10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Five<br />

discrete offenses and later grouped them together into a comprehensive law (thereby<br />

creating overlap), or that they first identified a general offense (dōrodokia) and later re-<br />

legislated its most egregious types, perhaps with harsher penalties in a further attempt to<br />

discourage potential offenders. 5 Alternatively, it is surmised that the overlap was<br />

consciously created to increase the likelihood of prosecution; procedural flexibility would<br />

enable someone to prosecute a dōrodokos and thereby incur just the right amount of risk. 6<br />

There are considerable problems in painting a broad legal history based on such<br />

generalizations about the development of Athenian law 7 ; even if we put these to one side,<br />

however, there are still further problems with this approach. In accounting for legal<br />

innovation, these scholars have proceeded from two basic assumptions: to curb<br />

corruption, the Athenians decided to define dōrodokia in law and they thereby created<br />

legal penalties that would act as deterrents to future dōrodokoi. To my mind, both of<br />

these assumptions are incorrect.<br />

These assumptions are remarkably similar to contemporary legal scholars’<br />

discussions of the rule of law. For those scholars, the rule of law is a central goal of anti-<br />

bribery legislation: the law, and ideally only the law, is to be used to provide a definition<br />

5 Broadly, these are the approaches taken by Hashiba (2006: esp. 76) and MacDowell (1983a), respectively,<br />

who have offered the only in-depth examinations of the legal history of dōrodokia in classical Athens. Of<br />

these, only the treatment of MacDowell (1983a) is comprehensive, but its conclusions have been rightly<br />

criticized by Todd (1993: 303n.16) and especially Hashiba (2006), whose own examination is more evenhanded<br />

yet does not aim to be exhaustive.<br />

6 Demosthenes posits precisely this reason for the variety of Athenian laws on theft: Dem. 22.25-7. He has<br />

been followed by Osborne (1985), Ober (1989: 144-5), Todd (1993: 160-3); see especially Carey (2004)<br />

for the criticism that this explanation does not account for the entire Athenian legal system. As I will<br />

argue in Chapter Seven, the motivation behind procedural flexibility in dōrodokia suits potentially<br />

stemmed from the need for different authoritative bodies to be the judge in different circumstances.<br />

7 See especially Humphreys (1983: 229-31), Cantarella (1987), Cohen (1989: 91), Todd (1993: 69-70) on<br />

the various dangers of adopting an evolutionary approach in the study of Athenian law. It is puzzling, in<br />

this regard, that Hashiba (2006: 68n.27) notes the problems with making evolutionary assumptions about<br />

the development of Athenian law, yet nevertheless posits that the general law against dōrodokia (as cited in<br />

Dem. 21.113) evinces “some intellectual sophistication of legislative language.” In effect, diachronic<br />

changes in the Demosthenic law are understood as increasingly sophisticated attempts at defining<br />

dōrodokia comprehensively. I offer a different approach below.<br />

217

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!