10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter Two<br />

troubling even without the overtones of bribery. Cleon’s corruption is particularly<br />

problematic because it enables him to escape accountability. 95 Accordingly, his bribe-<br />

giving enables him to invert his relationship with the dēmos so that he, not the dēmos,<br />

becomes master. 96 Just as Pericles’ control over public monies was called into question<br />

by accusations of dōrodokia, here too it is assumed that public speakers illegitimately<br />

control, and disproportionately benefit from, the allies’ imperial monies (esp. Ar. V. 660-<br />

79). All of the monies found in the ways corrupt politicians negotiate politics are thus<br />

cast as the bribes. Hence, that we find Cleon’s misthophoria recast as bribe monies<br />

strongly suggests that a number of Athenians thought that Cleon’s relationship to the<br />

dēmos, like Pericles’—specifically, his influence on the distribution of public funds—was<br />

inherently problematic.<br />

I am suggesting that, as with the Springhouse Decree and public works, with<br />

misthophoria and other political monies created around mid-century the dēmos self-<br />

consciously strove to be its own patron. It identified a money of Cimonian-style<br />

patronage—feeding the public—and refashioned it in democratic form, in effect blocking<br />

elite citizens from playing that role using the old monies of patronage. Nevertheless,<br />

elites like Pericles and Cleon, who previously would have derived political authority<br />

from the politics of patronage, instead tried to appropriate for themselves the dēmos’ new<br />

monies; in this way, they forged a new kind of politics. 97 Even if the picture I am<br />

95 esp. Ar. Eq. 801-9; cf. V. 669-79, 960-1.<br />

96 This point is explored at length in McGlew (2002: 86-111), which focuses on Aristophanes’ Knights and<br />

Cleon’s desire to control the dēmos. See also Wohl (2002) and Scholtz (2004) on the politics of<br />

domination latent in conceptualizing politicians as erastai.<br />

97 So in Aristophanes we find explicit comparisons between the contributions of new politicians and oldstyle<br />

patrons of the dēmos. In the Knights, for instance, the Sausage-seller uses metaphors of food<br />

consumption to compare his deeds to Themistocles: Ar. Eq. 810-19 with Anderson (1989: 15-16), Marr<br />

(1996). As Davidson (1993: 57-62) explores, the comparison, and implicit contrast, with past public<br />

officials signal how unjust the New Politicians’ patron-like redistributions were thought to be.<br />

118

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!