and whose pre-supposed foundation is not interrogated,<br />

the philosophical contemplation is concerned with the truth <strong>of</strong> the event,<br />

which exceeds any teleological or archaeological organization in<br />

objective cognition. If there is anything like ‘truth’ in philosophical<br />

presentations, this truth is not cognition <strong>of</strong> existence, in the sense<br />

that existence is not proved here, but validity <strong>of</strong> what is presented in<br />

philosophical presentation will be proved outside the work, by and<br />

in existing itself. So the rhythm <strong>of</strong> thinker’s thinking in a wandering<br />

path is diff erent from a scholarly treatise. Th e scholar attempts to<br />

prove a hypothesis or an axiom—<strong>of</strong> something existing, as possible<br />

or actual—in his research work; but what the poet thinker has to<br />

say is to be validated—by whom?—by existence itself. To think<br />

poetically is to renounce knowledge, and to expose being to that<br />

which exceeds knowledge, to that unapparent apparition <strong>of</strong> presence


372 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

that presences itself as an immemorial presencing before and beyond<br />

being, before and beyond knowledge. To poetize thinking is to make<br />

open that space, from the heart <strong>of</strong> thinking, that reveals the gift <strong>of</strong><br />

the immemorial and also the arriving <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise, the<br />

incalculable advents <strong>of</strong> the unthought: <strong>of</strong> what is not yet human<br />

truth and not yet human time.<br />

Th is manuscript could not be a Book. Perhaps the age <strong>of</strong> the Book<br />

is over. One no longer writes Book as such these days, not at least<br />

in Hegelian sense <strong>of</strong> ‘the Book’. Th is poet writer, who cherished for<br />

long time to write a book, has realized that his thoughts, coming<br />

towards him, refuse by their own accord to be collected and gathered<br />

into the unity <strong>of</strong> a book where a single logical train <strong>of</strong> thinking, a<br />

programmatic thesis or hypothesis arrive into a gathering point <strong>of</strong><br />

unity. It is not that the writer has a planned and accomplished a<br />

‘failed book’; it is rather otherwise. Th is (non)work is in fact born<br />

out <strong>of</strong> despair. Each time (are innumerable times) groundwork for<br />

this work have been prepared, each time it is found frustratingly<br />

unsatisfactory, so that this project is condemned to ever new attempt<br />

from beginning again and again, progressing only to a certain point<br />

that brings its own reversal, dissolution and perishing. Th is is a book<br />

<strong>of</strong> disaster, and not a book <strong>of</strong> completion. Th erefore this work does<br />

not know the song <strong>of</strong> Hegelian Owl <strong>of</strong> Minerva which sings only<br />

at the dawn. At best, this work is better be seen as ‘becoming in<br />

dissolution’ (Hölderlin 1988, pp. 96-100), or coming in perishing;<br />

which is the unworking or undoing that carries the ashes <strong>of</strong> Semele<br />

which the God Dionysus has reduced her to. Instead <strong>of</strong> being able to<br />

be tarrying with the fi re which is ‘the energy <strong>of</strong> thinking’ that Hegel<br />

(1998, p. 19) speaks <strong>of</strong> that is able to be ‘tarrying with the negative’,<br />

it is the dissolution to ashes that this book has become in perishing.<br />

Th erefore the dream <strong>of</strong> the book is renounced forever, for it is the<br />

character <strong>of</strong> thinking to arrive only by introducing its own interval,<br />

or moments <strong>of</strong> suspension that refuse a unitary centre. Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

the book singing the song <strong>of</strong> the Owl, this manuscript only presents<br />

discontinuous, repetitive attempts <strong>of</strong> ever new beginning, ever new<br />

embarking into new voyages <strong>of</strong> thinking. Provisionally we shall name<br />

this as constellation, or confi guration thinking: discontinuous, nonidentical<br />

thinking where thinking not being able to achieve systemic<br />

unity, fragments and repeats itself. It presents as stories <strong>of</strong> multiple


On Philosophical Research • 373<br />

voyages, none <strong>of</strong> them is accomplished, but everything is condemned<br />

to ashes. As such this work, in each <strong>of</strong> its pages, is bearing the agonal<br />

marks <strong>of</strong> this essential failure. Yet in this worklessness <strong>of</strong> a death, a<br />

death that refuses to work for the empty Universal, writing spaces itself<br />

open to the arriving <strong>of</strong> the Other. Each thinker who has undertaken,<br />

even once, such a voyage that seeks what is beyond, the unknown<br />

and has experienced within him this fragility <strong>of</strong> thinking, its essential<br />

powerlessness that henceforth pervades his existence with a certain<br />

mournfulness, as if thinking itself mourns itself in him. Th ere is<br />

something essential fragility in all thinking, barely a breath that faints<br />

away, especially when it aspires and ventures to essential thinking.<br />

Th is fragility is such as to resemble what Hegel calls ‘beauty without<br />

strength’ that cannot maintain itself in the face <strong>of</strong> death (Ibid.). Yet<br />

the fragile suff ering has about it something demonic which hardly can<br />

even attain to language. Language <strong>of</strong> this suff ering is almost to the<br />

point <strong>of</strong> muteness only by a breath. Th is suff ering in writing renders<br />

the philosopher, as Socrates gives it a name, demonic. Suff ering either<br />

elevates one beyond the common humanity, or throws us below<br />

where there no pearl shines. Henceforth he is destined to carry this<br />

mournfulness at the depth <strong>of</strong> his existence, incommunicable to<br />

any other mortals for to others he will only appear as that uncouth<br />

monster whose language falls below signifi cation or meaning.<br />

Th e fi gure <strong>of</strong> the thinker, which is non-fi gure par excellence,<br />

is the fi gure <strong>of</strong> a monster, or demon. Socrates knew something <strong>of</strong><br />

this experience himself and carried this demon as an ever lasting<br />

companion. Th e thinker must carry, in his fragility and non-power,<br />

the monstrosity <strong>of</strong> the unthought, to which his thought cannot attain<br />

to, in which thoughts founder and falter. Th e monstrosity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unthought renders the thinker as Aristotle speaks <strong>of</strong> him no longer<br />

belonging to either completely to the human order, nor to the divine<br />

order, for he is the open space where the immemorial appears that<br />

does not yet ‘properly’ belong to the order <strong>of</strong> ‘ the human’. Or, one<br />

can speak like Nietzsche <strong>of</strong> this monstrous ‘fi gure’ <strong>of</strong> the philosopher<br />

as both animal and God together: ‘to love alone one must be an<br />

animal or a god—says Aristotle. Th ere is yet a third case: one must<br />

be both—a philosopher’ (Nietzsche 1968, p. 23). Like Oedipus who<br />

in his blindness is exposed to the excess, the thinker is the eternally<br />

exiled one, homeless and abandoned, eating his heart out, banished


374 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

both by the divine order and the human order. Th is non-humanity <strong>of</strong><br />

the thinker, this monstrosity <strong>of</strong> the poet-voyager, whose humanity is<br />

robbed by the strange sea and the uncanny manifestation <strong>of</strong> the sky,<br />

he is that strange coupling <strong>of</strong> the animal and the divine, possessed by<br />

the excess, and seized by ‘the divine madness’ (Plato 2001, pp.111-<br />

198). By belonging neither to the human, nor to divine, he is fated<br />

to carry that monstrous passion, the passion <strong>of</strong> the unthought that<br />

transforms his whole existence so that his whole existence may become<br />

the site <strong>of</strong> the open where the unapparent makes itself manifest and<br />

the immemorial presences in his stammering tongue. Th e name<br />

<strong>of</strong> the thinker, the proper name <strong>of</strong> a thinker is none but what the<br />

unthought transforms him into, so that out <strong>of</strong> this peril <strong>of</strong> his being<br />

he may welcome the immemorial and the unapparent. A thinker is<br />

a metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the unthought. Th inking that is pursued in the<br />

pathway <strong>of</strong> thought is already always tempered with the unthought<br />

and the immemorial. If mortality itself is that which exceeds each<br />

time any concept that mortals give to it, this mortality adheres in the<br />

innermost ground <strong>of</strong> the thinking called ‘philosophical’.<br />

Why to think if the unthought does not transform the thinker? Is<br />

not the whole purpose <strong>of</strong> painting lies in that the painting transforms<br />

the painter herself? Writing by condemning the writer to the point <strong>of</strong> a<br />

demonic suff ering also frees him from death, at the instant <strong>of</strong> death, and<br />

opens him to the advent <strong>of</strong> another time. Writing is the movement—<br />

spacing <strong>of</strong> space and timing time—that traverses through the<br />

being <strong>of</strong> the writer, a movement that he cannot appropriate as<br />

constitutive <strong>of</strong> his self-presence or subjectivity, but that dispropriates<br />

him in advances, disowns him and abandons him. But this nonappropriation,<br />

this intrinsic fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the writer is also the promise<br />

<strong>of</strong> another time, a wholly otherwise <strong>of</strong> time. Th is is the time that<br />

heralds the arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly otherwise, which is not this or that<br />

particular mode <strong>of</strong> time, but timing <strong>of</strong> time, the spacing open <strong>of</strong> time<br />

where time itself arrives, grows, ripens. Th e movement <strong>of</strong> writing is<br />

An awaiting, in distress and in hope, when the fugitive Gods<br />

have abandoned the world, for the advent <strong>of</strong> another inception,<br />

and another inauguration when history itself momentarily stands<br />

still. Writing is this caesural interval between ending and another<br />

beginning. In this distress <strong>of</strong> the interval, an advent <strong>of</strong> the otherwise<br />

is announced and the promise <strong>of</strong> another coming is renewed, silently,


On Philosophical Research • 375<br />

when the day <strong>of</strong> History is exhausted and the dusk <strong>of</strong> the night has just<br />

begun. Th e movement <strong>of</strong> writing is this nocturnal movement outside<br />

the completion <strong>of</strong> history which unites, in a ‘monstrous coupling’<br />

mortality and the advent <strong>of</strong> the coming dawn, the immemorial<br />

promise and its redemptive fulfi lment. Th e monstrosity <strong>of</strong> writing<br />

bears this immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> the advent.<br />

In the writings <strong>of</strong> an epoch, the whole epoch writes itself. But<br />

more essential writing is more it speaks what could not have belonged<br />

to that epoch, the excess <strong>of</strong> that epoch, the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong><br />

that epoch—the missed fulfi lment, the departed gift, the erased hope<br />

and the forgotten dreams. Each epoch has its own logic <strong>of</strong> movement,<br />

and this logic excludes what it cannot incorporate. More essential<br />

writing is, more essential is poeticizing and thinking, more it speaks<br />

the ruins <strong>of</strong> history and the limit <strong>of</strong> that epoch. Philosophical writing,<br />

because it seeks the essential and not merely ephemeral and fashionable,<br />

is the writing at the limit <strong>of</strong> the world. More this mortality seizes the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> writing <strong>of</strong> an epoch with trembling and fear, more<br />

it announces the advent <strong>of</strong> the outside, at the limit <strong>of</strong> that epoch,<br />

namely, its break or discontinuity which, on that event, does not<br />

completely belong to it.<br />

Th is question <strong>of</strong> a time always to come was already haunting in<br />

my mind as a thought not yet thought when I was a post doctoral<br />

fellow at University <strong>of</strong> Marc Bloch in Strasbourg, France, working on<br />

my post Doc manuscript which was then called Travail <strong>of</strong> Mourning:<br />

Finitude and Intimation <strong>of</strong> Melancholy. However this question did<br />

not then arrive in the above mentioned formulation and articulation,<br />

but remained as a not-yet-thought in the thought <strong>of</strong> fi nitude that<br />

I was trying to elaborate at that time. What, then, I understood as<br />

fi nitude is nothing other than the in-fi nite movement <strong>of</strong> un-working<br />

the solidifi ed, sedimented artifi ce <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, a fi nitude that<br />

is intimated with the more originary melancholy that refuses to<br />

be ‘work’, to be production <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness, subjectivity, ego<br />

that recuperates its own loss in order to arrive at its self-presence,<br />

in a manner <strong>of</strong> Odysseus’ voyage. It was a question <strong>of</strong> thinking an<br />

originary melancholy that is outside the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity<br />

and work.<br />

Th e travail <strong>of</strong> mourning is this worklessness, ruination rather than<br />

‘work’, or eff ectuation <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness. In this manner, I wanted


376 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

to open up the ‘experience’ <strong>of</strong> mourning outside the dominant<br />

metaphysics <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, in a quasi-phenomenological manner,<br />

where—unlike the dominant phenomenological ontology <strong>of</strong> Eidos,<br />

<strong>of</strong> noema-noetic co-relation—the ‘experience’ itself to pushed to the<br />

utmost limit, no longer a constitutive-constituting self-consciousness<br />

or transcendental subjectivity, but rather an opening, or spacing<br />

towards a time yet to come. My thought somehow, not being able to<br />

go further this, got stuck up there. After an interval time <strong>of</strong> despair,<br />

I realized the necessity <strong>of</strong> introducing another movement, along and<br />

simultaneously with the movement <strong>of</strong> worklessness, a movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> affi rmation <strong>of</strong> a time ‘to come’, an originary movement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unapparent appearing <strong>of</strong> a time that fi rst <strong>of</strong> all opens, manifests,<br />

discloses, reveals the world to the mortals on the basis <strong>of</strong> which<br />

alone there makes sense <strong>of</strong> our politics and history, our ethics and<br />

metaphysics. As such, the various closures <strong>of</strong> our metaphysics and<br />

ethics, <strong>of</strong> our politics and history need to be opened to this openingrevelation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world, which is none but the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

temporalization itself, a phenomenon <strong>of</strong> time that cannot be thought<br />

within any phenomenological ontology, or within any subjective selfpresence<br />

<strong>of</strong> subjectivity, but as a ‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the unapparent.’<br />

Th is phenomenon <strong>of</strong> time ‘to come’ is the unconditional affi rmation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the outside which constitutes the messianic event <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> our thinking today, if it does not have to be enclosed<br />

within various conditioned and conditional thinking, is to rescue<br />

this phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the time ‘to come’ its unconditional character <strong>of</strong><br />

affi rming from closures <strong>of</strong> various immanent politics and ethics, <strong>of</strong> history<br />

and metaphysics. Th e unconditional in us is this event-character—<br />

erupting, arising and disappearing, rupturing and interrupting,<br />

transfi guring and redeeming—which <strong>of</strong>ten tends to be enclosed<br />

within various attempts at conditional and conditioned politics <strong>of</strong><br />

immanent self-consumption and self-appropriation. To rescue the<br />

unconditional, which is given as gift and promise at the opening <strong>of</strong><br />

the world, demands a movement <strong>of</strong> expropriation or dispropriation<br />

so that we may be abandoned to the unconditional, to the<br />

disclosive-revelatory phenomenon <strong>of</strong> the world. Th is movement <strong>of</strong><br />

expropriation, or dispropriation is the co-relative ‘concept’ that I am<br />

introducing here with the event <strong>of</strong> the time to come. What is to come is<br />

not this or that, but a fi nite coming each time, which—understood in


On Philosophical Research • 377<br />

relation to the unconditional movement <strong>of</strong> expropriation—is always<br />

a remnant, an ‘irreducible remainder’ (Schelling, 1936), an always<br />

to come. It is the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> time to come whose unapparent<br />

apparition cannot be grasped by any predicates <strong>of</strong> time and being,<br />

for it precedes and follows any predicative truth <strong>of</strong> logic. What has<br />

changed from the previous work, that is, my post doc manuscript, is<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the change <strong>of</strong> focus, or perspective. It is no longer the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nitude and melancholy in itself as such which is the concern <strong>of</strong><br />

this presence work, but the question <strong>of</strong> the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong><br />

time and hope for redemptive fulfi lment in relation to which the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> fi nitude may arise. Th e movement <strong>of</strong> expropriation may<br />

arise, or make sense only in its relation to the event <strong>of</strong> arrival as such,<br />

without which it remains mere interruption, ruination or unworking<br />

without transfi guration, without event, without the affi rmative and<br />

positive. Finitude alone, understood in the above manner, does not<br />

alone affi rm the event, even though the event itself is essentially fi nite<br />

that opens itself to the wounds <strong>of</strong> the infi nite.<br />

When this problem has begun to be clearer to me, I have devoted<br />

myself to the study <strong>of</strong> those thinkers and philosophers whose concern<br />

is this essential fi nitude <strong>of</strong> our existence that opens us, from the heart<br />

<strong>of</strong> fi nitude, to the immemorial promise <strong>of</strong> time yet to come: the<br />

works <strong>of</strong> Schelling, Hölderlin, Heidegger, Benjamin, Kierkegaard,<br />

Bloch and above all Franz Rosenzweig, teasing out the redemptive,<br />

utopian, messianic moments <strong>of</strong> their thinking. In this sense, this<br />

work in its reversal, can also be seen as extension, or complement to<br />

the question that I was already pursuing in my post doc manuscript<br />

at Strasbourg during the academic session 2006-2007. As such this<br />

work bears witness to the immense gratitude to both the institutions<br />

where I have been able to carry out my work—the most beautiful<br />

and inspiring institutions like University <strong>of</strong> Strasbourg, Strasbourg<br />

and Indian Institute <strong>of</strong> Advanced Study at Shimla.


Epilogue


§ Fragments<br />

If the dominant philosophical discourse is singularly pr<strong>of</strong>i ted from<br />

death, by being able to render death itself a ‘work’, writing—in fatigue<br />

and in patience—point towards experiences beyond the dominant<br />

philosophical discourse, especially in its dialectical-speculative form<br />

assumed in Hegel. If death is determined in Hegel to be constitutive<br />

<strong>of</strong> Concept, which accomplishes the dialectical-historical closure,<br />

it forgets thereby the true mourning—mourning for the death <strong>of</strong><br />

the Other, the mourning that is unredeemed within the dialectical<br />

historical self-presencing. It is therefore necessary to affi rm the hope <strong>of</strong><br />

a coming time, outside the dialectical-historical closure, the messianic<br />

hope <strong>of</strong> coming <strong>of</strong> the Other. Th is time beyond time, <strong>of</strong> which<br />

Emmanuel Levinas calls ‘patience <strong>of</strong> time’, remains inappropriable<br />

in ‘my’ self-presence: this impossibility <strong>of</strong> self-presencing out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

inexhaustible freedom that eludes all our manner <strong>of</strong> grounding, this<br />

groundless fi nitude is the condition <strong>of</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> our affi rmation <strong>of</strong><br />

a future to come. Th is, however, constitutes the task <strong>of</strong> our freedom,<br />

we who as existence-unto-fi nitude are born out <strong>of</strong> abyss, out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

non-self-present and therefore groundless ground. Writing or Saying<br />

addressed to the Other will, then, not be constitutive <strong>of</strong> speculativedialectical<br />

concept, but be a gift to the other and a promise <strong>of</strong> future.<br />

Th is poetic-aphoristic writing reads the works <strong>of</strong> Maurice Blanchot<br />

and Emmanuel Levinas to think fi nitude and language as gift and the<br />

necessity to affi rm a coming time.<br />

*<br />

Beginning with Hegel, let us say with him that there is a writing that<br />

is the secret <strong>of</strong> sense: it is the secret <strong>of</strong> ‘origin’, <strong>of</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> sense


382 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

to itself, <strong>of</strong> sense’s awakening from itself to itself, <strong>of</strong> sense’s coming<br />

to light from the slumber <strong>of</strong> sensuous indulgence. Th is writing<br />

allows itself to work, as a work <strong>of</strong> sense and a labour <strong>of</strong> Concept<br />

that presents itself to itself in a kind <strong>of</strong> self-originary presentation.<br />

Nothing precedes this self-originary work, since it begins with itself<br />

alone and originates with itself as (self) sense-presentation to itself,<br />

and also nothing follows it—itself being the fi rst and the last -- it<br />

thereby writes its own pre-face and post-face in which its pre-face and<br />

post-face coincides in a ‘co’ that is immanent to itself. It has the copula<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgement that joins in an immanent manner, while disjoining,<br />

the pre and the post. To think it in its intrinsic relation to time, this<br />

is writing that persists in the temporality <strong>of</strong> pre, the middle, and the<br />

post (or Subject, the Copula and Predicate), the writing that is Now<br />

presents itself simultaneously in the non-simultaneities <strong>of</strong> various<br />

nows, the Now that presents itself as non-now in various nows (by<br />

setting itself into variation <strong>of</strong> non-nows). Th e Now diff ers from itself,<br />

sets itself into variation and into non-simultaneity <strong>of</strong> non-nows and<br />

in that way, which is the ruse <strong>of</strong> the negative, it gathers into its selfpresent<br />

unity as unity <strong>of</strong> diff erences, or Now as unity <strong>of</strong> non-nows<br />

<strong>of</strong> diff erences. Since it is not the dead, life-less, mere formal unity<br />

(<strong>of</strong> mathematical truth, for example) but a speculative unity, this<br />

speculative writing is otherwise than the ‘night where all cows are<br />

black’, (Hegel 1998, p. 9) but presents itself as preserving in its unity<br />

<strong>of</strong> what is written as truth <strong>of</strong> the non-simul <strong>of</strong> nows, <strong>of</strong> diff erences<br />

that come to presence and disappear. What such a speculative writing<br />

looks like, which is otherwise than ‘absolute night where all cows are<br />

black’?<br />

Hegel (Ibid., pp. 59-60) asks us to write: ‘Now is Night’, which,<br />

in being written, is otherwise than the Day and Night, and is true<br />

even when it is no longer ‘now’ the night, even when the now the<br />

moment it is written itself is lapsed and disappeared without return,<br />

for the written ‘now’, in so far it is ‘written’, is preserved in truth as<br />

the Same that now, even though the now itself has disappeared. To<br />

the extent that every now presents to itself as its own absence, that<br />

means, by becoming stale, waste, pure expenditure and demise <strong>of</strong><br />

sense without return, it ruins the self-presence any memory <strong>of</strong> its<br />

own origin, it forgets to grasp that fainting murmur that has become


Fragments • 383<br />

outside the Now, it misses to sublate that cry outside speech and<br />

outside concept, as if the speculative Concept betrays itself. Th is is<br />

the great betrayal, the infi delity, the transgression <strong>of</strong> what presents<br />

itself as truth or knowledge. Th is cry betrays the Book, falls outside<br />

the Hegelian System, because it does not originate with the Book or<br />

the system and does not end with it either—for the Book in order<br />

to be something, to be itself must originate with itself and end with<br />

itself alone. Th erefore the Book always presents itself as the Book <strong>of</strong><br />

nothing, since it must begin with nothing (it must not presuppose<br />

anything, since any ‘something’ has a beginning outside <strong>of</strong> itself)<br />

and ends with nothing (since any ‘something’ is not ‘everything’,<br />

since the system—if it is at all the system, must have everything<br />

within itself). A peculiar result obtains here, which Schelling’s later<br />

philosophy articulates in its vehement critique <strong>of</strong> Hegelian attempt<br />

at the completion <strong>of</strong> the Book with the logical concept alone: in<br />

the Book nothing really is said, or written, the Book that claims to<br />

say everything and write everything and does not merely want to be<br />

‘the absolute where all cows are black’, since the Book has neither<br />

past nor future, neither time not eternity. A system or the Book that<br />

claims to found itself on the basis <strong>of</strong> negativity alone, this Book itself<br />

has neither past nor future within it, neither something nor nothing<br />

within it. Everything is outside the Book and nothing is outside the<br />

Book: nothing occurs, happens in the Book because the Book itself<br />

must happen, must occur absolutely, completely without remainder,<br />

without leftover so that everything is leftover, everything is remained<br />

apart from the Book, outside the Book. Th is exhaustion or fatigue<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Book reduces the Book to its own negativity or nothingness,<br />

<strong>of</strong> its worklessness. Th is Book does not know time, nor it knows<br />

death and mourning, for in the Book nobody dies 1 , nobody writes,<br />

nobody mourns. A true mourning presupposes a non-appropriable<br />

transcendence, a time <strong>of</strong> the outside and time <strong>of</strong> the other beyond<br />

self-presence and beyond the self-originating unity <strong>of</strong> the Now. It<br />

is only in this sense mourning has relation to the Other and is true<br />

mourning, for mourning is always mourning for the Other, which<br />

is not preserved in the unity <strong>of</strong> a self—foundational ground, or in<br />

the unity <strong>of</strong> a speculative Now. It is in this sense alone mourning<br />

has a relation to a past forever inappropriable and a future beyond<br />

calculation; it is in this sense writing has a relation to a dying that is


384 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

outside the sense <strong>of</strong> presence and its presence <strong>of</strong> sense, that does not<br />

preserve the truth <strong>of</strong> nows in being written Now as ‘Now is Night’.<br />

Not being able to work, not being work, writing is exposed to the<br />

utter abandonment <strong>of</strong> mourning, inconsolable mourning, infi nite<br />

mourning, and interminable mourning. Th is infi nite fi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

dying is an infi nite departure without return, an immeasurable<br />

disappearing without speech and voice. Writing: the murmur <strong>of</strong> the<br />

departed, the foundering <strong>of</strong> speech, the stammering fainting <strong>of</strong> the<br />

elapsed.<br />

Th ere is a writing that presents itself as sense <strong>of</strong> disaster and there<br />

is a writing, which no one writes, is otherwise than sense, that<br />

introduces, in the sense <strong>of</strong> disaster, a disaster <strong>of</strong> sense: disaster <strong>of</strong><br />

sense and not sense <strong>of</strong> disaster, even though disaster <strong>of</strong> sense is that<br />

from which sense as such, even the sense <strong>of</strong> disaster emerges. Th is<br />

is the most abysmal ‘origin’ <strong>of</strong> sense, ‘origin’ outside <strong>of</strong> sense and<br />

hence without ‘origin’ (since sense must present to itself its origin<br />

as sense). Schelling calls this origin ‘groundlessness’ (Abgrund), or<br />

abyss that gives the possibility <strong>of</strong> anything like ground at all and<br />

therefore cannot itself in turn be grounded or recuperated in the<br />

immanence <strong>of</strong> a speculative concept. Th e transcendence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

groundless, exceeding any self-presence, extends and lengthens time<br />

itself to infi nity, <strong>of</strong> what Schelling the ‘eternal past’ or ‘the darkness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the past’ which dialectical-historical memory cannot trace back to<br />

another self-presence. Levinas calls this time before as ‘immemorial<br />

past’, past that has never been present, that has never been a selfpresence,<br />

beyond the closure <strong>of</strong> the Book, abandoning the book to its<br />

fatigue, to its wearing away <strong>of</strong> itself or tearing away <strong>of</strong> itself beyond<br />

repair, or its unworking in an already time outside time. Th ere is<br />

something like mourning in all works and in all writings—writing<br />

that constitutes the Book and writing outside the Book: the disaster<br />

<strong>of</strong> mourning from which Socrates ‘the pure thinker <strong>of</strong> the West’,<br />

the philosopher who does not write, protects himself by driving<br />

away the mourned women for whom Socrates is the other, the other<br />

who does not return in the immortality <strong>of</strong> hope, in the hope <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immortality <strong>of</strong> soul so that inconsolable mourning traverses whom<br />

the death <strong>of</strong> the other aff ects beyond any measure. As if there occurs<br />

two deaths in Phaedo: death <strong>of</strong> oneself, who is Socrates himself, for


Fragments • 385<br />

whom immortality <strong>of</strong> the soul is promised through death, for whom<br />

death is only a passage and a promise since he has learnt how to<br />

die (‘Philosophy is to learn how to die’: says Socrates) so as not to<br />

die without return (without the gift <strong>of</strong> eternity), the invested death<br />

(Philosopher’s death); and then there is another death, for whom<br />

death is always death <strong>of</strong> the other and without sense, without any<br />

investment <strong>of</strong> sense, and hence dying without return and without<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>i t, inconsolable mourning <strong>of</strong> those who have not learned to die<br />

for other’s death, foolish and non-sense 2 <strong>of</strong> mourning that aff ects us<br />

by its nonsense, that does not leave them even to hope, disastrous<br />

mourning . Yet, is it not that already in the death <strong>of</strong> the philosopher,<br />

<strong>of</strong> the one who learns to know nothing, or better, learns to know that<br />

he does not know (Socrates is this exemplary fi gure par excellence),<br />

hope already marks an infi nite distance, a diachronic distance neither<br />

traversed and nor accomplished, neither measured nor guaranteed by<br />

knowledge even if it is hope for the immortality <strong>of</strong> the soul? Th is hope<br />

is the distance from all knowledge, even the philosophical knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> death, as if it is not enough to learn to die, as if knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

death is not enough for death so that hope, beyond the measurement<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge, is only that be borne in a passivity beyond measure,<br />

death that is, as Emmanuel Levinas calls it, ‘the patience <strong>of</strong> time’. 3<br />

Hope itself would have already made Socrates other than himself<br />

(other than a ‘self’) without recall, the ‘I’ <strong>of</strong> Socrates who has become<br />

the ‘he’: un-guaranteed dying outside time, disastrous dying whose<br />

remains would be for the other to write, the one for whom the dead<br />

is the other. It is always the other who writes, the other being the<br />

survivor and the mourned. Plato absents himself from the other’s<br />

death so that discourse be possible, so that writing is possible, and so<br />

that writing, in this possibility, also be that <strong>of</strong> mourning, the remains<br />

<strong>of</strong> the remaining, the impossibility <strong>of</strong> writing death, ‘the impossibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> all possibilities’, as if writing hesitates itself before itself and faints<br />

away in a murmur that refuses the name <strong>of</strong> an ‘event’ <strong>of</strong> fi nitude.<br />

Disaster does not occur; it does not fulfi l the requirement <strong>of</strong> being<br />

the event, even the event <strong>of</strong> being. Not being able to work, it falls<br />

short <strong>of</strong> its work, a hesitation before death, a trembling and a cry.<br />

‘Th e work <strong>of</strong> mourning: Th e inverse <strong>of</strong> dying’. (Blanchot 1992, p. 96).<br />

In Saying Now would not persist in all nows as contraction <strong>of</strong>


386 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

nows, so that in this non-returned and non-conserved dying <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Other, time is lengthened to infi nity and also diff ered to the infi nite<br />

passivity <strong>of</strong> patience, which is the patience <strong>of</strong> infi nity itself. It is the<br />

non-negative fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the Other that is aff ection, fi nitude which<br />

is neither the accomplishment <strong>of</strong> the end nor the annihilation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the once-lived. In Saying aff ection 4 aff ects, or the death <strong>of</strong> the<br />

other aff ects, and introduces in ‘me’ a disquietude, an inconsolable<br />

mourning. Levinas speaks <strong>of</strong> this aff ection as disquietude <strong>of</strong> the nonin-diff<br />

erence in the Same. Would not it then a mourning already<br />

always and in a time yet to come aff ect Saying and all Said, bestowing<br />

in our speech, in our action, in our existence an infi nite responsibility<br />

to the other, to the death <strong>of</strong> the other? Th e dialectical-historical task<br />

<strong>of</strong> constituting the universal world order on the basis <strong>of</strong> the labour<br />

<strong>of</strong> the negative and on the basis <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> death that converts<br />

even non-being into being will, then, be insuffi cient. Th e labour <strong>of</strong><br />

the negativity that we perform in our ‘mouth swallowing the water<br />

or in cutting the head <strong>of</strong> a cabbage’, 5 and in the ‘tarrying with the<br />

negative’ 6 which <strong>of</strong> all must be the most terrible, this power <strong>of</strong><br />

death is opened, in an ethical responsibility, to the utter passivity,<br />

to the dying <strong>of</strong> the other, to a death which is ‘the patience <strong>of</strong> time’.<br />

If Levinas calls this ‘patience <strong>of</strong> time’ diachrony, mourning would<br />

be the aff ection <strong>of</strong> this diachrony, or rather diachrony is that which<br />

aff ects us as mourning for the Other. It is a gift without presence,<br />

beyond the simul <strong>of</strong> self-presence, beyond the labour and power <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept.<br />

Gift without presence and without measure! Presence measures itself<br />

in the equivalences <strong>of</strong> nows into Now and measure, being measure<br />

(which is its ‘being’), assumes the time <strong>of</strong> presence, since only<br />

measure can be present and can be presented and since only presence<br />

can be measured. In the measure <strong>of</strong> presence and in this presence<br />

<strong>of</strong> measure, negativity eff ectuates its production where everything is<br />

exchanged—<strong>of</strong> being passing into nothing and nothing passing into<br />

being (Hegel 1975, p.134)—where, in pain and as logos, is produced<br />

the world and the Book. Remember Heidegger’s bringing to our<br />

notice the innermost connection <strong>of</strong> pain and logos in the labour <strong>of</strong><br />

the negative as the onto-theo-logical constitution <strong>of</strong> metaphysics<br />

(Heidegger 1959).But in giving gifts to the Other, where gift is none


Fragments • 387<br />

other than the giving, now would not exchange with all other nows<br />

and hence is without the Now that is sublation <strong>of</strong> the nows. A gift<br />

without salvation, without Aufhebung in the measurelessness <strong>of</strong> its<br />

giving, renouncing one’s hunger for the dying <strong>of</strong> the destitute other,<br />

destitute dying! Th ere is something like mournfulness, in the destitute<br />

dying without solace, in all giving and in renouncing; it’s a sadness<br />

without nostalgia for lost presence, without me assuming power or<br />

force, without the prerogatives <strong>of</strong> law: the patience <strong>of</strong> Saying, the<br />

fatigue <strong>of</strong> writing! Between Levinas (if we are allowed to say that<br />

Levinas is the ‘speaker’ <strong>of</strong> the patience <strong>of</strong> Saying) and Blanchot (if we<br />

are allowed to say that Blanchot as ‘writer’ <strong>of</strong> the fatigue <strong>of</strong> writing):<br />

mourning beyond measure would separate them from each other,<br />

gift would call them to each other into proximity. Between Levinas<br />

and Blanchot: time without temporality, the excess <strong>of</strong> exteriority, the<br />

interval <strong>of</strong> interruption.<br />

Yet is not it that language primarily presents itself as work <strong>of</strong> death,<br />

in being capable <strong>of</strong> death so as to be capable <strong>of</strong> language, in being<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> language so as to be able to die—in other words—so as<br />

to be able to be, to be able to maintain what is not maintainable,<br />

to preserve that which annihilates, to make appear and present<br />

what disappears so that this impotence <strong>of</strong> nothingness itself brings<br />

to birth what is ‘is’, the universal ‘Being in general’ (Hegel 1998,<br />

p.60)? Death, the impossibility par excellence, would then assume<br />

the source and origin <strong>of</strong> all possibilities as the power <strong>of</strong> non-power:<br />

‘the possibility <strong>of</strong> impossibility’ that Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong>. With<br />

this Hegelian philosophy attempts, in the most concentrated form<br />

<strong>of</strong> a system, to extract from death the possibility <strong>of</strong> something like<br />

possibility at all, the possibility <strong>of</strong> being and world, <strong>of</strong> history and<br />

time. Th rough nothingness, as nothingness <strong>of</strong> Hegel, the dead<br />

Hegel is resurrected in the reader’s Sunday reading so as Hegel not<br />

be mere corpse prey to the ‘unconscious appetite’ (Ibid., p. 271) <strong>of</strong><br />

the elemental or the arrested fetish <strong>of</strong> sense. Writing—the pyramid<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hegel, the nothingness <strong>of</strong> Hegel—is also the possibility <strong>of</strong> Easter<br />

Sunday which writing undertakes on his behalf as the work <strong>of</strong> death,<br />

the fulfi lment and completion <strong>of</strong> the Book, the accomplishment <strong>of</strong><br />

sense and its desire. Death <strong>of</strong> Hegel would, then, be the possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Hegel who is born out <strong>of</strong> his nothingness, born out <strong>of</strong> his ashes


388 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

once again, re-born in the reader’s reading his Book . But fatigue—<br />

the disaster <strong>of</strong> sense—traversing the Book, abandons the Book to the<br />

without Book. Th is is mourning for the dead Hegel who would not<br />

return and is not resurrected in the reader’s reading, the Good Friday<br />

not redeemed in Good Sunday. Th is is Hegel ravaged by thought<br />

whose writing is only the wrinkles on Hegel’s face, his infi nite fatigue<br />

that is borne in patience. Th is patience would not be recounted in<br />

the Book, in the System, but outside the Book’s restless negativity,<br />

outside its jurisdiction and outside its force.<br />

Blanchot’s writing: writing that, in the name <strong>of</strong> the proper name<br />

‘Blanchot’, in the naming the disappearing <strong>of</strong> the ‘I’, would name<br />

excessively or too little <strong>of</strong> Blanchot, writing that disappears without<br />

return, without resurrecting in the reader’s reading so that infi nite<br />

mourning traversing the Book, would not constitute the Book.<br />

Mourning for the departed who is not preserved, who has become the<br />

‘he’ without return, disaster without work, dying without possibility,<br />

even ‘the possibility <strong>of</strong> impossibilities’—impossible mourning, that<br />

is writing.<br />

Between Hegel and Blanchot—Lazarus dead and resurrected;<br />

Lazarus dead without return—writing traverses without crossing, or<br />

rather crossing that is to be crossed once again, that means, infi nite<br />

times. Infi nite crossing which is impossibility <strong>of</strong> crossing! Th e<br />

impossible traversal <strong>of</strong> writing, or the impossible transgression not<br />

recuperated in the speculative concept, for writing, in not being able<br />

to take charge <strong>of</strong> transgression against the law, does not even posit its nonpositing<br />

as transgressive.<br />

Let us say that law posits itself as work <strong>of</strong> death. All law founds<br />

itself, posits itself as an act <strong>of</strong> negation and presupposes violence<br />

which is the violence <strong>of</strong> positing. Th e Book, which is the totality <strong>of</strong><br />

sense, gathered by the labour and the pain <strong>of</strong> the negative, always<br />

appears as the Book <strong>of</strong> law. Hegel knew something about this, about<br />

death as ‘the supreme fulfi lment <strong>of</strong> work’ 7 which is the work <strong>of</strong> law:<br />

it is the empty sovereignty <strong>of</strong> law, force without sensible, signifi cation<br />

without existence. Yet mourning, not being able to posit anything, even<br />

the positing <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, is the de-positing <strong>of</strong> the Book in passivity, and


Fragments • 389<br />

exceeding the violence <strong>of</strong> law, opens itself to justice, understood as depositing<br />

transcendence: Blanchot calls this non-power as ‘writing’ and<br />

Levinas calls justice the non-related relation to the other’s fi nitude<br />

that is not posited but is patience and aff ection, which is the excess<br />

in death, as if death is not enough for the infi nity <strong>of</strong> mourning, as if<br />

the diachrony <strong>of</strong> aff ection is not measured on the basis <strong>of</strong> death. Is<br />

not it then justice must pass through, is itself none but this passing<br />

through, writing? Or that writing, in traversing the Book, attracted<br />

by the outside, is justice, always mourned justice. It is not the justice<br />

as the joining <strong>of</strong> jointure, but disjointed response to the other without<br />

presence.<br />

In the work <strong>of</strong> mourning, it is not grief that works: grief keeps watch.’<br />

(Blanchot 1995, p.51)<br />

A boy, adolescent, passes through the harvested fi eld <strong>of</strong> an autumnal<br />

evening. Th e harvested, golden corns lie gathered here and there<br />

by the farmers who have left for home, and the birds, silently<br />

fl ying back home in the eternal sky, partake the anguish <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dying sun, and the sky itself, illumined by the last amber <strong>of</strong> the<br />

day, has grown mute. Th e boy came home, and since then, as if<br />

infi nity <strong>of</strong> the days have passed and infi nite times the sun has set,<br />

infi nite times the birds have come home in autumnal evening in<br />

infi nite numbers, and the boy too has passed his adolescence, his<br />

youth and his manhood and himself has become the evening Sun<br />

<strong>of</strong> the autumnal evening, his birds too have drunk the wine <strong>of</strong><br />

youth and have now passed away silently in the sky. But what has<br />

happened that day, that evening in him outside him—with the<br />

sky, with the autumnal fi eld and with birds -- have not stopped<br />

happening in him from then onwards, and has recurred incessantly,<br />

thenceforth, every evening the same evening coming and repeating<br />

with a repetition that is infi nitely the same dying Sun, the same<br />

birds mute with anguish, the same harvested fi eld <strong>of</strong> golden corn.<br />

Henceforth he has carried, without being able to, the impossible<br />

and unnameable: henceforth he speaks and names, incessantly that<br />

has become his obsession, only to speak one and the only thing that<br />

he would have liked to speak to others, the one and the only thing<br />

he would have liked to share with others—that includes not only


390 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

humans, but also animals and birds and with the elemental forces<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature—to name to unnameable, to speak the unspeakable, to<br />

share the un-shareable enigma: the truth <strong>of</strong> a secret that he cannot<br />

bear, and that he bears it in this impossibility, in a patience <strong>of</strong><br />

time from where time takes its patience. Henceforth he speaks,<br />

obsessively and incessantly, in an irremediable compulsion that<br />

comes from elsewhere—and he speaks to the animals and birds, to<br />

the humans and to the silence and thunders <strong>of</strong> the sky—speaking<br />

everything so as not to speak the only essential he would like to<br />

speak, the single event that has happened without happening, the<br />

only and one important event <strong>of</strong> his life which he bore witness, and<br />

which he cannot testify. It has thenceforth grown silent within him<br />

more he spoke; it grew more solitary more he bonded with others;<br />

it grew more unnameable more he named all those around him:<br />

animals and birds, things and objects, humans and the divine. He<br />

has henceforth carried a secret <strong>of</strong> a distressed waiting which has<br />

deprived him <strong>of</strong> his selfhood, a self without self. Henceforth he is<br />

eternally on the way and his distress is the distress <strong>of</strong> the eternally<br />

awaiting one, the one who having to await has missed the name<br />

and the word, missed speech and its possibility, as if the secret whose<br />

solitude has no common with any commonality is born precisely<br />

at that moment when awaiting, born with it, gives speech for the<br />

fi rst time its possibility, the possibility <strong>of</strong> a coming time, when the<br />

speech is not yet, speech yet to be born. It is the speech <strong>of</strong> the one,<br />

the eternally awaiting one, who is yet to be born. It is awaiting for<br />

birth and revelation, for manifestation and opening. Henceforth he<br />

speaks everything with everyone, but silence grew with every speech,<br />

and in every speech there resonated that humming <strong>of</strong> that distant<br />

world, nearer than anyone and more distant than anything, there<br />

resonated that melancholy <strong>of</strong> the Sun and the tears <strong>of</strong> the golden<br />

corns, as if what has befallen on him, without happening anything<br />

‘this’ and ‘that’, outside time is none but the melancholy <strong>of</strong> speech<br />

itself, the melancholy <strong>of</strong> the name.<br />

Even if, supposing the time <strong>of</strong> writing is none other than Now that<br />

seeks to incorporate what has become stale when one writes, ‘Now<br />

is night’, the Now that is the eternal immobility <strong>of</strong> the coming and<br />

disappearing <strong>of</strong> every nows; then reading, yet to take place, would not


Fragments • 391<br />

come to pass, but would affi rm the future <strong>of</strong> reading, which means,<br />

the impossibility <strong>of</strong> reading. Th is reading, this future would not, then,<br />

belong to the ‘possibility <strong>of</strong> impossibilities’. To read Hegel, impossible<br />

each time, each time the singular and singularly interrupting would<br />

be to read him outside the Book, outside the system. Hegel’s his<br />

face ravaged by the labour <strong>of</strong> thinking, as one <strong>of</strong> his students recalls<br />

his face, would then belong to a future <strong>of</strong> reading outside his own<br />

system, outside his own Book. Th is exhaustion, this fatigue not yet<br />

exhausted in an accomplished time, would not be thought within<br />

Hegel’s own system <strong>of</strong> a certain Hegel, the Hegel bearing anonymous<br />

name <strong>of</strong> the Book. In that sense, the name <strong>of</strong> Hegel would be outside<br />

all names, through which names pass through without return, as if<br />

in every naming fi nitude <strong>of</strong> the named is announced each time, and<br />

thereby marking and eff acing the mark that marks the eff acement <strong>of</strong><br />

time. Let us remember the early Hegel who not yet having arrived at<br />

the system, suff ers the melancholia that threatens to lose the grasp <strong>of</strong><br />

entirety <strong>of</strong> his existence altogether, which is sought to be suppressed,<br />

suspended, surpassed in the System. Yet the same mourning aff ects<br />

his friend Hölderlin without measure which could not be suspended<br />

or suppressed in the system: inconsolable mourning for an absent<br />

origin outside thought, ‘the violence <strong>of</strong> the elements’ which as if<br />

‘Apollo strikes’ him (Hölderlin 1988a, p.152). Yet mourning not<br />

being yet recounted in the system in an accomplished time, would<br />

contaminate the system without striking anything and anyone in<br />

particular, introducing the unworking <strong>of</strong> disaster without destroying<br />

anything, tearing the work and exposing to the limitless that would<br />

not have limit as its limit to actualize itself. Th is disaster would strike<br />

everything and everyone, every sense and every element in the system,<br />

dispersed, so that nothing is salvaged, saved and resurrected intact,<br />

so that the Book, losing its centre, would allow itself to be hollowed<br />

out, not to be able to say anything, not to be able to do anything. Th e<br />

powerlessness <strong>of</strong> the Book: the face <strong>of</strong> Hegel ravaged by the passion<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking. To think is to mourn: in thinking we mourn everything<br />

that is fi nite, fragile and fainting without recall.<br />

‘Ruin <strong>of</strong> words, demise writing, faintness faintly murmuring: what<br />

remains without remains (the fragmentary).’ (Blanchot 1995, p.33)<br />

Not to think <strong>of</strong> time on the basis <strong>of</strong> death, which is, not to think <strong>of</strong>


392 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

in-fi nity <strong>of</strong> patience on the basis <strong>of</strong> either negativity in the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> sense, the sense <strong>of</strong> History, or on the basis <strong>of</strong> nothingness in the<br />

‘being-towards-death’: this is what we have learnt to think from<br />

Emmanuel Levinas. But the other death, the dying <strong>of</strong> the other, from<br />

which time takes patience, irreducible to negativity or nothingness<br />

in annihilation or decomposition is the infi nite patience which is<br />

otherwise than retention or protention, otherwise than intentionality<br />

that has the measure as the measure. 8 It is more ancient than any<br />

memory and more future than any anticipation. Such a patience<br />

unsays the Said so that Saying overfl ows sense and Said: the surplus<br />

<strong>of</strong> Saying, the surplus <strong>of</strong> mourning. Writing too, dying in not able to<br />

die, as if death is not enough <strong>of</strong> dying—the non-accomplished fatigue<br />

<strong>of</strong> writing—would not cease dying in the accomplished death. Such<br />

is writing, the measureless that is the limit without limitations, which<br />

is, the measurelessness <strong>of</strong> the limits that would not have limitations<br />

as its measure. Yet, is not it that Blanchot invites us to think measure<br />

itself as the limit 9 ? Measure which is the limit without limitations,<br />

would not have negativity as its limits in ‘Being-there-and-then’ 10 ,<br />

measure in which nothing is actualized, the non-posited measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> limits and the non-posited limits <strong>of</strong> measure; it is the measure<br />

that measures nothing, the non-measured measure, measure that is<br />

non-measure. So it is limit, limit that is not posited, that would not<br />

have any determined, accomplished limit as its limit, the non-limited<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> measure that would not have measure as its limit. Writing:<br />

the non-measured measure, the non-limited limits.<br />

What then remains between Saying and writing, on the dying <strong>of</strong><br />

the other when mourning is not measured on the basis <strong>of</strong> death?<br />

Should we call this non-contemporaneity between contemporaries<br />

‘friendship’? Friendship calls them towards each other to proximity<br />

and separates each from the other. Between friends: gift to the other<br />

in mourning, the gift <strong>of</strong> mourning.<br />

Th e World is not the totality <strong>of</strong> self and others, the totality <strong>of</strong> being<br />

and the beings <strong>of</strong> others, but rather the world is a gift, non-totalized<br />

and out <strong>of</strong> fi nitude, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as the world is fi nite, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as gift is<br />

singular each time.


Fragments • 393<br />

How to think the gift <strong>of</strong> the name that announces the fi nitude <strong>of</strong><br />

the named and the name itself, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as fi nitude is not reducible to<br />

negativity <strong>of</strong> the Concept and Sense? Th ere is, as it were, a note <strong>of</strong><br />

melancholy that adheres our fi nite existence, which also intimates the<br />

gift that is given to other. In the sadness in renouncing the claim to<br />

possess the world for one’s own possibility, even if it is ‘possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

impossibilities’ that Heidegger speaks <strong>of</strong>, there lies nobility. It is the<br />

intimation <strong>of</strong> a noble joy, because it affi rms the joy <strong>of</strong> future. Each<br />

time one speaks, or better, each time language is spoken in one, there<br />

is opening <strong>of</strong> time to come, there is freeing time from the seizure <strong>of</strong><br />

present, from the closure <strong>of</strong> positing. Language is not primordially<br />

auto-positing time <strong>of</strong> negativity, but an address to the coming one.<br />

Th e other is not posited in my address but is addressed towards, a<br />

towards which is not a calculable anticipation, but an incalculable time<br />

that remains. Language has this pr<strong>of</strong>ound relationship with future,<br />

with coming, with time that remains, more primordially than time<br />

<strong>of</strong> negativity and its pure positing work <strong>of</strong> death. Each time language<br />

is addressed to the other, each time opening to time to come, each<br />

time there is Hope for the coming, Hope that redeems time from<br />

the closure <strong>of</strong> self-presence, from the seizure <strong>of</strong> self-present. Hope<br />

redeems time and opens to transcendence. It opens to Love, beyond<br />

the self-positing <strong>of</strong> the negativity <strong>of</strong> the mere ‘not not’. Th e time <strong>of</strong><br />

evil, deprived <strong>of</strong> the time <strong>of</strong> the remains, does not know redemption.<br />

Evil is destruction <strong>of</strong> Hope, Hope that bursts forth each time one<br />

opens her lips. Evil is the refusal to know the ecstatic temporality <strong>of</strong><br />

non-posited past that murmurs in the lament <strong>of</strong> language at its limit;<br />

it is the refusal to know the incessant demand <strong>of</strong> ecstatic fi nitude that<br />

time itself must be renewed each time in each presence as revelation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the non-posited past. Th e impossible experience <strong>of</strong> mourning for<br />

the other is to be transfi gured into the messianic hope for coming <strong>of</strong><br />

the other, into a redemptive affi rmation.<br />

Th e task <strong>of</strong> the presence is the one <strong>of</strong> renewal: mourned renewal<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unredeemed past. Th is alone defi nes the nature <strong>of</strong> ‘work’ <strong>of</strong><br />

the dialectical-historical world. Work is no longer to be seen as the<br />

recuperative labour <strong>of</strong> memory <strong>of</strong> what has been, but remembrance <strong>of</strong><br />

the never present and renewal <strong>of</strong> hope yet to arrive. Together they do


394 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

not constitute ‘die homogene und leere Zeit’, ‘the homogenous and<br />

empty time’ (Benjamin 1977, p.258), but rather the constellation<br />

<strong>of</strong> temporalities, marked by unredeemed melancholy for the past<br />

and the messianic hope for the future. Th ey are connected, by that<br />

manner separated, by discontinuous abyss <strong>of</strong> temporality where<br />

times are joined disjointedly whose condition <strong>of</strong> jointure remains<br />

outside. Schelling asks us to think the event <strong>of</strong> temporality as cut,<br />

cision, dehiscence (die Scheidung), which is also de-cision, <strong>of</strong> presence.<br />

Th is makes time itself ecstatic, beyond any closure <strong>of</strong> the dialecticalhistorical<br />

time, whose ground lies ecstatically in an eternal outside,<br />

the unposited past and whose freedom ecstatically lies eternally<br />

ahead intimated in prophecy. Between them the decision <strong>of</strong> presence<br />

separates and thereby connects them, making temporalization itself<br />

into a passage <strong>of</strong> one to the other, past into future, melancholy into<br />

redemptive fulfi lment. Th e heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> the ecstatic outside<br />

inhabits the self-presence <strong>of</strong> any world-historical destiny. Th ese<br />

singular ecstasies are not particular instants subsumable to the empty<br />

universal time <strong>of</strong> the Concept where each birth monotonously passes<br />

into the other in a linear succession. Rather each birth is a surprise;<br />

each birth is a new hope and a renewal <strong>of</strong> time; each birth is an<br />

inauguration <strong>of</strong> ever new time, an ecstasy <strong>of</strong> fi nitude born out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

abyss <strong>of</strong> freedom.<br />

Joy is transfi guration <strong>of</strong> sorrow. According to Schelling, all<br />

transfi guration is an ecstatic decision, a cision and an overcoming.<br />

Unlike God who posits himself in an indissoluble ground, so that<br />

eternal past, eternal present and eternal future are an indissoluble<br />

unity, the fi nite being is the one whom totality excludes, for whom<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> time is only a never-actualized whole without totality.<br />

Th is fi nitude also makes his freedom ecstatic, abysmal and yet<br />

joyous. Man is this contradiction, this rupture, this cision, this<br />

disjoined jointure who accomplishes unity in a piecemeal fashion<br />

as assemblage. God’s unity is indissoluble, man’s unity is assemblage.<br />

Th is assemblage <strong>of</strong> singular ecstasies <strong>of</strong> temporalities is irreducible<br />

to the uniformity <strong>of</strong> the homogenous empty time. By emptying out<br />

<strong>of</strong> these ecstatic singularities <strong>of</strong> temporalities to the homogeneity <strong>of</strong><br />

the empty succession <strong>of</strong> concepts, the dominant metaphysics also<br />

deprives language its ecstasies, its bursting revelation out <strong>of</strong> fi nitude,


Fragments • 395<br />

its surprise <strong>of</strong> origin. As such, this dominant metaphysics, which has<br />

its highest accomplishment in dialectical-speculative onto-theo-logy,<br />

remains without language and without promise It remains without<br />

the thinking for the advent that enables for the coming to come and<br />

enables one to open to what remains to come.<br />

Th e onto-theo-logical constitution <strong>of</strong> metaphysics in its dialecticalspeculative<br />

form remains without language. Or rather it remains<br />

the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the one who refuses to speak. He pursues the<br />

dream <strong>of</strong> an autochthonous mythical speech which is addressed to<br />

no one, speech without hope and without language. Th e time <strong>of</strong> this<br />

mythical speech is the homogeneity <strong>of</strong> empty time. Such a speech<br />

lacks the ecstasy <strong>of</strong> fi nite existence that each time ecstatically exceeds<br />

all insistence in self-presence. Th e non-posited existence <strong>of</strong> the there, the<br />

never-to-sublated <strong>of</strong> the already past and equally non-posited <strong>of</strong> what<br />

remains cannot be thought as mere ‘not-not’ <strong>of</strong> the negativity.<br />

Hope is the hope for redemption. Th is alone redeems the melancholy<br />

by opening to a time yet to arrive, outside the ‘anxiety’ <strong>of</strong> our ‘beingtowards-death’,<br />

and beyond the ‘possibility <strong>of</strong> impossibility’ <strong>of</strong> having<br />

one’s time. Beyond anticipation, hope is the hope for having forever,<br />

eternally, the time that remains for the other: not -- possibility,<br />

impossibility, or even ‘possibility <strong>of</strong> impossibility’ <strong>of</strong> having one’s<br />

time. Anxiety does not redeem time, it only ecstatically keeps open to<br />

a possibility <strong>of</strong> not having possibility any more, which means, keeps<br />

open to a possibility <strong>of</strong> not being open any more, to a possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

not having to be anxious any more. Hope is otherwise: it is opened to<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> an infi nite opening for what is remaining to come.<br />

Only in relation to hope anxiety is meaningful, or anxiety is only<br />

de-limitation <strong>of</strong> hope. Anxiety partakes as anticipatable in the nonanticipatable<br />

time <strong>of</strong> coming <strong>of</strong> hope. Hope is beyond anticipation;<br />

it does not have the immanence and certainty <strong>of</strong> the ‘any moment’ <strong>of</strong><br />

anxiety over death. In hope time is released from the grasp <strong>of</strong> presence<br />

for the arriving. Th is redemption alone is the relation to the infi nite<br />

for the fi nite being which has its resonance <strong>of</strong> prayer. Man addresses<br />

himself to the infi nite in prayer. Th e dialectical-speculative spirit, ever<br />

imprisoned in the closure <strong>of</strong> labour and memory, ever imprisoned in<br />

the historical fate that does not know its ecstatic outside, the morose


396 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

time, does not know prayer, nor does it know the task <strong>of</strong> renewal<br />

and revelation. Th e disjunction that resonates in the songs <strong>of</strong> prayer,<br />

the disjunction between anticipatable and non-anticipatable coming,<br />

this disjunction permeates our prayer with an unspeakable note <strong>of</strong><br />

mourning. In all prayer is there a note <strong>of</strong> mourning and also a note <strong>of</strong><br />

hope. In prayer the mourned soul is opened to hope for redemption.<br />

As fi nite, existence is that is always ‘being-towards-death’ (Heidegger<br />

1962). Th e very fi rst cry <strong>of</strong> the new born reveals anew the truth <strong>of</strong><br />

the last; the beginning announces its end. Who can take away from<br />

the mortals the hope and fear <strong>of</strong> this truth, let alone philosophy that<br />

seeks to be the infi nite discourse, capable <strong>of</strong> reaching the Absolute,<br />

for it fear <strong>of</strong> death being only the vanity <strong>of</strong> the mortals? Th u begins<br />

Rosenzweig’s critique <strong>of</strong> philosophy, his meditations on birth and<br />

death, on love that is as strong as death and the eternal future <strong>of</strong><br />

redemption. To be fi nished is mortal, but to be mortal is also to<br />

remain open to eternity that is always to come. Th is alone makes hope<br />

meaningful for the mortals. Th erefore Absolute knowledge which is<br />

attained mere negatively as a logical becoming remains inconsolable<br />

for a being whose existence consists in his ‘being-towards-death’.<br />

To come—not this or that coming but the event <strong>of</strong> coming itself: this is<br />

the highest thought <strong>of</strong> promise and hope that philosophical thinking<br />

that attempts to think the unconditioned, can aspire to. ‘Th e<br />

Principle <strong>of</strong> Hope’ with which Ernst Bloch names this principle, the<br />

unconditioned principle <strong>of</strong> philosophical thinking par excellence, is<br />

the highest principle <strong>of</strong> philosophy. It is with hope that philosophy’s<br />

passion <strong>of</strong> origin begins and in whose messianic, redemptive<br />

fulfi lment lays philosophy’s eternal dream. Th is eternal hope for the<br />

event <strong>of</strong> remnant cannot be thought on the basis <strong>of</strong> predication,<br />

fi nality and result, but rather is the incalculable arrival <strong>of</strong> the wholly<br />

otherwise, which is always ‘to come’.<br />

Th e principle <strong>of</strong> hope—because such a principle endows upon<br />

philosophy its unconditional task—while it gives sense to our ethicopolitical<br />

tasks, it cannot be made itself into the principle <strong>of</strong> ‘this’ or<br />

‘that’ immanent, conditioned, self-consuming ‘politics’ or ‘ethics’ .<br />

What is thought with this principle <strong>of</strong> hope is a principle without


Fragments • 397<br />

archè and without telos. It is the name <strong>of</strong> pure transcendence, pure<br />

potentiality <strong>of</strong> taking place, and the event <strong>of</strong> arrival that cannot be<br />

nominalized, substantialized, or predicated. It is a principle that<br />

withdrawing from all apparitions gives sense to apparition, i.e. makes<br />

apparition possible.


§ Notes<br />

PROLOGUE<br />

1 Franz Rosenzweig speaks <strong>of</strong> the silence <strong>of</strong> the tragic hero <strong>of</strong> the mythical world:<br />

‘Th e hero as such as to succumb only because his demise entitles him to the supreme<br />

‘heroization’, to wit, the most closed-<strong>of</strong>f ‘selfi cation’ <strong>of</strong> his self. He yearns for this<br />

solitude <strong>of</strong> demise, because there is no greater solitude than this. Accordingly, the<br />

hero does not actually die after all. Death only cuts him <strong>of</strong>f , as it were, from the<br />

temporal features <strong>of</strong> individuality. Character transmitted into heroic self is immortal.<br />

For him, eternity was just good enough to echo his silence (Rosenzweig 1971, pp.<br />

78-79)’.<br />

The Open<br />

PART I – CONFIGURATIONS<br />

1 Günter Figal, following Heidegger, calls this ‘play space’ <strong>of</strong> the open as freedom,<br />

where freedom is no longer understood as a capacity <strong>of</strong> the human endowed with<br />

free will, but on the basis <strong>of</strong> the originary ‘play space’ on the basis <strong>of</strong> which any<br />

activity <strong>of</strong> the human is at all carried out (Figal 1998).<br />

2 Here ‘polis’ is no longer understood in its juridico legislative determination<br />

as ‘city state’, but in a more originary manner, as mortal existents’ more originary<br />

opening to each other.<br />

3 Martin Heidegger in his 1942-43 lectures on Parmenides thinks ‘the open’, in an<br />

essential relation to Parmenides’ essential word Aletheia, as the self-disclosing advent<br />

<strong>of</strong> Being to being that maintains a simultaneous closure <strong>of</strong> Being. Th is simultaneous<br />

non-simultaneity <strong>of</strong> the open that initiates the inception, or beginning, is the very<br />

timing <strong>of</strong> time or coming on the basis <strong>of</strong> which man founds his history, his politics


400 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

and ethics. Th e essential task, at the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> certain metaphysics, is to release<br />

(Gelassenheit), to free unto that ungrounded alethaic opening so that historical man<br />

gives himself the task <strong>of</strong> the inception anew, that means, to renew the promise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

inception. ‘Indeed, historical man’, says, Heidegger, ‘in so far as he is, always belongs<br />

within the bestowal <strong>of</strong> Being. Man, and only he, constantly sees into the open, in the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> the free, by which the ‘it is’ liberates each being to itself and on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />

this liberation looks at man in his guardianship <strong>of</strong> the open. Although man and only<br />

he constantly sees in the open, i.e., encounters beings in the free <strong>of</strong> Being, in order to<br />

be struck by them, yet he is not thereby entitled to bring Being itself explicitly into<br />

its own most, i.e., to being it into the open (the free), i.e., to poetize Being, to think<br />

it, and say it.’(p. 151). No doubt for Heidegger this historical people has remained<br />

to be the Germans. Th is historical people called ‘German humanity’, who are ‘the<br />

most metaphysical people’ are called upon to sacrifi ce themselves in this poetizing<br />

task <strong>of</strong> sacrifi ce for the sake <strong>of</strong> ‘preservation <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> Being’: ‘Th e highest form<br />

<strong>of</strong> suff ering is dying one’s death as a sacrifi ce for the preservation <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong><br />

Being. Th is sacrifi ce is the purest experience <strong>of</strong> the voice <strong>of</strong> Being. What if German<br />

humanity which, like the Greek, is called upon to poetize and think, and what if this<br />

German humanity must fi rst preserve the voice <strong>of</strong> Being... Th us what if the voice <strong>of</strong><br />

the beginning should announce itself in our historical destiny?’ (Heidegger 1992, p.<br />

167). In this way, Heidegger’s crypto-politics <strong>of</strong> disclosure has remained, even till the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> his career, even after his dissociation from Nazi politics, intimately bounded<br />

up with—at the least obvious level—a certain historical, metaphysical vision <strong>of</strong> the<br />

German humanity who is called upon to sacrifi ce on this purest task <strong>of</strong> poetizing<br />

and renewing the promise <strong>of</strong> inception, or the inception <strong>of</strong> promise itself, like the<br />

Greek. Veronique Fóti (1992) in her book Heidegger and the Poets painstaking brings<br />

out Heidegger’s crypto-politics <strong>of</strong> the Open, especially in the chapter <strong>of</strong> the book<br />

that she devotes to Heidegger’s reading <strong>of</strong> Rilke. Th e very promise <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s<br />

philosophical thinking that has sought to open up thinking outside the reductive<br />

totalization inherent in modern technology is immediately clouded by the archaic<br />

historical-metaphysical vision <strong>of</strong> a certain archè-crypto-political poetology. Th is<br />

present writer, acutely aware <strong>of</strong> the danger <strong>of</strong> this crypto politics, seeks to rescue the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> the Open without the historical-metaphysical vision <strong>of</strong> Heidegger, and<br />

thereby reading Heidegger, to a great extent, against Heidegger.<br />

4 ‘We never come to thoughts; they come to us’, Heidegger writes in ‘Th e Th inker<br />

as Poet’. (Heidegger 2001, p. 6)<br />

5 Hegel writes in Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit, ‘(1) I point out the ‘Now’, and it is<br />

asserted to be the truth. I point it out, however, as something that has been, or as<br />

something that has been superseded; I set aside the fi rst truth.(2) I now assert as the<br />

second truth that it has been, that it is superseded.(3) But what has been, is not; I<br />

set aside the second truth, its having been, its super session, and thereby negate the<br />

negation <strong>of</strong> the ‘Now’, and thus return to the fi rst assertion, that the ‘Now’ is. Th e<br />

‘Now’, and pointing out the ‘Now’, are so constituted that neither the one nor the<br />

other is something immediate and simple, but a movement which contains various<br />

moments. A Th is is posited; but it is rather an other that is posited, or the Th is is<br />

superseded; and this otherness, or the setting aside <strong>of</strong> the fi rst, is itself in turn set aside,


Notes • 401<br />

and so has returned into the fi rst. However, this fi rst, thus refl ected into itself, is not<br />

exactly the same as it was to begin with, viz., something immediate; on the contrary,<br />

on the contrary, it is something that is refl ected into itself, or a simple entity which, in<br />

its otherness, remains what it is: a Now which is an absolute plurality <strong>of</strong> Nows…<br />

Th e pointing-out <strong>of</strong> the Now is itself the movement which expresses what Now is in<br />

truth, viz., a result, or a plurality <strong>of</strong> Nows all taken together; and pointing-out is the<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> learning that Now is a universal. (Hegel 1998, pp. 63-64)<br />

6 Hegel writes in Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Nature: ‘Th e dimensions <strong>of</strong> time, present, future,<br />

and past, are the becoming <strong>of</strong> externality as such, and the resolution <strong>of</strong> it into the<br />

diff erences <strong>of</strong> being as passing over into nothing, and <strong>of</strong> nothing as passing over into<br />

being. Th e immediate vanishing <strong>of</strong> these diff erences into singularity is the present as<br />

Now which, as singularity, is exclusive <strong>of</strong> the other moments, and yet at the same time<br />

completely continuous in them, and is only this vanishing <strong>of</strong> its being into nothing<br />

and <strong>of</strong> nothing into its Being’. (Hegel 1970,p. 37)<br />

7 Schelling (1975) says in a letter after the death <strong>of</strong> Caroline: ‘I now need friends<br />

who are not strangers to the real seriousness <strong>of</strong> pain and who feel that the single<br />

right and happy state <strong>of</strong> the soul is the divine mourning in which all earthly pain in<br />

immersed.’<br />

Judgement and History<br />

1 Both Franz Rosenzweig and Kierkegaard in their singular ways have attempted<br />

to open up the immanent enclosure <strong>of</strong> a universal history to the transcendence <strong>of</strong><br />

the other order, that is, that <strong>of</strong> the infi nity <strong>of</strong> the divine where the singularity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

multiple beings is affi rmed, where singular mortals’ cry in the face <strong>of</strong> their irreducible<br />

mortality is not reduced to the speech <strong>of</strong> the being as universal and general.<br />

2 ‘Th is universality which the individual as such attains is pure being, death; it is a<br />

state which has been reached immediately, in the course <strong>of</strong> Nature, not the result <strong>of</strong> an<br />

action consciously done. Th e duty <strong>of</strong> the member <strong>of</strong> the family is on that account add<br />

this aspect, in order that the individuals ultimate being too, shall not belong solely to<br />

nature and remain something irrational, but shall be something done, and the right<br />

<strong>of</strong> consciousness be asserted in it… death is the fulfi llment and the supreme ‘work’<br />

which the individual as such undertakes on its behalf.’ Ibid.,p. 270.<br />

3 Hegel writes, ‘Death, if that is what we want to call this non-actuality, is <strong>of</strong><br />

all things the most dreadful, and to hold fast what is dead requires the greatest<br />

strength…But the life <strong>of</strong> Spirit is not the life that shrinks from death and keeps itself<br />

untouched by devastation, but rather the life that endures it and maintains itself<br />

in it. It wins its truth only when, in utter dismemberment, it fi nds itself. It is this<br />

power, not as something positive, which closes its eyes to the negative, as when we<br />

say <strong>of</strong> something that it is nothing or is false, and then, having done with it, turn<br />

away and pass onto something else; on the contrary, Spirit is this power only by<br />

looking negative in the face and tarrying with it’ (Ibid, p. 19).<br />

4 ‘Cision means ‘cut’, ‘slit’, ‘separation’, ‘disjunction’, or ‘divorce’. Scheidung<br />

means ‘De-cision’, and also ‘cision’ or ‘cut’. In addition Scheide also means vagina,<br />

sheath or opening <strong>of</strong> the female genitalia that is also separation or cut, the slit <strong>of</strong> two


402 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

lips that opens. Scheidung has the connotation <strong>of</strong> opening or coming, which is at<br />

once separation and disjunction.’ (Das 2008, p. 176)<br />

The Logic <strong>of</strong> Origin<br />

1 Ernst Bloch’s great work Th e Principle <strong>of</strong> Hope pursues, in a messianic visionary<br />

manner, the question <strong>of</strong> the origin itself as ‘not yet’. Bloch writes: ‘ Th e start <strong>of</strong> the<br />

beginning and the starting point called origin and world ground is to be found<br />

in precisely that Now and Here which has not yet emerged from itself, i.e. which<br />

has not yet moved from its place at all. Th is origin in the strict sense has itself not<br />

yet arisen, arisen out <strong>of</strong> itself; its Not is therefore in fact precisely the one which is<br />

ultimately driving history and tailoring historical processes to its requirements, but<br />

which has itself not yet become historical. Th is origin remains the incognito <strong>of</strong> the<br />

core which moves throughout all time, but which has not yet moved out <strong>of</strong> itself.<br />

Every lived moment would, therefore, if it has eyes, be a witness <strong>of</strong> the beginning <strong>of</strong><br />

the world which begins in it time and time again; every moment, when it has not<br />

yet emerged, is in the year zero <strong>of</strong> the beginning <strong>of</strong> the world.’ (Bloch 1995, p. 301)<br />

2 In this context, see Schelling’s (1994, pp. 134-163) critique <strong>of</strong> Hegel in his<br />

lectures On the History <strong>of</strong> Modern Philosophy.<br />

3 I refer again here to Schelling’s (1994, pp. 134-163) critique <strong>of</strong> Hegel in his<br />

lectures On the History <strong>of</strong> Modern Philosophy<br />

Language and Death<br />

1 In his Lectures on the Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Religion, Hegel says: ‘Th e natural, simple<br />

self-emancipation <strong>of</strong> the fi nite from its fi niteness is death. Th is is the renunciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fi nite, and here what the natural life is itself implicitly is made explicit really<br />

and actually. Th e sensuous life <strong>of</strong> what is individual or particular has its end in death.<br />

Particular experiences or sensations as particular are transient ; one supplants the<br />

other, one impulse or other drives away the another...In death the fi nite is shown to<br />

be annulled and absorbed. But death is only abstract negation <strong>of</strong> what is implicitly<br />

negative; it is itself a nullity, it is revealed a nullity. But explicit nullity is at the same<br />

time nullity which has been done away with, and is the return to the positive .<br />

Here cessation, liberated from fi niteness, comes in. Death does not present itself to<br />

consciousness as this emancipation from fi niteness, but this higher view <strong>of</strong> death is<br />

found in thought, and indeed even in popular conceptions, in so far as thought is<br />

active in them. (Hegel 1962, p. 182)<br />

Part II – The Lightning Flash<br />

Language <strong>of</strong> the Mortals<br />

1 I have translated this paragraph as follows: ‘`Begin’—that is something else than


Notes • 403<br />

'Inception’. A new weather condition, for example, begins with a storm; its inception<br />

is, however, is the transformation in advance, the complete transformation <strong>of</strong> air<br />

conditions . Beginning is each time with which something arises; inception that,<br />

from which something erupts (springs forth). Th e world war incepted on centuries<br />

ago in the spiritual-political history <strong>of</strong> the West. Th e world war began propound<br />

positioning. Th e beginning is left immediately; it disappears in the continuation <strong>of</strong><br />

the happening. Th e inception, the origin, comes to appearance as fore-shining and<br />

is fully there fi rst <strong>of</strong> all only at its end’.<br />

2 For Heidegger’s critique <strong>of</strong> Husserl’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘categorical intuition’, I refer to<br />

Heidegger’s seminars in Le Th or (Heidegger 2003).<br />

3 For an illuminating discussion on Kierkegaard’s notion <strong>of</strong> language and<br />

language’s relation to death, I refer to Ge<strong>of</strong>f rey A. Hale (2002, pp. 73-108).<br />

4 Th at death cannot be reduced to any programmatic projection <strong>of</strong> being, ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as death is not mere nothingness but the unknown and hence is irreducible to any<br />

ontological mastery or thematization: this thought runs throughout Emmanuel<br />

Levinas’ works. I refer to Levinas’ extraordinary lectures on God, Death and <strong>Time</strong><br />

(Levinas 2000). In his early work <strong>Time</strong> and the Other, Levinas speaks, ‘ Th e end<br />

<strong>of</strong> mastery indicates that we have assumed existing in such a way that an event can<br />

happen to us that we no longer assume, not even in the way we assume events—<br />

because we are always immersed in the empirical world—through vision. An event<br />

happens to us without our having absolutely anything ‘a priori’, without our being<br />

able to have the least project, as one says today. Death is the impossibility <strong>of</strong> having<br />

a project (Levinas 1987, p. 74).<br />

Pain<br />

1 Jacques Derrida, among contemporary philosophers, is most attentive to this<br />

(non)phenomenon <strong>of</strong> ‘originary mourning’ for an immemorial origin that has never<br />

been present, a mourning that is inextricably tied up with gift that always comes<br />

from the others, and with the proper name that is always given by the others which,<br />

for that matter, can never be appropriated by ‘me’ in the name <strong>of</strong> self-presence. For<br />

the relationship <strong>of</strong> gift and the proper name with the ‘originary mourning’ that<br />

escapes the econo-onto-thanatological determination <strong>of</strong> the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> presence, see<br />

my article on Derrida (Das 2010).<br />

2 Ernst Bloch’s great work Th e Principle <strong>of</strong> Hope pursues, in a grand visionary<br />

manner, this messianic thought <strong>of</strong> affi rmation that is given in our hope for future.<br />

Apollo’s Lightning Strike<br />

1 Rosenzweig writes <strong>of</strong> the tragic hero, ‘For that is the criterion <strong>of</strong> the self, the<br />

seal, the seal <strong>of</strong> its greatness as well as the stigma <strong>of</strong> its weakness: it keeps silent. Th e<br />

tragic hero has only one language which completely corresponds to him: precisely<br />

keeping silent. It has thus from the beginning. Th e tragedy casts itself in the artistic<br />

form <strong>of</strong> drama just in order to be able to represent speechlessness...by keeping silent’


404 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

the hero breaks down the bridges which connect him with God and the world, and<br />

elevates himself out <strong>of</strong> the fi elds <strong>of</strong> personality’ delimiting itself and individualizing<br />

itself from others in speech, into the icy solitude <strong>of</strong> self’ (Rosenzweig 1971, p.77).<br />

Part Three – Event<br />

The Irreducible Remainder<br />

1 Th e time <strong>of</strong> freedom cannot be reduced to the Self-presence <strong>of</strong> the Subject, but<br />

it is a time, in certain sense, outside time, which is the time <strong>of</strong> the beginning <strong>of</strong> time<br />

itself each time anew. In his Freedom essay, Schelling writes, ‘ Man, even though born<br />

in time, is nonetheless a creature <strong>of</strong> creation’s beginning. Th e act which determines<br />

man’s life in time does not itself belong in time but in eternity. Moreover it does not<br />

precede life in time but occurs throughout time (untouched by it) as an act eternal<br />

by its own nature. Th rough it man’s life extends to the beginning <strong>of</strong> creation, since<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> it he is also more than creature, free and himself eternal beginning’<br />

(Ibid., pp. 63-4)<br />

2 See Hölderlin’s Judgement and Being (1988). For an illuminating discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hölderlin’s relation to the Speculative Idealism, I refer to Lacoue-Labarthe’s Th e<br />

Caesura <strong>of</strong> the Speculative (1998)<br />

Part IV – Messianicity<br />

1I refer here to Dana Hollander’s remarkable discussion <strong>of</strong> Derrida’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

exemplarity, see (Hollander 2008)<br />

2 For Rosenzweig’s distinction <strong>of</strong> the qualitative infi nitude <strong>of</strong> messianic intensity<br />

<strong>of</strong> time from the quantitative infi nitude <strong>of</strong> the historical time, I refer to Stéphane<br />

Mosès’ Th e Angel <strong>of</strong> History (2009).<br />

3 Rosenzweig writes: ‘Th is constant increase is the form <strong>of</strong> permanence in love, in<br />

that and because it is the most extreme non-permanence and its fi delity is devoted<br />

solely to the present, singular moment: from the deepest infi delity and from this<br />

alone, it can thus become permanent fi delity; for only the non-permanence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

moment renders it capable <strong>of</strong> living every moment as new…’ (Rosenzweig 2005, p.<br />

176).<br />

4 ‘ For love is completely active, completely personal, completely alive,<br />

completely—speaking language; all true sentences issuing to it must be words that<br />

come from its mouth, words brought forth by the I. Th is one sentence alone, saying<br />

it is as strong as death, is an exception’ (Ibid., p. 217).<br />

5 Th e proper name denominates him who is singular without genus. Rosenzweig<br />

writes: ‘In places <strong>of</strong> articles, there appears the immediate determination <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proper name. With the call <strong>of</strong> the proper name, the world <strong>of</strong> Revelation enters into<br />

a real dialogue…that which has its own name can no longer be a thing or everyone’s<br />

thing; it is incapable <strong>of</strong> being entirely dissolved into the genus, for there is no genus<br />

to which it could belong; it is its own genus unto itself. It no longer has its place


Notes • 405<br />

in the world, or its moment in the becoming; rather it carried with it its here and<br />

now; the place where it is a center and the moment where it opens its mouth is a<br />

beginning’ (Ibid., p. 201).<br />

6 ‘…Th e Jewish people’, says Rosenzweig, ‘ stands outside the world…by living<br />

the eternal peace, it stands outside <strong>of</strong> a warlike temporality ; by resting at the goal<br />

that it anticipates in hope, it is separated from the march <strong>of</strong> those who draw near to<br />

it in the toil <strong>of</strong> the centuries’ (Ibid., p. 351).<br />

7 Levinas writes: ‘Th e age <strong>of</strong> philosophy is one in which philosophy is revealed<br />

on the lips <strong>of</strong> the philosophers…Th e end <strong>of</strong> philosophy is not the return to the age in<br />

which it has not begun, in which one was able not to philosophize; the end <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

is the beginning <strong>of</strong> an age in which everything is philosophy, because philosophy is not<br />

revealed through philosophers’ (Levinas 1990, p. 185, Italics the author’s). Levinas<br />

carries on: ‘Th e end <strong>of</strong> philosophy … Th e movement that led to the liberation <strong>of</strong><br />

man enslaves man within the system which he builds. In the State and nationalisms,<br />

in the socialist statism that emerges from philosophy, the individual experiences the<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> philosophical totality as a totalitarian tyranny’ (Ibid., p. 186).<br />

Fragments<br />

EPILOGUE<br />

1 One is here reminded <strong>of</strong> Franz Rosenzweig’s beginning note on his Th e Star <strong>of</strong><br />

Redemption: philosophy’s disavowal <strong>of</strong> death in its very claim to presuppose nothing<br />

so that the poisonous sting <strong>of</strong> death must not bite anyone anymore, so that in the<br />

quietness—even if the restlessness <strong>of</strong> negativity initiates movement, it reposes in<br />

this very restlessness not to have to presuppose anything—for it promises eternity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Concept, as the very accomplishment <strong>of</strong> the System, in the very annulling<br />

<strong>of</strong> the singular, for only singular is mortal and solitary. ‘ For indeed, an All would<br />

not die and nothing would die in the All. Only the singular can die and everything<br />

mortal is solitary. Philosophy has to rid the world <strong>of</strong> what is singular, and this undoing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Aught is also the reason why it has to be idealistic. For idealism, with<br />

the denial <strong>of</strong> everything that distinguishes the singular from the All, is the tool <strong>of</strong><br />

the philosopher’s trade. With it, philosophy continues to work over the recalcitrant<br />

material until the latter fi nally <strong>of</strong>f ers no more resistance to the smoke screen <strong>of</strong> the<br />

one-and-all concept. If once all were woven into this mist, death would indeed be<br />

swallowed up, if not into the eternal triumph, at least into the one and universal<br />

night <strong>of</strong> the Nought. And it is the ultimate conclusion <strong>of</strong> this doctrine that death<br />

is—Nought’ (Rosenzweig 1971, p.4).<br />

2 ‘ … Death concerns us by its nonsense’, says Emmanuel Levinas (2000, p.21). If<br />

‘death concerns us by its nonsense’, it is because in death, which is the very patience,<br />

there is the risk <strong>of</strong> nonsense, which is the nonsense <strong>of</strong> patience, <strong>of</strong> passivity that is<br />

patience. Levinas says,’ If patience has a meaning as inevitable is obligation, this<br />

meaning becomes suffi ciency and institution if there is not beneath it a glimmer <strong>of</strong><br />

nonsense. It is therefore necessary that there be on the egoity <strong>of</strong> the I the risk <strong>of</strong> a


406 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

nonsense, a madness. If this risk were not there, then patience would have a status,<br />

it would lose its passivity’ (Ibid., p.20).<br />

3 Levinas says, ‘…death is a point from which time takes all its patience; this<br />

expectation that escapes its own intentionality qua expectation; this ‘patience and<br />

length <strong>of</strong> time’, as the proverb says, where patience is like the emphasis <strong>of</strong> passivity<br />

…death understood as the patience <strong>of</strong> time.’ Ibid., pp. 7-8.<br />

4 Aff ection in mourning the dying <strong>of</strong> the Other without return aff ects us<br />

inconsolably beyond knowledge, certitude and excess <strong>of</strong> every consolation. Levinas<br />

says, ‘ as if there were an excess in death. It is a simple passage, a simple departure and<br />

yet a source <strong>of</strong> emotion contrary to every eff ort at consolation.’ (Levinas 2000, p. 9)<br />

5 Hegel writes <strong>of</strong> the negativity <strong>of</strong> death as the terrible work <strong>of</strong> absolute freedom, ‘<br />

the sole work and deed <strong>of</strong> universal freedom is therefore death, a death too which has<br />

no inner signifi cance or fi lling, for what is negated is the empty point <strong>of</strong> absolutely<br />

free self. It is thus the coldest and meanest <strong>of</strong> all deaths, with no more signifi cance<br />

than cutting <strong>of</strong>f a head <strong>of</strong> cabbage or swallowing a mouthful <strong>of</strong> water.’ (Hegel 1998,<br />

p. 360)<br />

6 ‘ … Spirit is the power only by looking the negative in the face, and tarrying<br />

with it. Th is tarrying with the negative is the magical power that converts it into<br />

being’ (Ibid., p.19).<br />

7 ‘…Death is the fulfi lment and the supreme ‘work’ which the individual as such<br />

undertakes on its behalf’ (Ibid., p.270).<br />

8 Levinas says <strong>of</strong> intentionality and its measure, ‘ Intentionality preserves the<br />

identity <strong>of</strong> the Same; it is thinking according to its measure, a thinking conceived<br />

on the modal <strong>of</strong> the representation <strong>of</strong> what is given, a noetic-noematic correlation.<br />

But being aff ected by death is aff ectivity, passivity, a being aff ected by the beyond<br />

measure, an aff ection <strong>of</strong> the present by the non-present …’ (Levinas 2000, pp.14-<br />

15).<br />

9 ‘…To think the measure is to think at the limit’ (Blanchot 1992, p. 39).<br />

10 ‘In Being-there-and-then, the negation is still directly one with the Being,<br />

and this negation is what we call a Limit (Boundary). A thing is what it is, only in<br />

and by reason <strong>of</strong> its limit. We cannot therefore regard the limit as only external to<br />

being which then and there. It rather goes through and through the whole <strong>of</strong> such<br />

existence’ (Hegel 1975, p. 136).


§ Bibliography<br />

Adorno, Th eodor W., Negative Dialectics, trans. E.B Ashton (London:<br />

Routledge, 1973).<br />

——, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Continuum,<br />

1987).<br />

——, Minima Moralia: Refl ections from Damaged Life (Verso: 1984).<br />

Aristotle, Th e Basic Works <strong>of</strong> Aristotle, ed., Richard McKeon (New York: Th e<br />

Modern Library, 2001).<br />

——, ‘Problems Connected with Prudence, Intelligence and Wisdom’ in<br />

Book XXX, Th e Works <strong>of</strong> Aristotle, Vol VII, Problemata, trans. E. S<br />

Forster (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971).<br />

Benjamin, Walter, Th e Arcades Project, trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin<br />

McLaughlin (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Th e Belknap Press Harvard<br />

University, 2002).<br />

——, Th e Origin <strong>of</strong> German Tragic Drama, trans. John Osborne (London<br />

and New York: Verso, 1998).<br />

——, ‘On Language as Such and the Language <strong>of</strong> Man’ in Selected Writings,<br />

Vol 1.: 1913-1926, ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings<br />

(Cambridge: Massachusetts: Th e Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> Harvard University<br />

Press, 1996).<br />

——, ‘Th e Task <strong>of</strong> the Translator’ in Selected Writings, Vol 1.: 1913-1926, ed.<br />

Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge: Massachusetts:<br />

Th e Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> Harvard University Press, 1996b), 253-263.<br />

——, ‘On Language as Such and on the Language <strong>of</strong> Man’ in Refl ections, ed.<br />

Peter Demetz, trans. Edmund Jephcott (New York: Schocken Books,<br />

1986), pp. 314-332.<br />

——, ‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Violence’ in Refl ections, ed. Peter Demetz, trans. Edmund<br />

Jephcott (New York: Schocken Books, 1986), pp. 277-300.


408 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

——, One Way Street, trans. Edmund Jephcott and Kingsley Shorter<br />

(London: NLB., 1979).<br />

——, ‘Über den Begriff der Geschichte’ in Illuminationen, (Frankfort:<br />

Sukhramp, 1977), pp. 251-261.<br />

Blanchot, Maurice, Th e Instant <strong>of</strong> My Death, with Jacques Derrida’s Demure:<br />

Fiction and Testimony, trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford,<br />

California: Stanford University Press, 2000).<br />

——, Th e Writing <strong>of</strong> the Disaster, trans. Ann Smock, (Lincoln: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Nebraska Press, 1995).<br />

——, ‘Th e Athenaeum’ in Th e Infi nite Conversation, trans. Susan Hanson<br />

(Minneapolis: University <strong>of</strong> Minnesota Press, 1993), pp. 351-359.<br />

——, Th e Step Not Beyond, trans. Lycette Nelson (Albany: State University<br />

<strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1992).<br />

——, La Communauté Inavouable, (Paris: Les Editions de Minuit, 1983).<br />

Bloch, Ernst, Th e Spirit <strong>of</strong> Utopia, trans. Anthony A. Nassar (Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 2000).<br />

——, Th e Principle <strong>of</strong> Hope, trans. Neville Plaice, Stephen Plaice and Paul<br />

Knight (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Th e MIT Press, 1995 & 1986),<br />

Vol. 1.<br />

——, Th e Principle <strong>of</strong> Hope, trans. Neville Plaice, Stephen Plaice and Paul<br />

Knight (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Th e MIT Press, 1995a), Vol. 3.<br />

Chrétien, Jean-Louis, Th e Unforgettable and the Unhoped For, trans. Jeff rey<br />

Bloechl (Fordham: Fordham University Press, 2002).<br />

Das, Saitya Brata, ‘(Dis)Figures <strong>of</strong> Death: Taking the Side <strong>of</strong> Derrida,<br />

Taking the Side <strong>of</strong> Death’ in Derrida Today (Edinburgh: Edinburgh<br />

University Press, 2010), 3: 1, pp. 1-20.<br />

——, Th e Open in Kritike (http://www.kritike.org/journal/issue_6/das_<br />

december2009.<strong>pdf</strong>)<br />

——, ‘Wholly Otherwise’, Journal for Cultural Research, (London:<br />

Routledge, 2008), 12:2,176.<br />

——, ‘Th e Melancholic Name’ in Journal for Cultural Research (London:<br />

Routledge, 2007), 11:2, pp. 111-123.<br />

Dastur, Francoise Telling <strong>Time</strong>: Sketch <strong>of</strong> a Phenomenological Chrono-logy,<br />

trans. Edward Bullard (London& New Brunswick, N J, 2000).<br />

Derrida, Jacques, Paper Machine, trans. Rachel Bowlby (Stanford: Stanford<br />

University Press, 2005).<br />

——, On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness, trans. Simon Critchley and<br />

Richard Kearney (London: Routledge, 2001).<br />

——, Monolingualism <strong>of</strong> the Other or Prosthesis <strong>of</strong> Origin, trans. Patrick<br />

Mensah (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 1998).


Bibliography • 409<br />

——, On the Name, ed. Th omas Dutoit, trans. David Wood, John P. Leavey<br />

and Ian McLeod (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995).<br />

——, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravati Spivak (John Hopkins<br />

University Press, 1994), Indian Edition from Motilal Benarassidas.<br />

——, Given <strong>Time</strong>: I. Counterfeit Money, trans. Peggy Kamuf (Chicago:<br />

Chicago University Press 1992).<br />

——, ‘Onto-Th eology <strong>of</strong> National Humanism (Prolegomena to a<br />

Hypothesis)’ in Oxford Literary Review, vol. 14, no 1-2 (1992a), pp.<br />

3-23.<br />

——, Th e Other Heading: Refl ections on Today’s Europe, trans. Pascale-Anne<br />

Brault and Michael Naas (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,<br />

1992b).<br />

——, ‘Ousia and Gramme: Note on a Note from Being and <strong>Time</strong>’, in<br />

Margins <strong>of</strong> Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 1982), pp. 29-68.<br />

Derrida, Jacques & Anne Doufourmantelle, Of Hospitality, trans. Rachel<br />

Bowlby (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000).<br />

Figal, Gunter , For a Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Freedom and Strife: Politics, Aesthetics,<br />

Metaphysics, trans. Wayne Klein (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New<br />

York Press, 1998).<br />

Foti, Veronique, Heidegger and the Poets: Poiesis, Sophia, Techné, (New Jersey,<br />

London: Humanities Press, 1992).<br />

Hale, Ge<strong>of</strong>f rey A., Kierkegaard and the Ends <strong>of</strong> Language (Minneapolis:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Minnesota Press, 2002).<br />

Hamann, J.G., Writings on Philosophy and Language, ed. Kenneth Haynes<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).<br />

Hegel, G.W.F, Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (New Delhi:<br />

Motilal Benarasidass, 1998).<br />

——, Logic, trans. William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).<br />

——, Hegel’s Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Nature, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon<br />

Press, 1970).<br />

——, Hegel’s Science <strong>of</strong> Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands, NJ:<br />

Humanities press international, 1969).<br />

——, Lectures on the Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Religion, Vol I, trans. E. B. Speirs (London:<br />

Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962).<br />

Heidegger, Martin, Th e Essence <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom, trans. Ted Sadler<br />

(London, New York: Continuum, 2005).<br />

——, Four Seminars, trans. Andrew Mitchell and Francois Raff oul (Indiana:<br />

Indiana University Press, 2003).<br />

——, Th e End <strong>of</strong> Philosophy, trans. Joan Stambaugh (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 2003a).


410 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

——, Poetry, Language, Th ought, trans. Albert H<strong>of</strong>stadter (New York:<br />

Harper and Row, 2001).<br />

——, Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Manheim (Delhi: Motilal<br />

Benarassidass, 1999).<br />

——, Contributions to Philosophy (from Enowning), trans. Parvis Emad and<br />

Kenneth Maly (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1999a).<br />

——, Ontology: Th e Hermenutics <strong>of</strong> Facticity, trans. John van Buren<br />

(Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1999b).<br />

——, ‘On the Question <strong>of</strong> Being’, in Pathmarks, trans. William McNeill<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 1998).<br />

——, ‘What is Metaphysics?’ in Pathmarks, trans. William McNeill<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 1998), pp. 82-96.<br />

——, Basic Concepts, trans. Gary E Aylesworth (Bloomington, Indiana:<br />

Indiana University Press, 1993).<br />

——, Parmenides, trans. Andre Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz (Indiana:<br />

Indiana University Press, 1992).<br />

——, Th e Principle <strong>of</strong> Reason, trans. Reginald Lilly (Bloomington: Indiana<br />

University Press, 1991).<br />

——, Schelling’s Treatise on the Essence <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom, trans. Joan<br />

Stambaugh (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1985).<br />

——, Th e Metaphysical Foundations <strong>of</strong> Logic, trans. Michael Heim (Indiana:<br />

Indiana University Press, 1984).<br />

——, ‘On <strong>of</strong> the Nature <strong>of</strong> Language’ in On the Way to Language, trans.<br />

Peter D. Hertz (New York: Harper & Row, 1982), pp. 57-110.<br />

——, ‘Hölderlins Hymnen “Germanien” und “Der Rhein”’, Gesamtausgabe,<br />

Band 39 (Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1980).<br />

——, ‘Th e End <strong>of</strong> Philosophy and the Task <strong>of</strong> Th inking’ in Basic Writings,<br />

ed. David Farrell Krell (London and Henley: Routledge and Kegan<br />

Paul, 1978), pp. 369-392.<br />

——, Th e Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William<br />

Lovitt (New York and Evanston: Harper and Row, 1977).<br />

——, Identity and Diff erence, trans. Joan Stambaugh (New York: Harper &<br />

Row, 1969).<br />

——, What is Called Th inking, trans. Fred D. Wieck and J. Glenn Gray<br />

(New York and Evanston: Harper and Row, 1968).<br />

——, Being and <strong>Time</strong>, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson, (New<br />

York: Harper and Row, 1962).<br />

——, Th e Question <strong>of</strong> Being, trans. Jean T. Wilde (London: Vision, 1959).<br />

Hölderlin, Friedrich, ‘Becoming in Dissolution’ in Essays and Letters on<br />

Th eory, trans. Th omas Pfau (Albany, State University New York Press,<br />

1988), pp.96-100.


Bibliography • 411<br />

——, ‘No. 240, To Casimir Ulrich Böhlendorff ’ in Essays and Letters on<br />

Th eory, trans. Th omas Pfau (New York: State University <strong>of</strong> New York,<br />

1988a), p.152.<br />

Hollander, Dana, Exemplarity and Choosenness: Rosenzweig and Derrida on<br />

the Nation <strong>of</strong> Philosophy (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2008).<br />

Jacobson, Eric, Th e Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Pr<strong>of</strong>ane: Th e Political Th eology <strong>of</strong> Walter<br />

Benjamin and Gershom Scholem (New York: Columbia University<br />

Press, 2003).<br />

Kierkegaard, Søren, ‘Repetition’ in Th e Kierkegaard Reader, ed. Jane<br />

Chamberlain and Jonathan Ree (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers,<br />

2001), pp. 108-150.<br />

——, ‘Th e Concept <strong>of</strong> Anxiety’, in Chamberlain, J. & Rée, J. (eds) Th e<br />

Kierkegaard Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), pp. 180-210.<br />

——, ‘Repetition’ in Fear and Trembling, Repetition, ed. and trans. Howard<br />

V Hong and Edna H Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press,<br />

1983).<br />

——, Th e Concept <strong>of</strong> Anxiety: A simple psychologically orienting deliberation on<br />

the dogmatic issue <strong>of</strong> hereditary sin, trans. Reider Th omte (Princeton:<br />

Princeton university press, 1980).<br />

——, Th e Concept <strong>of</strong> Dread, trans. Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1957).<br />

——, ‘At a Graveside’, in Th ree Discourses on Imagined Occasions, trans.<br />

Howard V. Hong and Edna Hong (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1993) pp.71-102.<br />

Lacan, Jacques, ‘Th e Mirror State as Formative <strong>of</strong> the Function <strong>of</strong> the I’ in<br />

Ecrits: Selection, (London: Routledge, 2001), pp. 1-8.<br />

Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe, Typography: Mimesis, Philosophy, Politics, ed.,<br />

Christopher Fynsk (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press,<br />

1998).<br />

Lacoue Labarthe, Phillippe and Jean Luc Nancy, Th e Literary Absolute: Th e<br />

Th eory <strong>of</strong> Literature in German Romanticism, trans. P Bernard and C.<br />

Lester (Albany: SUNY Press, 1988).<br />

Levinas, Emmanuel, God, Death and <strong>Time</strong>, trans. Bettino Bergo (Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 2000).<br />

——, Otherwise than Being: or Beyond Essence, trans. Alphonso Lingis<br />

(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).<br />

——, ‘ Between Two Worlds’ in Diffi cult Freedom, trans. Sean Hand<br />

(London: Athlone Press, 1990), pp. 181-201.<br />

——, <strong>Time</strong> and the Other, trans. Richard A Cohen (Pittsburgh &<br />

Pennsylvania: Duquesne University Press, 1987).


412 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

——, Totality and Infi nity, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne<br />

University Press, 1969).<br />

Marx, Karl & Friedrich Engels, Th e Communist Manifesto, trans. Samuel<br />

Moore (London: Penguin Books, 2002).<br />

Mosès, Stéphane, Th e Angel <strong>of</strong> History: Rosenzweig, Benjamin, Scholem, trans.<br />

Barbara Harshav (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009).<br />

Nancy, Jean Luc, Th e Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom, trans. Bridget Mcdonald<br />

(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993).<br />

——, Th e Birth to Presence, trans. Brian Holmes and others (Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 1993a).<br />

——, Th e Inoperative Community, ed. Peter Connor (Minneapolis:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Minnesota Press, 1991).<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich, Th us Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New<br />

York: Modern Library, 1995).<br />

——, Ecce Homo, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Penguin Books, 1992).<br />

——, On the Genealogy <strong>of</strong> Morals and Ecce Homo, trans. Walter Kaufmann<br />

(New York: Vintage Books, 1989).<br />

——, Daybreak, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1982).<br />

——, Twilight <strong>of</strong> the Idols and Anti-Christ, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Penguin<br />

Books, 1968).<br />

Plato, Th e Republic, trans. Desmond Lee (Penguin Books, 2003).<br />

——, ‘Apology’ in Selected Dialogues <strong>of</strong> Plato, trans. Benjamin Jowett (New<br />

York: Modern Library, 2001), pp. 279-323.<br />

——, ‘Phaedo’, in Th e Trail and Execution <strong>of</strong> Socrates, trans. Peter George<br />

(London: Th e Folio Society, MCMLXXII, 1972).<br />

Rosenzweig, Franz, Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption, trans. Barbara E. Galli<br />

(Wisconsin: Th e University <strong>of</strong> Wisconsin Press, 2005).<br />

——, Th e Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption, trans., William W. Hallo (London: Routledge<br />

and Kegan Paul, 1971).<br />

——, ‘Th e New Th inking’ in Philosophical and Th eological Writings, trans.<br />

Paul W. Franks and Michael L. Morgan (Indianapolis/Cambridge:<br />

Hackett, 2000), pp. 109-139.<br />

Schelling, F. W. J. von, Historical-Critical Introduction to the Philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

Mythology, trans. Richey, M. (Albany, NY: State University <strong>of</strong> New<br />

York Press, 2007).<br />

——, Th e Grounding <strong>of</strong> Positive Philosophy: Th e Berlin Lectures, trans. Bruce<br />

Matthews (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 2007a).<br />

——, Th e Ages <strong>of</strong> the World, trans. Jason M. Wirth (Albany: State University<br />

<strong>of</strong> New York, 2000).


Bibliography • 413<br />

——, On the History <strong>of</strong> Modern Philosophy, trans. Andrew Bowie (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1994).<br />

——, System <strong>of</strong> Transcendental Idealism, trans. Peter Heath (Virginia:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Virginia Press, 1993).<br />

——, Philosophie der Off enbarung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1977).<br />

——, ‘Brief Über den Tod Carolines vom 2. Oktober, 1809’, ed. Johann<br />

Ludwig Doderlein, Kleine Kommentierte Texte I (Stuttgart Bad<br />

Constatt: Fromann -Holzboog, 1975).<br />

——, Philosophical Inquiries into the Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom, trans. James<br />

Gutmann (La Salle: Illinois, 1936 & 1992).<br />

Schmitt, Carl, Political Th eology: Four Chapters on the Concept <strong>of</strong> Sovereignty,<br />

trans. George Schwab (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 2006).


§ Index<br />

Adorno, Theodor 261<br />

Aristotle 28, 93, 120, 124, 151, 197,<br />

238, 259, 350, 373<br />

Benjamin, Walter 8, 15, 20, 53, 124,<br />

139–41, 149, 154, 157, 161, 169,<br />

170, 194–95, 206–8, 214, 217–9,<br />

237–9, 242–3, 246–7, 310, 313,<br />

317–9, 321, 323–4, 328–9, 336,<br />

343, 349, 351, 369, 377<br />

On Language as Such and on the<br />

Language <strong>of</strong> Man 208, 217<br />

The Life <strong>of</strong> Students 351<br />

The Origin <strong>of</strong> German Tragic Drama<br />

139, 238<br />

Blanchot, Maurice 381, 387–9, 392<br />

Bloch, Ernst 6, 35, 39, 90, 186, 255,<br />

375, 377, 396<br />

Chrétien, Jean-Louis 24, 28, 61<br />

The Unforgettable and the Unhoped<br />

For 24, 61<br />

Das, Saitya Brata 142, 198<br />

Dastur, Francoise 46<br />

Derrida, Jacques 12, 14, 174, 270, 288,<br />

306–8, 314, 322, 337<br />

On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness<br />

270<br />

Onto-Theology <strong>of</strong> National Humanism<br />

306<br />

Hamann, J.G. 211<br />

Hegel, G.W.F. 10, 20, 34, 43–5, 50,<br />

54–7, 61–3, 65–8, 70, 72, 78,<br />

99–100, 103–5, 111, 119–21,<br />

125–6, 137–8, 151, 157, 161,<br />

163, 166, 177–9, 192, 214, 238–9,<br />

241–3, 257, 259–60, 263, 265, 273,<br />

314, 324–5, 356–7, 363, 365, 370,<br />

372–3, 381–2, 387–8, 391<br />

Heidegger, Martin 5, 8–11, 14–6, 19,<br />

24, 27–8, 35, 42, 68–71, 81, 85,<br />

87–8, 90, 107, 112–3, 117, 119,<br />

129, 133, 142–4, 146–53, 156,<br />

161–4, 169, 179, 185, 190–91,<br />

196–9, 201–2, 204–5, 208, 212,<br />

227, 232–6, 240–42, 244, 256–7,<br />

262, 269, 276, 278, 287–9, 291–<br />

300, 302, 344, 353–4, 359–60, 377,<br />

386–7, 393<br />

Being and <strong>Time</strong> 8, 24, 117, 142, 164,<br />

208, 240, 292, 299, 359<br />

The Question <strong>of</strong> Being 179<br />

Hölderlin, Friedrich 15, 26–7, 35, 44–6,<br />

83, 90, 92, 115, 127, 147, 162, 182,<br />

184, 196, 201, 203, 206–7, 210–11,<br />

281, 294, 300, 377, 391<br />

Jacobson, Eric 329<br />

Kierkegaard, Søren 21, 35, 43, 91, 99,<br />

103, 109, 114, 116–7, 157, 165,<br />

168, 171–4, 184–5, 236, 302, 377<br />

Lacan, Jacques 212<br />

Levinas, Emmanuel 51, 53–4, 311,<br />

315, 333–4, 355–7, 381, 384–7,<br />

389, 392


416 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

Marx, Karl 95<br />

Mosès, Stéphane 329<br />

The Angel <strong>of</strong> History 329<br />

Nancy, Jean Luc 82, 261–2<br />

The Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom 261<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich 68, 105, 113–4,<br />

120, 122, 150, 214, 343, 363,<br />

365–7, 373<br />

Plato 19, 27, 42, 106, 108, 190, 243–4,<br />

247–8, 259, 302, 343–4, 346,<br />

348–9, 351–3, 357, 366, 374, 385<br />

Rosenzweig, Franz 11, 14, 22, 35–6,<br />

43, 98, 100, 110, 119, 130, 134–6,<br />

138, 140, 152–3, 156, 158, 167–8,<br />

191–2, 194, 205, 214, 233, 235–6,<br />

248, 257, 305–6, 308–10, 312,<br />

314–39, 377, 396<br />

The Star <strong>of</strong> Redemption 22, 35, 43,<br />

130, 134, 136, 167, 214, 308,<br />

314–5, 317, 330, 339<br />

Schelling, F. W. J. Von 10, 11, 23,<br />

26–7, 33, 35, 41, 43, 45, 49,<br />

67–70, 73, 77, 79, 83, 94, 96–7,<br />

101, 103, 105–6, 125, 128, 138,<br />

150, 152, 156–8, 161, 166, 168,<br />

182–4, 190–91, 194, 203, 205, 212,<br />

214–21, 227, 229, 232–3, 235–6,<br />

248, 251–3, 257, 259–60, 262–8,<br />

271–4, 276–87, 289, 300–301, 321,<br />

344, 362, 377, 383–4, 394<br />

Philosophical Investigations into the<br />

Nature <strong>of</strong> Human Freedom 69,<br />

216–7, 221, 263, 267<br />

The Ages <strong>of</strong> the World 23, 69, 150, 233,<br />

259–60, 277<br />

Schmitt, Carl 123<br />

Socrates 244–6, 344, 346–51, 354, 364,<br />

373, 384–5<br />

Actuality 10, 26, 32, 58, 64–5, 68–70,<br />

73–4, 77, 101, 105, 115, 125, 138,<br />

168, 179, 183, 216, 218, 221, 227,<br />

229, 232, 234, 244, 254, 280,<br />

283–4, 286, 368, 371<br />

pure 26, 77, 227, 229, 232, 234,<br />

254, 283<br />

Causality 253–4, 264–7, 269–70,<br />

273–4, 277, 279, 291–2, 295–6,<br />

298–300<br />

problematic <strong>of</strong> 295, 296, 299<br />

Configuration 1, 14, 16–8, 35, 37, 40,<br />

45, 69, 102, 107, 110, 112, 131–5,<br />

139–44, 146–8, 150–56, 220, 253,<br />

257, 259–60, 272, 275–6, 282, 288,<br />

315–7, 362, 372<br />

Death 1, 6–7, 11–2, 18, 21–2, 24, 27,<br />

29–30, 32, 34, 39–40, 42–8, 52–3,<br />

56–60, 64–5, 68, 78, 80–81, 92,<br />

95, 99–101, 103, 112–4, 119–4,<br />

127–32, 136–8, 154–5, 158, 162–5,<br />

167–74, 176–8, 180, 182–5, 189–<br />

92, 194, 199, 203–7, 216, 219, 243,<br />

247–8, 280, 292, 294, 309, 315,<br />

320, 322, 325–6, 328, 335, 344,<br />

354–7, 361, 364, 367, 370, 373–4,<br />

381, 383–9, 391–3, 395–6<br />

negativity <strong>of</strong> 22, 29, 40, 45, 132, 356<br />

Erotic 343, 348–53<br />

Event 1, 5–11, 17, 19, 22, 24, 30–31,<br />

34–6, 40–47, 49, 51, 55–6, 59–61,<br />

68–70, 74, 76–8, 82, 93, 105–7,<br />

110–3, 117, 130–34, 137–9, 141–<br />

51, 154, 158, 161, 163–9, 171–3,<br />

186, 188, 191–4, 198, 203–4,<br />

208–14, 221, 223, 225–44, 246–53,<br />

257–8, 260–62, 264–6, 270–71,<br />

275–7, 279–80, 282, 286–9, 291–3,<br />

295–302, 305–10, 313–5, 317,<br />

319–28, 330, 334–5, 343, 345–8,<br />

352–3, 358–63, 366–7, 370–71,<br />

375–7, 385, 390, 394, 396–7<br />

Existence 1, 5–6, 8–11, 19–36, 39–42,<br />

44–5, 47, 49–50, 53, 57, 67, 70,<br />

73–5, 78–84, 86–7, 91, 93, 95–6,<br />

98–9, 101, 103–8, 114–6, 120, 123,<br />

126–7, 129–32, 134, 136–40, 147,<br />

150, 155, 158, 164–8, 170–71, 173,<br />

180–87, 189, 191–2, 194–5, 201,<br />

205, 207, 211, 213, 215–8, 222,


225, 227–33, 236–7, 239, 241,<br />

243–4, 246, 248–50, 253, 255–6,<br />

258–60, 262–3, 265–9, 271–9,<br />

281–4, 287–9, 291–8, 300, 302,<br />

309–10, 315, 320, 334–6, 338,<br />

343–9, 351–5, 359–71, 373–4, 377,<br />

381, 386, 388, 391, 393, 395–6<br />

mortal 21, 29, 33, 50, 70, 74–5, 103,<br />

106, 108, 181–2, 185<br />

Fate 21–2, 25, 28, 33, 101, 149, 225,<br />

244, 273, 275, 309, 317, 320,<br />

322–3, 325–6, 332, 368, 395<br />

Finitude 1, 8, 11, 14–6, 18–20, 22,<br />

24–6, 28–34, 36, 40, 42, 44–6,<br />

48–50, 56, 72–6, 78–9, 82, 84, 86,<br />

95, 98–9, 101, 106, 108–9, 113,<br />

115–6, 123, 128–30, 132, 139, 141,<br />

149, 156, 158, 161, 163, 166–8,<br />

170, 174, 177–8, 180, 182, 184,<br />

186–91, 194, 196, 204–5, 209–10,<br />

215–6, 218, 221, 226, 230, 236–7,<br />

241–2, 244–7, 250, 252–3, 256,<br />

258, 261–2, 264–5, 267–9, 277,<br />

285, 291–5, 297, 299, 315, 324,<br />

332, 355–8, 367, 374–5, 377, 381,<br />

384–6, 388–9, 391–4<br />

discontinuous 139<br />

radical 11, 20, 26, 29, 32–3, 44, 98,<br />

113, 167, 230, 264, 268<br />

Freedom 22, 33–5, 39, 69–76, 79,<br />

82–6, 114, 117, 128–9, 132, 136,<br />

158, 183, 214–7, 219–21, 233–6,<br />

241, 251–302, 323, 336, 359, 366,<br />

381, 394<br />

Gift 1, 5–6, 11, 13–5, 17–8, 20, 22–33,<br />

41–2, 44, 46–8, 50, 63, 73, 80–82,<br />

86, 89–90, 92–5, 106, 108, 111–2,<br />

114, 120, 124, 128–30, 139, 153–4,<br />

156, 158, 163, 166, 169–71, 173,<br />

175–6, 178, 180–84, 188–90,<br />

193–4, 196–200, 208–9, 215–9,<br />

221–2, 252–3, 256–8, 265, 267,<br />

271, 274, 277, 284–5, 287, 289–90,<br />

326, 338, 353, 357–8, 367, 372,<br />

375–6, 381, 385–7, 392–3<br />

Index • 417<br />

melancholic 180<br />

mournful 25<br />

non-economic 41, 158<br />

History 5–9, 12, 15–6, 20–23, 25,<br />

29–32, 39–72, 74–7, 79, 81–3, 85,<br />

89, 92, 97, 102, 107, 109, 111–2,<br />

116–22, 124, 129, 133–4, 141–2,<br />

157–8, 169, 171–2, 177–8, 182,<br />

185–8, 192–4, 199, 203–4, 207,<br />

211, 219–21, 225–8, 230–32,<br />

235–7, 241, 243, 247–8, 250, 252,<br />

256–7, 265, 271, 291, 294, 297,<br />

299, 305, 307–10, 314, 316–22,<br />

324, 326–9, 333, 335–8, 345,<br />

351, 355–8, 363, 365–7, 374–6,<br />

387, 392<br />

dialectical 60–61, 64, 169<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> 44, 51, 56–8<br />

speculative 44, 51, 57–8<br />

universal 12, 31, 32, 45–8, 52–3,<br />

56–7, 59, 62, 68, 107, 158,<br />

171–2, 177, 237, 248, 305, 318,<br />

321, 324, 326, 356–7, 365–6<br />

Judgement 8, 10, 30, 34–5, 43–4, 46,<br />

48–9, 51–60, 69–73, 75, 77, 124,<br />

127–8, 139, 169–70, 172–3, 179,<br />

182, 187, 195, 199, 207, 214–5,<br />

218–9, 260, 266, 274–7, 280–81,<br />

317–8, 320, 325–6, 360, 369, 382<br />

apophantic 8, 35, 57, 274, 360<br />

logical 34, 51<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> 49, 51, 75, 266, 275–7<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> 69–70<br />

Language 1, 8, 12, 14–5, 17–9, 29, 30,<br />

32, 35, 40–41, 47–8, 82, 94, 100–<br />

101, 106, 110, 113, 117, 119–32,<br />

134, 139, 147–50, 153–4, 161–78,<br />

180–82, 183–8, 190–96, 198–9,<br />

203–4, 206–22, 237, 239, 245–8,<br />

250, 252, 256, 287, 302, 305–7,<br />

310, 313, 318–9, 321–2, 325–6,<br />

328, 334–6, 339, 346–7, 352, 369,<br />

373, 381, 387, 393–5<br />

conceptual 171, 203–4, 206, 346–7<br />

gift <strong>of</strong> 128–30, 139, 153, 163, 169,


418 • THE PROMISE OF TIME<br />

171, 180–81, 196, 209, 215–7,<br />

219<br />

originary 187<br />

predicative 117, 187, 203<br />

pre-predicative 187<br />

pure 217, 245–7, 250, 310, 319<br />

Love 36, 85, 114, 124–8, 150, 211–5,<br />

217–20, 243–54, 264, 267–9, 271,<br />

277, 284, 289–90, 305–6, 308–14,<br />

317–8, 320, 322–8, 330–31, 333,<br />

337–8, 344, 349–53, 363, 373,<br />

393, 396<br />

Madness 19, 72, 82, 84–5, 93, 95–8,<br />

231, 250, 264, 301, 344, 363,<br />

366, 374<br />

Messianic 12, 329<br />

Metaphysics 61, 79, 142, 198, 259, 293<br />

Mortality 1, 11–2, 14, 16, 18, 21–30,<br />

32, 33–5, 40–47, 59, 76, 78–82,<br />

84–5, 89, 91, 93, 95, 98–101, 103,<br />

106–7, 115–7, 123, 128–9, 132,<br />

147, 154, 158, 161–4, 166–8, 170,<br />

176, 180–85, 189–91, 193, 201–4,<br />

206–8, 216, 218, 220, 222, 230,<br />

235–6, 244, 247, 253, 258, 280,<br />

315, 354–5, 361, 364, 367, 370,<br />

374–5<br />

pure facticity <strong>of</strong> 29<br />

Mourning 12–3, 18, 26–7, 31, 45,<br />

47, 49, 62–3, 65, 76, 81, 84, 92,<br />

111, 181, 192–6, 205, 245–6, 301,<br />

375–6, 381, 383–9, 391–3, 396<br />

Naming 14–5, 17, 30, 35, 40–41,<br />

47–8, 129, 132, 139, 141, 149, 154,<br />

170–71, 173, 177, 181, 192, 194–7,<br />

199, 207–11, 216–9, 221, 239, 246,<br />

248, 256, 258, 286, 288, 301, 318,<br />

327, 388, 391<br />

Pain 27, 45, 54, 67, 98–9, 120–21, 124,<br />

163, 174–81, 183, 193, 195, 198,<br />

386, 388<br />

Phenomenology 9–10, 13–4, 20, 43, 54,<br />

56–7, 61–2, 83, 87, 90, 93–4, 108,<br />

112, 121, 179, 227–8, 255, 315,<br />

325, 356, 360, 376<br />

Potentiality 29, 34, 69–70, 72–7, 80,<br />

102, 104–5, 125–6, 137–8, 168,<br />

229, 232, 234, 237, 244, 259, 365,<br />

368, 397<br />

passion <strong>of</strong> 69, 73, 75–7<br />

pure 29, 34, 70, 72–3, 80, 234, 365,<br />

368, 397<br />

<strong>Promise</strong> 5–7, 11–5, 18–9, 21, 23, 25,<br />

27, 30–33, 36, 40–42, 44, 47–50,<br />

52–5, 59–61, 66–7, 69, 73–4, 77,<br />

79–80, 82, 87–90, 93–5, 97, 103,<br />

109, 111–4, 116, 124, 126–7, 136,<br />

139, 149, 153, 156, 158, 161–3,<br />

168–9, 176, 180, 184–94, 196,<br />

198–9, 206, 208, 210–11, 214, 216,<br />

219, 227, 239, 242, 246–7, 249–50,<br />

252, 256, 284, 290, 305, 308–11,<br />

313, 317–25, 328–30, 332, 338,<br />

352, 357, 363, 369, 371, 374–7,<br />

381, 385, 395–6<br />

Recollection 90, 107–9, 111–6, 131–2,<br />

152, 157, 193–4<br />

Redemption 1, 6, 11, 20, 22, 35–6,<br />

42–3, 50, 66–7, 79–83, 90, 92–3,<br />

103, 107, 112–4, 116, 128–30, 132,<br />

134–6, 139, 152–5, 157–8, 167,<br />

177, 180, 186–94, 196, 198–9,<br />

206, 211–2, 214–22, 243, 249,<br />

252, 255–8, 264, 271, 284–5, 306,<br />

308, 310, 314–5, 317–20, 322, 326,<br />

329–33, 336, 339, 393, 395–6<br />

Remembrance 14, 18, 31, 39, 44, 48–50,<br />

90–91, 103, 107, 112, 117, 132,<br />

141, 145, 149, 153, 193–4, 196,<br />

199, 206, 208, 216, 219–21, 238–9,<br />

241, 260, 302, 321, 393<br />

Repetition 16–8, 49, 89, 99, 108–17,<br />

131–4, 140–41, 146, 156, 237,<br />

262–3, 266, 272, 274, 277, 280,<br />

307–8, 367, 389<br />

Revelation 7, 23, 25, 34, 36, 39–40, 47,<br />

72, 109, 125–6, 128–9, 132, 134–5,<br />

141, 145–6, 150, 152, 154–5,<br />

182–3, 185, 193, 209–20, 228, 231,<br />

237, 239, 247–8, 283, 287, 309,


314–5, 317, 319–20, 322–31, 333,<br />

376, 390, 393–4, 396<br />

<strong>Time</strong> 5, 8, 24, 50, 117, 126, 142, 153–4,<br />

164, 205, 208, 233–4, 240, 292,<br />

299, 359<br />

Transfinitude 156<br />

Translation 305–7, 309–11, 313,<br />

318–22, 324–5, 328–30, 332–3<br />

exemplarity <strong>of</strong> 306<br />

Truth 5, 7–8, 17–9, 23–4, 28, 51,<br />

54, 56, 58–60, 62–3, 65, 70–72,<br />

84–5, 93–4, 100, 109–10, 113, 117,<br />

121–2, 124, 127, 135, 139–40, 142,<br />

144–9, 164–5, 202–3, 212, 227,<br />

229–31, 234, 239, 242, 247, 275–6,<br />

281, 301–2, 305, 310–11, 314, 316,<br />

319–20, 322, 328–9, 343–9, 352–5,<br />

358, 360, 362–3, 365–8, 371–2,<br />

377, 382–4, 390, 396<br />

Violence 6–7, 13–5, 20, 25, 27, 41,<br />

47–9, 51–4, 60–61, 64–7, 78–9,<br />

83, 92, 115, 124, 127–8, 139, 141,<br />

150, 158, 178–80, 184, 187, 191–7,<br />

199, 205–7, 214, 220, 236, 238–9,<br />

243–4, 258, 275, 305, 307–8, 310,<br />

317, 320–21, 323, 326–7, 331,<br />

336–9, 343, 349, 351, 353, 357,<br />

360–61, 365, 388–9, 391<br />

Index • 419<br />

divine 206<br />

metaphysical 65–6, 79, 83, 206,<br />

337–9<br />

Work 1, 11, 12, 14, 18, 21, 22, 25, 29,<br />

32, 33, 34, 35, 44, 45, 46, 53, 57,<br />

58, 59, 60, 63, 65, 70, 81, 109, 114,<br />

130, 150, 169, 172, 175, 176, 177,<br />

178, 179, 212, 213, 219, 231, 233,<br />

234, 235, 247, 253, 259, 262, 264,<br />

270, 271, 273, 289, 297, 301, 314,<br />

320, 321, 322, 336, 337, 357, 358,<br />

359, 361, 362, 368, 370, 371, 372,<br />

373, 375, 377, 381, 382, 384, 385,<br />

387, 388, 389, 391, 393<br />

World 7, 22–4, 28–36, 39, 41, 45, 47–8,<br />

50, 67, 69, 77–8, 81, 85, 90, 93–6,<br />

102, 106, 114–5, 121, 123, 125–6,<br />

129–30, 135–7, 139–40, 143,<br />

146–7, 150, 152, 163, 169, 171–2,<br />

185–8, 191–3, 198–9, 210–15,<br />

228–9, 231, 233–4, 243–50, 256–<br />

60, 262, 265, 268, 277, 282, 287,<br />

292–5, 300–302, 308–9, 313, 315,<br />

317–8, 320–23, 325, 328, 330–31,<br />

333, 335–9, 343–4, 347–50, 354–5,<br />

358–60, 362, 367–8, 370, 374–6,<br />

386–7, 390, 392–4<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> the 28

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!