10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Three<br />

display of his largesse, the defendant’s catalogue of liturgical expenses signifies his<br />

innocence and illustrates how irrational his opponent’s claim surely must be.<br />

This is a remarkable argument in context. In other speeches defendants cite their<br />

liturgies as an argument from ethos: a demonstration of their good character and,<br />

occasionally, a reason why they should be treated leniently by the courts. 75 Indeed, this is<br />

how the defendant in Lysias 21 opens his speech, and he draws attention to this exact<br />

phenomenon after finishing his own catalogue of liturgies (Lys. 21.11, 17). Yet his<br />

argument from ethos subtly shifts into an argument from logos, or reason, in two different<br />

ways. He claims that, because elites plunder the city’s coffers, it would be “worth it”<br />

(a1cion) for the community to continue relying on a sure source of revenue, i.e. the<br />

defendant’s financial contributions, rather than to confiscate his property and to have the<br />

city manage it (Lys. 21.13-14). The defendant’s phrasing here is particularly strong, as<br />

he claims that he would make a better tamias—treasurer—than the official tamiai of the<br />

city (Lys. 21.14). 76 Precisely because the financial returns accrued by the city would be<br />

greater if the defendant were to keep his money than if the city were to take it,<br />

confiscating his property would be tantamount to injustice (cf. a)dikh/sete, Lys. 21.14).<br />

75 See above note 57.<br />

76 Schmitz (1995: 87-8) rightly discusses this passage in conjunction with the common rhetorical refrain<br />

that the polis would beneft most by letting the rich manage their own money, but it should be noted that the<br />

defendant here presents a variation on the standard topos. Rather than say that the polis would benefit less<br />

by taking his property than by leaving it alone, the defendant insinuates that the people would not benefit at<br />

all, for others would ‘divide it amongst themselves’ (diane/mountai, in the middle voice, Lys. 21.14). This<br />

subtle variation allows the defendant to transform his version into an argument about political justice. As a<br />

matter of justice, he assumes, the community is owed reciprocity, and only by letting the defendant remain<br />

tamias of his own property could that just outcome be obtained; otherwise, the community would suffer<br />

from negative reciprocity at the hands of plundering elites.<br />

160

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!