BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

historiantigua.cl
from historiantigua.cl More from this publisher
10.04.2013 Views

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Five Although this point must remain mere conjecture, we can see how thinking about the law as a translation of the dōrodokos from social type to legal entity actually reveals critical nuance in the law’s broader social meaning. In terms of legal process, Solon’s choice of matching the law against dōrodokia with the graphē dōrōn process may seem counterintuitive at first glance, but it makes good sense if we think in terms of domains of authority. If the lawgiver so loathed corruption among a small group of elite citizens, why, in order to address this corruption, would he institute an indictment of elite archons before a standing body of elite former archons (the Areopagus) who may have been opposed to the interests of the people? This question is easier to answer when we note that, as Danielle Allen has perceptively illuminated, a punishment like atimia was akin to religious purification. 79 Those who had taken dōra illicitly were thought to have violated the sanctity of their office and aligned themselves against the community’s interests. By acting against the community’s interests, the dōrodokos failed to provide a proper return, in essence contaminating his civic friendship with the community. Solon’s response was to purify the community by casting the offender outside its boundaries—precisely the kind of transformation of insider into outsider as was noted above. Crucially, the body that was to judge this offense was the most hallowed political body in the archaic polis: the Areopagus Council. Throughout the archaic and classical periods the Areopagus heard cases incurring the greatest religious pollution—murder, intentional wounding, cutting down Athens’ sacred olive trees, and serious political crimes in the first part of the democracy—meaning the pollution caused by bribery fell 79 Allen (2000: 209-11). On the similarities between religious purification and punishment in the Greek polis, see also Gernet (1981: 240-251, 265-7), Cantarella (1988). 249

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Five under their domain of authority. 80 Inasmuch as any derelict official had offended both the gods and the community at large, it was the Areopagus that properly assessed this offense and determined the proper recompense. 81 Although the people themselves would judge the justice of a magistrate’s specific judgment in an ephesis, the Areopagus was the natural choice to restore the larger relationship of reciprocity between official and community. Thinking in terms of domains of authority, therefore, allows us to make better sense of the Solonian law in action. By probing changes in the substance, punishment, and procedure entailed in the original law on dōrodokia, we have been able to reconstruct a much richer context for the original Solonian legislation. Although a functionalist approach might explain why Solon created some legislation on dōrodokia, the significance of this legislation, including its penalty and process, has been gleaned only by uncovering the process of ‘translating’ the dōrodokos into a legal entity. As we extend this legal history in the following chapter, we will find that a number of hallmarks of the democracy—including standardized public accountability and institutional bulwarks for collective action—were articulated in opposition to dōrodokia. By carving out a legal space for the dōrodokos, the Athenians established firm legal grounding for democratic politics. A number of key issues that surfaced within the Demosthenic law will be raised again in the next chapter. Solon’s concern that a single official or board might subordinate the community’s interests would trouble the Athenians for at least another 80 The Areopagus’ role as protector of the laws can be understood, in part, as an outgrowth of its role in policing religious pollution. After all, the Areopagus was renowned as a hallowed body: Dem. 59.80, IG ii² 204.16-33 (decree granting Areopagus authority over certain religious sanctuaries, 352/1). Note how the penalty for most of these crimes was exile, a purging of the offender from the community: so Allen (2000: 210-11). 81 Archaic literature depicts corrupt judges as offensive to especially Zeus and the goddess Dikē (Justice): Hom. Il. 16.386-8, Hes. WD 250-1, 256-62, Theog. 330. 250

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Five<br />

under their domain of authority. 80 Inasmuch as any derelict official had offended both<br />

the gods and the community at large, it was the Areopagus that properly assessed this<br />

offense and determined the proper recompense. 81 Although the people themselves would<br />

judge the justice of a magistrate’s specific judgment in an ephesis, the Areopagus was the<br />

natural choice to restore the larger relationship of reciprocity between official and<br />

community. Thinking in terms of domains of authority, therefore, allows us to make<br />

better sense of the Solonian law in action.<br />

By probing changes in the substance, punishment, and procedure entailed in the<br />

original law on dōrodokia, we have been able to reconstruct a much richer context for the<br />

original Solonian legislation. Although a functionalist approach might explain why<br />

Solon created some legislation on dōrodokia, the significance of this legislation,<br />

including its penalty and process, has been gleaned only by uncovering the process of<br />

‘translating’ the dōrodokos into a legal entity. As we extend this legal history in the<br />

following chapter, we will find that a number of hallmarks of the democracy—including<br />

standardized public accountability and institutional bulwarks for collective action—were<br />

articulated in opposition to dōrodokia. By carving out a legal space for the dōrodokos,<br />

the Athenians established firm legal grounding for democratic politics.<br />

A number of key issues that surfaced within the Demosthenic law will be raised<br />

again in the next chapter. Solon’s concern that a single official or board might<br />

subordinate the community’s interests would trouble the Athenians for at least another<br />

80 The Areopagus’ role as protector of the laws can be understood, in part, as an outgrowth of its role in<br />

policing religious pollution. After all, the Areopagus was renowned as a hallowed body: Dem. 59.80, IG<br />

ii² 204.16-33 (decree granting Areopagus authority over certain religious sanctuaries, 352/1). Note how the<br />

penalty for most of these crimes was exile, a purging of the offender from the community: so Allen (2000:<br />

210-11).<br />

81 Archaic literature depicts corrupt judges as offensive to especially Zeus and the goddess Dikē (Justice):<br />

Hom. Il. 16.386-8, Hes. WD 250-1, 256-62, Theog. 330.<br />

250

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!