10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Seven<br />

Given the difficulties of measuring the prevalence of bribery in any polity, let<br />

alone in a historical society like Athens, it is ultimately impossible to assess the accuracy<br />

of Lanni’s claim with respect to bribery in particular. There are, however, good reasons<br />

to think that at least with dōrodokia the enforcement of norms in the courts played out a<br />

bit differently than Lanni’s picture suggests. With dōrodokia, the Athenians used the<br />

courts, I argue, not simply to leverage already legitimate norms, as Lanni proposes, but<br />

especially to define which competing norms regarding dōrodokia should be legitimate.<br />

The Athenians effectively shifted the problem of definition we encountered above: it was<br />

up to an individual to define the offense, not according to some strict legal definition, but<br />

according to broader community norms. 22 More often than not, litigants on both sides of<br />

a trial thereby defined dōrodokia as a kind of harm to the people: prosecutors would<br />

claim that the outcomes tied to the receipt of gifts had been detrimental to the city, while<br />

defendants would claim that their actions had in fact benefited, not harmed, the<br />

community. 23<br />

In the case of dōrodokia, therefore, litigants offered their own conception of what<br />

constituted “harm to the people,” and a jury of hundreds of citizens—with potentially<br />

hundreds more looking on 24 —would cast their vote, effectively in favor of one definition<br />

over another. This was not a contest between two equally legitimate norms, but a<br />

22 It should be noted that dōrodokia may not have been the only offense for which this would have been<br />

true: hubris (~arrogance) and likely asēbeia (impiety) also were not strictly defined in law. See further<br />

Ostwald (1986: 528-36), Bauman (1990: 105-27), Carey (1994: 179), Cohen (1995: 143-62), Todd<br />

(2000a). With these offenses, too, it is possible that the lack of a legal definition intentionally fostered<br />

contestation of the norm itself.<br />

23 Both Cimon (ad Plut. Cim. 14.3) and the unnamed magistrate in Lysias 21 defend themselves on the<br />

grounds that they had benefited the polis. The juxtaposition of harm and benefit is particularly pronounced<br />

in Aeschines’ and Demosthenes’ mutual accusations of dōrodokia. Demosthenes, for example, proclaims<br />

how his opponent’s harmful actions were due to dōrodokia, while his own actions were both beneficial and<br />

unrelated to bribes: cf. Dem. 19.15-16, 18, 33, 45-6, 150-2 with 155 and 157, 205-8, 211-12, 223, 229-30.<br />

24 Lanni (1997) on the bystanders at Athenian trials. Likewise, audience members, whether bystanders or<br />

jury members, might create a roar (thorubos) of approval or disapproval: Bers (1985).<br />

306

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!