10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter One<br />

for example, by obtaining even just a rough approximation of what the Athenians<br />

considered an ‘abuse’, ‘public’, ‘power’, ‘private’ and ‘gain’, we might begin to<br />

understand which actions did and did not constitute bribery at Athens. From there we<br />

could more accurately differentiate between those actions that were really bribery at<br />

Athens and those that only seem (to us) like bribery but were perfectly licit for the<br />

Athenians, and so forth.<br />

Or so the theory goes. There are immediate, salient problems with taking a<br />

definition like “abuse of public power for private gain”—already laden in specific<br />

normative terms, it seems—and trying to translate it from one normative context to<br />

another. Even within a given set of cultural norms, it is unclear on what grounds<br />

‘abuse’ should be defined. Is it a violation of formal (legal) rules regarding the conduct<br />

of public officials, an action that goes contrary to the public interest, or one that goes<br />

against the public’s conception of what is acceptable? 2 Again, we could simply limit<br />

ourselves to one way of defining ‘abuse’ (or ‘power’ or ‘gain’, for that matter). But<br />

doing so obscures the crucial political work done by, say, limiting our scope to formal<br />

regulations of official conduct while disregarding both public opinion about what the law<br />

should say and the extent to which the law is seen to foster the public interest. This is not<br />

just an issue of asking, when a particular law is thought unjust, whether it should be<br />

2 These three options correspond to a modified version of Arnold Heidenheimer’s (1989) threefold<br />

typology of definitions of corruption. Heidenheimer differentiates between defining ‘abuse’ according to<br />

the norms of public office (i.e. legal norms) or the public interest; alternatively, under a market-based<br />

approach, public officials qua rational (utility maximizing) agents always tend to use public office to<br />

maximize private gain or influence. As Philp (1997: 445) has convincingly shown, however, market-based<br />

approaches always already incorporate legalistic definitions insofar as they presume that proper official<br />

conduct is determined by the law. In place of the market-oriented approach, therefore, I have included<br />

Gibbons’ (1989) definition based on public opinion even though this approach has not gained much<br />

traction; see also Peters and Welch (1978). Legalistic approaches can be found in Leys (1965), Nye<br />

(1967), Scott (1972). Public interest approach: Gronbeck (1978). Market-based model: Banfield (1975),<br />

Rose-Ackerman (1978, 1999), Klitgaard (1988), Goudie and Stasavage (1998), della Porta and Vannuci<br />

(1999), Lambsdorff (2002).<br />

27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!